Datenbank/Lektüre


Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Lonergan; Wittgenstein, 'Philosophische Untersuchungen'; Unterschied zw. normaler und ursprünglicher Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache

Kurzinhalt: Die Entdeckung einer neuen Anwendung ist ein geistiger Akt, der durch den neuen Gebrauch zum Ausdruck kommt. Die Erfindung eines neuen Wortes ist ein geistiger Akt, der durch das neue Wort zum Ausdruck kommt.

Textausschnitt: 64/X In einem wertvollen Beitrag, der auf der dreiundzwanzigsten Jahresversammlung der 'Catholic Theological Society of America' gehalten wurde, erklärte Edward MacKinnon: (258; Fs)

65/X 'Seit der Veröffentlichung von Wittgensteins 'Philosophische Untersuchungen' gibt es einen wachsenden Konsens, daß die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache wesentlich öffentlich und nur im abgeleiteten Sinne privat sei. Wenn dies nicht so wäre, könnte Sprache nicht als Vehikel intersubjektiver Kommunikation dienen. Folglich wird die Bedeutung eines Terminus hauptsächlich durch Klärung seines Gebrauchs oder der Gruppe seiner Verwendungen erklärt, die mit ihm verknüpft sind. Dies erfordert sowohl eine Analyse, wie Termini innerhalb der Sprache fungieren, oder eine Untersuchung der Syntax, als auch eine Analyse der außersprachlichen Zusammenhänge, in denen ihr Gebrauch angemessen ist, oder der Fragen der Semantik und Pragmatik. (258; Fs) (notabene)

66/X Eine Folge dieser Position [...] ist es, daß die Bedeutung eines Wortes nicht durch Verweisung oder Rückführung auf private geistige Akte erklärbar ist. Nach herkömmlicher scholastischer Lehre haben Worte Bedeutung, weil sie Begriffe zum Ausdruck bringen. Bedeutungen liegen primär in Begriffen, in privaten geistigen Akten oder Zuständen, und dann erst abgeleitet in der Sprache, die solch einen Begriff zum Ausdruck bringt. Innerhalb dieser Sicht der Sprache stellt Transzendenz kein allzu schwieriges Sprachproblem dar. Ein Wort wie etwa 'Gott' kann ein transzendentes Wesen bedeuten, wenn es eben dies ist, was man beim Gebrauch dieses Wortes meint. So tröstend eine derart einfache Lösung sein mag - sie geht leider nicht.'1 (258; Fs) (notabene)

67/X Ich halte das für eine klare und hilfreiche Diskussionsgrundlage und möchte einige Bemerkungen anfügen, um meine eigene Position klarzumachen. (259; Fs)

68/X Erstens glaube ich nicht, daß sich geistige Akte ohne einen tragenden Ausdrucksstrom ereignen. Der Ausdruck muß nicht unbedingt sprachlich sein; er braucht nicht adäquat zu sein; er braucht auch nicht der Aufmerksamkeit anderer vorgelegt zu werden - aber er ereignet sich. In der Tat berichtet Ernst Cassirer, daß Forscher, die die Aphasie, Agnosie und Apraxie untersuchten, diese Störungen der Sprache, des Wissens und des Handelns allgemein miteinander verknüpft fanden.2 (259; Fs)

69/X Zweitens bezweifle ich nicht, daß die gewöhnliche Bedeutsamkeit der normalen Sprache ihrem Wesen nach öffentlich und nur in abgeleitetem Sinne privat ist. Denn Sprache ist ja gerade dann normal, wenn sie in gemeinsamem Gebrauch ist. Sie ist in gemeinsamem Gebrauch aber nicht, weil irgendein isoliertes Individuum zufällig entschieden hat, was sie bedeuten soll, sondern weil alle Individuen der betreffenden Gruppe verstehen, was sie bedeutet. In ähnlicher Weise lernen Kinder und Ausländer eine Sprache, indem sie zum Ausdruck gebrachte geistige Akte nachvollziehen. Aber sie lernen die Sprache, indem sie lernen, wie sie gewöhnlich gebraucht wird, so daß ihre private Kenntnis der normalen Sprache vom allgemeinen Gebrauch abgeleitet wird, der seinem Wesen nach öffentlich ist. (259; Fs)

70/X Drittens, was für die gewöhnliche Bedeutsamkeit der normalen Sprache gilt, gilt nicht für die ursprüngliche Bedeutsamkeit jedweder Sprache, ob normal oder literarisch oder fachspezifisch. Denn alle Sprache entwickelt sich, und zu jedem Zeitpunkt besteht jede Sprache jeweils aus den Ablagerungen der Entwicklungen, die bisher erfolgten und nicht veraltet sind. Sprachentwicklungen bestehen nun in der Entdeckung neuer Anwendungen für vorhandene Wörter, in der Erfindung neuer Wörter und in der Verbreitung solcher Entdeckungen und Erfindungen. Alle drei Vorgänge sind Sache zum Ausdruck gebrachter geistiger Akte. Die Entdeckung einer neuen Anwendung ist ein geistiger Akt, der durch den neuen Gebrauch zum Ausdruck kommt. Die Erfindung eines neuen Wortes ist ein geistiger Akt, der durch das neue Wort zum Ausdruck kommt. (259; Fs) (notabene)

71/X Die Kommunikation der Entdeckungen und Erfindungen kann technisch erfolgen durch Einführung von Definitionen, oder spontan, wenn z. B. A seine neue Wortkonstellation äußert, B antwortet, A in Bs Antwort erfaßt, wie erfolgreich er bei der Übermittlung des von ihm Gemeinten war, und er, je nach Ausmaß des Mißlingens, weitere Entdeckungen und Erfindungen sucht und ausprobiert. Durch einen Vorgang von Trial and Error nimmt ein neuer Wortgebrauch Gestalt an, und wenn eine genügend weite Verbreitung des neuen Wortgebrauchs erfolgt, dann ist ein neuer normaler Gebrauch eingeführt. Anders als die normale Bedeutsamkeit entsteht die Bedeutsamkeit als solche in ausgedrückten geistigen Akten, wird durch ausgedrückte geistige Akte übermittelt und vervollkommnet, und wird zur Normalsprache, wenn die vervollkommnete Kommunikation auf eine genügend große Zahl von Individuen ausgedehnt wird. (259f; Fs)

72/X Viertens scheint hinter dieser Verwechselung von normaler Bedeutsamkeit und ursprünglicher Bedeutsamkeit noch eine weitere verborgen zu sein. Denn zwei ganz verschiedene Bedeutungen kann man der Aussage beilegen, alle philosophischen Probleme seien Sprachprobleme. Wenn man Sprache als Ausdruck geistiger Akte versteht, wird man schlußfolgern, daß philosophische Probleme ihren Ursprung eben nicht nur im sprachlichen Ausdruck, sondern auch in geistigen Akten haben, und es könnte geschehen, daß man viel mehr Aufmerksamkeit den geistigen Akten widmet als dem sprachlichen Ausdruck. (260; Fs)

73/X Man kann aber auch der Meinung sein, geistige Akte seien bloß okkulte Entitäten, oder, falls sie wirklich existieren, sich die Philosophen bloß endlos abarbeiten, wenn sie ihnen besondere Aufmerksamkeit schenken, oder zumindest, wenn sie sie zur Grundlage ihrer Methode machen. Bei einer reduktionistischen Auffassung, oder bei einer mehr oder minder starken methodologischen Option, kann man dafür eintreten, den philosophischen Diskurs, zumindest den grundlegenden philosophischen Diskurs auf den Gebrauch der normalen Sprache zu beschränken, die vielleicht durch die Metasprachen der Syntax, der Semantik und der Pragmatik erhellt wird. (260; Fs)

74/X Wenn man sich jedoch diesen Ansatz zu eigen macht, kann man die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache nicht unter Berufung auf die sie hervorbringenden geistigen Akte erklären. Das wäre eine einfache Lösung. Es wäre eine wahre Lösung. Es ist aber keine zulässige Lösung, denn sie macht geistige Akte wieder zur Grundlage der Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache und tut dadurch gerade das, was die philosophische oder die methodologische Entscheidung verboten hat. Zudem übersieht man leicht innerhalb dieses Horizonts den Unterschied zwischen der Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache, die zur normalen Sprache geworden ist, und der hervorbringenden Bedeutsamkeit, die sie besitzt, wenn sie dabei ist, normale Sprache zu werden. Auf der Basis dieses Übersehens kann man behaupten, daß die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache ihrem Wesen nach öffentlich und nur in abgeleiteter Weise privat ist. (260; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Befangenheit, Scotosis

Kurzinhalt: Grundsätzlich ist die Scotosis ein unbewußter Prozeß. Sie tritt nicht in bewußten Akten auf, sondern in der Zensurfunktion, welche das Aufkommen psychischer Inhalte lenkt.

Textausschnitt: 1. Der Common Sense als intellektuell (173-81)

212b Das Licht und das Streben der intelligenten Untersuchung entfaltet sich methodisch in der Mathematik und in den empirischen Wissenschaften. Im Kinde ist es ein geheimes Wunder, das in einer Kaskade von Fragen herausbricht, wenn einmal das Geheimnis der Sprache erschlossen ist. Nur zu früh geht die Kontrolle über das Fragen verloren und überdrüssige Erwachsene werden immer häufiger getrieben, sich mit der Ausrede herauszuwinden: 'Mein Liebes, das kannst du noch nicht verstehen.' Das Kind möchte alles auf einmal verstehen. Es vermutet nicht, daß es in der Akkumulation von Einsichten eine Strategie gibt; daß die Antworten auf viele Fragen von wieder anderen Fragen abhängen; daß oft genug das Aufmerken auf diese anderen Fragen nur durch die Einsicht erfolgt, daß man, um interessanten Fragen zu begegnet, bei recht uninteressanten beginnen muß. Es gibt also den Forschungsgeist selbst, der allen Menschen gemeinsam ist und in dem die wissenschaftliche Einstellung besteht. In seinem Urzustande ist er allerdings ungeschult. Unsere intellektuellen Karrieren beginnen im unablässigen 'Was?' und 'Warum?' der Kindheit zu knospen. Sie kommen zum Blühen nur dann, wenn wir gewillt oder gezwungen sind, das Lernen zu erlernen. Sie bringen nur Früchte nach der Entdeckung, daß wir die Antworten, wollen wir sie wirklich in den Griff bekommen, irgendwie für uns selbst herausfinden müssen. (212f; Fs)

213a So wie es die spontane Untersuchung gibt, so gibt es auch eine spontane Anhäufung zusammenhängender Einsichten. Denn Fragen sind nicht ein Aggregat isolierter Monaden. Insofern auf eine Frage eine Einsicht folgt, muß man nur auf der Basis dieser Einsicht handeln oder sprechen oder vielleicht auch nur denken, damit deren Unvollständigkeit ans Licht tritt und so zu einer neuen Frage führt. Insofern dieser weiteren Frage wiederum durch die befriedigende Antwort einer weiteren Einsicht begegnet wird, wird derselbe Prozeß wiederum einen anderen Aspekt der Unvollkommenheit ans Licht bringen und damit Anlaß geben zu noch weiteren Fragen und weiteren Einsichten. Derart ist der spontane Prozeß des Lernens. Er ist eine Anhäufung von Einsichten, in denen jeder aufeinanderfolgende Akt die Genauigkeit der vorgehenden Akte vervollständigt und ihre Unzulänglichkeit überdeckt. So wie der Mathematiker von Bildern durch Einsichten und Formulierungen zu Symbolen fortschreitet, welche weitere Einsichten stimulieren, so wie der Wissenschaftler von Daten durch Einsichten und Formulierungen zu Experimenten fortschreitet, welche weitere Einsichten stimulieren, so ist auch der spontane und selbstkorrigierende Lernprozeß ein Kreislauf, in welchem Einsichten ihre Unzulänglichkeiten offenbaren, indem sie zu Taten oder Worten oder Gedanken führen, und durch diese Offenbarung die weiteren Fragen auf den Plan rufen, welche zu weiteren Einsichten führen. (213; Fs)

213b Ein solches Lernen erfolgt nicht ohne Lehren. Denn das Lehren ist das Mitteilen von Einsicht. Es wirft die Hinweise aus, die zutreffenden Fingerzeige, welche zur Einsicht führen. Es schmeichelt der Aufmerksamkeit, um die ablenkenden Bilder zu vertreiben, welche der Einsicht im Wege stehen. Es stellt die weiteren Fragen, welche die Notwendigkeit weiterer Einsichten klarmachen, um den erworbenen Vorrat zu modifizieren und zu ergänzen. Es hat die Strategie der sich entwickelnden Intelligenz erfaßt, und es beginnt so beim Einfachen, um zum Komplizierteren fortzuschreiten. All dies wird von professionellen Lehrern, die ihren Beruf im Griff haben, bewußt und explizit getan. Worauf wir hier aber hinweisen möchten, ist, daß es auch — obwohl unbewußt und implizit — von den Eltern gegenüber ihrem Nachwuchs und von den Gleichgestellten untereinander getan wird Sprechen ist eine menschliche Elementarkunst. Mit ihrer Hilfe teilt jeder den anderen mit, was er weiß, und ruft zugleich Widersprüche hervor, die ihn auf das aufmerksam werden lassen, was er übersehen hat. Doch noch eindrucksvoller als das Sprechen ist das Tun. Taten erwecken unsere Bewunderung und spornen uns zur Nachahmung an. Wir sehen zu, um zu begreifen, wie man etwas macht. Wir experimentieren, um zu sehen, ob wir es selbst machen können. Wir sehen erneut hin um das Übersehen auszumachen, das uns scheitern ließ. Auf diese Weise gelangen die Entdeckungen und Erfindungen von Individuen in den Besitz vieler, um auf der Grundlage ihrer Erfahrung kontrolliert, der Prüfung durch ihre weiteren Fragen unterzogen und durch ihre Verbesserungen modifiziert zu werden. Aus dem gleichen Grund ist auch die spontane Zusammenarbeit von Individuen das gemeinschaftliche Entwickeln von Intelligenz in der Familie, dem Stamm, der Nation, der Rasse. Nicht nur werden die Menschen mit einem ursprünglichen Trieb zu untersuchen und zu verstehen geboren; sie werden in eine Gemeinschaft hineingeboren, welche über einen gemeinschaftlichen Fundus geprüfter Antworten verfügt, und aus diesem Fundus kann jeder seinen Anteil beziehen, ihm zugemessen entsprechend seiner Kapazität, seinen Interessen und seiner Energie. Nicht nur entfaltet sich der selbstkorrigierende Lernprozeß innerhalb des privaten Bewußtseins des Individuums; denn durch die Sprache und noch mehr durch das Beispiel wird eine anhaltende Mitteilung erwirkt, welche zugleich jeden Fortschritt weitergibt und prüft und verbessert und so die Errungenschaft jeder Generation zum Ausgangspunkt der nächstfolgenden macht. (214; Fs)

214a Wir haben von der spontanen Untersuchng, der spontanen Anhäufung von verbundenen Einsichten und der spontanen Zusammenarbeit der Mitteilung auf die Notion des Common Sense als einer intellektuellen Entwicklung hin gearbeitet. Es wird sich nun ganz natürlich die Frage nach dem genauen Inventar dieses allen zugänglichen Speichers stellen. Wie definiert er seine Termini? Welche sind seine Postulate? Welche sind die Schlußfolgerungen, die er aus den Prämissen ableitet? Wenn die Frage nun aber naheliegend genug ist, ist doch die Antwort schwieriger. Denn die Antwort beruht auf einer jener merkwürdigen Einsichten, die nur gerade eben die falsche Voraussetzung der Frage erfaßt. Definitionen, Postulate und Ableitungen sind die Formulierung einer allgemeinen Erkenntnis. Sie beziehen sich nicht auf das Einzelne, sondern auf das Allgemeine, nicht auf das Konkrete, sondern auf das Abstrakte. Der Common Sense ist im Unterschied zu den Wissenschaften eine Spezialisierung der Intelligenz auf das Einzelne und Konkrete. Er ist gemein, ohne allgemein zu sein; denn er besteht in einem Satz von Einsichten, der solange unvollständig bleibt, bis nicht zumindest eine Einsicht in die vorhandene Situation hinzukommt; und ist die Situation einmal vorbei, so ist die hinzugefügte Einsicht nicht mehr relevant, so daß der Common Sense sofort zu seinem Normalzustand der Unvollständigkeit zurückkehrt. Der Common Sense scheint von der Analogie her zu argumentieren, aber seine Analogien entziehen sich einer logischen Formulierung. Die Analogie, die der Logiker untersuchen kann, ist lediglich ein Fall der heuristischen Prämisse, daß Ähnliches ähnlich verstanden wird. Sie kann einen gültigen Beweis nur dann liefern, wenn die zwei konkreten Situationen keine signifikante Unähnlichkeit aurweisen. Der Common Sense aber kann direkt von seinen akkumulierten Einsichten her operieren, weil er nicht artikuliert zu sein braucht. Den Ähnlichkeiten der Situation entsprechend, kann er sich auf einen unvollständigen Satz von Einsichten berufen. Der signifikanten Verschiedenheit der Situationen entsprechend, kann er die verschiedenen, für jede Situation relevanten Einsichten hinzufügen. (215; Fs)

215a Der Common Sense mag also zu verallgemeinern scheinen. Aber eine Verallgemeinerung, die vom Common Sense vorgebracht wird, hat eine Bedeutung, die von der wissenschaftlichen Verallgemeinerung recht verschieden ist. Die wissenschaftliche Verallgemeinerung zielt darauf ab, eine Prämisse anzubieten, aus der korrekte Ableitungen gezogen werden können. Die vom Common Sense angebotenen Verallgemeinerungen sind aber nicht als Prämissen für Ableitungen gemeint. Sie wollen vielmehr Fingerzeige vermitteln, die es normalerweise nützlich ist [sic], im Gedächtnis zu behalten. Sprichwörter sind weit älter als Prinzipien, und sie verlieren — ähnlich den grammatischen Regeln — ihre Gültigkeit nicht ob ihrer vielen Ausnahmen. Sie zielen nämlich nicht darauf ab, den abgerundeten Satz von Einsichten des Wissenschaftlers auszudrücken, der entweder für alle Fälle gilt oder für keinen, sondern den unvollständigen Satz von Einsichten, auf den man sich in jedem konkreten Fall bezieht, der aber unmittelbar relevant wird, nur wenn ein ausgiebiges Herumsehen zu den notwendigen zusätzlichen Einsichten geführt hat. Sieh hin, ehe du springst! (215; Fs)

215a Nicht nur unterscheidet sich der Common Sense von der Logik und von der Wissenschaft in der Bedeutung, die er den Analogien und Verallgemeinerungen zuweist. In all seinen Äußerungen operiert er von einem besonderen Gesichtspunkt her und verfolgt ein ihm eigenes Ideal. Die heuristischen Annahmen der Wissenschaft nehmen die Bestimmung von Naturen vorweg, welche immer in derselben Weise unter ähnlichen Umständen handeln, und ebenso die Bestimmung von idealen Normen der Wahrscheinlichkeit, von denen die Ereignisse nur in nichtsystematischer Weise divergieren. Wenn sich der Wissenschaftler auch darüber im klaren ist, daß er diese Bestimmungen nur durch eine Reihe von Annäherungen erreichen wird, weiß er doch auch, daß selbst annähernde Bestimmungen die logischen Eigenschaften der abstrakten Wahrheit besitzen müssen. Die Termini müssen demnach unzweideutig definiert sein, und sie müssen exakt immer in dieser unzweideutigen Bedeutung verwendet werden. Die Postulate müssen aufgestellt werden ihre Voraussetzungen müssen untersucht werden, ihre Implikationen erforscht. Daraus resultiert automatisch eine technische Sprache und eine formale Sprechweise. Man ist nicht nur gezwungen, zu sagen, was man meint, und zu meinen, was man sagt, sondern die Übereinstimmung zwischen Meinen und Sagen hat auch die exakte Einfachheit solcher primitiver Äußerungen wie: 'Dies ist eine Katze.' (215f; Fs)

216a Der Common Sense strebt seinerseits nie nach einer allgemein gültigen Erkenntnis und er versucht auch nie, erschöpfend mitzuteilen. Sein Interesse gilt dem Konkreten und dem Einzelnen. Seine Funktion ist es, jede Situation zu meistern, wie sie eben aufkommt. Seine Vorgehensweise besteht darin, einen unvollständigen Satz von Einsichten zu erzielen, der allein dadurch zu vervollständigen ist, daß man bei jeder Gelegenheit die weiteren Einsichten hinzufügt, welche die Untersuchung der Gelegenheit ergibt. Es wäre falsch, wenn der Common Sense versuchte, seinen unvollständigen Satz von Einsichten in Definitionen und Postulaten zu formulieren und ihre Voraussetzungen und Implikationen auszuarbeiten. Denn der unvollständige Satz ist nicht das Verstehen irgendeiner konkreten Situation oder irgendeiner allgemeinen Wahrheit. Ebenso wäre es ein Irrtum für den Common Sense, eine systematische Formulierung seines vervollständigten Satzes von Einsichten in einem bestimmten Falle zu versuchen; denn jede systematische Formulierung hat das Allgemeine im Visier; und jede konkrete Situation ist partikulär. (216; Fs)
216b Es folgt, daß der Common Sense mit einer technischen Sprache nichts anfangen kann und keine Tendenz zu einer formalen Sprechweise hat. Er ist damit einverstanden, daß man sagen soll, was man meint, und meinen, was man sagt. Aber seine Übereinstimmung zwischen Sagen und Meinen ist zugleich subtil und fließend. Wie das Sprichwort sagt, ist ein Zwinkern ebenso gut wie ein Nicken, d.h. ein kurzer Wink genügt. Denn der Common Sense sagt nicht nur, was er meint; er sagt es jemandem; er beginnt damit, die Intelligenz des Gesprächspartners zu sondieren; er schreitet fort, indem er bestimmt, welche weiteren Einsichten diesem mitgeteilt werden müssen; er unternimmt diese Mitteilung nicht als eine Übung in formaler Logik, sondern als ein Kunstwerk; und er hat zu seiner Verfügung nicht nur alle Ressourcen der Sprache, sondern auch die Unterstützung des modulierten Klanges und des wechselnden Tonvolumens, die Eloquenz des Gesichtsausdruckes, die Emphase der Gesten, die Wirksamkeit von Pausen, die Suggestivkraft von Fragen, die Bedeutsamkeit von Auslassungen. Es folgt, daß der einzige Interpret von Common Sense-Äußerungen der Common Sense selbst ist. Denn die Relation zwischen Sagen und Meinen ist die Relation zwischen sinnfälligen Vorstellungen und intellektuellem Erfassen, und wenn diese Relation so einfach und exakt wie in der Aussage 'Dies ist eine Katze' sein kann, so kann sie doch auch all die Zartheit und Subtilität, all die Geschwindigkeit und Wirksamkeit annehmen, mit der eine inkarnierte Intelligenz ihr Erfassen einer anderen Intelligenz mitteilen kann, indem sie erfaßt, was die andere noch zu erfassen hat, und welche Handlung oder welches Zeichen oder welcher Ton sie zu diesem Erfassen führen könnten. Eine solche Vorgehensweise ist offensichtlich logisch, wenn man mit 'logisch' 'intelligent und vernünftig' meint. Ebenso offensichtlich ist eine solche Vorgehensweise nicht logisch, wenn man mit 'logisch' die Konformität mit einem Satz allgemeiner Regeln meint, die für jeden Fall aus einem definierten Bereich gültig sind; denn kein Satz allgemeiner Regeln kann mit der Findigkeit der Intelligenz in ihrer Anpassung an die Möglichkeiten und Anforderungen konkreter Aufgaben der Selbst-Mitteilung Schritt halten. (216f; Fs)

217a Genau so wie die elliptischen Äußerungen des Common Sense einen tieferen Grund haben, als viele Logiker und praktisch alle Polemiker erreichen konnten, so ist auch die Ebene der Realität, auf die sich die Common Sense-Bedeutung bezieht, von der Ebene verschieden, welche die Wissenschaft erforscht. Es ist gesagt worden, daß die Wissenschaft von der Beschreibung zur Erklärung fortschreitet, von den Dingen in Relation zu unseren Sinnen durch Messungen zu den Dingen in Relation zueinander. Es ist klar, daß sich der Common Sense nicht mit den Relationen der Dinge zueinander beschäftigt, und daß er nicht die technischen Termini verwendet, welche die Wissenschaftler erfinden, um diese Relationen auszudrücken. Dieser offensichtliche Unterschied liefert nun aber keine Prämisse für den Schluß, daß das Objekt der wissenschaftlichen Beschreibung dasselbe ist wie das Objekt der Common Sense-Mitteilung. Es ist wohl wahr, daß beide Äußerungstypen mit den Dingen in Relation zu unseren Sinnen zu tun haben. Aber es ist auch wahr, daß sie dies von verschiedenen Gesichtspunkten her und mit verschiedenem Ziel tun. Wissenschaftliche Beschreibung ist das Werk eines ausgebildeten wissenschaftlichen Beobachters. Sie leistet der Forderung des Logikers nach vollständiger Artikuliertheit und erschöpfender Aussage Genüge. Sie trägt das Gepräge der Vorwegnahme des Wissenschaftlers, die reinen Konjugate zu erzielen, welche die Relationen der Dinge zueinander ausdrücken. Denn wenn die wissenschaftliche Beschreibung sich auch auf Dinge in Relation zu unseren Sinnen bezieht, so tut sie das mit einem weiter liegenden Zweck und unter der Anleitung einer Methode, die auf dessen Realisierung hinstrebt. (217; Fs)

217b Der Common Sense hat andererseits keinerlei theoretische Neigungen. Er verbleibt vollständig in der vertrauten Welt der Dinge für uns. Die weiteren Fragen, durch die er Einsichten ansammelt, werden eingeschränkt durch die Interessen und Sorgen des menschlichen Lebens, durch die erfolgreiche Erfüllung der Alltagspflichten, durch die Entdeckung umittelbarer Lösungen, welche funktionieren In der Tat ist der höchste Kanon des Common Sense die Beschränkung weiterer Fragen auf den Bereich des Konkreten und Einzelnen, des Unmittelbaren und Praktischen. Im Common Sense vorwärtszukommen bedeutet, die allesverschlingende Tendenz der untersuchenden Intelligenz zurückzuhalten und jede Frage, deren Beantwortung keinen unmittelbar handgreiflichen Unterschied zur Folge hat, als irrelevant, wenn nicht gar töricht zur Seite zu wischen. So wie der Wissenschaftler sich gegen die Einführung in seinen Forschungsbereich von metaphysischen Fragen, die seinem Kanon der Selektion nicht genügen, in herbem Protest verwehrt, so ist der Mann des Common Sense (und nur des Common Sense!) allzeit auf der Hut vor aller Theorie, stets bereit, den Vorbringer von Ideen milde zu fragen, welchen Unterschied diese machen würden, und sich dann, wenn die Antwort weniger lebhaft und weniger schnell als ein Reklamespruch ausfällt, nur noch darum besorgt, eine Entschuldigung auszudenken, um den Kerl loszuwerden. Common Sense-Menschen sind nämlich beschäftigt. Sie haben die Arbeit dieser Welt zu tun. (217f; Fs) (notabene)
218a Wie kann nun aber die Arbeit dieser Welt intelligent oder effizient getan werden, wenn sie von Common Sense-Menschen getan wird, die sich keine Sekunde lang über wissenschaftliche Methode Gedanken machen? Diese Frage kann, glaube ich, beantwortet werden, wenn wir bei einer anderen beginnen. Warum benötigen Wissenschaftler die wissenschaftliche Methode? Warum müssen so intelligente Menschen belastet werden mit der Ausrüstung von Laboratorien und langweiligen Büchern aus Fachbibliotheken? Warum müssen sie in Beobachtung und Logik geschult werden? Warum sollen sie auf abstruse Fachwörter und abstraktes Räsonnieren verpflichtet werden? Klar deshalb, weil ihr Forschen vom Vertrauten zum Unvertrauten fortschreitet, vom Offensichtlichen zum Entlegenen. Sie haben sich den Dingen in Relation zu uns in der Art und Weise zuzuwenden, welche zu den Dingen als in Relation zueinander führt. Wenn sie die allgemeinen Beziehungen der Dinge zueinander erreichen, bemühen sie sich jenseits des angestammten Bereiches der Einsicht in sinnliche Vorstellungen, und sie benötigen die Krücken der Methode, um ihr Hinsehen auf Dinge zu fixieren, die weder sinnlich gegeben, noch konkret, noch partikulär sind. (218; Fs)

218b Der Common Sense hat andererseits keinerlei derartige Bestrebungen. Er hält es mit dem Unmittelbaren und Praktischen, dem Konkreten und Einzelnen. Er verbleibt in der vertrauten Welt der Dinge für uns. Raketen und Weltraumstationen sind überflüssig, wenn man beabsichtigt, auf dieser Erde zu bleiben. Ebenso ist die wissenschaftliche Methode überflüssig für die Ausübung der Aufgaben des Common Sense. Wie die Wissenschaften ist er eine Anhäufung verbundener Einsichten in die Daten der Erfahrung. Wie die Wissenschaften ist er die Frucht einer weitreichenden Zusammenarbeit. Wie die Wissenschaften wurde er nach seinen praktischen Resultaten geprüft. Und doch gibt es einen tiefen Unterschied. Die Wissenschaften haben nämlich theoretische Absichten, und der Common Sense hat keine. Die Wissenschaften wollen präzise und mit allgemeiner Gültigkeit sprechen; aber der Common Sense nur zu Personen und nur über das Konkrete und Einzelne. Die Wissenschaften benötigen Methoden, um ihre abstrakten und allgemeinen Objekte zu erreichen; aber die Wissenschaftler benötigen den Common Sense, um ihre Methoden angemessen anzuwenden, wenn sie die konkreten Aufgaben der einzelnen Untersuchungen ausführen, so wie auch die Logiker den Common Sense benötigen, wenn sie verstehen sollen, was in jedem konkreten Akt menschlicher Äußerung gemeint ist. Es ist bewiesen worden, daß eine Komplementarität zwischen klassischen und statistischen Untersuchungen besteht; es ist jetzt vielleicht evident geworden, daß das Ganze der Wissenschaften und dazu der Logik eine Entwicklung der Intelligenz ist, welche zu der Entwicklung, die wir Common Sense nennen, komplementär ist. Die rationale Wahl ist nicht zwischen Wissenschaft und Common Sense; sie ist vielmehr die Wahl beider: der Wissenschaft, um das Allgemeine zu meistern, und des Common Sense, um das Partikuläre anzugehen. (219; Fs) (notabene)

219a Es bleibt, die Differenzierungen des Common Sense zu erwähnen. Denn mehr noch als die Wissenschaften ist der Common Sense in spezialisierte Abteilungen aufgeteilt. Für jeden Unterschied in der Geographie, für jeden Unterschied in der Beschäftigung, für jeden Unterschied in den sozialen Einrichtungen gibt es eine entsprechende Variation des Common Sense. An einem gegebenen Ort, in einem bestimmten Beruf und in einer bestimmten Gruppe von Menschen kann ein Mensch in intelligenter Mühelosigkeit jeder Situation begegnen, in der er sprechen oder handeln soll. Er weiß jederzeit, was los ist, was richtigerweise gesagt werden soll, was eben getan werden muß und wie man es anpacken soll. Seine Erfahrung hat ihn durch den Kreis von Eventualitäten geführt, welche in seinem Milieu vorkommen. Seine Intelligenz ist immer wach gewesen. Er hat Fehler gemacht und er hat gelernt, sie nicht zweimal zu begehen. Er hat jene Verstandesschärfe entwickelt, welche Bewegungen zur Kenntnis nimmt, die von der vertrauten Routine abweichen; die Besonnenheit, welche diese abschätzt, ehe er sich in einen Handlungsverlauf einläßt; den Erfindungsreichtum, der die Antwort findet, welche dem neuen Problem begegnet. Er ist eine Verkörperung des Ideales des Common Sense; aber seine Leistung ist nur für seine Umgebung relevant. Man verlege ihn unter andere Menschen an einen anderen Ort oder in einen anderen Beruf, und solange er sich damit noch nicht vertraut gemacht hat, solange er sich noch nicht einen neuen Satz von Einsichten erworben hat, kann er Zaudern und Ungeschicklichkeiten nicht vermeiden. Er muß neu wieder lernen, worum es geht; er muß mit den Tricks eines neuen Berufes vertraut werden; er muß in kleinen Zeichen die sich verändernden Gemütslagen derer herausspüren, mit denen er zu tun hat. Derart ist also die Spezialisierung des Common Sense. Er paßt sofort die Individuen in jeder Lebenslage an die Arbeit an, die sie gewählt haben, oder an das Los, das ihnen zugefallen ist und außerdem bringt er all jene ganz kleinen Unterschiede der Gesichtspunkte und Mentalitäten hervor, welche Männer und Frauen trennen, alt und jung, Stadt und Land, bis schließlich die kumulativen Unterschiede und das gegenseitige Unverständnis der verschiedenen Gesellschaftsschichten, verschiedenen Nationen, verschiedenen Zivilisationen und verschiedenen historischen Epochen der menschlichen Geschichte erreicht werden. (219f; Fs)

220a Wir haben versucht, die intellektuelle Komponente im Common Sense zu begreifen. Wir begannen bei den spontanen Fragen, den spontanen Anhäufungen von Einsichten und der spontanen Zusammenarbeit, um sie zu prüfen und verbessern. Als nächstes formulierten wir die zentrale Notion eines habituellen aber unvollständigen Satzes von Einsichten, der durch geeignete Variationen in jedem konkreten Satz von Umständen vervollständigt wird, die Reden oder Handeln verlangen. Es wurde gezeigt, daß eine derartige intellektuelle Entwicklung nicht nur auf eine Meisterung des Konkreten und Einzelnen abzielt, sondern ihr Ziel auch auf eine konkrete und partikuläre Weise erreicht, welche mit den allgemeinen Regeln der Logik und den allgemeinen Methoden der Wissenschaft kontrastiert, indes eine notwendige Ergänzung sowohl für die konkrete Verwendung allgemeiner Techniken als auch die konkrete Anwendung allgemeiner Konklusionen liefert. Schließlich wandten wir uns den Differenzierungen des Common Sense zu, welche sich nicht durch theoretische Unterschiede wie die Abteilungen der Wissenschaft, sondern durch die empirischen Unterschiede von Ort und Zeit, Umständen und Milieu vermehren. (220; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Verdrängung; Aberration, Ablehnung

Kurzinhalt: Unterschied zw. Aberration (repression) und bewusster Ablehung

Textausschnitt: 2.7.2 Verdrängung [192-93]

56/06 Und es ist auch nicht bloß der Verstand, der in Verwirrung versetzt wird. Die Scotosis ist eine Aberration, nicht nur des Verstandes, sondern auch der Zensurfunktion. So wie der Wunsch nach Einsicht die Oberfläche durchdringt, um schematische Bilder hervorzubringen, welche dann die Einsicht aufkommen lassen, so hat das Nicht-Wollen einer Einsicht die entgegengesetzte Wirkung der Verdrängung eines Schemas, welches die Einsicht suggerieren würde, aus dem Bewußtsein. Nun ist diese Aberration der Zensurfunktion umgekehrt zu dieser. Die Zensurfunktion ist primär konstruktiv; sie wählt aus und ordnet Materialien an, welche im Bewußtsein in einer Perspektive aufkommen, die eine Einsicht entstehen lassen; diese positive Aktivität impliziert einen negativen Aspekt, indem nämlich andere Materialien links liegengelassen und andere Perspektiven nicht ans Licht gebracht werden. Dieser negative Aspekt der positiven Aktivität führt allerdings nicht irgendwelche Anordnung oder Perspektive ein in die unbewußten Forderungsfunktionen der neuralen Muster und Prozesse. (233; Fs) (notabene)

57/06 Im Gegensatz dazu ist die Aberration der Zensurfunktion primär repressiv; ihre positive Aktivität ist es, Perspektiven vom Auftauchen im Bewußtsein abzuhalten, welche unerwünschte Einsichten entstehen lassen würden; sie führt, wenn man so sagen will, den Ausschluß von Anordnungen ein in das Feld des Unbewußten; sie schreibt die Weise vor, in der neuralen Forderungsfunktionen nicht begegnet werden soll; und der negative Aspekt dieser ihrer positiven Aktivität ist die Zulassung beliebiger Materialien in jeder anderen Anordnung oder Perspektive im Bewußtsein. (233; Fs) (notabene)

58/06 Schließlich unterscheiden sich beide, Zensurfunktion und ihre Aberration, von einer bewußten Zuwendung zu einer möglichen Verhaltensform und von einer bewußten Ablehnung, sich in einer solchen Weise zu verhalten. Denn die Zensurfunktion und ihre Aberration sind vor der bewußten Aufmerksamkeit operativ und sie betreffen direkt nicht, wie wir uns zu verhalten haben, sondern was wir zu verstehen haben. Eine Ablehnung, sich in einer gegebenen Weise zu verhalten, ist keine Ablehnung zu verstehen; weit davon entfernt, bewußte Aufmerksamkeit zu verhindern, intensiviert die Ablehnung sie und macht ihr Wiederauftreten umso wahrscheinlicher. Während es schließlich wahr ist, daß bewußtes Ablehnen verbunden ist mit einem Aufhören der bewußten Aufmerksamkeit, beruht diese Verbindung doch nicht auf einer Umwölkung der Intelligenz, sondern auf einer Verschiebung der Bemühung, des Interesses und der Sorge. Entsprechend sind wir gehalten, den Terminus Verdrängung auf das Wirken der abirrenden Zensurfunktion zu beschränken, welche damit beschäftigt ist, die Einsicht zu verhindern. (233f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Erkenntnistheorie, Epistemologie, Metaphysik; Wende zur Interiorität; Fragen, Grundfragen ; Aristoteles

Kurzinhalt: So findet die Wende zur Interiorität statt. Die Allgemeinwissenschaft ist erstens Erkenntnistheorie (was tust du, wenn du erkennst?), zweitens Epistemologie (warum ist dieses Tun Erkennen?), und drittens Metaphysik

Textausschnitt: 75/XII Aristoteles und seine Anhänger anerkannten spezielle Wissenschaften, die sich mit Seiendem bestimmter Arten befaßten, sowie eine Allgemeinwissenschaft, die sich mit dem Sein als Sein befaßt. Nun zielen die Natur- und Humanwissenschaften darauf, Rechenschaft über alle Sinnesdaten zu geben. Wenn es demzufolge eine Allgemeinwissenschaft geben soll, dann müssen ihre Daten die Daten des Bewußtseins sein. So findet die Wende zur Interiorität statt. Die Allgemeinwissenschaft ist erstens Erkenntnistheorie (was tust du, wenn du erkennst?), zweitens Epistemologie (warum ist dieses Tun Erkennen?), und drittens Metaphysik (was erkennst du, wenn du dies tust?). Eine solche Allgemeinwissenschaft ist der Allgemeinfall der Methoden der speziellen Wissenschaften und nicht - wie im Aristotelismus - der Allgemeinfall des Inhalts der speziellen Wissenschaften. (317; Fs) (notabene)

76/XII Diese Wende zur Interiorität wurde auf verschiedene Weise von Descartes über Kant bis zu den deutschen Idealisten des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts versucht. Doch darauf folgte eine noch nachdrücklichere Wende vom Wissen zum Glauben, zum Willen, zum Gewissen, zur Entscheidung und zur Aktion bei Kierkegaard, Schopenhauer, Newman, Nietzsche, Blondel, den Personalisten und Existenzialisten. Die Richtung dieser Wende ist richtig in dem Sinne, daß die vierte Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins - die Ebene der Überlegung, Bewertung, Entscheidung und Handlung - die vorhergehenden Ebenen des Erfahrens, Verstehens und Urteilens aufhebt. Sie geht über diese hinaus, stellt ein neues Handlungsprinzip auf und eine neue Art von Handlungen, lenkt diese auf ein neues Ziel, aber weit davon entfernt, sie verkümmern zu lassen, bewahrt sie sie und führt sie zu einer volleren Erfüllung. (317f; Fs) (notabene)

77/XII Die vierte Ebene hebt nicht nur die vorhergehenden drei auf, auch unterscheiden sich die vorhergehenden drei erheblich vom spekulativen Verstand, der die selbstevidenten und notwendigen Wahrheiten erfassen sollte. Ein derart spekulativer Verstand konnte vollständige Autonomie beanspruchen und tat dies auch: Böser Wille konnte schwerlich die Erfassung selbstevidenter und notwendiger Wahrheiten beeinträchtigen, und ebensowenig die notwendigen Schlußfolgerungen, die sich aus solcher Wahrheit ergeben. Tatsächlich jedoch ist das, was die menschliche Intelligenz in Daten erfaßt und in Begriffen zum Ausdruck bringt, nicht eine notwendig relevante Intelligibilität, sondern nur eine möglicherweise relevante Intelligibilität. Solche Intelligibilität ist wesentlich hypothetisch und daher stets eines weiteren Überprüfungs- und Verifizierungsprozesses bedürftig, ehe sie als de facto relevant für die vorliegenden Daten behauptet werden kann. So kam es dazu, daß die moderne Wissenschaft unter Leitung der Methode steht, und die Methode, die man wählt und der man folgt, ergibt sich nicht nur aus dem Erfahren, Verstehen und Urteilen, sondern auch aus einer Entscheidung. (318; Fs)

78/XII In gedrängter Form habe ich eine Reihe von grundlegenden Wandlungen aufgezeigt, die sich in den letzten viereinhalb Jahrhunderten ereigneten. Sie modifizieren das Bild, das der Mensch von sich und seiner Welt hat, ebenso wie seine Wissenschaft und seine Auffassung von Wissenschaft, seine Geschichte und seine Auffassung von Geschichte, seine Philosophie und seine Auffassung von Philosophie. Die Wandlungen betreffen drei grundlegende Differenzierungen des Bewußtseins, und alle drei1 liegen völlig außerhalb des Horizonts der griechischen Antike und des mittelalterlichen Europa. (318; Fs)

79/XII Diesen Wandlungen setzten Geistliche im allgemeinen aus zwei Gründen Widerstand entgegen. Der erste Grund war vielfach der, daß Geistliche das Wesen dieser Wandlungen nicht wirklich erfaßten. Der zweite Grund lag darin, daß diese Wandlungen gewöhnlich von einem Mangel an intellektueller Bekehrung begleitet und daher dem Christentum feindlich gesinnt waren. (318; Fs)

80/XII Moderne Wissenschaft ist eines, die außerwissenschaftlichen Meinungen der Wissenschaftler sind aber etwas anderes. Unter den außerwissenschaftlichen Meinungen der Naturwissenschaftler war bis zur Übernahme der Quantentheorie ein mechanistischer Determinismus zu finden, der die Natur falsch darstellte und menschliche Freiheit und Verantwortlichkeit ausschloß.2 (318; Fs)

81/XII Auch die moderne Geschichtswissenschaft ist eines, und die philosophischen Annahmen der Historiker sind etwas anderes. H. G. Gadamer untersuchte die Annahmen von Schleiermacher, Ranke, Droysen und Dilthey.3 In etwas gedrängterer Form hat Kurt Frör festgestellt, daß die Arbeit der Historiker in der ersten Hälfte des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts durch eine Mischung von philosophischer Spekulation und empirischer Forschung gekennzeichnet war, daß aber der immer einflußreicher werdende Positivismus die Spekulation in der zweiten Hälfte des Jahrhunderts beseitigte.4 Der sich daraus ergebende Historismus drang auch in die biblischen Untersuchungen ein, und hier fand er durch die Arbeiten von Barth und Bultmann einen starken Widerhall. Beide anerkannten die Bedeutung moralischer und religiöser Bekehrung. Bei Barth zeigte sich das in seiner Forderung, daß die Bibel zwar historisch, ebenso aber auch geistlich zu lesen sei; und geistliches Lesen sei nicht bloß eine Sache frommer Gefühle im Leser, es habe auch auf jene Realitäten zu achten, von denen die Bibel spricht.5 Für Bultmann ist die religiöse und moralische Bekehrung die existentielle Antwort auf den Ruf oder auf die Herausforderung des Kerygma. Doch solch eine Antwort sei ein subjektives Ereignis, und seine Objektivierung ende im Mythos.6 Wenn auch Bultmann kein gewöhnlicher Positivist ist, weil er um das 'Verstehen' weiß, zerfällt für ihn das Studium der Bibel aber doch in zwei Teile: den wissenschaftlichen Teil, der von religiösem Glauben unabhängig ist, und den religiösen Teil, der die mythischen Objektivierungen der Bibel tiefer durchdringt bis zu den subjektiven religiösen Ereignissen, von denen sie Zeugnis ablegt. (319; Fs)

82/XII Bei beiden, Barth und Bultmann, kommt, wenn auch auf unterschiedliche Weise, die Notwendigkeit intellektueller, wie auch moralischer und religiöser Bekehrung deutlich zum Vorschein. Nur eine intellektuelle Bekehrung kann dem Fideismus von Barth abhelfen. Nur eine intellektuelle Bekehrung kann die säkularistische Auffassung von wissenschaftlicher Exegese beseitigen, wie sie von Bultmann vertreten wurde. Dennoch ist intellektuelle Bekehrung allein nicht genug. Sie muß noch in eine philosophische und theologische Methode expliziert werden, und eine derart explizite Methode muß eine Kritik der Methode der Naturwissenschaft und der Methode der Gelehrsamkeit einschließen. (319f; Fs)









Wenn es demzufolge eine Allgemeinwissenschaft geben soll, dann müssen ihre Daten die Daten des Bewußtseins sein. So findet die Wende zur Interiorität statt. Die Allgemeinwissenschaft ist erstens Erkenntnistheorie (was tust du, wenn du erkennst?), zweitens Epistemologie (warum ist dieses Tun Erkennen?), und drittens Metaphysik (was erkennst du, wenn du dies tust?). Eine solche Allgemeinwissenschaft ist der Allgemeinfall der Methoden der speziellen Wissenschaften und nicht - wie im Aristotelismus - der Allgemeinfall des Inhalts der speziellen Wissenschaften.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Methode: acht funktionalen Spezialisierungen in der Theologie; Forschung, Interpretation, Geschichte, Dialektik, Fundamente (Bekehrung), Lehre, Systematik, Kommunikation

Kurzinhalt: Die Dialektik hat es mit dem Konkreten, dem Dynamischen und dem Widersprüchlichen zu tun und findet daher in der Geschichte christlicher Bewegungen reichlich Material.

Textausschnitt: 9/5 In diesem Abschnitt legen wir eine kurze Beschreibung von acht Funktionalen Spezialisierungen innerhalb der Theologie vor, nämlich

(1.) Forschung,
(2.) Interpretation,
(3.) Geschichte,
(4.) Dialektik,
(5.) Fundamente,
(6.) Lehre,
(7.) Systematik und
(8.) Kommunikation. Später werden wir versuchen, die Gründe für die vorstehende Einteilung, ihre genaue Bedeutung und ihre Implikationen anzugeben. Im Augenblick geht es uns jedoch nur um den vorläufigen Hinweis auf die inhaltliche Bedeutung funktionaler Spezialisierungen in der Theologie. (136; Fs)

10/5
(1.) Die Forschung macht die für die theologische Untersuchung einschlägigen Daten verfügbar. Sie ist entweder allgemein oder speziell. Die spezielle Forschung befaßt sich mit der Zusammenstellung jener Daten, die für irgendeine besondere Frage oder für ein Problem relevant sind, z. B. die Lehrmeinung von Herrn X zur Frage Y. Derart spezielle Forschung arbeitet um so schneller und effektiver, je vertrauter sie im Umgang mit den Werkzeugen ist, die ihr von der allgemeinen Forschung zur Verfügung gestellt werden. Die allgemeine Forschung lokalisiert alte Städte, gräbt sie aus und erfaßt sie kartographisch. Sie füllt die Museen und reproduziert oder kopiert Inschriften, Symbole, Bilder und Statuen. Sie entziffert unbekannte Schriften und Sprachen. Sie sammelt und katalogisiert Manuskripte und bereitet kritische Textausgaben vor. Sie stellt Verzeichnisse, Tabellen, Repertoires, Bibliographien, Auszüge, Bulletins, Handbücher, Wörterbücher und Enzyklopädien zusammen. Vielleicht wird sie uns eines Tages ein vollständiges System zur Informations-Auffindung in die Hand geben. (136; Fs)

11/5
(2.) Während die Forschung uns zugänglich macht, was geschrieben wurde, versteht die Interpretation, was gemeint war. Sie erfaßt diese Bedeutung in ihrem eigenen geschichtlichen Kontext, in Übereinstimmung mit dessen eigener Weise und Ebene des Denkens und des Ausdrucks, sowie im Licht der Umstände und der Intention des Autors. Ihr Ergebnis ist der Kommentar oder die Monographie. Interpretation ist ein Unternehmen voller Fallgruben und heute noch zusätzlich erschwert durch die von der Erkenntnistheorie, Epistemologie und Metaphysik übernommenen Probleme. Wir werden darauf zurückkommen, wenn wir uns später mit der Hermeneutik befassen. (136; Fs)

12/5
(3.) Geschichte ist fundamental, speziell oder allgemein. Die fundamentale Geschichte sagt uns wo (Ort, Gebiet) und wann (Daten, Perioden) wer (Personen, Völker) was tat (öffentliches Leben, äußere Taten), welchen Erfolg er erzielt, welche Rückschläge er erlitten und welchen Einfluß er ausgeübt hat. Daher schildert sie die leichter erkennbaren und allgemein anerkannten Züge menschlicher Aktivität je nach ihrer geographischen Erstreckung und zeitlichen Abfolge so spezifisch und präzise wie möglich. (136f; Fs)

13/5 Die spezielle Geschichtsschreibung berichtet über Bewegungen kultureller Art (Sprache, Kunst, Literatur, Religion), institutioneller Art (Familie, Sitten, Gesellschaft, Erziehung, Staat, Gesetz, Kirche, religiöse Gemeinschaften, Wirtschaft, Technologie) oder lehrmäßiger Art (Mathematik, Naturwissenschaften, Geisteswissenschaften, Philosophie, Geschichte, Theologie). (137; Fs)

14/5 Die allgemeine Geschichte ist vielleicht nur ein Ideal. Sie wäre fundamentale Geschichte, die durch spezielle Geschichtsschreibung erklärt und ergänzt wird. Sie würde eine Gesamtschau bieten oder etwas, das dem nahe kommt. Sie würde die Information, das Verständnis, das Urteil und die Einschätzung des Historikers im Hinblick auf die Summe der kulturellen, institutionellen und lehrmäßigen Bewegungen in ihrer konkreten Umgebung zum Ausdruck bringen. (137; Fs)

15/5 Geschichte als funktionale Spezialisierung innerhalb der Theologie hat es, unterschiedlich abgestuft und auf verschiedene Weise, mit fundamentaler, spezieller und allgemeiner Geschichte zu tun. In der Hauptsache hat sie die fundamentale Geschichte vorauszusetzen. Ihr wesentliches Anliegen ist die lehrmäßige Geschichte christlicher Theologie mit deren Antezedentien und Konsequenzen in der kulturellen und institutionellen Geschichte der christlichen Religion sowie der christlichen Kirchen und Gemeinschaften. Auch zur allgemeinen Geschichtsschreibung kann sie letztlich nicht auf Distanz bleiben, da man die Unterschiede zwischen den christlichen Kirchen und Gemeinschaften, die Beziehungen der verschiedenen Religionen zueinander sowie die Rolle des Christentums in der Weltgeschichte nur im Rahmen einer vollständigen Gesamtschau begreifen kann. (137; Fs)

16/5 Auf die Geschichte kommen wir später noch zurück. Nicht weniger als die Hermeneutik wurden auch das historische Denken und die historische Kritik der Gegenwart - über ihre spezifischen Aufgaben hinaus - in die philosophischen Grundprobleme unserer Zeit verwickelt. (137; Fs)

17/5
(4.) Unsere vierte funktionale Spezialisierung ist die Dialektik. Obwohl dieser Terminus sehr unterschiedlich verwendet wird, ist der Sinn, in dem wir ihn hier gebrauchen, recht einfach. Die Dialektik hat es mit dem Konkreten, dem Dynamischen und dem Widersprüchlichen zu tun und findet daher in der Geschichte christlicher Bewegungen reichlich Material. Alle Bewegungen sind zugleich konkret und dynamisch, während christliche Bewegungen ihrerseits durch äußere und innere Konflikte gekennzeichnet sind, ob man das Christentum nun als Ganzes oder auch nur diese oder jene größere Kirche oder Gemeinschaft betrachtet. (137f; Fs)

18/5 Inhalte der Dialektik sind demnach in erster Linie die Konflikte, die ihren Mittelpunkt in christlichen Bewegungen haben, doch sind diesen noch die sekundären Konflikte in den historischen Darstellungen und theologischen Deutungen jener Bewegungen hinzuzufügen. (138; Fs)

19/5 Neben den Inhalten der Dialektik ist ihr Ziel zu beachten. Dieses ist hoch und weitgesteckt. Wie es der empirischen Naturwissenschaft um eine vollständige Erklärung aller Phänomene geht, so geht es der Dialektik um einen möglichst weiten Blickwinkel. Sie sucht nach einer einzigen Grundlage oder nach einem Gesamt aufeinander bezogener Grundlagen, von dem aus sie zum Verständnis der Eigenart, der Gegensätze und der Beziehungen der vielen Standpunkte gelangen kann, die sich bei widerstreitenden christlichen Bewegung, ihren widerstreitenden Geschichtsdarstellungen und ihren widerstretenden Deutungen zeigen. (138; Fs)

20/5 Außer den Konflikten unter Christen und dem fernen Ziel eines umfassenden Standpunkts gibt es noch in Vergangenheit und Gegenwart das Faktum der vielen divergierenden Standpunkte, aus denen Konflikte erwachsen. Solche Standpunkte zeigen sich in Glaubensbekenntnissen ebenso wie in den gelehrten Werken der Apologeten. Sie zeigen sich aber auch - oft sogar noch viel lebendiger - in unbemerkten Annahmen und Versehen, in Vorliebe und Aversion sowie in den heimlichen aber sehr bestimmten Entscheidungen der Gelehrten, der Schriftsteller, der Prediger und auch der Männer und Frauen in den Kirchenbänken. (138; Fs)

21/5 Die Untersuchung dieser Standpunkte führt uns über das reine Faktum hinaus zu den Gründen für den Konflikt. Wenn man diese miteinander vergleicht, so zeigt sich, wo die Differenzen unaufhebbar, wo sie komplementär sind und innerhalb eines größeren Ganzen zusammengebracht und überwunden werden könnten, und wo man sie als sukzessive Stadien eines einzigen Entwicklungsprozesses ansehen kann. (138; Fs)

22/5 Außer dem Vergleich gibt es die Kritik. Nicht jeder Standpunkt ist kohärent, und diejenigen, die einen nicht kohärenten vertreten, können aufgefordert werden, zu einer folgerichtigen Position überzugehen. Nicht jeder Grund ist ein stichhaltiger Grund, und die Christenheit hat nichts zu verlieren durch das Ablegen von unguten Gründen, von ad hoc Erklärungen und Klischees, die nur Verdächtigung, Ressentiment, Abneigung und Bosheit hervorrufen. Nicht jeder irreduzible Unterschied ist ein ernster Unterschied, und die es nicht sind, kann man an zweite, dritte oder vierte Stelle rücken, so daß man Aufmerksamkeit, Studium und Analyse jenen Unterschieden widmen kann, die tatsächlich ernst und tief sind. (138f; Fs)

23/5 Unter Dialektik ist demnach eine verallgemeinerte Apologetik zu verstehen, die im ökumenischen Geist geführt wird, die letztlich auf einen umfassenden Standpunkt zielt und sich diesem Ziel nähert, indem sie die Unterschiede anerkennt, deren wirkliche und offenkundige Gründe sucht und überflüssige Gegensätze beseitigt. (139; Fs)

24/5
(5.) Wie die Bekehrung für das christliche Leben von grundlegender Bedeutung ist, so gibt eine Objektivierung der Bekehrung der Theologie ihre Fundamente. (139; Fs)

25/5 Unter Bekehrung verstehen wir eine Umwandlung des Subjekts und seiner Welt. Normalerweise handelt es sich hierbei um einen längeren Prozeß, obwohl ihre ausdrückliche Anerkennung auf wenige gewichtige Urteile und Entscheidungen konzentriert sein kann. Dennoch ist Bekehrung nicht bloß eine Entwicklung oder gar eine Reihe von Entwicklungen. Sie ist vielmehr ein sich ergebender Kurs- und Richtungswechsel. Es ist so, als gingen uns die Augen auf, als schwinde und stürze unsere frühere Welt. Etwas Neues taucht auf und trägt Frucht in ineinandergreifenden kumulativen Entwicklungsfolgen auf allen Ebenen und in allen Räumen des menschlichen Lebens. (139; Fs) (notabene)

26/5 Bekehrung ist existentiell, in höchstem Maße personal und ganz innerlich; doch ist sie nicht derart privat, daß sie einsam und allein wäre. Sie kann sich bei vielen ereignen, und diese können eine Gemeinschaft bilden, um sich gegenseitig in ihrer Selbst-Umwandlung zu stützen und einander bei der Ausarbeitung der Implikationen und der Erfüllung der Verheißung ihres neuen Lebens zu helfen. Und was gemeinschaftlich werden kann, das kann auch geschichtlich werden, das kann von Generation zu Generation übergehen, kann von dem einen kulturellen Umfeld auf ein anderes übergreifen. Es kann sich den wandelnden Umständen anpassen, neuen Situationen begegnen, in ein anderes Zeitalter hinein überleben und in einer anderen Periode oder Epoche neu erblühen. (139; Fs) (notabene)

27/5 Bekehrung als gelebte Bekehrung beeinflußt alle bewußten und intentionalen Handlungen des Menschen. Sie lenkt seinen Blick, durchdringt seine Vorstellungskraft und löst die Symbole aus, die bis in die Tiefen seiner Seele vordringen. Sie bereichert sein Verstehen, lenkt seine Urteile und verstärkt seine Entscheidungen. Bekehrung aber als gemeinschaftliche und geschichtliche Größe, als eine Bewegung mit ihren eigenen kulturellen, institutionellen und lehrmäßigen Dimensionen, ruft eine Reflexion hervor, die diese Bewegung thematisiert und ausdrücklich ihre Ursprünge, Entwicklungen, Ziele, Errungenschaften und ihr Versagen erforscht. (139f; Fs) (notabene)

28/5 Insofern als Bekehrung selbst thematisiert und ausdrücklich objektiviert wird, taucht nun die fünfte funktionale Spezialisierung auf: es sind die 'Fundamente'. Diese Fundamente unterscheiden sich von der alten Fundamentaltheologie in zweifacher Hinsicht. Erstens war die Fundamentaltheologie ein theologisch Erstes; sie folgte nicht den vier anderen Spezialisierungen, die wir als Forschung, Interpretation, Geschichte und Dialektik bezeichnet haben. Zweitens war die Fundamentaltheologie ein Block von Lehren - de vera religione, de legato divino, de ecclesia, de inspiratione scripturae, de locis theologicis. Im Gegensatz hierzu bieten die Fundamente nicht Lehren, sondern nur den Horizont, innerhalb dessen die Bedeutung der Lehren erfaßt werden kann. So wie im religiösen Leben gilt: 'Der irdisch gesinnte Mensch läßt sich nicht auf das ein, was vom Geist Gottes kommt. Torheit ist es für ihn, und er kann es nicht verstehen' (1 Kor 2,14), so sind in der theologischen Reflexion über das religiöse Leben die Horizonte zu unterscheiden, innerhalb derer die religiösen Lehren verstanden oder nicht verstanden werden können; diese Unterscheidung ist grundlegend. (140; Fs) (notabene)

29/5 Zu gegebener Zeit werden wir uns fragen, wie Horizont zu verstehen und zu definieren ist und wie sich ein Horizont vom anderen unterscheidet. Wir können jedoch sogleich anmerken: Wie die Bekehrung echt oder unecht sein kann, so kann es auch viele christliche Horizonte geben, und nicht alle müssen eine echte Bekehrung repräsentieren. Und obwohl es möglich ist, sich echte Bekehrung auf mehrfache Weise vorzustellen, scheint dennoch die Anzahl möglicher Bekehrungsweisen weit geringer als die Anzahl möglicher Horizonte zu sein. Daraus folgt, daß unsere 'Fundamente' eine Verheißung in sich tragen: die Aufhellung der durch die Dialektik aufgedeckten Konflikte und das Auswahlprinzip, das die verbleibenden Spezialisierungen leiten wird, die sich mit der Lehre, der Systematik und der Kommunikation befassen. (140; Fs)

30/5
(6.) Die Lehre bringt Tatsachen- und Werturteile zum Ausdruck. Sie befaßt sich demnach mit den Behauptungen und Verneinungen nicht nur der dogmatischen Theologie, sondern auch der moraltheologischen Disziplin, der aszetischen und mystischen Theologie, der Pastoraltheologie und ähnlicher Zweige. (140f; Fs)

31/5 Solche Lehren stehen im Horizont der 'Fundamente'. Sie erhalten ihre genaue Definition von der Dialektik, ihren positiven Reichtum an Abklärung und Entfaltung aus der Geschichte und ihre Grundlagen durch die Interpretation jener Daten, die der Theologie eigen sind. (141; Fs)

32/5
(7.) Die Tatsachen und Werte, die durch die Lehren behauptet werden, lassen weitere Fragen entstehen. Denn der Ausdruck der Lehre kann bildhaft oder symbolisch sein. Er kann beschreibend sein und letzten Endes bloß auf der Wortbedeutung beruhen, statt auf einem Verständnis der Realitäten. Er kann, wenn man ihn preßt, schnell vage und unbestimmt werden, ja er kann sich, wenn man ihn genau untersucht, in Widerspruch und Trugschluß verstrickt erweisen. (141; Fs)

33/5 Die Systematik als funktionale Spezialisierung versucht diese Probleme aufzugreifen. Ihr geht es um die Ausarbeitung angemessener Begriffssysteme, um offensichtliche Widersprüchlichkeiten zu beseitigen und zu einem gewissen Begreifen geistlicher Dinge zu gelangen, und dies von ihrer eigenen inneren Kohärenz her, wie auch durch Analogien, die von einer vertrauteren menschlichen Erfahrung angeboten werden. (141; Fs)

34/5
(8.) Bei der Kommunikation geht es um die Theologie in ihren Beziehungen nach außen. Diese sind dreifacher Art. Es gibt interdisziplinäre Beziehungen zur Kunst, zur Sprache und Literatur, zu anderen Religionen, zu den Natur- und Geisteswissenschaften, zur Philosophie und Geschichte. Sodann sind die Übertragungen (transpositions) zu nennen, die das theologische Denken entwickeln muß, wenn die Religion ihre Identität behalten und zugleich Zugang zu Geist und Herz der Menschen aller Kulturen und Klassen finden soll. Und schließlich bedarf es der Anpassungen, die nötig sind, um die verschiedenen Kommunikationsmittel, die an verschiedenen Orten und Zeiten jeweils zugänglich sind, voll und angemessen zu nutzen. (141; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: unknown, pursuit, ideal of knowledge, Pythagoras, Galileo, Kepler, Newton, Einstein

Kurzinhalt: Wissensstreben: Suche des Unbekannten; Ideal des Unbekannten in d. Wissenschaft: von der Zahlenharmonie zur Statistik u. Quantenmechanik,

Textausschnitt: () It is not merely a tendency towards an object, it is a conscious tendency. But in seeking knowledge, not only do we tend towards it, not only do we do so consciously, but we also do so intelligently. Moreover, we do so critically
()
The pursuit of knowledge, then, is the pursuit of an unknown, and the possibility of that pursuit is the existence of an ideal.
()
... there is a connection between mathematics and the sounds that are harmonious!
()
All of these further discoveries are analogous to the Pythagorean discovery of harmonic ratios: Archimedes' law relating displacement and buoyancy; Galileo's law of falling bodies; Kepler's three laws of planetary motion. In each case there was formulated a mathematical expression verifiable in concrete data.
()
I have illustrated the development of an ideal of knowledge. What is the ideal? It is the mathematization of nature. It starts from particular laws; it moves towards a system; and its great achievement was Newtonian system. It lasted for a few hundred years, but it had been on the basis of Euclidean geometry. Einstein moved it to another basis, a more general geometry, and quantum mechanics has taken us right out of the field of law and system. The fundamental ideal has become states and probabilities.
()
When scientists still fail to obtain theories that satisfy all the data, they change the ideal itself from law and system to states and probabilities.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Aristoteles, scholastic, analysis, synthesis, Thomist Trinitarian theory

Kurzinhalt: Scholastisches Wissenschaftsideal, Wissen durch Ursachen, resolutio, compositio; Trinität (Augustinus, Thomas) : Verschwinden d. Dinge, Verbleiben der Relationen, Periodensystem

Textausschnitt: () The scholastic definition of a science is 'certain knowledge of things through their causes.' ... The scholastics called the first part of this movement resolution into the causes, resolutio in causas, analysis. The second part of the movement was compositio ex causis, synthesis.
()
What happened is that analysis and synthesis survived, but not the things and causes as understood by Aristotle.
()
There is nothing in the New Testament about persons or nature; these technical terms do not occur. ... Augustine explained the processions by a psychological analogy. He said they were something like the movement in the mind from understanding to conception, from judgment to willing. So first we have missions, then persons and nature, then properties, relations, processions.
()
In Trinitarian theory, then, we have analysis and synthesis. We have the analytic movement up to St Thomas, and the synthetic movement in St Thomas' Summa theologiae. But we do not have things, and we do not have causes. God is not a thing in the sense of the Aristotelian predicaments, and the generation of the Son by the Father is not a matter of causality. The Son is not another God, and neither is the Holy Ghost. Things and causes vanish, but analysis and synthesis remain.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: self-appropriation, dynamism, presence, introspection, empirical, intelligent, rational consciousness

Kurzinhalt: Selbstaneignung: von außen zur Dynamik der inneren Bewegung, Beispiel: Präsenz, Introspektion, 4 Stufen des Bewusstseins,

Textausschnitt: () The trick in self-appropriation is to move one step backwards, to move into the subject as intelligent - asking questions; as having insights - being able to form concepts; as weighing the evidence - being able to judge. We want to move in there where the ideal is functionally operative prior to its being made explicit in judgments, concepts, and words.
()
Moving in there is self-appropriation; moving in there is reaching what is prepredicative, preconceptual, prejudicial.
()
To sum up: there is a merely material sense of presence - the chairs are present in the room; there is a second sense - one person is present to the other; there is a third sense - a person has to be somehow present to himself for others to be present to him.
()
What is important, in other words, is the looker, not the looked-at, even when the self is what is looked at. So it is not a matter of introspection in any spatial sense, in any sense of 'looking back into,' because what counts is not the presence of what is looked at, but the presence of the subject that looks, even when he is looking at himself.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: self-appropriation, ready made ideal, blocking self-appropriation, summary

Kurzinhalt: Selbstaneignung gemäß des eigenen Ideals, Qualis quisque est, Blockierung der inneren Tendenz gemäßt des selbstgemachten Ideals, Zusammenfassung

Textausschnitt: () Now there is a joker in this business of self-appropriation. We do not start out with a clean slate as we move towards self-appropriation. We already have our ideals of what knowledge is, and we want to do self-appropriation according to the ideal that is already operative in us ...
()
... self-appropriation is not a simple matter of moving in and finding the functionally operative tendencies that ground ideals. It is also a matter of pulling out the inadequate ideals that may be already existent and operative in us.
()
Qualis quisque est, talis finis videtur ei.
()
Why is it, ... that in the course of seven hundred years only seven scholastics advert to the possibility, and only some of those accept it? It is this existential problem. It is the presence of a ready-made ideal of what knowledge must be, blocking self-appropriation.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: 'already out there now real'

Kurzinhalt: Lonergans Erklärung des already out

Textausschnitt: Because the consciousness is practical, and because practical consciousness is concerned with dealing with situations, and because the situation is already there to be dealt with, we have the 'already.' The consciousness is extroverted, its focus is 'out.' Because the consciousness is in a body, it is 'out there'; the body is always in one place, and 'there is what is 'out.' Consciousness has memories, and it has anticipations, but it is active in the 'now.' It can be deceived by appearances in a very momentary way perhaps; the kitten might be deceived by an extremely realistic picture of a saucer of milk, but then it would not be 'real' milk because, when the kitten tried it, it would not obtain the ordinary satisfactions it obtains when it tries a saucer of 'real' milk.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Malinowski, Trobriand Islanders, Hitler, Vakuum, Hauptproblem

Kurzinhalt: Bronislaw Malinowski's Magic, Science, and Religion; Lonergans Vergleich zwischen uns u. den Eingeborenen;

Textausschnitt: Now in our civilization, there has been a very marked tendency - it is not a universal rule or a necessary law - for scientific thinking to be positivist, pragmatist, antimetaphysical. One can discern a dichotomy (in a much more cultivated form, of course) existing in this mentality which is similar to the dichotomy in the mentality of the Trobriand Islanders.
()
But while the person who is a scientist or a mathematician does not suffer too much from that blank, the general population does suffer. For example ... But then the country was taken over , Hitler. If a vacuum exists in the popular mind, a terrific irrational national convulsion can result. This is one of the main problems of our time.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteil, Satz, non asserendo sed recitando

Kurzinhalt: Judgment and Propositions, Unterschied zw. Urteil und Proposition

Textausschnitt: () The act of judgment is the act that adds assent to a proposition, that changes a proposition from the expression of an object of thought, the expression of some bright idea that comes into your mind, into an object of affirmation.
()
Questions on the second level are questions for intelligence: What? Why? How often? But questions on this third level are questions for reflection: Is it? Is it so? Whether this or that? The answers on the third level are of the type yes or no. It is or it is not. There are two basic alternatives. Those answers can also be modal: they can be qualified in as many ways as one pleases - possibly, probably, certainly, I don't know, we'll see. However, they are all of the basic type, it is and it is not.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Aristoteles, Einsicht, quidditas, Wasfrage, Warumfrage

Kurzinhalt: Insight in Aristotle, Mondfinsternis, 4 Typen von Fragen, What is a man?: was bedeutet warum -> Materie, Form,

Textausschnitt: () Aristotle divides questions into four types:
(1) What? What is it?
(2) Is it?
(3) Why is it so?
(4) Is it so?
()
Aristotle's answer was, What means why. How can what mean why? In some cases, he says, it is quite easy to see.
()
His doctrine of matter and form arises out of this problem. When you ask, 'What is a man?' you mean, 'Why is this a man?' You have this, what you point to, the materials. You ask, 'Why is this a man?' The answer is the soul.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: 3 Arten von Definition: Wortdefinition, erklärende u. implizite; Hilbert

Kurzinhalt: Nominal, Explanatory, and Implicit Definition, Hilbert's Geometrie: Punkte und Linien; die implizite (implicit) Definition sieht völlig von der materie ab -> Relation

Textausschnitt: () three types of definition: nominal, explanatory, and implicit. Nominal definition supposes insight into the use of words.
()
An explanatory definition adds a further element which, if not added in the definition, would have to be added by way of a postulate.
()
Finally, the postulational element of the explanatory definition can be used alone, and then the definition is implicit. Implicit definition is of far greater generality. In Hilbert's Foundations of Geometry, points and straight lines are defined by the postulate, A straight line is determined by two and only two points. Two points and a straight line are set in correlation; if we have two points, that will determine what we mean by a straight line, and if we have a straight line, that will determine what is meant by a point. The only thing that is settled is the relation between the two points and a straight line.
()
By 'point' Hilbert does not mean position without magnitude, something that you approximate by a dot, nor does he mean by 'line' something with length but without breadth or thickness. That is one case of his definition, but his definition is satisfied equally directly if by a straight line you mean ...
()
Implicit definition, then, prescinds from the matter; it gets entirely away from the matter. It is just the expression of the relational element, and it picks out what is of scientific significance, introducing us to complete generality.
()
When you base your geometry on implicit definitions, you are dealing purely with relations; you have moved on to a further stage of abstraction. Implicit definitions are simply relational structures, and the terms of the relations are left indeterminate. When definitions are implicit, the concrete meaning can be anything that will satisfy them.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Hilbert, Lonergan's Schema -> Relation, self-appropriation

Kurzinhalt: 4-fältige Struktur: the four terms are defined by their relations to one another; die Bedeutung dieser Relation erwächst im Maße der Selbstaneignung

Textausschnitt: () Insofar as you have no self-appropriation whatever, the four terms stand as do Hilbert's points and lines in their implicit definition. There is a purely relational structure; the four terms are defined by their relations to one another,
()
the definitions have to remain merely implicit if you have no self-appropriation at all. But in the measure that you have some degree of self-appropriation, the four terms take on a meaning from your experience of yourself;
()
These terms, then, have a fixed element - their mutual relations - and a variable element that increases with self-appropriation. So they are analogous - something fixed and something variable - and consequently they are open.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Aristoteles, Syllogismus, to ti ên einai, quod quid erat esse: intelligibile in sensibilibus

Kurzinhalt: Mond: causa cognoscendi, causa essendi; Mittelterm als Antwort auf die Frage; Unterschied zw. Definition (to ti estin) und Form;

Textausschnitt: () ... The example states: if the moon has phases, then it is a sphere; the moon goes through phases; therefore, it is a sphere. ... When phases is the middle term, we have the causa cognoscendi, the reason why we know. But when the sphere is the middle term, we have the causa essendi, the reason why the thing is so.
()
Aristotle's doctrine of the explanatory syllogism shows that he is trying to do in his logic something that the symbolic logician is trying to avoid.
()
Aristotle holds that the answer to all questions is a matter of finding the middle term. It must be found not only when there are three terms but even in the case of the simple question, What is the moon?
()
What is the difference between to ti ên einai and to ti estin, between the form and the definition? It is the difference, with which we have already dealt, between the content of the insight and the conception, the general definition. Aristotle moved back as best he could - and it is marvelous that he did as well as he did - from conception to insight, by talking about their objects: to ti ên einai, the form; to ti estin, the definition; and also ousia (essence).
()
'What is a man?' He says that ti estin means dioti, or why is it, or propter quid; that quid means propter quid; and that what means why. But how can one ask, 'Why is a man?' That does not seem to make much sense; but one can make it make sense by asking, 'Why is this a man?' just as 'Why are these bricks and stones a house?'
()
The to ti ên einai is what you understand before you are able to formulate it; it is the form, intelligibile in sensibilibus (the intelligible in the sensible).

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteil, hinreichende Begründung (sufficiency), Trinität (Thomas, Augustin)

Kurzinhalt: von reflektiven Verstehen zum Urteil; hinreichende Begründung -> entweder Urteil oder Selbstwiderspruch; rationale Notwendigkeit zum Urteilen,

Textausschnitt: () He has the sufficiency of the evidence, and it is up to him to judge; and if he does not judge he is introducing a contradiction within himself. He is rational, he is a reasonable being, and yet he is defaulting on his rationality if he grasps the sufficiency of the evidence and does not judge.
()
That is the rational necessity of judging. Judging, then, in the third place, is the fruit of the actual rationality of consciousness, and that aspect of judgment provides Augustinian and Thomist Trinitarian theory with its psychological analogy: the procession of the Son from the Father is not a matter of causing; it is a matter of the 'because' that occurs within a spiritual being.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Untergliederung von Lonergan' Schema

Kurzinhalt: 1 ensation, perception, (free) images 2 inquiry, insight, conception 3 reflection, reflective understanding, judgment

Textausschnitt: () The terms for that level are now: sensation, perception, (free) images. For the second and third levels, they are the same as in Insight, with minor variations: inquiry, insight, conception; and reflection, reflective understanding, judgment.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteil, Verpflichtung, Gedächtnis, La Rochefoucauldm memory, judgement

Kurzinhalt: Urteil als persönlicher Akt; Ausdruck der eigenen Vernünftigkeit ohne jeden Zwang; Verantwortlichkeit für das Urteil; Judgment is something that is entirely yours;

Textausschnitt: () There is the person who understands, and there is the intellect by which, the act by which, he understands. And from that aspect, as related to the person, the judgment is a personal commitment. One of de La Rochefoucauld's witty remarks ... Memory is not completely under our control. But the judgment is a personal act, a personal commitment.
()
Judgment is something that is entirely yours; it is an element in personal commitment in an extremely pure state. Because it is so personal, so much an expression of one's own reasonableness apart from any constraint, because all alternatives are provided for, it is entirely one's own responsibility. Because it is entirely one's own responsibility, one does not complain about one's bad judgments; one is responsible for them.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteil an sich, Bestandteile des Urteils, Urteil als Setzung (nicht Bildung) einer Hypothese; Thomas, Aristoteles

Kurzinhalt: Urteil als Verbindung, Teilung; Thomas: Verbindung of essence with existence; judgment in which one posits synthesis; Wahrheit als Kern des Urteils; proper, borrowed content; implicit content: truth

Textausschnitt: () However, from the Thomist viewpoint the relevant composition is composition of essence with existence on the objective side. The act of judgment is not an act of synthesis, but an act in which one posits synthesis. A theory, a hypothesis, a proposition, a definition, already contains a synthesis. Judgment does not add further synthesis; it simply posits the synthesis that is the object of thought.
()
Since judgment is positing synthesis, we can distinguish in the judgment between its proper content and its borrowed content. The proper content is the positing, the 'Yes,' the 'No,' 'It is,' 'It is not.' The borrowed content is the object of thought which is reached by conception on the second level.
()
Besides the explicit content of the synthesis and its positing - one borrowed, one proper - there is the implicit content. When I say, 'It is,' I also mean, 'It is true that it is.' Truth is the implicit content of every judgment. The implicit content can be made explicit; but it is really included in the simple statement, 'It is.'

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Struktur des rationalen Bewusstseins

Kurzinhalt: Rational Consciousness, principle of noncontradiction, Prinzip des ausgeschlossenen Dritten, Nichtwiderspruchsprinzip, Element d. Absolutheit und Objektivität

Textausschnitt: () On the first level we have sensations, perceptions, and images. On the second level we understand, and understanding yields objects of thought - 'It may be heavy, and it may be light; if I could only get my hand around it and move it quickly, I would know which it is.' Then one performs the experiment, makes the judgment, and says, 'This is heavy.' When one says that, one does not mean 'It feels heavy' or 'There is pressure on my hand.' One is talking about it. There is an element of objectivity entering in.
()
These four points characterize the whole process of rational consciousness. The process begins with the question, Is it or is it not? It includes the principle of excluded middle, provided the question is fairly put -either it is or it is not, either one or the other. It includes the principle of noncontradiction - it cannot be both. It involves an element of the absolute, the ground of what we mean when we speak of the eternality of truth. Finally, it involves an element of objectivity. When we judge we go beyond all question of feelings and appearances, and we say, 'It is so' or 'It is not so.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: allgemeine Form des reflektiven Verstehens, Urteil; das bedingte Unbedingte; Syllogismus

Kurzinhalt: virtually unconditioned; if A, then B; but A; therefore B; Funktion des Syllogismus; Gründung der Prämisse von wenn A, dann B im Prozess des Denkens selbst

Textausschnitt: () The general form of the grasp of the virtually unconditioned may be put syllogistically: If A, then B; but A; therefore B, where A and B severally represent one or more propositions. In the major, B is presented as a conditioned: If A, then B. In the minor, the condition is fulfilled: A. We have the conclusion because the combination of major and minor exhibits B as virtually unconditioned.
()
is that it puts into form the object of reflective understanding. Reflective understanding is aided by the syllogistic form of exposition because the syllogism exhibits the conclusion, the prospective judgment, the conditioned, as a virtually unconditioned.
()
In other words, if A and B, as representing the conditions and conditioned in a virtually unconditioned, must always be judgments, then we are driven back to an infinity of prior judgments before we can have one. There has to be an infinity, because every final judgment, every judgment B, depends upon other judgments. If, however, we can find A and the major premise, If A, then B, within the prior process of knowing, and reflective understanding capable of using A and B as they exist in this prior state, then we can get the judgment.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteil, Tatsachenurteil, Syllogismus

Kurzinhalt: Concrete Judgments of Fact; Beispiel: es wird etwas geschehen; Syllogismus eines Tatsachenurteils,

Textausschnitt: () We can put this syllogistically. If the same set of things is in different states at different times, then in the intervening time something has happened; but this same set of things was in one state this morning and now is in another state; therefore, something has happened.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteil; Kriterium der Richtigkeit: keine weiteren relevanten Fragen

Kurzinhalt: Judgments on the Correctness of Insights; wann ist eine Einsicht richtig; Thomas: Syllogismus im Traum; Urteil als Verpflichtung - Gedächtnis

Textausschnitt: () Insights head towards a limit. When you reach that limit you have the invulnerable insight, that is, you have reached a point where further questions de facto do not arise. There can be further questions, but they are not relevant. The man comes home and says, 'Something happened.'
()
One needs for judgment a fuller control of all faculties than one needs for insight. The control of judgment requires the poise of consciousness and the control over sensitive presentations and images that can be disturbed in the human makeup. If that control is disturbed, judgment is disturbed. St Thomas says that we can syllogize in our dreams, but when we wake up we find that we have made some mistake.
()
In other words, besides the alternatives of 'is' and 'is not,' 'certainly,' 'probably,' and 'possibly,' there is also an indefinite number of alternatives that can be introduced by qualifying the judgment, paring it down, making it still less and less that you are asserting. The more you qualify the judgment, the easier it is to arrive at the point where your insights are invulnerable
()
The point is not that no further relevant questions occur to me, but that there are no further relevant questions.
()
Good judgment is a personal commitment; people complain about their memory but not about their judgment. Judgment is a personal commitment that involves one's own rationality. It is a contingent event; it usually depends upon an extremely large number of factors. But it is something that does happen; we do judge; there are things we are absolutely certain about, things that it would be silly to have any doubts about no matter how hesitant we may be.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Urteile im Bereich d. Wissenschaft; Masse: Euklid, Einstein; logische Form

Kurzinhalt: Probable Judgments; wahrscheinliche Urteile; allgemeine Form des wissenschaftlichen Arguments: If A, then B; but B; therefore A; logisch nicht zwingend

Textausschnitt: () However, insofar as this law is understood on the assumptions of a Euclidean space, it has to be revised when special relativity is introduced and space is no longer strictly Euclidean. In other words, assumptions that lie on a remote level may be changed, and then the law will not be used in exactly the same sense as before. In general, ...
()
In mechanics and dynamics, the concept of mass is fundamental; in relativity, mass does not have exactly the same properties as it has in Newtonian mechanics. Insofar as special relativity is said to have been sufficiently established, that is, to be still more probable than Newtonian mechanics, there is a change in that fundamental notion.
()
The scientist does not reach the virtually unconditioned. The scientific argument from verification is generally of the following type: If A, then B; but B; therefore A. If the theory, A, is true, then we have all these things that we account for; but we have all these things accounted for; therefore, the theory is a fairly good account of them. This is not a logically valid argument; but ...

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Anylatische Propositionen und Prinzipien; Anselm: ontologisches Argument; kontingent; Kausalgesetz

Kurzinhalt: Analytic Propositions and Principles; if A, then B; A; therefore B; Übergang von analyt: Proposition -> Prinzip: Tatsachenurteil;

Textausschnitt: () If you define any A as what has a relation to B, that is, if by definition A is what has a relation R to B, then you can say ... We have here, then, an example of a virtually unconditioned. The proposition 'If there is an A there is a relation R to B' is conditioned; it is true under certain circumstances or conditions. What are the conditions? The conditions to be fulfilled are fulfilled by a definition:
()
Analyticity is simply the structure of the judgment: If A, then B; A; therefore B. The judgment, as resting upon a virtually unconditioned, is resting upon that structure; and that structure, as a structure, is something that can be satisfied by rules of syntax and definitions made ad hoc.
()
In other words, an analytic proposition becomes an analytic principle in the measure that the defined terms in their defined sense occur in concrete judgments of fact.
()
Let us take an illustration from the ontological argument for the existence of God. Necessary existence exists necessarily. This is at least an analytic proposition; ... However, if you can say that there exists a necessary existence, that there is something that exists necessarily, then you transform the analytic proposition into an analytic principle. In other words, the ontological argument is valid if God exists.
()

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: 3 Klassen von analytischen Prinzipien

Kurzinhalt: Analytische Prinzipien in: Philosophie, empirischen Wissenschaften, Mathematik

Textausschnitt: I divide analytic principles into three classes. First, there are those in which the verifying judgments, so to speak, the concrete judgments of fact that transform analytic propositions into analytic principles, are affirmed simply. That is the philosophic case. Secondly, there are those in which the concrete judgments of fact that effect the transformation are affirmed provisionally. That is what occurs in the empirical sciences. Finally, there is the third case for mathematics, and I speak of these as serially analytic principles.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Self-appropriation; Selbstaneignung; implizite Definition; Füllung einer relationalen Struktur

Kurzinhalt: Selbstaneignung als Inhalt einer Definition (postulational definition) eines Satzes von Ausdrücken, die durch Relationen bestimmt werden; die Affirmation setzt die hypothetische Struktur als Faktum

Textausschnitt: 71/5 What we have been doing is determining the knowing subject by implicit definitions; and the meaning of those implicit definitions is given a positive content by one's own self-appropriation, insofar as I am aware of myself as experiencing, inquiring intelligently, and judging rationally. The fulness of my self-appropriation is the measure of the meaning, the significance, that I can give to a merely postulational definition of that set of terms by their internal relations. In other words, self-appropriation is the experiential element that is expressed in the set of relations defined by this set of terms; and the judgment of self-affirmation, treated in chapter 11 of Insight, is the judgment relevant to self-appropriation. If you think of the knowing in this judgment 'I am a knower' as our knowing external objects, we must then add that this knowing, on all its levels, is something that enters into my presence to myself. In the first sense of presence, the chairs are present in the room. In the second sense, you are present to me. But in the third sense, I have to be present to myself for anyone to be present to me. In self-appropriation, it is this third presence with which we are concerned.
()
The whole set of definitions in these lectures could be only a relational structure. Self-appropriation gives it meaning, but as a hypothetical construct. Chapter 11 of Insight will add affirmation, will determine the hypothesis as fact, will make my presence to myself known.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Prozess der self-affirmation; Verifikation der bewussten Vorgänge

Kurzinhalt: Vorgang der Selbstaffirmation; Urteil über sich als eines Erkennenden, Einsehenden usw.,

Textausschnitt: 1.1 Verification of a Set of Events
()
But we do not see that the pressure is 64 when the volume is 1, and that the pressure is 32 when the volume is 2. Those are statements, judgments. What we can see, by taking a look, is a measuring rod set against the dimensions of the volume. Similarly ...
()
In the measure that one has achieved self-appropriation, one is capable of verifying in oneself that one is a unity-identity-whole that senses, perceives, imagines, inquires, understands, formulates, reflects, grasps the unconditioned, and judges. But there is a difference between verifying in the one case and verifying in the other. In the first case, one uses one's external senses, and one simply sees the position of the needle on a dial

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Self-affirmation; transzendentales Ego

Kurzinhalt: Schluss auf eine Einheit (transzendentales Ego), die den verschiedenen Tätigkeiten zugrunde liegen muss; verification of the transcendental ego

Textausschnitt: () If we have perceptions and empirical presentations by themselves, and inquiry completely separate, the inquiry will not be about the presentations. For inquiry to be about the presentations, we have to have a unity.
()
One at least must postulate a transcendental ego that performs all of these activities, even if it is not given in consciousness. Even if one's consciousness is simply of the single acts and there is no consciousness of one subject of the series of acts, still one has to postulate such a subject, the transcendental ego, the condition of the possibility of knowing.
()
They are my perceiving, my inquiring, my understanding, long before the perceiving, inquiring, and understanding are distinguished from one another. The unity of the subject is given prior to any thinking about it.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Self-affirmation als Objektivation seines selbst

Kurzinhalt: Selbstaneignung als Objektivation; kurze Frage nach dem Bewusstsein Christi; Widerspruch zwischen: what explicitly I say and what implicitly I am

Textausschnitt: () ... The self is appropriated in the sense that we conceive it and judge it, but that very conceiving and judging enables us to find it; and, fundamentally, we can find it insofar as we ask questions.
()
So self-knowledge - the process from being present to oneself, and finding typical activities in that self, to understanding how these activities are combined, and from that combination working out a theory of what it is to be a knower - is an objectification of oneself.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: self-affirmation als description und explanatory definition; das Ich ist nicht bloß "hypothetisch"

Kurzinhalt: Aussagen über die Selbstaneignung: Synthese der Vorteile von Beschreibung und erklärender Definition; behaviorist, linguistic analyst

Textausschnitt: () Is this a descriptive account of the knower, or is it an explanatory account? Our distinction between description and explanation was between the type of knowledge that appeals ultimately to the relations of things to us and the type of knowledge that involves relations of things to one another. It is clear that this is an explanatory account, insofar as it isolates fundamental elements, distinctive steps in the cognitional process, which are definable by their relations to one another.
()
Again, while the account is explanatory, it is not hypothetical in the sense in which explanatory science is hypothetical. Each of the elements is directly verifiable.
()
Is this account, then, descriptive or explanatory? It has the advantages of both, one may say. It has all the advantages of the concreteness of the descriptive type insofar as the elements and the unity are verifiable in consciousness. It has all the advantages of the explanatory type insofar as the different elements are of their very nature interdependently linked together in the process.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Selbsterkenntnis, Unmöglichkeit einer Revision

Kurzinhalt: self-knowledge; die Möglichkeit einer Revision setzt immer schon diese 3-fältige Struktur voraus; fundamental invariant pattern

Textausschnitt: () Let us suppose that there occurs a revision. The revision will be based upon further data. The further data may be given either by external sense or by internal consciousness, by the subject present to himself; so to have a reviser there must be external sense or internal consciousness. Unless we have that we cannot get further data; we cannot have any data at all. Moreover, if there is to be a new theory, we hope it is something intelligent. If it is intelligent, it will result from insight. Again, we hope we will be able to express it. It is not enough to say, 'I have a wonderful insight into what knowledge really is, but I can't tell you what it is.' We hope we will be able to conceive it. Moreover, it will have to be not simply a theory but a verified theory. When the new theory is proposed we will want to know whether it is right, or if it is better than the old one; so there will have to be critical reflection in the new theory. Again, if we are going to accept the new theory we will want to grasp the unconditioned; so there will have to be the grasp of the 'nconditioned. On that grasp of the unconditioned will depend the judgment, otherwise we would be unreasonable. So the possibility of a revision presupposes this analysis.
()
... we have arrived at a fundamental invariant pattern. Any future advance in self-knowledge may fill out this pattern with further details, may enrich it with all sorts of conclusions; but to be a revision it has to preserve this pattern.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Selbstaffirmation als Tatsachenurteil

Kurzinhalt: Self-affirmation and Judgment of Fact; jedes Tatsachenurteil setzt voraus: Erfahrung, Intelligenz, Urteil

Textausschnitt: () What we mean by fact is what is known through experience, understanding, and judging. Fact is not simply sensible presentation; it is not simply seeing my hand outstretched with something across it. ... To put it more simply, any judgment presupposes the unconditioned or it is not absolute. The unconditioned presupposes a conception; otherwise you do not have a conditioned, something determinate about which to make your judgment. This conditioned inherent in the conception results from inpsight and inquiry, and you have to have something to have insight into and to inquire about; so you need experience.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: 3 Arten von Objekten: agent object, the terminal object, and the final object

Kurzinhalt: final object: motus in imaginem est idem ac motus in imaginatum; Unterschied zw. Bild und "Gebildetem"; Urteil und Begriff als Zielobjekt u. Finalobjekt

Textausschnitt: () One can speak of objects metaphysically, and then one distinguishes three types of objects: the agent object, the terminal object, and the final object. The agent object is illustrated by seeing.
()
motus in imaginem est idem ac motus in imaginatum. Imagining both produces an image and wants to represent some object, what is imagined. There is a distinction between the image and what is imagined. We do not produce in ourselves what is imagined, otherwise we could produce in ourselves anything sensible. But we form the image within ourselves to move to the final object.
()
As in the imagination, so in judgment we can speak of a terminal and a final object. The terminal object which you produce in yourself is the concept and the judgment, and through that concept and judgment there is a finality, a final object. But is that final object, known through the concept and the judgment - is that really what is real?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Unbegrenztheit des Strebens nach Wissen, Obskurantismus

Kurzinhalt: The Range of Knowing; Unbegrenztheit des Wissensstrebens; the range of our desire to know is unrestricted;

Textausschnitt: () In the sense of radical potency, radical teleology, radical finality, I think it can be shown that our knowing is unlimited.
()
We can ask if there is anything beyond our total range. If we ask that, we have already asked a question about existence with regard to what lies beyond any hypothetical range one might like to set.
()
Is there a radical limitation to our mind, such that the question cannot even arise? There is not such a limit if we ask whether there are objects beyond the natural range; when we put that question our interest already transcends any hypothetical range. If this is so, then the range of our intellect, the radical range and not the range of what will fall within actual achievement at any future date, is unlimited. The range of our radical capacity, the range of our desire to know, then, is unrestricted. The object is everything about everything.
()
To brush questions aside in principle ... is to run counter to the nature of one's intellect. It is an obscurantism. The radical meaning of obscurantism is implicitly or explicitly holding the thesis that the range of our knowledge, the range of our desire to know, is limited.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Begriff (notion) des Seins; Sein als Zielobjekt der Vernunft

Kurzinhalt: The Notion of Being, Sein als Ausdruck eines uneingeschränkten Strebens; intellect: potens omnia facere et fieri; Sein als Objekt des transitiven Verbs "wissen"; Obskurantismus

Textausschnitt: () When St Thomas wants to prove that the object of our intellect is ens, he adduces the Aristotelian account of intellect, the potens omnia facere et fieri, able to make and become all things, a potential omnipotence, and he says that because it is omnia, it is ens, being. ... Being, then, is a final object, the term of an unrestricted tendency, desire, effort to know. We work towards it. As through imagination we have an immanently produced object, an image, and through the image have a representation of what is imagined, so through understanding and judgment we have immanently produced objects, what is conceived and what is affirmed, through which we know what is, being. And that being can be considered in either of two ways, distributively or collectively. Distributively, one talks about beings; collectively, one talks about the totality of everything that is.
()
If being is the object towards which our intellectual knowledge tends, then to know is to know being; being is the object of the transitive verb 'to know.' We have a fundamental identity: intellectual knowing of the type we have described and explained is identical with knowing being.
()
If your intellect were something that was confined within a finite range, then there could possibly be questions that you could brush aside without any reason whatever, and so a certain measure of radical obscurantism would be justified. But if no obscurantism whatever is justified, then in principle there is no finite limit to our knowing.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Intelligente und rationale Finalität

Kurzinhalt: Intelligent and Rational Finality; bewusste u. unbewusste Finalität (Aristoteles, Stein - Hunger); Staunen als Audruck d. intelligenten Finalität; Reflexion als Audruck d. rationalen Finalität

Textausschnitt: () A fundamental distinction is made between unconscious and conscious finality. According to Aristotle, any object has a finality to be at the center of the earth,
()
Intellectual and rational consciousness has a finality to the unlimited objective, to being. The finality is in what is present to itself when it is intellectually alert or critically reflective. To wonder is to manifest the finality of an intelligent subject, and to be critically reflective is to manifest the finality of a rational subject. We move from a level of sense presentations, perception, and images to a level of insight and conception, inasmuch as we are intellectually alert, inasmuch as we have not only verbal questions or questions conceptually expressed, but also that root of questioning that is intellectual curiosity, wanting to understand something.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Finalität und Inhalt des Wissens; Wesen und Sein; Cajetan (Menschheit - Mensch)

Kurzinhalt: Finality and the Contents of Knowing; die intelligente und rationale Finalität durchdringt alles Denken; Form als Begrenzung der Finalität

Textausschnitt: () Intelligent and rational finality underpins all contents in our knowing; it penetrates them all; and it goes beyond them all.
()
The matter may be illustrated by a consideration of the standard question, What is subsistence? There is a whole series of scholastic opinions on it. ... The question is put by Cajetan in terms of the difference betwen humanity and man. ... If it is just matter and form, what you conceive as a result of grasping soul in these data is humanity; but if it is this matter and form as a determination of being, it is a man. Humanity, id quo est, is abstract; man, id quod est, is concrete. Humanity is a principle limiting the being to being a man.
()
What is it that you conceive? If you attend only to the sensible presentation and the insight, then what you conceive is humanity, a compound of matter and form. But if you consider the finality of intellect towards being, what you are trying to conceive is being, and matter and form are a determination of that being, and you conceive a man. De facto, we form concrete terms before abstract ones because of the finality of intellect towards being. We have the content 'being' from the desire to know, and the determination of the content from the intelligible form in the sensible matter. According to Cajetan's theory of subsistence, 'man' adds to 'humanity' a mode. On the present analysis, 'man' means a being. You do not know a being until you make a judgment, but you are thinking about being on the level of intelligence.
()
In cognitional process there are not merely data of sense and the form grasped in insight, but also finality, the intellectually and rationally conscious finality of intellect towards being. Because of the finality, this humanity is thought as part of a whole, as the matter and form of something that is compounded not merely of matter and form but also of existence. This illustrates the penetration of all contents by being. Your questions are questions about being: What is it? Is it so? Your questions have their root in this fundamental finality.
()
This finality also goes beyond all contents. Any degree of understanding gives rise to further questions, to further understanding, and when you reach the further understanding you ask whether it is so. Affirming 'It is so' will itself give rise to further questions. When you grasp the unconditioned, you want to move to the level of knowing being.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Seins als proportioniertes Objekt, Intelligibilität des Seins, Thomas: Weisheit

Kurzinhalt: Finality as a Structured Notion (potency, form, and act), Sein ist intelligibel: ens per essentiam, ens per participationem; Weisheit im Zusammenhang mit geistiger Finalität bei Thomas

Textausschnitt: () Insofar as knowing develops on three stages, it is inevitable that the known involves a combination of three contents. If knowing is experiencing and understanding and judging, and if all three are required to have the known, then the known will involve a content from the experiencing, a content from the understanding, and a content from the judging, all combined into a single object.
()
This combination of all three contents in a single object is what is classically termed the proportionate object of our intellect - potency, form, and act ..
()
Again, if being is the object of the verb 'to know,' and our knowing is by inquiry and insight, reflection and judgment, then to say that something is a being is also to say that it is intelligible. The intelligible is what you can know by understanding and judging.
()
So we have arrived at a notion of being that is unrestricted, that includes everything about everything, that is not within any genus. It underpins, goes before, penetrates, runs into, coincides with, and goes beyond any particular act of knowing and any particular content of knowing which we may have. It is the core of all meaning, and it is a structured notion.
()
For Aquinas, the highest intellectual habit is wisdom. It is wisdom that selects the terms that determine the principles which determine everything in our knowledge. But how do we acquire wisdom? We cannot use principles here, for wisdom is their source. Aquinas would derive wisdom from two sources: ... One's choice of the notion of being is going to determine everything else. So we have to have the right notion of being to acquire wisdom, but also we have to have wisdom to settle what the right notion of being is.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Debatte um a priori als Folge der Erkenntnis als taking a look; stattdessen: Erkenntnis als antologische Vollkommenheit

Kurzinhalt: The Notion of the A Priori; Schluss: a priori, a posteriori, a simultaneo; synthetische Aussagen a priori (Kant); spiritual x-rays; anstelle: Frage nach a priori: Fr. nach Bedeutung

Textausschnitt: () 'The a priori' is a term used in three contexts. First, it is used with regard to reasoning or inference. An a priori inference is from the cause to the effect; an a posteriori inference is from the effect to the cause; an a simultaneo inference is from the mere concept of the thing. You cannot have an a priori proof of the existence of God because God has no cause. Any argument for God's existence in terms of cause and effect has to be from the effect to the cause, an a posteriori argument.
()
Kant spoke of the a priori particularly with regard to propositions or judgments. His notion of an a priori proposition or judgment is that it is absolutely independent of experience.
()
Kant assigns absolutely a priori propositions two characteristics, necessity and universality.
()
Kant further divides a priori propositions into analytic and synthetic, ...
()
On the other hand, if knowing is conceived not as looking but as an ontological perfection of the subject,
()
A third sense of the a priori was also introduced by Kant with regard to intuitions and concepts. Kant holds that there are a priori intuitions, a priori concepts, and also a priori ideas. He reaches an a priori intuition by removing from intuition all of its contingent elements. If you are looking at a body and you remove the color, shape, hardness, its impenetrability, and so on, you are left with empty space; you don't remove that: it is intrinsic to having an intuition. So the space is a priori. Similarly, with regard to the concept, ...
()
Now the real issue is, How much of knowing is from the subject, and how much is from the object?
()
Knowing can be conceived as intrinsically or essentially a matter of confrontation, of taking a look, seeing what is there, intuition. Since knowing, on this account, is what comes from the look, anything that comes from the subject is not knowing at all; and if it comes from the subject, that just means it is not knowing. Knowing is what is given in the look, and what is known is what is out there to be looked at and seen when one looks. One may go further and distinguish between sensible looks (looks through one's senses) and spiritual looks (looks with one's intellect, interior and spiritual x-rays that penetrate the essence of things and see the essence that is there).
()
If you conceive knowing as a perfection, then the question of the a priori, of what comes from the subject and what comes from the object, is of minor moment. ... We have, then really two questions, a question of fact and a question of significance. It is the question of significance that concerns us, ...
()
Our account certainly involves a dependence of knowing on the subject. But it is not simply our account. We know because it is natural to us. Plants do not know, because it is not natural to them to know. Animals have sense knowledge, but not intellectual knowledge. But we know. Why?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: natürliche "Erkenntnis" Gottes, Sein als a priori by nature; Sein als das zuerst Erkannte (Thomas)

Kurzinhalt: The Notion of Being as Natural; Erkenntis von Natur aus und durch Erwerb; Engel, Möglichkeit zu Erkennen und intellectus agens by nature; natural desire to know God; knowing being is natural insofar

Textausschnitt: () First, in ordinary scholastic terms the distinction is between what is known by nature and what is known by acquisition.
()
Consequently, while by nature we have knowing in potency, it is by acquisition that we move to knowing in act. Our potency to know, our capacity to know, is from nature, but any actual knowing involves some influence from the object. ... An object is needed to effect the transition from the potency to see to. the act of seeing. Again, sight sees nothing but the colored, the luminous; by nature it is restricted to that. The potency determines the range of possible objects attained by ocular vision.
()
So, in traditional theory, with regard to intellectual knowledge we have by nature the agent intellect that uses our sensible knowledge to produce acts of understanding. The capacity to understand, the agent intellect, the sensitive potencies, and correlations among these three are from nature; but an actuation of the process requires, first, the actual perceptions and the formation of images, and then the intervention of inquiry at that occasion.
()
Moreover, in intellect the habits of science in general are all acquired. The human intellect, at the start, is like a blackboard on which nothing is written. It is only gradually that we acquire the sciences. Still, there is a reference to something known by nature in Aristotle, namely, the principle of contradiction, and in St Thomas the habitus principiorum is described not as an acquired habit but as a natural habit. ... St Thomas also affirms that being is naturally known. Just as sense - sight, for example - is a potency that by nature is determined to a certain range of possible objects, so also intellect has by nature a determinate range. It is potens omnia facere et fieri; its range is everything. According to St Thomas, because its range is everything, its range is being.
()
St Thomas also speaks of a natural desire to know God by his essence. ... A desire to know God by his essence is something natural. It is not something acquired, produced in us, something we get out of objects.
()
In the doctrine found in St Thomas there is the equation between knowing and knowing being: knowing is natural; therefore, knowing being is natural. Being is somehow a priori? The answer to that problem is that traditionally being is said to be known by nature; it is natural knowledge.
()
If we acknowledge a natural habit, if we acknowledge that there are not only acquired habits in the intellect, but that there is also a natural habit of first principles on which absolutely everything else depends, then ... Knowing is natural, and therefore knowing being is natural. Knowing being is natural insofar as we have natural potencies and some natural habits. The whole of our knowing is not by acquisition, by the action of objects on us; part of it is had from nature. We have some resemblance to God, who is completely independent of all objects, and to the angels, who are largely independent of objects.
()
The fundamental moment in the notion of being lies in the capacity to wonder and reflect, and that as potency we have from nature. If a person naturally does not have the capacity to wonder, to be surprised by what he sees or hears or feels, to ask why, to ask what's happening, what's up then there is no remedy; there is nothing we can do. We cannot endow people with intelligence. Intelligence fundamentally is this capacity to ask questions, and this capacity is entirely from nature.
()
Because our questions are about being, and the range of our capacity for asking questions is unlimited, being is absolutely universal and absolutely concrete, the object towards which knowing moves.
()
What our knowing aims at is knowing everything about everything. On the level of potency, this is from nature, and it is independent of experience. We must have it to be able to ask questions, to wonder, to set the process going. However, the occurrence of actual wonder, actual inquiry, is not absolutely independent of experience. ... The potency is from nature; the exercise involves experience.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Menschheit: allgemeine Materie und Form; Mensch: Form + Materie im Hinblick auf Sein; id quo -> id quod

Kurzinhalt: Understanding and Experience; Bilder (image) nicht bloß Anreiz für Einsicht, sondern ihr Objekt wie Farbe für Sicht; abstract essence, particularized essence; von der Wesenheit zum Seienden

Textausschnitt: () ... images are not simply an occasion for insight, as Plato held; they are not simply a disposition, as Avicenna held, but they are the object. The images present to our intellects, to our understanding, their object. And he quotes the familiar phrase from Aristotle that images stand to understanding as colors stand to sight. The image is an object with respect to the insight: it is the object in the same sense as the color is the object of seeing.
()
There is a point to notice about the intelligibility of the image. Qua image, it is simply potential intelligibility, it is not actually intelligible; qua understood, it is the intelligible in act, identical with the act of understanding. Color as seen is not on the wall actually, it is there potentially; color as seen is identical with the act of seeing. Not that the intelligibility grasped is only in the act of understanding: it is potentially in the imaged from the fact that the image causes it.
()
... There are three cases: abstract essence, 'humanity'; particularized essence, 'this instance of humanity'; and the universal or particular thing, 'man' or 'this man.'
()
By your insight into the image you are able to formulate the conditions, the elements in the image, necessary to having the insight. If you see in this circle that the curve must be perfectly round if all of the radii are equal, if that is what insight grasps in the image, then you can proceed to the definition of a circle, which is something like a definition of man. But you can proceed in more abstract fashion. You can select simply what is grasped by insight, namely, necessity and the conditions for that necessity, and then you have an abstract essence. Implicit definitions are of this sort.
()
When the content of the insight into the phantasm is formulated in a conception, the conception may simply express form and common matter, and then you have 'humanity' or 'circularity.' It may express individual matter and form, and then you have 'this instance of humanity' or 'this instance of circularity.' Or, you can go further, and in the form and individual matter understand the full potentiality of being, and then you make the step from the id quo to the id quod
()

If you think simply of the insight and the experiential data, then what you formulate is just how much of the data is necessary for having the insight, and you get abstract essence. Recalling the example of the circle, you have to have a plane surface, a curve, and equality of all radii; but you need not have this plane, this curve, and radii of this size, because that is irrelevant. If you consider the process, as starting from insight into phantasm, as heading towards conception, as concerned with picking out the essential, you get abstract essence - humanity, or circularity, so to speak - form and common matter. If you think of this process as serving a different end, if you have grasped the abstract essence and you want to consider this instance of it, then, since what is operating is an intelligent consciousness, you can pick out the data that de facto fall under the present insight, and you get a particularized essence, this instance of humanity. But insofar as this wonder, this inquiry, represents a fundamental finality, intelligence grasps, when it goes on to the particularized essence, the potentiality of being.
()
The insight and the experience together can give you either an abstract essence or a particularized essence, depending on your point of view; but insofar as that essence satisfies the requirements of intelligence with respect to its finality, insofar as it meets the criterion of intrinsic intelligibility, you move from essence to being, from the id quo to the id quod.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Erfahrung - Urteil; die Erfassung des virtuell Unbedingten sowohl by nature als auch in Abhängigkeit

Kurzinhalt: Judgment and Experience; Thomas über Habitus: das Ganze ist größer als der Teil -> Lonergans Erklärung: Übergang vom id qou zum id quod; Zusammenfassung (summary) über Finalität (a priori - a posteriori)

Textausschnitt: () When St Thomas discusses the habit of first principles, he gives a great deal of attention to the fact that the whole is greater than the part, and that that is fundamental in all cognitional theory. But he does not explain what he means. At least I found no text in which he did explain it. What might be the relevance of the whole being greater than the part, as something fundamental in all cognitional process, is the transition from the id quo to the id quod, ...
()
Now insofar as there is a requirement, a criterion of the virtually unconditioned, there is operative something that we have from nature; but insofar as we grasp the virtually unconditioned, we are dependent. We are certainly not knowing something, grasping something, that is absolutely independent of experience. You cannot have the fulfilment of the conditions for a virtually unconditioned without the experiential level, without the experience either of outer sense or of inner consciousness. Again, ... So the act of grasping the virtually unconditioned is in no sense absolutely independent of experience. 0n the other hand, the requirement that you have to have the virtually unconditioned if you are to judge, and that if you have the virtually unconditioned you cannot be rational and not judge - not without doing violence to your own rational consciousness - that is had from nature.
()
Briefly, then, the intention of being functions as a finality. It is radically from nature, and it functions in knowledge as a finality, a guide, a criterion, a requirement. It is absolutely transparent; it is not an a priori that determines what you will know, but it demands, it initiates, the process of knowing, guides the process, and sets criteria by which one carries out the process correctly or incorrectly. It sets the process going as inquiry, and it guides it by a requirement of intelligibility through which one effects the transition from essence to being, from essentia to ens.
()
To put the question in terms of independence, Is your knowing being independent of experience absolutely? The answer is simply, No, it is not absolutely independent. On the other hand. Is there anything in your knowing of being that comes from nature? Yes, there is but that which we have by nature is a perfect transparence. It does not prejudge any issue. ...
()
The a posteriori and the a priori, experiencing and not experiencing, however, are not the fundamental categories in which a satisfactory answer to the question is obtained. The fundamental categories are what we know by nature and what we know by acquisition.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: absolute Objektivität; Urteil als Brücke zw. Subjekt u. Objekt

Kurzinhalt: Notion of Objectivity, Absolute Objectivity, A is; B is; C is; A is not B nor C..., die Erfassung des virtuell Unbedingten als Brücke; Objektivität: Reich der realen Distinktionen

Textausschnitt: () A is; B is; C is; A is not B nor C; B is not C nor A, and so on. If you have a set of affirmative and negative judgments in that pattern, then A, B, and C are distinct objects. By an object we mean what you know through a set of true judgments.
()
In other words, there is no problem of a bridge. If you can reach the judgment, you are there. An object means no more than that A is. If I am A, and A is, and B is, and A is not B, then we have a subject: I am a knower (established in chapter 11); and we have an object: something that A knows, that I know, that is not myself, that is not the subject. Through true propositions, you can arrive at an objective world. That is the principal notion of objectivity.
()
The virtually unconditioned is an unconditioned, and an unconditioned is an absolute. An unconditioned is not dependent, qua unconditioned, on anything. Not depending on anything, it is not dependent on the subject. The process of knowing when you grasp the unconditioned and affirm it, moves beyond subjectivity by the mere fact that you reach an unconditioned. You step in, through the judgment, into an absolute realm.
()
The bridge between subject and object is through absolute objectivity positing an absolute realm within which real distinctions occur. What are distinct objects? A is, B is; A is not B; consequently, there are two. If that is true, then in this absolute realm there are two. If one of them is a knower and the other is not, then one is the subject and the other is not a subject but just an object. ... That judgment does not give you a sense of yourself; you have to have that sense to be able to make the judgment properly - to go through the argument of chapter 11. You have to be familiar with your own experience and intelligence and reasonableness. But that familiarity is just the experiential side. When you know yourself through the judgment, you know yourself as objectified.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Finalität als Kriterium für wahre und falsche Subjektivität;

Kurzinhalt: Normative Objectivity, wahre Objektivität und Subjektivität im Gefolge der "geistigen" Finalität

Textausschnitt: () There is another way of conceiving subjectivity. This process has a guide in the pure desire to know, in its finality. That finality as such withraws a man from other concerns; it gives the detachment, the disinterestedness, of the inquirer, of the one who is concerned to know what is. Objectivity is yielding to the dominance of that finality; it is not allowing desires and fears to interfere with it. Insofar as your desires and fears are interfering with this process, you have subjectivity in the sense that is opposed to objectivity. Again, inquiry, the demand for intelligibility, the demand for the unconditioned, are norms immanent within this cognitional process itself. Insofar as one is meeting those requirements, one is objective. Insofar as one's desires or fears or any other factor in one's makeup are interfering with the execution of this process according to its own immanent norms, one's judgments will be merely subjective.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Objektivität und psychische Abnormalität

Kurzinhalt: Experiential Objectivity; Einsicht und Erfahrung als per se infallible and per accidens; die Welt des psychische Abnormlen: nicht Gegenstand d. Physik usw.; Kriterium für richtige Erfahrung: Intelligenz, Urteil

Textausschnitt: () However, what one is imagining may not be the same as what there is to be sensed, what can be sensed, what is given. Insight is per se infallible and per accidens makes mistakes. It is infallibleg because it is insight into what we imagine, and it is per accidens mistaken insofar as what we imagine may be very different from what is to be seen or heard or tasted or smelt or felt.
()
The freely produced or what is produced by psychological aberration is a perfect counterfeit of what is given. Still, it is given not for normal living but for the science of abnormal psychology. From that given, you arrive at a true account of abnormal psychology. It is not a suitable given for doing physics, ...
()
However, while the person in the pathological state cannot spot what is wrong, those who are not in that state can spot what is wrong with him. He does not have the freedom of control of the sensitive processes that permit correct judgment. You cannot settle this question of the difference between the given and the abnormally produced by saying that when you are normal you are able to take a look to see what is there, and when you are not normal you look and see what is not there. In either case, all you have is the look, and to know whether you are normal or abnormal you would have to have a super-look in which you would look not merely at your looking but at what it was looking at.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: 3 Probleme d. Objektivität, Tonquédec, Maréchal (Kant), Selbstwiderspruch im Subjekt

Kurzinhalt: The Problem of Objectivity, Erkennen nicht als Schau, sondern als Vervollkommnung (perfection), contradiction within the subject; Qualis unusquisque est, talis et finis videtur ei

Textausschnitt: () ... the notion of absolute objectivity as such does not exclude relativism. A relativist could admit that notion of absolute objectivity, but he would say we never actually reach it; we never reach the virtually unconditioned. It is only when we understand everything about everything that we really get hold of the unconditioned.
()
Which way is right? Are we right in saying that normative objectivity is meeting the exigences of the pure desire to know? Or would it be more correct to say that normative objectivity is paying attention to the object, seeing what is out there to be seen?
()
De Tonquédec works out a complete theory of knowledge in terms of seeing, confronting. His approach is entirely in terms of objectivity in the sense of taking a look, and he has a bit of difficulty handling judgment. Knowing is looking, and that position dominates his entire exposition and investigation. In Maréchal, however, we have just the opposite. For Maréchal, finality is the dominant notion.
()
Different answers here will determine different criticisms of Kant. Thus de Tonquédec holds that what is wrong with Kant is his ideal of pure reason and the categories of understanding; Kant should be content with intuition, and put more stress on it. Maréchal, however, criticizes Kant for putting too much stress on intuition and not enough on judgment. My own position is that for Kant you have knowing when intuition operates in such a way that you have concepts. But he does not recognize judgment and grasp of the unconditioned; he does not make the unconditioned a key point.
There is, then, a problem of objectivity, and the problem has different aspects. The first of these is the question of the starting point.
()
The point is to complete the circle. One way to complete the circle is to begin from knowing. But one can begin with the metaphysics of the object, proceed to the metaphysical structure of the knower and to the metaphysics of knowing, and move on to complement the metaphysics of knowing with the further psychological determinations that can be had from consciousness. From those psychological determinations one can move on to objectivity and arrive at a metaphysics. One will be completing the same circle,
()
The second aspect of the problem of objectivity regards the directive notion of knowing. This is the basic issue. What is your dominant opposition? Is knowing, with de Tonquédec, a looking? Or is it, with Maréchal, basically a perfection? ... Consequently, Kant's position does not square with his theory.
()
What is the fascination of the view of knowing as looking? Is it merely a mistake? Not entirely. There is involved another factor, the subject himself. We saw that self-appropriation involves development of the self which is to be appropriated, and the same problem recurs here.
()
There is a contradiction within the subject. There is a dynamic of events in human development; it is animal, intelligent, and rational. Consequently, the weight that can be carried by the rational part of man is a variable, but we are always living. To meet the problem, one must shift one's basis. The shift from animal to intelligent level occurs philosophically as the shift from sensism and related positions to essentialism. The shift from intelligent to rational level occurs philosophically as the shift from essentialism to existentialism in our sense, that is, to a position which makes truth dominant and operative in a fundamental way in one's philosophy. Qualis unusquisque est, talis et finis videtur ei:
()
There is, finally, a third aspect to the problem of objectivity, the cognitional problem of fact. What is true? What do we know? The conversion, on the intellectual side, is effected by the study of facts. Whether one adverts to it or not, the finality of the subject is operative; but through the study of facts one can bring the subject to a fruitful advertence to the conflict between what he holds as theory and what he does in actual knowing and practice.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Metaphysik, Dialektik zw. desire to know und "Welt" (Sorge); Kriterium: Realität, Objektivität

Kurzinhalt: Definition of Metaphysics, The Underlying Problem, Nacht des Mystikers, Spannung zw. Welt u. pure desire to know, 3 Elemente einer Dialektik

Textausschnitt: () ... we acknowledge a pure desire to know correlated with a universe of being. On the subjective side there is a desire to know by correct understanding in true judgment, and the objective of this desire is a universe of being whose reality corresponds to the totality of true judgments - knowing everything about everything. () Now this universe of being is not identical with 'my world' - Heidegger' s Welt.
()
The night of sense of the mystics is the destruction of one's Welt, but our aim is not to destroy it or to bring it into coincidence with the universe of being, or to transpose it into that universe, but rather to highlight the idea of the real, and so to remove the conflict.
()
The trouble, then, lies with the notion of the real. Is the real to be identified with the universe of being, or is it to be settled by my autobiography? ... But the pure desire to know can also become a dominant Sorge, and then, though there will not be a complete elimination of merely personal concern, still this world of one's concern will move into coincidence with the universe of being.
()
Now if our view is right - that the underlying problem is a tension between the Welt and the pure desire to know - then the solution is dialectical. Dialectic is concerned with three factors. First, it is concerned with the concrete: in the present case, with the concrete subject and his Sorge. Secondly, dialectic is concerned with the contradictory: the contradiction is not in propositions but in the subject, for the subject as intelligent and rational consciousness is not identical with the subject of Sorge, hence what is real in the Welt is not real in the universe of being, and vice versa. Thirdly, dialectic is concerned with change: the contradiction involves a tension, a tension in the concrete, and so heads for change.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Position - Gegenposition: desire to know - Erkennen als Schau (Kriterium Realität),

Kurzinhalt: Positions and Counterpositions, Selbstwiderspruch, basic set - consequent set, Selbstaufhebung der Gegenposition; Entwicklung bei position - wechselnder Grund bei counterposition, Descartes, Hume

Textausschnitt: () The totality of propositions can be divided into a basic set and a consequent set. The basic set, in the present approach, has to do with knowledge. What is it to know? What is objectivity? What is reality? ... In our philosophy the answer to these questions is determined by the subject as intelligently and rationally conscious, but in the opposed notions knowing is looking, objectivity is what can be seen, and reality is what's there. Besides the basic set, there is the consequent set of propositions, ... the meaning of consequent propositions changes with the meaning of the basic: with every basic meaning of knowing, objectivity, and reality, you give a meaning as well to all other propositions.
()
Now basic propositions are either positions or counterpositions. They are positions if propositions on knowing, objectivity, and reality are expressions of intelligent and rational consciousness and compatible with its orientation to the universe of being. They are counterpositions if they are expressions which are contradictory to the positions and incompatible with orientation to the universe of being. The counterpositions express Sorge and its Welt insofar as Sorge differs from the pure desire to know and the Welt differs from the universe of being.
()
implicitly intelligence and reasonableness are criteria for his utterance; explicitly, if he is in a counterposition, his utterance is opposed to these criteria. He is uttering a counterposition, but his utterance as human claims to be intelligent and rational.
()
Positions develop. ... On the other hand, counterpositions tend to their own reversal: when the content of the utterance is contrasted with its fundamental implicit claim, there is a manifest contradiction, and the counterposition will collapse.
()

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Metaphysik als alles über alles (konkret und allgemein); als Synthesis zw. Sorge und Sein Grundlage aller Wissenschaften

Kurzinhalt: Metaphysics as Synthesis; Sein als everything about everything, Beziehung zw. Metaphysik und anderen Wissensgebieten

Textausschnitt: () Being is completely universal: it includes everything. Being is completely concrete: it includes everything about everything. It is in terms of that notion of being that we developed a notion of metaphysics. Metaphysics is not a concern with the reality of the candlestick or the snuffbox; it is a concern with the universe as opposed to a world determined by a Sorge, by a concern. It is concerned with a synthesis.
()
First, metaphysics underlies all other departments, because all other departments are specializations of the total basic inquiry.
()
First, metaphysics underlies all other departments, because all other departments are specializations of the total basic inquiry.
()
Secondly, metaphysics penetrates all other departments.
()
Thirdly, metaphysics transforms the results of other departments.
()
While this tension, on the moral level, is familiar, it exists equally on the cognitional level. There is development not merely on the moral side of man, there is a more fundamental development on the cognitional side, in the transition from a world defined by Sorge to a world defined by the pure desire to know, and all the implications in that.
()
Finally, metaphysics unifies other departments.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Metaphysik: implizit, problematisch, explizit

Kurzinhalt: Implicit and Problematic Metaphysics, Humanwissenschaften erweisen die Notwendigkeit einer Metyphysik

Textausschnitt: () The metaphysics with which we are concerned is a metaphysics that is implicit in everyone by the simple fact that he is a conscious subject that experiences, understands, and judges.
()
Besides the implicit stage in metaphysics, there is a problematic stage. The need for making the implicit explicit is felt, but the explicitation is not achieved. The problematic stage can be general or particular,
()
The problematic stage arises, in particular, insofar as there is a desire for a satisfactory method for the human sciences. In The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, Husserl makes the point that,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Explizite Metaphysik, Definition: integrale heuristische Struktur des proportionierten Seins

Kurzinhalt: Explicit Metaphysics

Textausschnitt: () Metaphysics becomes explicit insofar as the implications of the pure desire to know and its unfolding are worked out with regard to the structure of reality and the unification of knowledge. So we come to our definition: explicit metaphysics is the conception, affirmation, and implementation of the integral heuristic structure of proportionate being.
()
... metaphysics in two steps. There is, first of all, metaphysics with regard to this world and, secondly, there is the question of the existence of God ... The experiental element is what differentiates proportionate being from being in general.
()
What the being is in each particular case - even what proportionate being is - is a question to be answered by a particular science. But, as we have very briefly indicated in these lectures, and as we have attempted to indicate more fully in Insight, the sciences are heuristic. ... Where we ordinarily ask, 'What is the nature of [...]?' the physicist, with a somewhat more elaborate heuristic structure, asks, 'What is the function that governs these phenomena?' and he attempts to determine that function in two ways. First,
()
The scientist is heading for something, inquiring into something - 'Think about it precisely; give it a symbol.' What is happening? He is anticipating an act of understanding in which he will understand the data in question and all similar data. The scientist not only anticipates the act of understanding, but he also anticipates the expression of the act of understanding in some conception. Where the mathematician says 'x' and the physicist mentions 'some indeterminate function,' in ordinary speech one says 'the nature of...' What is the nature of light? The nature of light is what we will understand, what we will know, when we understand light. This heuristic procedure anticipates the future act of understanding and its conceptualization, and it uses that anticipation to guide the process towards attaining the act of understanding in question.
()
Just as there is heuristic structure with regard to acts of understanding, so there is a total heuristic structure; there is the total goal of intelligent and rational consciousness as such. We have named that goal 'being'. When we speak of knowing being, we mean knowing everything about everything. But we do not know everything about everything; we are simply anticipating the totality of acts of understanding and judgment by which we could completely achieve the ideal, the goal, set us by our desire to know.
()
The metaphysician not only posits a general x, being, what one will know when one understands correctly everything about everything, but he can also break being up: into being completely, and being that is proportionate being.
()
Any proportionate being will involve what corresponds to the three contents - this is a fundamental premise in our movement towards a metaphysics of proportionate being - and we can name them potency, form, and act. When science reaches its ideal goal of complete understanding of all phenomena, what will science be?
()
What is explicit metaphysics? It is the subject achieving self-appropriation, knowing himself as a knower, and using that knowledge to determine the general structure of his possible object and the relations between the particular departments in knowing that object.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Metaphysik, Kategorien, erklärendes Wissen

Kurzinhalt: Metaphysics and Explanatory Knowledge; Feuer - phlogiston

Textausschnitt: () We have three accounts of fire. How can those three accounts be of the same thing? Phlogiston is precisely not one of the four elements, and a chemical process is not any substance but just process. Where do we find the common point between the three successive theories, so that we may say that Aristotle's notion of fire was wrong?
()
... there is a fundamental difference between the notion of metaphysics we are presenting and what has become fairly common down a number of centuries in scholastic notions of metaphysics. In Aristotle, the predicaments are clearly distinguished; but that is a list of descriptive categories.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Metaphysik: analoges Verstehen, Verhältnis zwischen Wesen und Sein; x1/y2, x2/y2 (x: Wesen - y: Sein);

Kurzinhalt: When one has proper knowledge of a thing, one is understanding it by its essence; but when one has analogical knowledge, one also has some understanding, an understanding of a proportion, of an analogy ...

Textausschnitt: 1. Metaphysical Analysis

1/9 If intellect is intelligence, it seems a fair question to ask,1 What does the metaphysician understand? If he does not understand anything, he does not seem to be using his intelligence. If he does understand something, what is it? Traditionally, the definition of metaphysics is that it is the science of being qua being. This suggests that it is not the science of any particular class of beings. It is not understanding what the physicist understands, what the chemist understands, what the biologist understands, what the anthropologist understands, or what the theologian understands. There does not seem to be anything left for the metaphysician to understand. (200; Fs)

2/9 Again, what he understands does not seem to be being as an abstract residue. One can say that common to all men is intelligence, common to all men and animals is sense, common to men and animals and plants is life, common to those three and the inorganic world is matter, common to all of them and to the angels and to God is substantiality, and common to substances and accidents there is something. What finally is left, after you have taken away what is proper to everything, one may say, is what the metaphysician studies. However, that which is finally left is not anything that exists; it seems to be nothing. Whatever you understand, you understand some essence; essence is what you know when you understand. What is finally left after you have removed what is proper to everything does not seem to be any essence. (200f; Fs)

3/9 Again, one could conceive metaphysics as understanding the essence of God, the essence of the ens per essentiam. God, understanding his own essence, understands absolutely everything else, everything that is possible and everything that is actual, all in a simple intellectual apprehension that is identical with himself. In that case, if one had God's understanding of himself by which God also understands everything else, one would be a metaphysician who understood something; and indeed, the object of that understanding would be being in its total extension. However, we are not God, and in this life we do not have the beatific vision by which we participate in God's knowledge. Moreover, the beatific vision is something beyond the proportion of our natures; consequently, it does not seem to be what constitutes the metaphysician qua metaphysician. (201; Fs)

4/9 What, then, does the metaphysician understand, if it is not any particular class of beings, not the abstract residue of all beings, and not the ens per essentiam? I do not think that the answer is that the metaphysician understands nothing whatever. What does he understand? (201; Fs)

1.1 Analogous Understanding

5/9 I think we have to distinguish between two types of understanding. In theology at least, it is necessary to distinguish between proper knowledge of a thing - knowledge of a thing by its essence - and analogical knowledge; and this suggests two types of understanding. When one has proper knowledge of a thing, one is understanding it by its essence; but when one has analogical knowledge, one also has some understanding, an understanding of a proportion, of an analogy. (201; Fs)

6/9 One may say, then, that the knowledge of the essences of different types of beings pertains to the particular departments of knowledge, and the metaphysician leaves knowledge of those essences to the people working in the particular departments. What will be determined in the various departments are the essences of the different kinds of beings, and that is proper knowledge. But the metaphysician has analogical knowledge. For him, the essences function as a series of x's. When we were discussing the concept of being,2 we saw that in essence intelligence grasps the possibility of being; because of essence, it raises the question of existence. There is a connection, then, between essence and being, essence and existence; beings are compounded of essences and existences. One might say as a first approximation that the metaphysician is concerned with the proportion between essences and existences, with the analogy of the series x1/y1, x2/y2, etc., where existences are indicated by the y's and essences by the x's. That analogy is the occupation of the metaphysician. His understanding is analogous. It is an understanding of being and of all being, but it is not a matter of understanding essences proper to each being. Metaphysics is understanding and exploiting the analogy in all being. This account of metaphysics at least introduces a familiar element. (201f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Analogie in der Metaphysik leitet sich vom Verstehen d. Verstehens ab; Aristoteles (Metaphysik, Buch 9): Form - Potenz : Einsicht - Daten; Verständnis des proportionierten Seins -> analoges Verständnis des absoluten Seins

Kurzinhalt: We can examine in some detail just precisely what is the relation between what is grasped by insight and what is presented in data ... It is not simply that potency is the determinable and form is whatever determines, ...

Textausschnitt: 1.2 The Fundamental Set of Analogies

7/9 If, however, we go on to ask, 'Just what are these proportions? How do we obtain these proportions?' I should say that, in the fundamental case, it is by understanding understanding, by insight into insight. The metaphysician's understanding is analogous, and fundamentally the analogies come from an understanding of understanding. In the first instance, they come from an understanding of human understanding, and so we have a metaphysics of proportionate being. In the second instance, one goes beyond the first stage to the absolute being by analogy, and one has some analogous understanding of absolute understanding. That is the root of the analogies employed in metaphysics. It is a matter of understanding understanding, insight into insight. (202; Fs)

8/9 A standard analogy in metaphysics, that has its origin with Aristotle, is the analogy of form to potency.a Aristotle gives an account of it in the ninth book of the Metaphysics, in terms of a first type of the analogy of potency to act. What is that analogy in its fundamental case? It is the analogy of insight to data, of what is grasped by insight to what is presented by imagination. Aristotle illustrates this analogy by saying that as sight is to eyes, so hearing is to ears, and taste is to the palate, and so on. This illustration is exact. Sight is what we know by insight. We can take a look at eyes, but when we understand the eyes we say that they are organs of sight; sight is the form of the organ that is the eye. (202f; Fs)

9/9 Again, Aristotle elsewhere remarks that the soul is to the whole animal as sight is to seeing.1 Existence is to essence as judgment is to conception, as affirmation is to what is the affirmed content. As conception results from the combination of insight and data, so essence results from the combination of form and potency. But there we have a second instance of potency and act. Aristotle's illustration for this second instance of potency and act - the relation of form to act - is that as sight is to seeing, so the faculty of hearing is to the act of hearing, auditus ad audiendum.2 We happen to use the same word in English both for the faculty of hearing and for the act, but still, the faculty is the form of the organ, the ear, and the act is distinct from both the organ and the faculty, for there are times when we are not hearing anything.3 (203; Fs)

10/9 Our study of knowledge introduces us into the traditional analogies in a fundamental form in which we can control them.c We can examine in some detail just precisely what is the relation between what is grasped by insight and what is presented in data. That is a fundamental instance that can be illustrated wherever you can illustrate the relation of form and potency. On the other hand, you will also note that this analogy gives precision to the relation between form and potency. It is not simply that potency is the determinable and form is whatever determines, and you can apply that distinction wherever you please, ad infinitum. We have form and potency when we have the analogy of insight and data. Again, we have the analogy of existence and essence where we have the analogy of judgment and conception. We may have a triple-termed analogy: potency to form to act, as data in the intellectual pattern of experience to insight to judgment. (203; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Zwei Klassen von Einsicht: zentrale - konjugate Form; Substanz - Akzidenz; Hierarchie der konjugaten Formen

Kurzinhalt: Central and Conjugate Forms; When data are considered as particular, and a multiplicity of data are referred to a single unity, you have a grasp of form of one type, which we may call central or substantial form.

Textausschnitt: 1.3 Central and Conjugate Forms

11/9 Let us return to the relation between what is grasped by insight and what is presented in data, and examine it in further detail. Forms, insights, divide into two fundamental classes that are quite distinct. When data are considered as particular, and a multiplicity of data are referred to a single unity, you have a grasp of form of one type, which we may call central or substantial form. We have insights into data as particular. It is in considering these data that I have insight into the unity of this man. Consequently, there is a central form in beings, a central form which corresponds to what is grasped when you say it is one and the same over a spatiotemporal volume of particular data. (204; Fs)

12/9 But when you compare data with one another, build up classifications by similarity, and proceed to work out the relations of things to one another, you arrive at scientific laws. Those laws involve relations, determinate relations of things to one another. A law is an expression of an intelligibility; it involves something corresponding to form. This gives us a second type of form, conjugate or accidental form. There is a determinateness in potency and act that comes from the form. Judgment only says 'Yes.' The form corresponds to data, but it is the ground of the intelligibility grasped in the data. If there are different types of form, there must be different types of potency and different types of act. (204; Fs)

13/9 Again, we have spoken of higher viewpoints. For a while, intelligence works along with data, under the guidance of certain insights and formulations. When it comes up against difficulties, intelligence starts all over again, reformulating all of its fundamental conceptions. That is the result of further insights that constitute a higher viewpoint with respect to the previous set of insights. In the first instance, higher viewpoints regard the development of human intelligence. But higher viewpoints also have a relevance to the hierarchy in things. (The notion of a hierarchy in things involves a very complex argument that I had best not attempt to summarize.1) For the forms on any given level, there is a set of laws. From that set of laws a certain number of schemes of recurrence can be developed. The schemes of recurrence can be brought to light by a physicist, a chemist, and so on. The regular events that occur on that level may be entirely explained by the laws and schemes on that level; but it may also happen that they are not. (204; Fs)

14/9 In the biological unit of the cell, there is taking place a continuous release of chemical actions, and every one of those actions occurs in accordance with the laws of chemistry. But if it is not possible through chemical laws and the schemes of recurrence that can be devised in chemistry to account for the regularity with which those chemical processes take place in the cell, you have to appeal to a higher viewpoint to account for the regularity, and you introduce conjugate forms on the biological level with their laws and schemes. If in the animal you find regularities that cannot be accounted for by the totality of laws and schemes of recurrence on the biological level, you postulate another higher level. You have grounds for another higher viewpoint, in which are introduced the conjugates of the sensitive level. If you find, with regard to men, that all of the laws and schemes of sensitive psychology, which pertain to the psychic level, do not account for the intelligible talk that men carry on, you have to go on to a still higher level and posit intellectual forms that account for human behavior. (205; Fs)

15/9 The idea of a higher viewpoint, while it was first developed in terms of the development of human intelligence, also provides us with an analogy for the hierarchy of conjugate forms, accidental forms, that are found in single beings. The conjugate acts of a lower level, insofar as they occur regularly and are accounted for by the laws and schemes of recurrence of the lower level, pertain simply to that lower level. If, on the other hand, there is a regularity in the conjugate acts of a lower level that is not accounted for by that level, then there is an information of that lower level by conjugate forms of a higher level. (205; Fs)

16/9 For example, take the flow of images in an animal (insofar as the animal has a flow of images): you do not need to postulate intelligence to account for it. However, the flow of images in a man, with all of the subsequent psychology resulting from the images and ending up in talk, is not accounted for without introducing higher integrations. We can all witness and experience the process of learning, and discover that to be able to talk intelligently, properly, on a matter, one has to have a prior development of understanding. Teaching is principally an encouragement, a help, in that development of understanding. Consequently, Aristotle says2 that to teach, the fundamental requirement is that you understand. If you do not understand, you are not going to help anyone else to understand. Now it is insofar as there is a higher integration of images and the motor activities involved in speech on the level of intelligence that you have the recurrence of intelligible content in speech, and the domination of speech by an intellectual intention. The relation of insight to data is, in its proper meaning, a case in which a higher conjugate form is controlling an otherwise coincidental multiplicity of conjugate acts on a lower level. When this analogy is pushed to the lowest level, we have, on the side of the accidents, the multiplicity3 - the empirical residue involved in space-time; and on the substantial, central side, we have prime matter. (205f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Kritik an der Phänomenologie (phenomenology) am Beispiel des Kreises

Kurzinhalt: Teile der Materie, der Form (Aristoteles); der Begriff geht über das Vorstellbare hinaus;

Textausschnitt: The concept steps beyond the level of what can be presented empirically. The circle that satisfies the definition is not anything we can imagine; it can only be conceived. The selection from the data of what is essential to the insight leaves behind elements that are necessary for having any empirical presentation at all, or at least it can do so.
()
In this connection, Aristotle in his Metaphysics (book 7, chapter 10) distinguished between parts of the matter and parts of the form. It is the same distinction we made with respect to the image in the example of the circle. In the circle, parts of the matter are the color of the background, the color of the line, ... Parts of the form are the elements that have to be there to have the insight: radii, center, perimeter, and equality.
()
The Aristotelian distinction between parts of the matter and parts of the form offers, I think, a fundamental clue to what the phenomenologist is after. The phenomenologist does not want to describe absolutely everything. He gives a selective description, a description of what is significant or, as he himself says, of what is essential, of what is relevant. That description, the presentation of data that communicates to us what is essential, is a selection of the parts of the form that are in the matter. It is not discussion on the level of conception, where one tries to give a general formula that covers all possible cases. The phenomenologist presents us with a concrete situation, and in that concrete situation he picks out the parts of the form from the viewpoint of certain insights. It is a concrete mode of communicating insights. I do not say, of course, that this formulation of phenomenology is that of any phenomenologist, but I think it is a good clue to understanding what phenomenologists are doing.
()
Epistemological, metaphysical, and philosophical questions arise on a level that we have not dealt with yet, while phenomenology as engaged in phenomenological description is not even talking on the level of conception.
()
**Phenomenologists are communicating insight through the concrete, and not through the general conception that selects what is essential and is found in every case.** Phenomenology is talking to the Athenians the way the Athenians could understand, not in the way Socrates did, for which he was put to death.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Intelligibilität der Wahrscheinlichkeit = per accidens = kata symbebekos; Lonergan, Aristoteles

Kurzinhalt: What is the intelligibility of probability? Aristotle's conception of the terrestrial process is that it is a coincidental process. Any event presupposes a cause acting *now*

Textausschnitt: Now with regard to the intelligibility: What is the intelligibility of probability as I affirm it? Well, probability as I affirm it is the intelligibility in what Aristotle would call the per accidens - that's St Thomas - the kata symbebekos. Aristotle's conception of the terrestrial process is that it is a coincidental process. Any event presupposes a cause acting now. Why does this cause act now? Well, you have to invoke some other cause to account for the 'now.' And why does that cause act now? You have to invoke some further one. And the cause that accounts for this other agent acting now is a cause per accidens. There is no nature that is such that it will cause other things to act now. Its nature is some universal property.

This is the Aristotelian theory.a Consequently Aristotle deduces the eternity of the world, and the fact that this terrestrial process is a coincidental process. To account for the regularity and continuity of terrestrial process he goes on to his theory of the influence of the heavens. That's where the theory of the influence of the heavens comes in, in Aristotelian theory.

Where does probability make a difference between Aristotle's account and the coincidental process? It's insofar as probability is the assertion of an intelligibility in the coincidental itself. Probability as conceived in Insight is an affirmation of an intelligibility within a field that classical law is not capable of handling.

So probability is not simply unintelligible as we conceive it. It presupposes the inverse insight that classical law cannot handle certain types of event, cannot provide a systematic general explanation of certain types of event. But through probability theory, you get the next best: you get something that's general, regards all cases, and so on.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Intelligibilität der Form und des Aktes; Unintelligibilität des Aktes; Frage nach Gott

Kurzinhalt: Form is intelligible in itself. Potency has an intelligibility, not in itself, but from its form. Act is not intelligible in itself

Textausschnitt: Form is intelligible in itself. It's what you know by insight, by understanding. It's as much of the thing as you know insofar as you're understanding it. And that is a pure intelligibility. But potency, the empirical residue, is not intelligible in itself. It's intelligible in form. The empirical residue as such is a limit to the intelligibility we find in data. But insofar as one fully grasps the nature of form, I believe one finds a certain intelligibility in the empirical residue, in potency. Potency has an intelligibility, not in itself, but from its form.
()
Again, act - existence, or event - is not intelligible in itself. It's contingent. You know existence or event through judgment, through the proper content of judgment. That proper content results from a grasp of the virtually unconditioned. The virtually unconditioned is a conditioned whose conditions happen to be fulfilled. Because the conditions merely happen to be fulfilled, the act is contingent. There is a defect of intelligibility in act. Act is not intelligible in itself. The existents in this world of our experience have not an intelligibility in themselves - we postulate a cause for them. If the universe were completely intelligible in itself, it would be impossible to argue from the universe to the existence of God, because you'd have no reason to go beyond the universe to attain complete intelligibility.
()
If the universe were in itself completely intelligible, then intelligence would have no lever, no fulcrum, by which it could go beyond the universe. There has to be a defect in the intelligibility of this universe to have arguments that will take us beyond the universe, to complete the intelligibility.
()
And that's quite clear from any of the arguments that are employed. In any of the arguments from causality you argue from the contingency. Or, you argue from the order of the universe not being accountable for by the universe; in other words, it's there as a fact, but if you have an intelligible order, the existence of that intelligible order is not accounted for without an intelligence. And so on. You are always arguing from some defect in the intelligibility of this universe.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Isomorphismus, Parallelität zwischen Erkennen und Welt; distinctio realis zw. Sein und Wesen

Kurzinhalt: Why is this structure in knowledge a structure in reality? real distinction between essence and existence

Textausschnitt: Now, is that the real world? Might not the real world be something totally different from that? That's the question?
()
Well, first of all, the answer to that question is of course to ask the man what he means by the real world. And if he means by the real world what he knows intelligently and rationally, then he means being by the real world. And if he doesn't mean something that's the fruit of his intelligence and rationality, well, we needn't bother about him.
()
Now you can either say that intelligibility is identical with being, so that if there are differences in intelligibility there'll be a structure in being; or, you can say the intelligibility is only in the subject, it's not in the object. If you take the first, it's a matter of comparing the different senses of intelligibility - intelligibility in itself, intelligibility in the other, and different types of intelligibility in the other - to see that there'll be that structure in the being. If you say the intelligibility is just in the knower and not in the being, then you're making the being an unknowable. Because what you know by understanding correctly is intelligible.
()
The further question: Why is this structure in knowledge a structure in reality?
()
I think in other words that that problem in its traditional form is the problem of the real distinction between essence and existence. And historically we've had all sorts of people holding there is a distinction, but it's just a distinction in our minds. And for me the point to the controversy is: The problem doesn't lie in the word 'distinction,' it lies in what you mean by reality.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Struktur, Begriff, intelligent - intelligibel

Kurzinhalt: A technician makes a machine. The machine is not intelligent but the man who makes it; The concept is intelligible, it isn't intelligent, but the insight

Textausschnitt: A technician makes a machine. The machine is not intelligent but the man who makes it, who designs it, has to be intelligent ... The man is intelligent, the machine is intelligible. Your relations in cognitional structure are of the type 'intelligent'; your relations in the material thing, for example, are of the type 'intelligible.' The concept is intelligible, it isn't intelligent, but the insight is the act of a man qua intelligent, and the concept is intelligible because it's a product of the insight, or of the man with the insight.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: (Schulbuch) Konzeptualismus; Ding -> Sprung zu Begriff; Newman: illative sense; Thomas - Averroes, Avicenna

Kurzinhalt: Intellect as Intelligence; the first element of intellectual knowledge is the concept. Then you compare concepts, and they're either contradictory...

Textausschnitt: Latin scholastic manual ... you form concepts, and they're little nuggets. And they're functions of the thing; they're not dependent upon any intelligently conscious process; they're first; the first element of intellectual knowledge is the concept. Then you compare concepts, and they're either contradictory, or necessarily related, or neither the one nor the other. Then you make judgments, and you make judgments in virtue of the sufficiency of the evidence. And what's the evidence? Well, it's your concept ... From your sense data you can build up your theory of sensation in terms of knowing the sense data. From the words you can say we have to have knowledge of universals. You have principles, because these universals are necessarily linked together. And they're analytic: the predicate says just what's in the subject. There aren't any synthetic ones; if you say there are, you're a Kantian. There's no relevance of inquiry, understanding, the development of understanding, the way understanding develops, and no clear, explicit account of what exactly critical reflection is. We ask the question, An sit? But what goes on? What precisely is that moment in your knowing? Where does it come from, and what does it lead to?
()
Again, we speak of weighing the evidence. I believe that my account of reflective understanding is, in different terms, but roughly equivalent to, what Newman calls the illative sense. Newman was concerned with that same problem, What's the ground of the assent? The ground of the assent is grasping the sufficiency of the evidence. I worked it into a formula for an insight, the virtually unconditioned, that eliminates the metaphors.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Form und Akt; Erkennbarkeit der Form, Form als Kern, Wirkursache; Akt zu Form wie Urteil zu Begriff

Kurzinhalt: Form is intelligible in itself. Contingent act, finite act, is not intelligible in itself. It is intelligible in the other; material essence is intelligible in itself because

Textausschnitt: Form is intelligible in itself. Contingent act, finite act, is not intelligible in itself. It is intelligible in the other. Existence and events are contingent; they're what corresponds to the proper content of judgment. The proper content of judgment depends upon a virtually unconditioned. A virtually unconditioned is what in fact is unconditioned - in fact has its conditions fulfilled. There's a limitation on the intelligibility there, and for that reason you are led to postulate efficient causes to account for contingent existence and contingent events.
()
Form is the nucleus. It's what we know insofar as we understand. But only an object that is exclusively form is totally intelligible in itself - an object, a reality, in which its form is also its act, by identity. Then you have total intelligibility in itself.
()
Form, where it's just a component of the real, is the nucleus of intelligibility intrinsic to that reality. Essence is intelligible in itself; material essence is intelligible in itself because, while essence includes both form and potency, or form and matter, and the matter or potency is not intelligible in itself, still it is intelligible in the form, and you've included the form in the essence.
()
Now just as the judgment of existence is related to the concept of essence, so existence is related to essence - there is an isomorphism.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Einsicht und visio beatifica

Kurzinhalt: Insight and the Beatific Vision; knowing the ens per essentiam is the beatific vision in Thomist theory

Textausschnitt: But what's behind my concept of the notion of being is this: once you set down, posit, that intellect is intelligence, that abstraction is an intelligent operation in which you omit the irrelevant and grasp the essential - such a notion of abstraction means that you cannot have an abstraction of a concept, being, because to have abstraction in that sense, you have to grasp the essence of being; and to grasp the essence of being you have to have the ens per essentiam as the object of your knowledge, and know that object by its essence. And knowing the ens per essentiam is the beatific vision in Thomist theory.
()
Just as in God essence and existence are identical, so in the beatific vision grasp of essence is also knowledge of existence.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Common sense als Spezialisierung des Verstehens

Kurzinhalt: Just as there are certain types of knowing that are no business of the chemist, but belong to the physicist, so common sense is another specialization of human understanding

Textausschnitt: And common sense is a specialization of knowledge. Just as there are certain types of knowing that are no business of the chemist, but belong to the physicist, and so on all along the line, so common sense is another specialization of human understanding. It's for dealing with the concrete in practical living. And the man of common sense de facto is guided by his judgment. If you stop him and ask him whether the real is what's already out there now, or what you know in a true judgment, he'll say, 'It's what's already out there now.' But then he's talking outside his specialty; you're asking him a philosophic question. If you ask him, ... But if you get commonsense people to do some commonsense action, you'll see that they use their judgment -when they're not sure, they hem and haw and avoid the issue, put it off, and so on.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Das Problem der Sozialwissenschaften

Kurzinhalt: Social Science; Unterschied zw. Der Erforschung eines Dinges oder Menschen; bei Ausschluss der Freiheit Rechtfertigung von Propaganda und psychologische konditionierung

Textausschnitt: I think so. The problem is that where your object is an empirically, intelligently, rationally conscious subject that develops in his intelligence and reasonableness, you're dealing with an entity that, even from the viewpoint of your scientific method, has to be approached in a manner essentially different from the study of atoms or plants or animals. And it's only insofar as the human sciences will be willing to expect some philosophic commitments or, on the other hand, be masters of all possible philosophic commitments that they'll be able to think on a level that is truly human in their human sciences.
()
But if he thinks of economic activity as predictable events in the same manner as the nineteenth-century physicists did, or as statistically probable events, he's dealing with an objective manifold, and his only way of dealing it will be through government, or through propaganda, or through psychological conditioning, or through the police state, or what you please. The link between the human science and its application will not be human; it will be subhuman. It's a problem of considerable dimensions - a number of dimensions that are all pretty enormous.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Aristoteles, Widerspruch in seinen Prinzipien; Physik; Unveränderbarkeit Gottes

Kurzinhalt: einerseits: Wissenschaft je nach den Ursachen; anderseits: Erklärung der Physik als Theorie der Bewegung -> unvollständige Verwirklichung der Kategorien (Ort, Qualität, Quantität)

Textausschnitt: I think that Aristotle in his Physics violated his own principles. He, or at least the Aristotelian corpus - it's very difficult to say what is from Aristotle - but in that body of writings he distinguished his predicaments from causes, and science is conceived in terms of causes. But Aristotle's Physics is fundamentally a theory of motion, and motion is defined as the incomplete realization of three of the predicaments.
()
Again, quality, or change of quality - what's called alteration, alloi-ôsis - is change in the sensibilia propria, in color, hot and cold, wet and dry, smooth and rough, and so on. What is 'becoming white'? Well, it's an incomplete realization of 'being white.' What is 'heating'? It's an incomplete realization of 'being hot, at a certain intensity of heat,' and so on. (366; Fs)
Similarly, for quantity.
()
The categories, the predicaments, form the basis, then, on which he develops his theory of motion. Science becomes not a reduction of reality to its causes - certain knowledge of things through their causes -but knowledge of things through the predicaments, so that science, instead of advancing from description to explanation in causes, starts circling around within the descriptive field.
()
The definitions I worked out, of potency, form, and act, are exactly what Aristotle uses in his psychology. Eye, sight, seeing, are potency, form, act. The capacity to will, habits of will, and acts of will are potency, form, act. The possible intellect, habits of intellect (the acquisition of a science), and acts of understanding are potency, form, act, again - all analogous to prime matter, substantial form, and existence. And that in Aristotle, I believe, survives, when systematically collected. But Aristotelian physics has doubled back on the descriptive element, and that's why it was a block to the development of science. And that's what sets the problem of just what kind of a department of philosophy cosmology is.
()
... there are other types of argument for that exclusion of change from God. If you have change, you have some sort of finality. You have some sort of potentiality, imperfection, some perfection to be acquired. And if you posit unlimited act, well, you're excluding the possibility of change in quite a different way from the argument from the supposition of matter. In other words, matter isn't the only type of potency. It's by the negation of potency, capacity for development, that you get the immutability of God.
()
I should qualify what I said before. If you conceive metaphysics in terms of necessity and impossibility, you haven't got from change a metaphysical argument. But if you conceive metaphysics, as I do, as what is true as a matter of fact in our knowledge - there are factual conditions for it - then metaphysics differs from physics, not in terms of necessity and impossibility, but on the level at which it considers the same reality.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Kant und die praktische Vernunft; Maréchal und Finalität

Kurzinhalt: falsche Erkenntnistheorie, doch hohe Moral: Stoa, Kant; so Kant can attribute validity to the ideas of reason from the viewpoint of action that he I cannot from the viewpoint of knowledge.

Textausschnitt: It is interesting to note that the stoics had a very elevated moral doctrine, while in their epistemology and their views of reality they were materialists. It illustrates the point that one can have self-appropriation and grasp its implications in the moral field and not do so in the more complicated field of cognitional theory and metaphysics.
()
In Kant, one has something similar: a theory of knowledge that excludes, to a great extent, knowledge of reality and, at the same time, an ethical doctrine of remarkable elevation.
()
In the Critique of Pure Reason the conditions for a possible experience are not the same as the conditions for a possible course of action. A possible course of action regards something in the future, something you are going to do, not something you know. The conditions are not exactly the same, and so Kant can attribute validity to the ideas of reason or the ideals of reason from the viewpoint of action that he I cannot from the viewpoint of knowledge.
()
But at least part of Maréchal's idea seems to have been that to introduce finality in the intellect would be to confer on speculative intellect the same type of validity that Kant acknowledges in practical intellect. But because of the role that Kant ascribes to intuition in knowledge, he cannot at the same time give primacy to judgment, and he cannot at the same time give primacy to a finalistic view of knowledge, namely, that knowledge is something we move towards, not something we build upon intuitions.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Leiden und Gerechtigkeit Gottes; Auferstehung

Kurzinhalt: In the death and resurrection of Christ we have the tremendous symbol of Christianity that interprets for us the meaning of life

Textausschnitt: In the death and resurrection of Christ we have the tremendous symbol of Christianity that interprets for us the meaning of life. The Christian knows that if the master has suffered, there is nothing incongruous in his own suffering; and he knows that as the master rose again, so the Father is able to transform, to make all things work unto the good. That understanding of the meaning of human life that is mediated to us through the death and resurrection of Christ, as through a symbol, an image, is something on which our intellectual and moral and spiritual lives can develop, and in their development see more and more of its profundity. And that is God's expression of himself to us.
()
As you see, the question of suffering, like all concrete existential questions, heads on to the religious, to the supernatural. Just as there is a self-appropriation that involves a development in us and implies a development in us - to be men - so the situation that is the human condition leads us on further to what we name the supernatural life, to a life in which God loves us in the full sense of love. Love involves a quasi identification. ... It presupposes an advance made by God as a lover, in the full sense of loving, and it means our response, and it means our response in which we love one another because we love God - and if we don't love one another we don't know God, in the words of St John's epistle

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Problem der Geschichte, der historische Jesus, Huizinga - Relativismus; Geschichte auf d. Ebene des Urteils

Kurzinhalt: Collingwood - Dedektivgeschichte mit falschen Zeugen; Exegeten: not seeking to arrive at truth, it is seeking to reconstitute the image of the past

Textausschnitt: illustrates his concept of history as science, at least one aspect of it, by a detective story in which all the clues were planted and all the witnesses were lying. The detective's problem was to find out what really happened by seeing why the clues would be planted and why the people were lying. In other words, ...
()
There can be false ideals in historical inquiry. German exegetes during the nineteenth century spent a great deal of time trying to reach the historical Jesus, to get behind the gospel to what really happened and what really was said, and they came to the conclusion that it couldn't be done. You can't reach the historical Jesus. ... It is not seeking to arrive at truth, it is seeking to reconstitute the image of the past, the cinema of the past, and the soundtrack of the past, where you haven't got the evidence for doing so. The astronomer
()
You can have history under a relativist influence ... and it was to the effect that history is a culture interpreting its past to itself, and the interpretation varies with the present, so that you have German history of, say, 1810, 1840, 1870, ..
()
Can there be an approach to history in terms of truth, the third level, judgment? I think that there can be. ... The fundamental problem is the problem of interpretation, and how you arrive at a correct interpretation. Insofar as there are counterpositions active and successful within the field of those writing history, insofar as most historians certainly would not be interested in any methodical discussion, this more or less puts the historians, the people who did the work, in the same class as the physicists who are very good at performing experiments but not so hot at the mathematics. A situation is created by quantum mechanics and relativity: the people who could do the experiments, for a while anyway, were complaining,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Objektivität und Isomorphismus; Grundfrage: Intelligibilität des Seins

Kurzinhalt: fundamental decision: Is or is not being intelligible? If it is not; Sorge - oder: this tiny little thread of the pure desire to know that is found in us at times; Beispiel: Fleischeternal light

Textausschnitt: I'm putting the cart before the horsec for people who know by taking a look!
There is a fundamental decision; you can't have it both ways. With regard to the precise issue: Is or is not being intelligible? If it is not, there is no reason for supposing that you could know it by understanding or by judgment, and, if it is something you can't know at all, then it is outside the field of possible questions or suspicions. It is nothing. Insofar as being is what is to be known by intelligent grasp and reasonable affirmation, then being is intelligible, because the intelligible is just what is grasped.
()
The 'real world' for people with that difficulty is what corresponds to one's Sorge, one's concern, and one's concern is not exclusively a matter of the pure desire to know. One's concern includes all of one's sensitivity, all of one's intersubjectivity, all of one's affectivity, and so on and so forth. It involves the whole man, not this tiny little thread of the pure desire to know that is found in us at times - when you do an awful lot of arguing and proving, then it's there. And that is what the real world corresponds to, and that real world is had by us in a more elevated fashion.
()
These things become clearer by taking a step further and going into the metaphysics. Why is it that our minds are capable, by understanding and judgment, of knowing what really is? It is because they are created participations of the uncreated light. St Augustine held that we knew truth not by looking outside us, but within, and not properly looking within but in a changeless light, an incommutable light, contemplating the eternal reasons. And St Thomas takes up this doctrine, which was current among Augustinians in the Middle Ages, and he says, 'Do we look at the eternal reasons? Do we judge things by the eternal reasons?' ... And, St Thomas says, we judge things by the eternal reasons not in the sense that we take a look at the eternal reasons, but in the sense that the very light of our intelligence is a created participation of the uncreated light that is God himself. Just as the uncreated light that is God himself is the ground of all possibility and actuality - it is a real omnipotence - so this created participation of the eternal light, that is our intelligence, that comes to light in intelligent and rational consciousness, is an intentional omnipotence, a capacity to ask questions about everything and, by understanding and forming concepts and making judgments, to know them.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Isomorphismus; Intelligens als Teilnahme (Partizipation) am ungeschaffenen Licht, Augustin, Thomas

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: These things become clearer by taking a step further and going into the metaphysics. Why is it that our minds are capable, by understanding and judgment, of knowing what really is? It is because they are created participations of the uncreated light. St Augustine held that we knew truth not by looking outside us, but within, and not properly looking within but in a changeless light, an incommutable light, contemplating the eternal reasons. And St Thomas takes up this doctrine, which was current among Augustinians in the Middle Ages, and he says, 'Do we look at the eternal reasons? Do we judge things by the eternal reasons?' ... And, St Thomas says, we judge things by the eternal reasons not in the sense that we take a look at the eternal reasons, but in the sense that the very light of our intelligence is a created participation of the uncreated light that is God himself. Just as the uncreated light that is God himself is the ground of all possibility and actuality - it is a real omnipotence - so this created participation of the eternal light, that is our intelligence, that comes to light in intelligent and rational consciousness, is an intentional omnipotence, a capacity to ask questions about everything and, by understanding and forming concepts and making judgments, to know them.
()
Let us try, therefore, to distinguish the different stages in this isomorphism. We have three levels in our cognitional process, an experiential, an intellectual, and a rational. And to take the simplest type of example, we will suppose that there does exist a perfect circle, and on the experiential level we see it, ...
()
Now we have three acts, or three levels of activity, and they presuppose one another -just as cooking the meat presupposes buying it, and eating it presupposes cooking it. These three levels are mutually related, and complementary
()
Now those three components are distinct as notions, they are notionally distinct. With regard to the three components as contents in my mind, you can say that P is not Q and P is not R and Q is not R, where P, Q, and R are these three, and you consider them as notions - there is a notional distinction, as contents in the mind. And the proof is that what is grasped here, what is grasped by insight, is intelligible in itself; the data are not intelligible in themselves, they are merely given, they are intelligible in the other. One and the same cannot have contradictory predicates. A cannot be both B and not-B. You cannot say the content 'data' and the content 'intelligible necessity' are really just one content with two predicates, two aspects, because the aspects are contradictory: one is intelligible in itself, the other is not, and intelligibility is a relevant predicate to these contents.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Spannung zw: Augustinus: mens, animus - anima (Aristoteles); Aristoteles: Potenz - Akt Objekt (Kausalität, nicht Interiorität)

Kurzinhalt: De anima; Seele - Potenz - Akt - Objekt; our immediate concern is to find in Aristotle the point of insertion for Augustinian thought; bei Aristo. u. Thomas: introspective skills

Textausschnitt: The Aristotelian framework was impressive. First, it was a general theory of being, a metaphysics. Secondly, it was a general theory of movement, a physics in that now antiquated sense. Thirdly, it was a general theory of life, a biology. Fourthly, it was a general theory of sensitivity and intelligence, a psychology.
()
The interlocking of each part with all the others precluded the possibility of merely patchwork revisions. As Professor Butterfield has observed, to correct Aristotle effectively, one must go beyond him; and to go beyond him is to set up a system equal in comprehensiveness and more successful in inner coherence and in conformity with fact. Still, such attempts have been made and, indeed, in two quite different manners.
()
It is not difficult to discern. I distinguished above four components in the Aristotelian framework. I must hasten to add that, in a sense, the distinction between the third and fourth, between biology and psychology, is not as clear, as sharp, as fully developed as may be desired. ... At the same time, it fails to bring out effectively the essential difference between an investigation of plant life and an investigation of the human mind ...
()
Souls are differentiated by their potencies; potencies are known by their acts; acts are specified by their objects. But what is meant by an object? That is the decisive question. For the meaning given the term 'object' will settle the specification given acts; the specification of acts will settle the distinction between potencies; and the distinction between potencies will settle the essential differences between the souls of plants, animals, and men.
()
A modern reader is apt to take it for granted that by an object Aristotle must mean the intentional term of a conscious act. But quite evidently Aquinas was of a different opinion. In his commentary he defines objects in terms, not of intentionality, but of causality:
()
If vegetative acts are not accessible to introspection, sensitive and intellectual acts are among the immediate data of consciousness; they can be reached not only by deduction from their objects but also in themselves as given in consciousness. Finally, when conscious acts are studied by introspection, one discovers not only the acts and their intentional terms but also the intending subject, and there arises the problem of the relation of subject to soul, of the Augustinian mens or animus to the Aristotelian anima.
()
As we shall see, Aquinas explicitly appealed to inner experience and, I submit, Aristotle's account of intelligence, of insight into phantasm, and of the fact that intellect knows itself, not by a species of itself, but by a species of its object, has too uncanny an accuracy to be possible without the greatest introspective skill. But if Aristotle and Aquinas used introspection and did so brilliantly, it remains that they did not thematize their use, did not elevate it into a reflectively elaborated technique, did not work out a proper method for psychology, and thereby lay the groundwork for the contemporary distinctions between nature and spirit and between the natural and the human sciences.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Die Bedeutung des Wortes (verbum) bei Augustin; Ausdruck des Wissens des Geistes um sich selbst; Stoa: verbum insitum, prolatum; verbum intus prolatum

Kurzinhalt: Augustinus, verbum prolatum, verbum insitum, verbum intus prolatum; verbum verum de re vera, nihil de suo habens ..., what his own mind knew immediately about itself

Textausschnitt: 10/I It is time to turn to Augustine: a convert from nature to spirit; a person that, by God's grace, made himself what he was; a subject that may be studied but, most of all, must be encounteredd in the outpouring of his self-revelation and self-communication. The context of his thought on verbum was trinitarian, and its underlying preoccupation was anti-Arian. It followed that the prologue to the fourth Gospel had to be freed from any Arian implication. To achieve this end Augustine did not employ our contemporary techniques of linguistic and literary history. He did not attempt a fresh translation of the Greek word logos, but retained the traditional verbum. Church tradition, perhaps, precluded any appeal to the Stoic distinction between verbum prolatum and verbum insitum.1 In any case he cut between these Stoic terms to discover a third verbum that was neither the verbum prolatum of human speech nor the verbum insitum of man's native rationality but an intermediate verbum intus prolatum. Naturally enough, as Augustine's discovery was part and parcel of his own mind's knowledge of itself, so he begged his readers to look within themselves and there to discover the speech of spirit within spirit, an inner verbum prior to any use of language, yet distinct both from the mind itself and from its memory or its present apprehension of objects. (6; Fs) (notabene)

11/I Though I cannot attempt here to do justice to the wealth of Augustine's thought or to the variety of its expression,2 at least it will serve to illustrate my meaning if, however arbitrarily, I select and briefly comment on a single passage. (7; Fs)

Haec igitur omnia, et quae per se ipsum, et quae per sensus sui corporis, et quae testimoniis aliorum percepta scit animus humanus, thesauro memoriae condita tenet, ex quibus gignitur verbum verum, quando quod scimus loquimur, sed verbum ante omnem sonum, ante omnem cogitationem soni. Tunc enim est verbum simillimum rei notae, de qua gignitur, et imago eius, quoniam de visione scientiae visio cogitationis exoritur, quod est verbum linguae nullius, verbum verum de re vera, nihil de suo habens, sed totum de ilia scientia de qua nascitur. Nec interest quando id didicerit, qui quod scit loquitur (aliquando enim statim ut discit, hoc dicit), dum tamen verbum sit verum, id est, de notis rebus exortum.3

FN 8:
['All these things, therefore, those perceived (by the human mind) through itself, and those perceived through the senses of its body, and those perceived by the witness of others, all these things which the human mind knows, it holds firmly established in the treasury of memory; from these is brought forth a true word when we utter what we know, but a word that is before all sound, (indeed) before all thought of sound. For then a word is most like the known thing from which it is brought forth and most an image of that thing, since from the vision of knowledge a vision of thought arises, which is a word of no language, a true word of a true thing, having nothing of its own, but everything from that knowledge from which it is born. Nor does it matter when the one who utters what he knows learned it - for sometimes he speaks as soon as he learns - provided however that the word is true, that is, having its origin in things known'] Augustine, De trinitate, XV, xii, 22; ML 42, 1075. [We add an English translation of Latin words and phrases in Lonergan's next paragraph: linguae nullius, of no language; gignitur, is brought forth; nascitur, is born; nihil de suo habens, having nothing of its own; sed totum de illa scientia de qua nascitur, but everything from that knowledge from which it is born; quod scimus loquimur, we utter what we know; de visione scientiae visio cogitationis exoritur, from the vision of knowledge a vision of thought arises; qui quod scit loquitur, who utters what he knows; verbum simillimum rei notae, a word most like the known thing; imago eius, an image of [that thing]; verbum verum de re vera, a true word of a true thing; dum tamen verbum sit verum, id est, de notis rebus exortum, provided however that the word is true, that is, having its origin in things known.] (notabene)

12/I In this passage, then, the Augustinian verbum is a nonlinguistic utterance of truth. It differs from expression in any language, for it is linguae nullius. It is not primitive but derived: gignitur, exoritur, nascitur. Its dependence is total: nihil de suo habens, sed totum de illa scientia de qua nascitur. This total dependence is, not blind or automatic, but conscious and cognitive: quod scimus loquimur; de visione scientiae visio cogitationis exoritur; qui quod scit loquitur. Finally, this total dependence as conscious and known is the essential point. It makes no difference whether the verbum has its ground in memory or in recently acquired knowledge. What counts is its truth, its correspondence with things as known: verbum simillimum rei notae; imago eius; verbum verum de re vera, nihil de suo habens, sed totum de illa scientia de qua nascitur; dum tamen verbum sit verum, id est, de notis rebus exortum. (7f; Fs)

13/I Such, at least in one passage, is what Augustine had to say about verbum. Many more passages might be cited, and they would reveal him saying different things or the same things in a different manner. But sooner or later it would be necessary to advance from the simpler question of what he said to the more difficult question of what he meant. Since I am writing not a study of Augustine but an introduction to a study of Aquinas, I must leap at once to the more difficult question, though not to answer it in detail, but only to indicate the source from which the answer must proceed. (8; Fs)

14/I A blind man may listen to a disquisition on color, but he is bound to find it obscure. A person who is deaf may read a book on music, but he will have a hard time deciding whether the author is talking sense or nonsense. In similar fashion it is only by introspection that one can discover what an introspective psychologist is talking about. If what Augustine had to say about verbum was true, then it corresponded exactly to what Augustine knew went on in his own mind. If what Augustine had to say about verbum was universally true, then it corresponds exactly to what Augustine knew goes on in any human mind. If one supposes Augustine to be right and, at the same time, entertains an admiration for Newman, one is going to ask whether the Augustinian couplet of memoria and verbum is parallel to Newman's couplet of illative sense and unconditional assent.e But if one desires to get beyond words and suppositions to meanings and facts, then one has to explore one's own mind and find out for oneself what there is to be meant; and until one does so, one is in the unhappy position of the blind man hearing about colors and the deaf man reading about counterpoint. (8; Fs)

15/I About such matters Augustine was explicit. Unde enim mens aliquam mentem novit, si se non novit? Neque enim ut oculus corporis videt alias oculos et se non videt... Mens ergo ipsa sicut corporearum rerum notitias per sensus corporis colligit, sic incorporearum per semetipsam. Ergo et semetipsam per se ipsam novit...4 (8; Fs)
FN: ['For whence does the mind know some (other) mind, if it does not know itself? Nor (does it see) the way the eye of the body sees other eyes and does not see itself... Our mind itself therefore, as it gathers knowledge of corporeal things through the senses of the body, so also (does it gather knowledge) of incorporeal things through itself. Therefore it knows itself too through itself] Ibid. IX, iii, 3; ML 42, 962 f.

16/I Moreover, for Augustine, the mind's self-knowledge was basic; it was the rock of certitude on which shattered Academic doubt; it provided the ground from which one could argue to the validity both of the senses of one's own body and, with the mediation of testimony, of the senses of the bodies of others. So the passage we have quoted and explained begins with this threefold enumeration: quae per se ipsum, et quae per sensus sui corporis, et quae testimoniis aliorum percepta scit animus humanus. The enumeration merely summarizes what had been set forth at greater length in the immediately preceding paragraph;5 and that paragraph, of course, only resumes a theme that is recurrent from Augustine's earliest writings on. (9; Fs)

FN: Ibid. XV, xii, 21; ML 42, 1073-75. [Translation of Latin in text: 'those things which the human mind perceives through itself, and those it perceives through the senses of its body, and those it perceives by the witness of others, all these things which the human mind knows']

17/I Clearly enough, it was neither per sensus sui corporis nor by alienorum corporum sensus that Augustine knew of a verbum that was neither Latin nor Greek, neither sound nor even the thought of sound. The Augustinian affirmation of verbum was itself a verbum. For it to be true, on Augustine's own showing, it had to be totally dependent on what Augustine's mind knew through itself about itself. On the existence and nature of such knowledge Augustine had a great deal to say, and there is no need for us to attempt to repeat it here. Though it cannot be claimed that Augustine elevated introspection into a scientific technique, it cannot be doubted that he purported to report in his literary language what his own mind knew immediately about itself. (9; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: verbum bei Thomas im Zusammenhang von Lonergans Buch

Kurzinhalt: Thomas in der Tradition von Augustinus und Aristoteles; Gliederung des Buches entsprechend der Bedeutung von verbum bei Thomas; quid sit, an sit

Textausschnitt: So we come to Aquinas. Because he conceived theology as in some sense a science, he needed Aristotle, who more than anyone had worked out and applied the implications of the Greek ideal of science. Because his theology was essentially the expression of a traditional faith, he needed Augustine, the Father of the West, whose trinitarian thought was the high-water mark in Christian attempts to reach an understanding of faith. Because Aquinas himself was a genius, he experienced no great difficulty either in adapting Aristotle to his purpose or in reaching a refinement in his account of rational process - the emanatio intelligibilis - that made explicit what Augustine could only suggest. Because, finally, Aquinas was a man of his time,
()
The first two chapters are concerned with the core of psychological fact. Aquinas identified verbum with the immanent terminal object of intellectual operation; he distinguished two intellectual operations, a first in answer to the question quid sit, and a second in answer to the question an sit.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: inneres Wort: Wirkursache (causa efficiens) -> äußeres Worte; Syllogismus: inneres, vorgestelltes, äußeres Wort

Kurzinhalt: Gegensatz und Beziehung zw.: inner - outer word, inner word is an efficient cause of the outer, the inner word is what can be meant (significabile) or what is meant (significatum) by outer words, and inversely ...

Textausschnitt: 6/1 The first element in the general notion of an inner word is had from a contrast with outer words - spoken, written, imagined, or meant. Spoken words are sounds with a meaning: as sounds, they are produced in the respiratory tract; as possessing a meaning, they are due to imagination according to Aristotle, or, as Aquinas seems to have preferred, to soul; it is meaning that differentiates spoken words from other sounds, such as coughing, which also are produced in the respiratory tract.1 Written words are simply signs of spoken words;2 the issue was uncomplicated by Chinese ideograms. A similar simplicity is the refreshing characteristic of the account of imaginatio vocis:3 a term that seems to embrace the whole mnemonic mass and sensitive mechanism of motor, auditory, and visual images connected with language. Finally, the outer word that is some external thing or action meant by a word is dismissed as a mere figure of speech.4 (14; Fs)

7/1 There is a twofold relation between inner and outer words: the inner word is an efficient cause of the outer; and the inner word is what is meant immediately by the outer. The aspect of efficient causality seems to be the only one noticed in the commentary on the Sentences: the inner word is compared to the major premise of a syllogism; the imagined word to the minor premise; and the spoken word to the conclusion.5 Later works do not deny this aspect6 but I think I may say that subsequently the whole emphasis shifted to the second of the two relations mentioned above. Repeatedly one reads that the inner word is what can be meant (significabile) or what is meant (significatum) by outer words, and inversely, that the outer word is what can mean (significativum) or what does mean (significant) the inner word.7 (14f; Fs)

8/1 There is no doubt about this matter, though, frankly, it is just the opposite of what one would expect. One is apt to think of the inner word, not as what is meant by the outer, but as what means the outer; the outer word has meaning in virtue of the inner; therefore, the inner is meaning essentially while the outer has meaning by participation. That is all very true, and St Thomas knew it.8 But commonly he asked what outer words meant and answered that, in the first instance, they meant inner words. The proof was quite simple. We discourse on 'man' and on the 'triangle.' What are we talking about? Certainly, we are not talking about real things directly, else we should all be Platonists. Directly, we are talking about objects of thought, inner words, and only indirectly, only insofar as our inner words have an objective reference, are we talking of real things.9 The same point might be made in another fashion. Logical positivists to the contrary, false propositions are not meaningless; they mean something; what they mean is an inner word, and only because that inner word is false, does the false proposition lack objective reference.10 (15; Fs)

9/1 Such is the first element in the general notion of an inner word. It is connected with the well-known anti-Platonist thesis on abstraction that the mode of knowing need not be identical with the mode of reality, that knowledge may be abstract and universal though all realities are particular and concrete. It also is connected with the familiar Aristotelian statement that 'bonum et malum sunt in rebus, sed verum et falsum sunt in mente.'11 Because outer words may be abstract, and true or false, because real things are neither abstract nor true nor false, the immediate reference of their meaning is to an inner word. (15f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: 7 Elemente: general notion - inneres Wortes

Kurzinhalt: Verhältnis zw. innerem u. äußerem Wort; Einteilung des inneren Wortes keine point-to-point correspondence; wie Funktion zum Abhängigen; Urteil, Begriff; Vergleich mit Erfinder

Textausschnitt: Aquinas, in his commentary, denied a point-to-point correspondence between inner and outer words, arguing that inner words correspond to realities, while outer words are the products of convention and custom, and so vary with different peoples. However, since the inner word is in the intellect, and since apprehension of the singular involves the use of a sensitive potency it should seem that the correspondence of realities to inner words is, at best, like the correspondence between a function and its derivative; as the derivative, so the inner word is outside all particular cases and refers to all from some higher viewpoint.
()
A third element in fixing the nature of the inner word is connected intimately with the preceding. What is the division of inner words? On this question, four major works of Aquinas and a large number of his commentators are silent. On the other hand, silence is no argument against positive statement. Four other works of recognized standing divide inner words into the two classes of definitions and judgments, and three of these recall the parallel of the Aristotelian twofold operation of the mind ... This clearly supposes that the judgment is an inner word, for only in the judgment is there truth or falsity. ... Finally, as stated above, the correspondence of inner words is mainly, not to outer words, but to reality; but reality divides into essence and existence; and of the two Aristotelian operations of the mind 'prima operatic respicit quidditatem rei; secunda respicit esse ipsius.
()
A fourth element in the general notion of an inner word is that it supplies the object of thought. What is abstract, what is true or false is not, as such, either a real thing or a mere copy of a real thing. It is a product of the mind. It is not merely a product but also a known product; and as known, it is an object. The illuminating parallel is from technical invention. ... there is the same general form of intellectual process, for in both certain general principles are known, in both a determinate end is envisaged, in both the principles are applied to the attainment of the end, and in both this application leads to a plan of operations that as such is, not knowing what is, but only knowing the idea of what one may do.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Lonergans "dritter" Weg der Erkenntnis, nichtrationale Erklärung d. Wirklichkeit: Empirist, Sensist, Positivist, Pragmatist, Idealist

Kurzinhalt: in und durch dem Intellekt kommt es zur Erkenntnis von Dingen, Erkennen: Tier, Mensch; accept the sense of reality as criterion of reality, and you are a materialist, ... accept reason as a criterion but retain

Textausschnitt: A fifth element in the general notion of an inner word is that in it and through it intellect comes to knowledge of things. ... Take it as knowledge of reality, and there results the secular contrast between the solid sense of reality and the bloodless categories of the mind. Accept the sense of reality as criterion of reality, and you are a materialist, sensist, positivist, pragmatist, sentimentalist, and so on, as you please. Accept reason as a criterion but retain the sense of reality as what gives meaning to the term 'real,' and you are an idealist; for, like the sense of reality, the reality defined by it is nonrational. Insofar as I grasp it, the Thomist position is the clearheaded third position: reason is the criterion and, as well, it is reason - not the sense of reality - that gives meaning to the term 'real.' The real is what is; and 'what is' is known in the rational act, judgment.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Zweifache Tätigkeit des Intellekts; Idee als Gewusstes und Medium des Wissens

Kurzinhalt: quod quid est, to ti estin; Belege durch Thomas

Textausschnitt: The first act of intellect is knowledge of the quod quid est, to ti estin, the 'What is it?' By definition, this knowledge involves neither truth nor falsity, ...
()
On the other hand, the second operation of intellect ... introduces the duality of idea and thing and makes the former the medium in and through which one apprehends the latter. Thus, our knowledge of God's existence is just our knowledge of the truth of the judgment 'Deus est.' ... For just as the inner word is a medium between the meaning of outer words and the realities meant, so also the inner word is a medium between the intellect and the things that are understood.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Aristoteles, Syllogismus, Mondphasen
Syllogismus, middle term, Mondphasen

Kurzinhalt: Die Mondphasen als Mittelterm, der Mond als Subjekt, die Kugel als Prädikat

Textausschnitt: The phases are the causa cognoscendi of the sphericity of the moon; we know the moon is a sphere because it goes through these phases. If it were just a disc the whole circle would always be illuminated; because it has a spherical surface, we see its phases. The phases are the middle term; the moon, the subject; sphericity, the predicate. In that case, syllogism expresses an insight. But syllogism is relevant to the third level, as exhibiting the virtually unconditioned. Syllogism is an expression of the idea of validity; the idea of the virtually unconditioned connects judgment with the absolute.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Aristoteles, Mondphasen, Syllogismus

Kurzinhalt: What is an eclipse of the moon?' and 'Why is the moon thus darkened?' are, not two questions, but one and the same

Textausschnitt: Again, to take Aristotle's stock example, 'What is an eclipse of the moon?' and 'Why is the moon thus darkened?' are, not two questions, but one and the same. Say that the earth intervenes between the sun and the moon, blocking off the light received by the latter from the former, and at once you know why the moon is thus darkened, and what an eclipse is. The second and fourth questions, then, ask about causes; but a cause supplies the middle term in the scientific syllogism; and if the cause exists, its consequent necessarily exists. Hence, all four questions are questions about the middle terms of scientific syllogisms. The first and third ask whether there is a relevant middle term; the second and fourth ask what the relevant middle term is.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Lonergan, was ist X;

Kurzinhalt: (1) whether there is an X, or (2) what is an X, or (3) whether X is Y, or (4) why X is Y. Meno; Grasping the cause is, not an ocular vision, but an insight into the sensible data

Textausschnitt: The superficial eye will pair off the first two questions together and the last two; but the significant parallel is between the first and the third, and between the second and the fourth. In modern language the first and third are empirical questions: they ask about matters of fact; they can be answered by an appeal to observation or experiment. But the fourth question is not empirical; it asks for a cause or reason; and, at least in some cases, the second question is identical with the fourth, and hence it too is not empirical, but likewise asks for a cause or reason. Thus, 'Why does light refract?' and 'What is refraction?' are, not two questions, but one and the same. Again, to take Aristotle's stock example, 'What is an eclipse of the moon?' and 'Why is the moon thus darkened?' are, not two questions, but one and the same. Say that the earth intervenes between the sun and the moon, blocking off the light received by the latter from the former, and at once you know why the moon is thus darkened, and what an eclipse is. The second and fourth questions, then, ask about causes; but a cause supplies the middle term in the scientific syllogism; and if the cause exists, its consequent necessarily exists. Hence, all four questions are questions about the middle terms of scientific syllogisms. The first and third ask whether there is a relevant middle term; the second and fourth ask what the relevant middle term is.
()
But this answer only raises a further question. Granted that we know what is meant by 'What is X?' when that question can be recast into an equivalent 'Why V [sic] is X?' yet one may ask, quite legitimately, whether there always is a V. It is simple enough to substitute 'Why does light refract?' for 'What is refraction?' But tell me, please, what I am to substitute for 'What is a man?' or 'What is a house?'
()
In the Posterior Analytics he remarked that, if a man were on the moon during its eclipse, he would not have to ask the first question - whether there is an eclipse - for the fact would be obvious; moreover, he would not even have to ask the second question - what an eclipse is - for that too would be obvious; he would see the earth cutting in between the sun and himself, and so at once would grasp the cause and the universal. Grasping the cause is, not an ocular vision, but an insight into the sensible data. Grasping the universal is the production of the inner word that expresses that insight.
()
And, Aquinas explains, if one reached the universal from such brief acquaintance, that would be a matter of conjecturing that eclipses of the moon always occurred in that fashion.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Was ist ein Mensch, Transformation der Frage: klarere Sicht bei Thomas

Kurzinhalt: Umwandlung der 2. in die 4. Frage; What is a man?' = 'Why is V a man?; Sinn: Subjekt - Einsicht in Daten: Mittelterm - Begriff: Prädikat; causa essendi, Formalursache;

Textausschnitt: ... how to transform questions of the second type into questions of the fourth type in such ultimate and simple cases as, What is a man? What is a house? The clue lies in the fact of insight into sensible data. For an insight, an act of understanding, is a matter of knowing a cause. Presumably, in ultimate and simple cases, the insight is the knowledge of a cause that stands between the sensible data and the concept whose definition is sought. Though Aristotle's predecessors knew little of such a cause - for the cause in question is the formal cause - Aristotle himself made it a key factor in his system; and it was to the formal cause that he appealed when, in the Metaphysics, he attempted to settle the meaning of such questions as, What is a man? What is a house? The meaning is, Why is this sort of body a man? Why are stones and bricks, arranged in a certain way, a house? What is it that causes the matter, sensibly perceived, to be a thing? To Scholastics the answers are self-evident. That which makes this type of body to be a man is a human soul. That which makes these stones and bricks to be a house is an artificial form. That which makes matter, in general, to be a thing is the causa essendi, the formal cause.
()
'What is a man?' is equivalent to 'Why is V a man?' - where V stands for the sensible data of a man, and the answer is the formal cause, the soul. Now this does not imply that one is to answer the question, What is a man? by the proposition, A man is his soul. That answer is patently false. The formal cause is only part of the whole, and part can never be predicated of the whole. The fallacy that leads to this false conclusion is that, while we have transposed 'What is X?' into 'Why V is X?' we have yet to transpose the formal cause, which answers 'Why V is X?' back to the answer of 'What is X?' That transposition is from formal cause to essence or quiddity. Neglect of this second transposition by Aristotle has led to considerable obscurity: for among the meanings of 'substance' Aristotle will write the causa essendi, the to ti en einai, the form. Very accurately Aquinas hit upon the root of the confusion: 'Essentia enim et forma in hoc conveniunt quod secundum utrumque dicitur esse illud quo aliquid est. Sed forma refertur ad materiam, quam facit esse in actu; quidditas autem refertur ad suppositum, quod significatur ut habens talem essentiam.' Questions of the second type ask about the suppositum: for example, What is a man? Transposed to the fourth type, they ask about the matter: for example, Why is this type of body a man? Common to both questions is inquiry into the quo aliquid est, which, relative to the matter, is the form, but relative to the suppositum, is the essence, that is, the form plus the common matter.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Beschränkung des Traktats in der Behandlung des Menschen

Kurzinhalt: Wiederum: kurze Zusammenfassung im Kontext des: jetzt schon da draußen; die logische stringente Art des Traktates wird der Erfassung des Menschen nicht gerecht

Textausschnitt: Noch weitere Einschränkungen treten zutage, wenn wir uns der menschlichen Ebene zuwenden. Zu den Komplexitäten der genetischen Methode kommen hier die noch schwerer wiegenden Komplexitäten der dialektischen Methode. Um die Sache zu vereinfachen, haben wir unsere philosophische Position in den Termini eines einfachen Gegensatzes ausgearbeitet: Entweder ist das Reale das Sein, oder es ist eine Unterabteilung des "jetzt schon da draußen"; entweder wird die Objektivität durch intelligente Untersuchung und kritische Reflexion erreicht, oder sie ist eine Sache des genauen Hinschauens auf das, was "da draußen" ist; entweder besteht das Erkennen in einem Aufstieg von der Erfahrungsebene zur Ebene des Verstehens und Formulierens und weiter zur Ebene des reflektierenden Erfassens und Urteilens, oder aber ist sie ein unaussprechbares Gegenübertreten, das das Erkannte dem Erkennenden gegenwärtig macht.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Isomorphie in Metaphysik und Logik; Logik als Wissenschaft

Kurzinhalt: Metaphysik: Isomorphie der Strukturen von Erkenntnis und proportioniertem Sein; Logik: Parallele zwischen den Bedingungen der Erkenntnis und den Bedingungen der möglichen Termini der Bedeutung

Textausschnitt: Derart sind also die Einschränkungen des Traktates, und sie offenbaren recht überzeugend die Wichtigkeit einer Unterscheidung zwischen Logik als Wissenschaft und Logik als Technik. Die Logik als Wissenschaft kann aus der Erkenntnisanalyse abgeleitet werden. So wie die Metaphysik auf dem Obersatz der Isomorphie der Strukturen von Erkenntnis und proportioniertem Sein beruht, so beruht die Logik auf dem Obersatz der Parallele zwischen den Bedingungen der Erkenntnis und den Bedingungen der möglichen Termini der Bedeutung. So sind die Termini möglicher Bedeutung den Prinzipien der Identität und des Nicht-Widerspruchs unterworfen, weil das Urteil ein innerlich rationaler Akt ist, der bejaht oder verneint.
()
Schließlich, der Grund des Urteils im reflektierenden Erfassen des virtuell Unbedingten offenbart die ganz verschiedene Basis der gültigen Ableitung, die von der Form "Wenn 577 A, dann B; aber A; deshalb B" ist, wobei A und B Aussagen oder Sätze von Aussagen sind.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Materialist; Leugnung der Existenz der Seele; Leugnung der Objektivität des Intelligiblen

Kurzinhalt: ... for the denial of soul today is really the denial of the objectivity of the intelligible, the denial that understanding, knowing a cause, is knowing anything real.
leer leerleer

Textausschnitt: 36/1 For the materialist, the real is what he knows before he understands or thinks: it is the sensitively integrated object that is reality for a dog; it is the sure and firm-set earth on which I tread, which is so reassuring to the sense of reality; and on that showing, intellect does not penetrate to the inwardness of things but is a merely subjective, if highly useful, principle of activity. To the Pythagoreans the discovery of harmonic ratios revealed that numbers and their proportions, though primarily ideas, nonetheless have a role in making things what they are; and for Aristotle the ratio of two to one was the form of the diaposon.1 Socratic interest in definition reinforced this tendency,2 but the Platonist sought the reality known by thought, not in this world, but in another. (33; Fs) (notabene)

37/1 Aristotle's basic thesis was the objective reality of what is known by understanding: it was a commonsense position inasmuch as common sense always assumes that to be so; but it was not a commonsense position inasmuch as common sense would not be ablej to enunciate it or even to know with any degree of accuracy just what it means and implies. Aristotle is the representative of unconscious common sense; but conscious common sense found voice in the eminent Catholic doctor and professor of philosophy whom I heard ask, 'Will someone please tell me what all this fuss is about ens?' When, then, Aristotle calls the soul a logos, he is stating his highly original position, not indeed with the full accuracy which his thought alone made possible, but in a generic fashion which suited his immediate purpose; and it is that generic issue that remains the capital issue, for the denial of soul today is really the denial of the objectivity of the intelligible, the denial that understanding, knowing a cause, is knowing anything real. (33f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Einsicht verhält sich zum Phantasma wie Form zu Materie

Kurzinhalt: Einsicht erfasst das Objekt; von hier aus eröffnet sich der Weg zur philosophischen Form

Textausschnitt: ... the essential definition proceeds from an act of understanding; the real thing is what it is because form has actuated matter. The Aristotelian term T2 was a logical effort to isolate understanding and form, and one has only to consider the difficulties of such isolation to grasp why Aquinas dropped this Aristotelian effort as abortive and proceeded on lines of his own. Because the act of understanding - the intelligere proprie - is prior to, and cause of, conceptualization, because expression is only through conceptualization, any attempt to fix the act of understanding, except by way of introspective description, involves its own partial failure; for any such attempt is an expression, and expression is no longer understanding and already concept. Again, in a sense, the act of understanding as an insight into phantasm is knowledge of form: but the form so known does not correspond to the philosophic concept of form;n insight is to phantasm as form is to matter; but in that proportion, form is related to prime matter, but insight is related to sensible qualities; strictly, then, it is not true that insight is grasp of form; rather, insight is the grasp of the object in an inward aspect such that the mind, pivotingo on the insight, is able to conceive, not without labor, the philosophic concepts of form and matter. (38; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Einsicht in Phantasma als erster Teil des Prozesses hin zur wesentlichen Definition

Kurzinhalt: Erfahrung: Einsicht in Phantasma; Scotus, Kant: Leugnung dieser Sicht

Textausschnitt: Insight into phantasm is the first part of the process that moves from sense through understanding to essential definition. Though Aquinas derived the doctrine from Aristotle, he also affirmed it as a matter of experience: 'Quilibet in se ipso experiri potest, quod quando aliquis conatur aliquid intelligere, format sibi aliqua phantasmata per modum exemplorum, in quibus quasi inspiciat quod intelligere studet.' However, to many profound minds, so brief a description seems to have been insufficient. Scotus flatly denied the fact of insight into phantasm.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: phantasma; Unterschied zwischen Lernen und wissenschaftlicher Tätigkeit; Prozess von Sinneserfahrung, über Gedächtnis ...

Kurzinhalt: phantasm has to produce the act of insight whereas ... Prozess: Sinne, Gedächtnis, Erfahrung; Thomas: Erkennen des Universalen im Sinn; Intellect: nicht nur Erkennen des Universalen

Textausschnitt: The difference between invention or learning and use of science is that, in the first instance, phantasm has to produce the act of insight whereas, in subsequent instances, informed intellect guides the production of an appropriate phantasm; in other words, in the first instance we are at the mercy of fortune, the subconscious, or a teacher's skill, for the emergence of an appropriate phantasm; we are in a ferment of trying to grasp we know not what; but once we have understood, then we can operate on our own, marshaling images to a habitually known end.
()
Though theoretical science proceeds from principles known of themselves, yet these principles are obtained from sense, as explained in the second book of the Posterior Analytics. There the account is of a process from many sensations to a memory, from many memories to an element of experience, and from many elements of experience to grasp of a universal.
()
Aquinas, at least when commenting on Aristotle, could affirm the necessity of some knowledge of the universal in sense ... This position is impossible if one defines intellect as that which alone knows the universal; it is inevitable if by intellect one means the faculty which is subject of acts of intelligence, understanding, etc.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Intellekt als intellect-in-process; Einsicht der Engel; Aristoteles: verschiedene Substanzen; Thomas: Einsicht der Engel,

Kurzinhalt: Abhängigkeit des Intellekts vom Phantasma: contra Kant; Platon, Aristoteles: Extrapolation; aristotelische und thomistische Theorie des Intellekts: verschiedene Substanzen - Engel

Textausschnitt: This dependence of human intellect on sense for its object and for the preparatory elaboration of its object implies that human intellect is essentially intellect-in-process or reason. We do have occasional flashes of insight; but angelic, and still more, divine knowledge is exclusively that sort of thing, a continuous blaze of the light of understanding. ... Hence the theory of innate ideas - and, one may add, of Kantian a priori forms - contradicts the experience we all have of working from, and on, a sensible basis towards understanding.
()
As soon as Aristotle arrived at the meaning of the question, What is a man? he immediately concluded that the separate substances must be objects of a different type of knowledge and inquiry. The Platonist extrapolation to higher regions was modeled on the universal concept, and Aristotle rightly criticized the anthropomorphism of such a procedure. Aristotle's own extrapolation is not from universal concepts, but from the act of insight: ... Thus the pure Aristotelian theory of intellect is to be sought in the Aristotelian account of his separate substances ... Similarly, the pure Thomist theory of intellect is to be sought in the Thomist account of angelic knowledge, and from that account J. Peghaire rightly begins his investigation of Thomist notions of intellect and reason.
Now, just as human intellect is mainly reason, because it operates from sense as a starting point, so the quiddity known by the human intellect is different in kind from that known by the angelic. The angel has no senses, and so his acts of understanding cannot be insights into sensibly represented data

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Emanatio Intelligibilis; Unterschied zwischen dem Hervorgehen des inneren Wortes und dem nat. Werden

Kurzinhalt: emanatio intelligibilis; 3 Unterschiede: Potentialität - reine Intelligibilität

Textausschnitt: 54/1 The procession of the inner word, we are told, is an emanatio intelligibilis. This brings us to our main point. All causation is intelligible, but there are three differences between natural process and the procession of an inner word. The intelligibility of natural process is passive and potential: it is what can be understood; it is not an understanding; it is a potential object of intellect, but it is not the very stuff of intellect. Again, the intelligibility of natural process is the intelligibility of some specific natural law, say, the law of inverse squares, but never the intelligibility of the very idea of intelligible law. Thirdly, the intelligibility of natural process is imposed from without: natures act intelligibly, not because they are intelligent, for they are not, but because they are concretions of divine ideas and a divine plan.
()
On the other hand, the intelligibility of the procession of an inner word is not passive nor potential; it is active and actual; it is intelligible because it is the activity of intelligence in act; it is intelligible, not as the possible object of understanding is intelligible, but as understanding itself and the activity of understanding is intelligible. Again, its intelligibility defies formulation in any specific law; inner words proceed according to the principles of identity,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Der menschliche Verstand als Bild, nicht bloß als Spur der Trinität

Kurzinhalt: because its processions are intelligible in a manner that is essentially different from ... other natural process

Textausschnitt: Now it is only to restate the basic contention of this and subsequent articles to observe that the human mind is an image, and not a mere vestige, of the Blessed Trinity because its processions are intelligible in a manner that is essentially different from, that transcends, the passive, specific, imposed intelligibility of other natural process. Any effect has a sufficient ground in its cause; but an inner word not merely has a sufficient ground in the act of understanding it expresses; it also has a knowing as sufficient ground, and that ground is operative precisely as a knowing, knowing itself to be sufficient. To introduce a term that will summarize this, we may say that the inner word is rational, not indeed with the derived rationality of discourse, ... For human understanding, though it has its object in the phantasm and knows it in the phantasm, yet is not content with an object in this state. It pivots on itself to produce for itself another object which is the inner word as ratio, intentio, definitio, quod quid est.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas: Intellekt ist quod quid est; inner word (inneres Wort) als Produkt des Verstehens

Kurzinhalt: Intellekt = Verstehen; intelligere is understanding; we do not know anything by sight unless it is colored. But the proper object of intellect is quod quid est

Textausschnitt: It remains that the principal meaning of intelligere is understanding. ... He repeatedly affirmed that the quod quid est is the proper object of intellect ...
()
Whatever intellect knows, it knows through the quod quid est which is the substance of the object: just as whatever is known by sight is known through color, so what is known by intellect is known through the quod quid est. What cannot be known by intellect in that manner cannot be known at all. However,
()
Apart from certain natural concepts, of which we shall speak later, it cannot even be suggested that Aquinas thought of conception as an automatic process. Conceptualization comes as the term and product of a process of reasoning. As long as the reasoning, the fluctuation of discourse, continues, the inner word is as yet unuttered. But it also is true that as long as the reasoning continues, we do not as yet understand; for until the inner word is uttered, we are not understanding but only thinking in order to understand.
'Again, no cognitive power knows anything except in relation to its proper object; for example, we do not know anything by sight unless it is colored. But the proper object of intellect is quod quid est, that is, the substance of the thing, ...
()
In the second place, Aquinas considered the inner word to be a product of the act of understanding

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Conceptualization, inneres Wort, Begriffsbildung als Produkt des Verstehens (reasoning)

Kurzinhalt: inner word, in jeder Frage geht es um einen Mittelterm: when one asks what a stone is, one asks for the middle term between

Textausschnitt: Apart from certain natural concepts, of which we shall speak later, it cannot even be suggested that Aquinas thought of conception as an automatic process. Conceptualization comes as the term and product of a process of reasoning. As long as the reasoning, the fluctuation of discourse, continues, the inner word is as yet unuttered. But it also is true that as long as the reasoning continues, we do not as yet understand; for until the inner word is uttered, we are not understanding but only thinking in order to understand. Hence understanding and inner word are simultaneous, the former being the ground and cause of the latter.
()
f one is willing to take a broad view on reasoning, to conceive syllogism with some of the intellectual suppleness of Aristotle, one will be willing to grant that every question either asks whether there is a middle term, or asks what the middle term is; that when one asks what a stone is, one asks for the middle term between the sensible data and the essential definition of the stone; between those two, there has to occur an act of understanding, and leading up to such understanding there is the discourse or reasoning of scientific method ... Already we have seen that from the fact that human understanding had its object in phantasm, Aquinas deduced that human intellect was mostly reason; one should not be surprised when he goes on to affirm that we have to reason in order to form concepts.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Abstraktion als Weglassen des Unwichtigen; 3 Grade von Abstraktion

Kurzinhalt: materia individualis, materia designata, materia signata; time and place as such explain nothing; interessant: to know the past as past ... is the work of sense; wieder: Beispiel Kreis

Textausschnitt: As a second preliminary, we may explain that by a psychological account of abstraction we mean the elimination by the understanding of the intellectually irrelevant because it is understood to be irrelevant. That, we submit, is the very point of the celebrated three degrees of abstraction. What is variously termed materia individualis, materia designata, materia signata, the hic et nunc, cannot be an explanatory factor in any science; it is irrelevant to all scientific explanation; it is irrelevant a priori; time and place as such explain nothing, ... Intellect abstracts from the hic et nunc. ... Properly, intellect does not remember; to know the past as past, like knowing the present, is the work of sense.
()
In other words, the 'here and now,' or the 'there and then,' as such are irrelevant to understanding, explanation, the assigning of causes; and from them intellect abstracts, inasmuch as and because it understands that irrelevance. The datum 'round' is understood as necessitated by equal radii in a plane surface; 'equal radii in a plane surface' is abstracted as common matter from phantasm and spoken in an inner word
()
The second degree of abstraction is similar to the first: as all science prescinds from the 'here and now,' so all mathematics prescinds from all sensible qualities - from colors, sounds, tactile experiences, tastes, odors; the color of the geometrical figure, of the arithmetical or algebraic symbol, is never relevant to the mathematical theorem.
()
Finally, the third degree of abstraction prescinds from all matter, individual and common, sensible and intelligible, to treat of 'ens, unum, potentia et actus, et alia huiusmodi.' It does so, because metaphysical theorems are valid independently of any sensible matter of fact and of any condition of imagination.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: 3 Grade von Begriffsbildung, emanatio intelligibilis; Begriff als Ergebnis einer Einsicht

Kurzinhalt: Abstraktion nach Thomas (Aristoteles): abgeleitet vom Akt des Verstehens; Selbstbesitz des Verstehens als Bedingung der Begriffsbildung;

Textausschnitt: Conceptualization is the self-expression of an act of understanding; such self-expression is possible only because understanding is self-possessed, conscious of itself and its own conditions as understanding; insofar as the understanding has its conditions all within the intelligible order, the expression abstracts from all that is sensible and imaginable, and so is in the third degree; insofar as the understanding has conditions in the imaginable, but not in the empirical, order of sensible presentations, the abstraction is of the second degree; insofar as the understanding has conditions within the empirical order of sensible presentations, the abstraction is of the first degree; but there is always some abstraction; for the 'here and now' of sensible presentation or of imagination is never relevant to any understanding. ... The Aristotelian and Thomist theory of abstraction is not exclusively metaphysical; basically, it is psychological, that is, derived from the character of acts of understanding. On the other hand, it is in the self-possession of understanding as the ground of possible conceptualization that one may best discern what is meant by saying that the self-expression of understanding is an emanatio intelligibilis, a procession from knowledge as knowledge, and because of knowledge as knowledge.
()
The concept is the definition, provided there is a definition. Perhaps enough has been said to make the point that defining is a fruit of intelligence, the quid rei of understanding the thing, and the quid nominis of understanding the language. But what about ultimate concepts that defy definition?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: auch "letzte" Begriffe (hier: Potenz, Akt, ens) abgeleitet von Einsicht,

Kurzinhalt: Akt und Potenz abgeleitet von Einsicht, Intelligibilität als Grund von Potentialität, bumpkin, actus essendi

Textausschnitt: But what about ultimate concepts that defy definition? ... In closed eyes we discern the possibility of actual seeing; in eyes we discern the possibility of sight; what is possible is the act, and its possibility is the potency; both are objective, but the act is objective when it occurs, the potency when the act is possible; and that objectivity of possibility is, for instance, what makes die difference between an invention and a mere bright idea. Ultimate concepts, like derived concepts, proceed from understanding.
()
I think much less ink would be spilt on the concept of ens were more attention paid to its origin in the act of understanding. Tell any bumpkin a plausible tale and he will remark, 'Well now, that may be so.' 'Well now, that may be so.' He is not perhaps exercising consciously the virtue of wisdom, which has the function of knowing the 'ratio entis et non entis.' But his understanding has expressed itself as grasp of possible being. Intelligibility is the ground of possibility, and possibility is the possibility of being; equally, unintelligibility is the ground of impossibility, and impossibility means impossibility of being.
()
Hence, the first operation of intellect regards quiddities, but the second, judgment, regards esse, the actus essendi. Note, however, that being is not reduced through possibility to intelligibility as to prior concepts; being is the first concept; what is prior to the first concept is, not a prior concept, but an act of understanding

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Erfahrung ist nicht eigentlich die Quelle des Seins, sonst wäre das Sein reduziert auf Erfahrung - Kant

Kurzinhalt: though it is not as such the source of the concept of being - else, as Kant held,

Textausschnitt: To affirm actual being, more than a plausible tale is wanted; for experience, though it is not as such the source of the concept of being - else, as Kant held, the real would have to be confined to the field of possible experience - still it is the condition of the transition from the affirmation of the possibility to the affirmation of the actuality of being. Hence, the first operation of intellect regards quiddities, but the second, judgment, regards esse, the actus essendi. Note, however, that being is not reduced through possibility to intelligibility as to prior concepts; being is the first concept; what is prior to the first concept is, not a prior concept, but an act of understanding; and like other concepts, the concept of being is an effect of the act of understanding.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: der Begriff des Seins (Seinsbegriff) als conceptualization des Intellekts selbst u. die Folgerungen daraus

Kurzinhalt: but the concept of being, on the above showing, is the conceptualization of intelligibility as such; potens omnia fieri; d. Seinsbegriff ist nicht analog

Textausschnitt: From this it follows that the concept of being is natural to intellect; for intelligibility is natural to intellect, for it is its act; and conceptualization is natural to intellect, for it is its activity; but the concept of being, on the above showing, is the conceptualization of intelligibility as such, and so it too is natural to intellect.
()
Again, it follows that the content of the concept of being is indeterminate; for it is conceived from any act of understanding whatever; it proceeds from intelligibility in act as such. Again, it follows that the concept of being cannot be unknown to intellect; for its sole condition is that intellect be in any act of understanding. Again, it follows that being is the object of intellect: for intellect would not be intellect were it not at least potens omnia fieri, in potency to any intelligibility; but what of its nature is potens omnia fieri must have being as its object. Finally, it is impossible to recount in a sentence or so the position of Aquinas on analogy; but one may note briefly that, on the above showing, the concept of being cannot but be analogous; being is always conceived in the same way - as the expression of intelligibility or intelligence in act

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Zwei Arten der processio: Definition, Urteil; Ähnlichkeit und Unterschied

Kurzinhalt: parallel between the two types of procession of inner words. Both definition and judgment proceed from acts of understanding

Textausschnitt: It may be helpful to indicate at once the parallel between the two types of procession of inner words. Both definition and judgment proceed from acts of understanding, but the former from direct, the latter from reflective understanding. Both acts of understanding have their principal cause in the agent intellect, but ... Again, both acts of understanding have their instrumental or material causes, but the direct act has this cause in a schematic image or phantasm, while the reflective act reviews not only imagination but also sense experience, and direct acts of understanding, and definitions, to find in all taken together the sufficient ground or evidence for a judgment. Hence, while the direct act of understanding generates in definition the expression of the intelligibility of a phantasm, the reflective act generates in judgment the expression of consciously possessed truth through which reality is both known and known to be known.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Compositio vel divisio: zweites inneres Wort; Thomas über "ist" (est)

Kurzinhalt: origin in the Aristotelian use of grammar for..., est, simpliciter dictum, significat in actu esse, but consequently and implicitly, 'est' means the true or false

Textausschnitt: Compositio vel divisio is the usual Thomist name for the second type of inner word. Its origin lies in the Aristotelian use of grammar for the specification of philosophic problems. In the Categories one is told to distinguish between simple and composite forms of speech: the latter are illustrated by 'the man runs,' 'the man wins'; the former by 'man,' 'runs,' 'wins.' In the Peri hermeneias ...
()
This passage Aquinas discussed at length, drawing an illuminating distinction between the primary and the consequent meanings of the verb 'est.' Primarily, '[...] est, simpliciter dictum, significat in actu esse'; but consequently and implicitly, 'est' means the true or false. For the primary meaning of 'est' is the actuality of any form or act, substantial or accidental; but consequently (because actuality involves synthesis with the actuated), and implicitly (because the actuated subject is understood when actuality is affirmed), there is the connotation of truth or falsity in this and other verbs.
()
In Aristotle, it is true, this distinction between the merely synthetic element in judgment and, on the other hand, the positing of synthesis is not drawn clearly.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Compositio: im Ding, im inneren und äußeren Wort; Wahrheit als Synthese im Geist und Ding

Kurzinhalt: Sokrates ist ein Mann; truth is not merely the subjective, mental synthesis. It is the correspondence between mental and real synthesis; incomplexa erkannt als complex und inversely

Textausschnitt: there is the real composition in things themselves; there is the composition of inner words in the mind; there is the composition of outer words in speech and writing. The last of these three is obvious:
... However, there is no doubt about the existence of an inner composition: ... Finally, the ground and cause of the composition that occurs in the mind and in speech is a real composition in the thing. Thus, the proposition 'Socrates is a man' has its ground and cause in the composition of a human form with the individual matter of Socrates; the proposition 'Socrates is white' has its ground and cause in the composition of a real accident 'whiteness' with a real subject 'Socrates.'
()
The one point to be noted here is that truth is not merely the subjective, mental synthesis. It is the correspondence between mental and real synthesis. More accurately, in our knowledge of composite things, truth is the correspondence of mental composition with real composition or of mental division with real division; falsity is the noncorrespondence of mental composition to real division or of mental division to real composition.
()
But besides our knowledge of composite substances there are three other cases in which the foregoing account of truth suffers modal variations: in our knowledge of simple substances the incomplexa are known complexe; inversely, when simple substances know composite objects, the complexe are known incomplexe; finally, in the self-knowledge of the absolutely simple substance, knowing and known are an identity, and so truth can be named a correspondence in that case only by the artifice of a double negation

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Entfremdung; Nichtbeachtung der transzendentalen Vorschriften; Die Grundform der Ideologie

Kurzinhalt: ... nach der hier vorgelegten Analyse besteht die Grundform der Entfremdung in der Nichtbeachtung der transzendentalen Vorschriften: Sei aufmerksam; sei einsichtig; sei vernünftig; sei verantwortungsbewußt!

Textausschnitt: 81/II Der Begriff Entfremdung wird in vielfältig verschiedenem Sinn gebraucht, doch nach der hier vorgelegten Analyse besteht die Grundform der Entfremdung in der Nichtbeachtung der transzendentalen Vorschriften: Sei aufmerksam; sei einsichtig; sei vernünftig; sei verantwortungsbewußt! Die Grundform der Ideologie ist demnach eine Lehre, die solche Entfremdung zu rechtfertigen sucht. Von diesen Grundformen können alle anderen abgeleitet werden, da die Grundformen das Sozialgut verderben. Wie die Selbst-Transzendenz den Fortschritt fördert, so wendet die Verweigerung der Selbst-Transzendenz den Fortschritt in kumulativen Niedergang. (66; Fs) (notabene)

82/II Abschließend möchten wir anmerken, daß eine Religion, die die Selbst-Transzendenz nicht nur bis zur Gerechtigkeit, sondern bis zur sich-selbst-aufopfernden Liebe vorantreibt, in der Menschengemeinschaft eine Erlösungsrolle spielen wird, insofern eine solche Liebe das Unheil des Niedergangs rückgängig machen und den kumulativen Prozeß des Fortschritts wiederherstellen kann.1 (66; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Aristoteles: Synthese des Verstandes vielleicht gebildet nach Empedokles' Vorstellung der Entstehung

Kurzinhalt: Beispiel: Diagonale, Maß, irrationale Zahl: ich kann jedes dieser Elemente einzeln verstehen: it is a third to see that an irrational cannot be a measure; 2 Begriffe verschmelzen in einem

Textausschnitt: Mental synthesis is of concepts. As one defined term proceeds from one insight into phantasm, so two defined terms proceed from two insights. Such multiple insights and definitions may be separate, isolated, atomic. But it also happens that one insight combines with another,
()
For he appealed to the naive evolutionary theory of Empedocles that fancied an initial state of nature in which heads existed apart from necks and trunks apart from limbs ...
()
In like manner, Aristotle contended, intellect puts together what before were apart. It is one thing to understand that the diagonal stands to the side of a square as root two to unity; it is another to grasp that that proportion is an irrational; it is a third to see that an irrational cannot be a measure.
()
Note the nature of the conjunction: it is not that two concepts merge into one concept; that would be mere confusion; concepts remain eternally and immutably distinct.b But while two concepts remain distinct as concepts, they may cease to be two intelligibilities and merge into one.
()
where before there were two acts of understanding, expressed singly in two concepts, now there is but one act of understanding, expressed in the combination of two concepts. This combination of two, as a combination, forms but a single intelligible, a single though composite object of a single act of understanding.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas: intelligere multa per unum: auch bei Prinzipien

Kurzinhalt: Psychologische Tatsache: Einsichten bilden höhere Einheiten,

Textausschnitt: The psychological fact that insights are not unrelated atoms, that they develop, coalesce, form higher unities, was fully familiar to Aquinas. ... Knowledge of first principles is not exclusively a matter of comparing abstract terms or concepts; no less than the terms, the nexus between them may be directly abstracted from phantasm, so that, just as the concept, so also the principle may be the expression of an insight into phantasm.
()
The summit of such sweep and penetration is the divine intellect; for the divine act of understanding is one, yet it embraces in a single view all possibles and the prodigal multiplicity of actual beings

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas, natürlich gewusste Prinzipien, 2 Arten von ersten Prinzipien; ens als Objekt, principle of noncontradiction

Kurzinhalt: Such a natural habit differs both from acquired habit and from infused habit, Satz vom Widerspruch, Ganzes - Teil,

Textausschnitt: Reasoning not merely terminates in understanding; equally it begins from understanding; for unless we understood something, we never should begin to reason at all. Accordingly, to avoid an infinite regress, it is necessary to posit a habitus princpiorum, which naturally we possessc. Such a natural habit differs both from acquired habit and from infused habit. The natural habit, though it has a determination from sense, results strictly from intellectual light alone; the acquired habit ... Nowhere, to my knowledge, did Aquinas offer to give a complete list of naturally known principles. His stock examples are the principle of noncontradiction and of the whole being greater than the part. But it does not follow that the list of such principles is quite indeterminate. As there are naturally known principles, so also there is an object which we know per se and naturally. That object is ens; and only principles founded upon our knowledge of ens are naturally known.
()
If we are correct in urging that intelligibility is the ground of possibility and that possibility is possibility of being, so that the concept of being is known naturally because it proceeds from any intelligibility in act (= any intelligence in act), then it is equally clear that the principle of noncontradiction is known naturally; for ...
()
The other stock example of a naturally known principle is that the whole is greater than the part. ... For, as every being is one, so every finite being is a whole compounded of parts, an ens quod made up of entia quibus. Moreover, we know this naturally. Natural form stands to natural matter, as intelligible form stands to sensible matter; and when by a natural spontaneity we ask quid sit, we reveal our natural knowledge that the material or sensible component is only a part and that the whole includes a formal component as well.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas: Prinzip: das Ganze ist größer als das Teil

Kurzinhalt: Zwei Fragen offenbaren die Gültigkeit dieses Prinzips: quid sit? An sit?

Textausschnitt: The other stock example of a naturally known principle is that the whole is greater than the part. ... For, as every being is one, so every finite being is a whole compounded of parts, an ens quod made up of entia quibus. Moreover, we know this naturally. Natural form stands to natural matter, as intelligible form stands to sensible matter; and when by a natural spontaneity we ask quid sit, we reveal our natural knowledge that the material or sensible component is only a part and that the whole includes a formal component as well. Similarly, when by a natural spontaneity we ask an sit, we again reveal our natural knowledge that the whole is not just a quiddity but includes an actus essendi as well.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Composition or Division: Zusammenfassung

Kurzinhalt: Fifthly, reasoning in its essence is simply the development of insight; it is motion towards understanding. In the concrete such development is a dialectical interplay of sense, memory, imagination, insight, definition, critical reflection, judgment ...

Textausschnitt: Next, many insights into many phantasms express themselves severally in many definitions; none of these singly is true or false; nor are all together true or false, for as yet they are not together. Thirdly, what brings definitions together is not some change in the definitions; it is a change in the insights whence they proceed. Insights coalesce and develop; they grow into apprehensions of intelligibility on a deeper level and with a wider sweep; and these pro-founder insights are expressed, at times indeed by the invention of such baffling abstractions as classicism or romanticism, education, evolution, or the philosophia perennis, but more commonly and more satisfactorily by the combination, as combination, of simple concepts. Fourthly, such synthetic sweep and penetration comes at first blush to the angel, but man has to reason to it; his intellect is discursive. Still, it is not pure discourse. Without initial and natural acts of understanding, reasoning would never begin; nor would there be profit or term to reasoning, did it not naturally end in an act of understanding in which the multiple elements of the reasoning process come into focus in a single view. Fifthly, reasoning in its essence is simply the development of insight; it is motion towards understanding. In the concrete such development is a dialectical interplay of sense, memory, imagination, insight, definition, critical reflection, judgment; we bring to bear on the issue all the resources at our command. Still, the more intelligent we are, the more we are capable of knowing ex pede Herculem; then the more rapid is our progress to the goal of understanding, and the less is our appeal to the stylized reasoning of textbooks on formal logic. Again, once we understand, we no longer bother to reason; we take in the whole at a glance. With remarkable penetration Aquinas refused to take as reason the formal affair that modern logicians invent machines to perform. He defined reason as development in understanding; and to that, formal reasoning is but an aid.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Urteil: Wissen und Sinneswahrnehmung ist weder wahr noch falsch, erst die Reflexion darüber

Kurzinhalt: The issue, then, is not knowledge as true or false but knowledge as known to be true or false;

Textausschnitt: The issue, then, is not knowledge as true or false but knowledge as known to be true or false. Even sense knowledge may be true or false. Just as good and bad regard the perfection of the thing, so true and false regard the perfection of a knowing. True knowing is similar, false is dissimilar, to the known. But though sense knowledge must be either similar or dissimilar to its object, it neither does nor can include knowledge of its similarity or dissimilarity. Again, a concept must be either similar or dissimilar to its object; but intellectual operation on the level of conceptualization does not include knowledge of such similarity or dissimilarity. It is only in the second type of intellectual operation, only in the production of the second type of inner word,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Problem der Übereinstimmung zw. Gewusstem und Ding; Thomas Antwort auf den naiven Realist

Kurzinhalt: a comparison between the knowing and its standard; Thomas wusste um den Maß im Urteil, The Thomist standard lay in the principles of the intellect itself:

Textausschnitt: Such reflection presents a familiar puzzle. To judge that my knowing is similar to the known involves a comparison between the knowing and its standard; but either the standard is known or it is not known; if it is known, then really the comparison is between two items of knowledge, and one might better maintain that we know directly without any comparing; on the other hand, if the standard is not known, there cannot be a comparison. This dilemma of futility or impossibility frightens the naive realist, who consequently takes refuge in the flat affirmation that we know,
()
Not only did he admit the necessity of a standard, but also he does not seem to have considered as standard either of the alternatives against which the above dilemma is operative; for his standard was neither the thing-in-itself as thing-in-itself and so as unknown, nor was it some second inner representation of the thing-in-itself coming to the aid of the first in a futile and superfluous effort to be helpful.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Schlaf: Form außerhalb von Raum u. Zeit; Urteil immer in Zeit; Mathematik, Naturwissenschaft

Kurzinhalt: quod quid est takes us outside time and space; but the act of compositio vel divisio: specification of time; Wahrheit immer im mind; nur in Gott ewige Wahrheit

Textausschnitt: Knowledge of the quod quid est takes us outside time and space; but the act of compositio vel divisio involves a return to the concrete. In particular, whatever may be hymned about eternal truths, human judgments always involve a specification of time. Indeed, since truth exists only in a mind, and since only the mind of God is eternal, there can be but one eternal truth.
()
Automatically, the natural scientist who neglects sense falls into error; his work is to judge things as they are presented to the senses. On the other hand, the mathematician is not to be criticized because no real plane surface touches no real sphere at just one point; the criterion of mathematical judgment is not sense but imagination. Similarly, metaphysical entities are not to be called into question because they cannot be imagined; for metaphysics transcends not only sense but imagination as well.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Urteil: material und formal, zweifache Quelle: Sinn, intelletktuelles Licht; 'ratio terminatur ad intellectum'

Kurzinhalt: materially from developing insight (which unites distinct intelligibilities into single intelligibilities); formally from a reflective activity of reason

Textausschnitt: Judgment, then, may be described as resulting remotely and, as it were, materially from developing insight, which unites distinct intelligibilities into single intelligibilities, but proximately and, as it were, formally from a reflective activity of reason. This reflective activity involves the whole man, and so it is conditioned psychologically by a necessity of being wide awake. Again, human knowledge has a twofold origin - an extrinsic origin in sensitive impressions, and an intrinsic origin in intellectual light in which virtually the whole of science is precontained. Hence the reflective activity whence judgment results is a return from the syntheses effected by developing insight to their sources in sense and in intellectual light.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Urteil als Hervorgang des 2. inneren Wortes; processio, emanatio intelligibilis; Urteil: Zusammenfassung

Kurzinhalt: For no less than the first type of inner word, the second also proceeds from an intelligere; Intellekt: 1 Ebenen von Aktivität

Textausschnitt: ... and we may infer that the reflective activity of reason returning from the synthesis of intelligibilities to its origin in sense and in naturally known principles terminates in a reflective act of understanding, in a single synthetic apprehension of all the motives for judgment, whether intellectual or sensitive, in a grasp of their sufficiency as motives and so of the necessity of passing judgment or assenting. For no less than the first type of inner word, the second also proceeds from an intelligere. No less than the procession of the first type, the procession of the second is an emanatio intelligibilis.
()
The general outline of Thomist analysis of human intellect is now, perhaps, discernible. There are two levels of activity, the direct and the reflective. On the direct level there occur two types of events: there are insights into phantasm which express themselves in definitions; there is the coalescence or development of insights which provides the hypothetical syntheses of simple quiddities. On the reflective level these hypothetical syntheses are known as hypothetical; they become questions which are answered by the resolutio in principia. This return to sources terminates in a reflective act of understanding, which is a grasp of necessary connection between the sources and the hypothetical synthesis; from this grasp there proceeds its self-expression, which is the compositio vel divisio, the judgment, the assent.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: 3 Arten von intellekturellen Habitus, duale Weisheit; Weisheit als Grund von Intellekt u. Wissenschaft

Kurzinhalt: science, intellect, wisdom; habit of intellect: the first principles of demonstrations; habit of wisdom: the first principles of reality; Intellekt u. Weisheit in Bezug auf Erfassung d Prinzipien; virtus quaedam omnium scientiarum

Textausschnitt: There are, then, three habits of speculative intellect. Most easily recognized of the three is the habit of science, which has to do with the demonstration of conclusions. However, demonstration does not admit indefinite regress, and so there must be some prior habit that regards first principles. In fact, two such prior habits are affirmed, intellect and wisdom ... For the habit of intellect regards the first principles of demonstrations, while the habit of wisdom regards the first principles of reality. The habit of intellect is comparatively simple: grasp of first principles of demonstrations results from knowledge of their component terms; if one knows what a whole is and what a part is, one cannot but see that the whole must be greater than its part; the habit of such seeing is the habit of intellect.
()
On the other hand, the habit of wisdom has a dual role. Principally, it regards the objective order of reality; but in some fashion it also has to do with the transition from the order of thought to the order of reality. ... While art orders human products, and prudence orders human conduct, science discovers the order which art prudently exploits; but there is a highest, architectonic science, a science of sciences - and that is wisdom.
()
The habit of intellect is the habit of knowing the first principles of demonstrations; but knowledge of first principles is just a function of knowledge of their component terms. If the simple apprehension of these terms is a matter of direct understanding, still it is wisdom that passes judgment on the validity of such apprehensions and so by validating the component terms validates even first principles themselves.
... Hence both intellect and science depend upon the judgment of wisdom. Intellect depends upon wisdom for the validity of the component terms of principles; science depends upon wisdom for the validity of its consequence from intellect; so that wisdom, besides being in its own right the science of the real as real, also is 'virtus quaedam omnium scientiarum.'

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Lonergan, Aristoteles Metaphysik: Buch 1: Ursachen, 2-5: epistemologisch ... 6: Substanz, Potenz

Kurzinhalt: Epistemologie in Metaphysik schon bei Aristoteles; Philosophie als Weisheit; Eule, Straße; thus truth and reality are parallel:

Textausschnitt: Acknowledgment of an epistemological element in the habit of wisdom goes back to its classical exposition in the Metaphysics of Aristotle. ... But for a resumption of the objective viewpoint so established, one must leap to book 6 (E). There one finds an account of the real, followed by accounts of substance or essence, of (potency and act, of unity and opposition, and of the separate substances. But the intervening books 2 to 5 are gnoseological, methodological, almost epistemological. Knowledge of causes has to be true.
()
One may say that philosophers are in the position of people walking the streets; to know the facades of houses is easy, but to know their interiors difficult. So too, there are palpable truths and hidden truths. In particular, knowledge of the separate substances is hard to come by, for in their regard we are just owls in daylight
()
Thus truth and reality are parallel: what has a cause of its reality, also has a cause of its truth; again, as the reality that grounds other reality is the more real, so the truth that grounds other truth is the more true; as an infinite regress in the demonstration of truths is untenable, so also is an infinite regress in the grounding of one reality by another. There is, then, something of which the reality is most real and the truth most true, and it is the object of wisdom.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Unvollständigkeit der arstotelischen Metaphysik

Kurzinhalt: Identität im Verstehen, der Akt des Dinges als esse naturale, aber dieses esse ist nicht identisch mit dem Wissen selbst (außer bei Gott)

Textausschnitt: Again, the wise man knows the difference between appearance and reality. He is ready to refute the sophistries that would confound the two, but he is not prepared to discuss how our immanent activities also contain a transcendence. Aristotelian gnoseology is brilliant but it is not complete:e knowledge is by identity; the act of the thing as sensible is the act of sensation; the act of the thing as intelligible is the act of understanding; but the act of die thing as real is the esse naturale of the thing and, except in divine self-knowledge, that esse is not identical with knowing it.
()
But the problem of knowledge, once it is granted that knowledge is by identity, is knowledge of the other. As long as faculty and object are in potency to knowing and being known, there is as yet no knowledge. Inasmuch as faculty and object are in act identically, there is knowledge indeed as perfection but not yet knowledge of the other. Reflection is required, first, to combine sensible data with intellectual insight in the expression of a quod quid est, of an essence that prescinds from its being known, and then, on a deeper level, to affirm the existence of that essence. Only by reflection on the identity of act can one arrive at the difference of potency. And since reflection is not an identity, the Aristotelian theory of knowledge by identity is incomplete.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Unterschied zw. Plato und Aristoteles im Hinblick auf das Wissen: Identität - Anschauung

Kurzinhalt: One knows by what one is; the reason why we know is within us; It is the light of our own intellects

Textausschnitt: But it is well to grasp just where the strength of the Aristotelian position lies. One might side with Plato and say knowing of its nature is knowing the other. But this brings up insoluble difficulties with regard to knowledge in the absolute being; for even Plato was forced to admit, in virtue of his assumptions, that absolute being, if it knows, must undergo motion.
()
Aquinas was quite aware of this profound cleavage between Platonist and Aristotelian gnoseology: 'Et hoc quidem oportet verum esse secundum sententiam Aristotelis, qui ponit quod intelligere contingit per hoc quod intellectum in actu sit unum cum intellectu in actu ... Secundum autem positionem Platonis, intelligere fit per contactum intellectus ad rem intelligibilem, [...]"
()
The Thomist validation of rational reflection is connected with the Augustinian vision of eternal truth. Augustine had argued that we know truth not by looking without but by looking within ourselves.
()
Now the Platonism of this position is palpable, for its ultimate answer is not something that we are but something that we see; it supposes that knowledge essentially is not identity with the known but some spiritual contact or confrontation with the known. Such a view Aquinas could not accept. One knows by what one is. Our knowledge of truth is not to be accounted for by any vision or contact or confrontation with the other, however lofty and sublime. The ultimate ground of our knowing is indeed God, the eternal Light; but the reason why we know is within us. It is the light of our own intellects; and by it we can know because 'ipsum enim lumen intellectuale quod est in nobis, nihil est aliud quam quaedam participata similitudo luminis increati.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas und Epistemologie; Unterschied zw. Sinn u. Intellekt

Kurzinhalt: Thomas wusste darum, dass sich die Wahrheit vom Wissen um uns selbst herleitet

Textausschnitt: The act of the thing as sensible is the act of sensation; the act of the thing as intelligible is the act of understanding; but we can proceed from these identities to valid concepts of essence and true affirmations of existence, because such procession is in virtue of our intellectual light, which is a participation of eternal Light. Such is the Thomist ontology of knowledge. But is there also a Thomist epistemology?
()
Now there happens to be a text in which Aquinas did maintain that our knowledge of truth is derived from our knowledge of ourselves. Sense knowledge, because unreflective, is irrelevant to the procession of the Word.
()
Sense knowledge is true; sense is aware of its own acts of sensation. But sense, though true and though conscious, nevertheless is not conscious of its own truth; for sense does not know its own nature, nor the nature of its acts, nor their proportion to their objects. On the other hand, intellectual knowledge is not merely true but also aware of its own truth. It is not merely aware empirically of its acts but also reflects upon their nature; to know the nature of its acts, it has to know the nature of their active principle, which it itself is; and if it knows its own nature, intellect also knows its own proportion to knowledge of reality. Further, this difference between sense and intellect is a difference in reflective capacity. In knowing, we go outside ourselves; in reflecting, we return in upon ourselves. But the inward return of sense is incomplete,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Erkenntnis d. Seele, Intellekt: in genere intelligibilium

Kurzinhalt: human intellect: in genere intelligibilium just a potency; Sehen: nicht seiner selbst bewusst, darum schon untauglich für die Erklärung des Intellekts

Textausschnitt: Knowledge of soul, then, begins from a distinction of objects; specifying objects leads to a discrimination between different kinds of act; different kinds of act reveal difference of potency; and the different combinations of potencies lead to knowledge of the different essences that satisfy the generic definition of soul.
()
Thus the human soul does not know itself by a direct grasp of its own essence; that is the prerogative of God and of the angels. ... The fact is that human intellect is in genere intelligibilium just a potency; unless its potency is reduced to act, it neither understands nor is understood. On the other hand, the acquisition of an understanding of anything, of any habitual scientific knowledge, makes our intellect habitually capable not only of understanding the scientific object in question but also of understanding itself. ... It was by scrutinizing both the object understood and the understanding intellect that Aristotle investigated the nature of possible intellect. And, indeed, we can have no knowledge of our intellects except by reflecting on our own acts of understanding. Evidently, the Aristotelian and Thomist program is not a matter of considering ocular vision and then conceiving an analogous spiritual vision that is attributed to a spiritual faculty named intellect. On the contrary, it is a process of introspection that discovers the act of insight into phantasm and the definition as an expression of the insight, that
()
... there is to be found in the independent Thomist writings not a few additional points of introspective psychology. Of these the most fundamental is the distinction between what we should call an empirical awareness of our inner acts and a scientific grasp of their nature. The scientific grasp is in terms of objects, acts, potencies, essence of soul.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Argument gegen Averroisten; thomistische Psychologie

Kurzinhalt: The standard argument against the Averroists was the affirmation 'hic homo intelligit'; grasp the nature of your acts of understanding, and you have the key to the whole of Thomist psychology.

Textausschnitt: The standard argument against the Averroists was the affirmation 'hic homo intelligit': deny such a proposition, and since you too are an instance of hic homo, you put yourself out of court as one who understands nothing; but admit it, and you must also admit that each individual has his own private intellectus possibilis by which he understands.
()
... grasp the nature of your acts of understanding, and you have the key to the whole of Thomist psychology.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: intellektuelles Licht, light of agent intellect: known per se ipsum; Vergleich: intellektuelles, körperliches Licht

Kurzinhalt: agent intellect: known per se ipsum; soul: does not know its own essence by its own essence; but its own intellectual light by its own intellectual light

Textausschnitt: For Aquinas the term 'intellectual light' is not simply a synonym for the Aristotelian term 'agent intellect.' He debated with the Avicennists whether agent intellect was immanent or transcendent. But he never thought of debating whether intellectual light is immanent or transcendent. Indeed, when he argued that agent intellect was immanent, he was arguing for an identification of agent intellect with the ground of intellectual light. Hence ... Both the nature of agent intellect and, in particular, Aristotle's comparison of agent intellect with light, lead one to identify agent intellect with the immanent cause of "What we call the flash of understanding, the light of reason. What is, then, this lumen animae nostrae?
()
Just as corporeal light is seen in seeing any color, so also intelligible light is seen in apprehending any intelligibility. Again, just as corporeal light is seen, not as an object, but in knowing an object, so also intelligible light is seen, not as an object, but 'in ratione medii cognoscendi." Thirdly, intellectual light is a medium not in the sense that it is a known object by means of which another object is known; it is a medium in the sense that it makes other objects knowable. Just as the eye need not see light except insofar as colors are illuminated, so a medium in the given sense need not be known in itself but only in other known objects. Fourthly, with these restrictions we may say that the light of agent intellect is known per se ipsum. The soul does not know its own essence by its own essence; but in some fashion it does know its own intellectual light by its own intellectual light, not indeed to the extent that that light is an object, but inasmuch as that light is the element making species intelligible in act.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Manifestation des intellektuellen Lichtes, prima lux, zweifache Quelle unserer Erkenntnis, visio beatifica

Kurzinhalt: the light of agent intellect is said to manifest first principles, our intellectual light derives its efficacy from the prima lux which is God, beatific vision, Kunst

Textausschnitt: There is, then, a manner in which the light of our souls enters within the range of introspective observation. The most conspicuous instance seems to be our grasp of first principles. Scientific conclusions are accepted because they are implied by first principles; but the assent to first principles has to have its motive too, for assent is rational; and that motive is the light that naturally is within us. ... Just as conclusions are convincing because principles are convincing, so our intellectual light derives its efficacy from the prima lux which is God. Hence the divine and the human teachers may collaborate without any confusion of role. The human teacher teaches inasmuch as he reduces conclusions to principles; but all the certitude we possess, whether of conclusions or of principles, comes from the intellectual light within us by which God speaks to us.
()
However, the experienced effects of intellectual light, as the evidence of principles, the motive of assent, the immanent ground of certitude, are not the only instances in which intellectual light, in its indirect fashion, enters into the range of consciousness. It is constitutive of our very power of understanding. It is the principle of inquiry and of discourse ...
()
As the principle of inquiry, intellectual light is the source of that search for causes which reveals the natural desire of man for die beatific vision. Our knowledge has a twofold source - an extrinsic origin on the level of sense, but an intrinsic origin in the light of our intellects. Sense is only the materia causae of our knowledge. The object of understanding is supplied and offered to us, as it were materially, by the imagination; formally, as object of understanding, it is completed by intellectual light. Perhaps, agent intellect is to be given the function of the subconscious effect of ordering the phantasm to bring about the right schematic image that releases the flash of understanding; for agent intellect is to phantasm as art is to artificial products.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: intellectus possibilis; Rahner scheint über Loergan hinauszugehen

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: With regard to the act of understanding itself, at all times a distinction is drawn between possible intellect, habit of science, and the actuation of this habit; but in earlier writings there is a further distinction introduced within the habit of science between an element of light and, on the other hand, species as element of determination. ... Hence, while phantasm caused in possible intellect the determination of the act of understanding, agent intellect caused the element of immaterialization, of intelligibility in act.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas, Aristoteles, Urteil im Verhältnis zum intellektuellen Licht; Prophet: Urteil

Kurzinhalt: relation of intellectual light to judgment -> beyond the Aristotelian theory of agent intellect; Urteil des Propheten, cognitional potency ->s fixed by the light under which it operates

Textausschnitt: Inasmuch as the act of understanding grasps its own conditions as the understanding of this sort of thing, it abstracts from the irrelevant and expresses itself in a definition of essence. But inasmuch as the act of understanding grasps its own transcendence-in-immanence, its quality of intellectual light as a participation of the divine and uncreated Light, it expresses itself in judgment, in a positing of truth, in the affirmation or negation of reality.
()
For it is the light of intellect that replaces the Augustinian vision of eternal truth; and regularly one reads that we know, we understand, we judge all things by a created light within us which is a participation, a resultant, a similitude, an impression of the first and eternal light and truth. ... The range of a cognitional potency is fixed by the light under which it operates: ... Knowing truth is a use or act of intellectual light, and so judgment occurs according to the force of that light. Hence the prophet judges according to an infused light, and the essence of prophecy lies in such judgment; for a prophet need not be the recipient of a revelation but only pass judgment on data revealed to another; such was the case of Joseph, who judged Pharaoh's dreams; such also perhaps was the case of Solomon, who judged with greater certitude and from a divine instinct what naturally is known about nature and human morals.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Thomas: Betonung der Unbegrentzheit des natürlichen Lichtes; Seinsbegriff

Kurzinhalt: as active is potens omnia facere; as passive, it is potens omnia fieri; intellectual light is referred to its origin in uncreated Light

Textausschnitt: ... Thomist thought does stress that native infinity, and on the other hand, from such infinity one can grasp the capacity of the mind to know reality.
()
as active is potens omnia facere; as passive, it is potens omnia fieri. This is not merely an Aristotelian commonplace which Aquinas endlessly repeated; he also knew how to transpose and apply it in rather startling fashion. Any finite act of understanding has to be a pati, because intellect as intellect is infinite. Because of its infinite range, the object of intellect must be ens; this object cannot be unknown; it is known per se and naturally. As there are different types of intellect, so there are different modes of knowing ens. Since ...
()
For the concept of ens is not just another concept, another quod quid est, another but most general essence; the concept of ens is any concept, any quod quid est, any essence, when considered, not as some highest common factor nor again simply in itself, but in its relation to its own actus essendi, which is known in the act of judgment. ... further, since we know we know by knowing what we are, it is by reflection on the nature of intellect that we know our capacity for truth and for knowledge of reality. But the native infinity of intellect as intellect is a datum of rational consciousness. It appears in that restless spirit of inquiry, that endless search for causes which, Aquinas argued, can rest and end only in a supernatural vision of God. ... Just as Thomist thought is an ontology of knowledge inasmuch as intellectual light is referred to its origin in uncreated Light, so too it is more than an embryonic epistemology inasmuch as intellectual light reflectively grasps its own nature and the commensuration of that nature to the universe of reality.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Leben -> Aktualisierung der Potentialität des natürlichen Lichtes (Schema); Prinzip des Auschluss des Dritten

Kurzinhalt: child -> learn to distinguish between fact and fiction; to say that any X is real is just to assign it a place in that scheme; how do we grasp the scheme itself? At its root it is just the principle of excluded middle

Textausschnitt: The child has to learn to distinguish sharply between fact and fiction; the young man has not yet acquired a sufficiently nuanced grasp of human living for the study of ethics to be profitable; each of us, confronted with something outside the beaten track of our experience, turns to the expert to be taught just what it is. Still, in all this progress we are but discriminating, differentiating, categorizing the details of a scheme that somehow we possessed from the start. To say that any X is real is just to assign it a place in that scheme; to deny the reality of any Y is to deny it a place in the universal scheme.
()
But how do we grasp the scheme itself? At its root it is just the principle of excluded middle: X either is or else is not. And in its details the scheme is just the actuation of our capacity to conceive any essence and rationally affirm its existence and its relations. Since within that scheme both we ourselves and all our acts of conceiving and of judging are no more than particular and not too important items, the critical problem - and this is our second remark - is not a problem of moving from within outwards, of moving from a subject to an object outside the subject. It is a problem of moving from above downwards, of moving from an infinite potentiality commensurate with the universe towards a rational apprehension that seizes the difference of subject and object in essentially the same way that it seizes any other real distinction. Thus

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Kritisches Problem: Bewegung nicht von Subjekt zu Objekt, sondern von "oben" nach "unten"; Realismus

Kurzinhalt: Problem of moving from an infinite potentiality commensurate with the universe towards a rational apprehension ...; unmittelbarer Realismus

Textausschnitt: the critical problem - and this is our second remark - is not a problem of moving from within outwards, of moving from a subject to an object outside the subject. It is a problem of moving from above downwards, of moving from an infinite potentiality commensurate with the universe towards a rational apprehension that seizes the difference of subject and object in essentially the same way that it seizes any other real distinction. Thus realism is immediate, not because it is naive and unreasoned and blindly affirmed, but because we know the real before we know such a difference within the real as the difference between subject and object. Again, the critical problem has the appearance of insolubility only because the true concept of the real is hidden or obscured, and in its place there comes the false substitute that by the real we mean only another essence, or else that by the real we mean the object of modern existentialist experience - the mere givenness of inner or outer actuality, which truly is no more than the condition for the rational transition from the affirmation of possible to the affirmation of actual contingent being.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Weisheit, Trinität

Kurzinhalt: In us the principle and term of that doubling are not identical; procession of the divine Word: the principle and the term of the doubling are identical ... Even in the Godhead the duality of wisdom is not overcome utterly

Textausschnitt: We know by what we are; we know we know by knowing what we are; and since even the knowing in 'knowing what we are' is by what we are, rational reflection on ourselves is a duplication of ourselves. In us the principle and term of that doubling are not identical. In the procession of the divine Word the principle and the term of the doubling are identical, but the relations of principle to term and of term to principle remain real, opposed, subsistent, eternal, equal personalities - Father and Son in the consubstantiality of intellectual generation. Even in the Godhead the duality of wisdom is not overcome utterly; even there in some sense one may speak of a sapientia genita. But though the duality of wisdom never disappears totally, yet it tends towards that limit. Some remarks on the approach towards the limit are our concluding concern.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Dualität d. Weisheit; intellektuelles, ungeschaffenes Licht; Aristoteles, Thomas übersteigt ihn

Kurzinhalt: It never is pure understanding but always understanding this or understanding that; Thomas geht im Erfassen des unbeschränkten Strebens über Aritstoteles hinaus

Textausschnitt: This pure quality is intellectual light. But in its pure form we have no experience of it. It never is just inquiry but always inquiry about something. It never is pure understanding but always understanding this or understanding that. Even so, we may discern it introspectively, just as externally we discern light in seeing color. But ... But Aquinas measured that desire, to find in the undying restlessness and absolute exigence of the human mind that intellect as intellect is infinite, that ipsum esse is ipsum intelligere and uncreated, unlimited Light, that though our intellects because potential cannot attain naturally to the vision of God, still our intellects as intellects have a dynamic orientation, a natural desire, that nothing short of that unknown vision can satisfy utterly. For Augustine our hearts are restless until they rest in God; for Aquinas, not our hearts, but first and most our minds are restless until they rest in seeing him.
()
The basic duality of our wisdom is between our immanent intellectual light and the uncreated Light that is the object of its groping and its straining. The same duality is also the basic instance of the opposition and distinction between what is first quoad nos and what is first quoad se: ontologically the uncreated Light is first; epistemologically our own immanent light is first, for it is known not by some species but per se ipsum as the actuating element in all intelligible species. ... Towards it we are moved in a dialectical oscillation, envisaging more clearly now one pole and now another, with each addition to either at once throwing more light on the other and raising further questions with regard to it.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Selbsterkenntnis: 3 Arten; Norm und Sollen können nicht erreicht werden vom bloß Faktischen

Kurzinhalt: Now knowledge of the norm, of the ought-to-be, cannot be had from what merely happens to be and, too often, falls far short of the norm. Normative knowledge has to rest upon the eternal reasons. But this resting, ...

Textausschnitt: 77/2 Perhaps in this connection we may note most conveniently a particular aspect of the soul's self-knowledge. The most nuanced account of this is to be found in the De veritate,1 where three types of self-knowledge are distinguished. There is the empirical self-knowledge, actual or habitual, based upon the soul's presence to itself; there is the scientific and analytic self-knowledge that proceeds from objects to acts, from acts to potencies, from potencies to essence; but besides this pair, with which we are already familiar, there is also a third. It lies in the act of judgment which passes from the conception of essence to the affirmation of reality. Still, it is concerned not with this or that soul, but with what any soul ought to be according to the eternal reasons; and so the reality of soul that is envisaged is not sorry achievement but dynamic norm. Now knowledge of the norm, of the ought-to-be, cannot be had from what merely happens to be and, too often, falls far short of the norm. Normative knowledge has to rest upon the eternal reasons. But this resting, Aquinas explained, is not a vision of God but a participation and similitude of him by which we grasp first principles and judge all things by examining them in the light of principles.2 (101; Fs)

78/2 Wisdom through self-knowledge is not limited to the progress from empirical through scientific to normative knowledge. Beyond the wisdom we may attain by the natural light of our intellects, there is a further wisdom attained through the supernatural light of faith, when the humble surrender of our own light to the self-revealing uncreated Light makes the latter the loved law of all our assents. Rooted in this faith, supernatural wisdom has a twofold expansion. In its contact with human reason, it is the science of theology, which orders the data of revelation and passes judgment on all other science.3 But faith, besides involving a contact with reason, also involves a contact with God. On that side wisdom is a gift of the Holy Spirit, making us docile to his movements, in which, even perceptibly, one may be 'non solum discens sed et patiens divina.'4 (101; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Mystisches Erlebnis, Erfahrung der Seele von sich selbst; Gott im Gedächtnis; memoria

Kurzinhalt: the soul is present to itself in rational consciousness, that from the divine presence in the soul intellect receives the light necessary for understanding, Taste and see how the Lord is sweet

Textausschnitt: mystical experience. Early in the Sentences, in discussing the imago Dei in the human soul, it is asked whether knowledge and love of God and of self are constantly in act. In the Summa this question is answered negatively for the peremptory reason that everyone now and then goes to sleep. But in the early work the answer is affirmative, and it is given in two forms - first ...
()
It amounts to saying that the soul is present to itself in rational consciousness. But from that presence to oneself it is not too easy a step to the presence of God to oneself. ... Now it is true that, apart from prying introspection, self-knowledge within rational consciousness is neither a discernere, nor a cogitare, nor an intelligere with a fixed object. But must one not enter into the domain of religious experience to find this awareness of one's spiritual self prolonged into an awareness of God?
()
A similar, if less acute, question arises in the De veritate, where one reads that the presence of God in the mind is the memory of God in the mind.
()
A necessary condition of understanding is within nature, and we are told that from the divine presence in the soul intellect receives the light necessary for understanding. Further, if one goes back to Aquinas's explicit accounts of the term memoria, one finds that it is habitual knowledge, and even that the mind is present to itself and God present to the mind before any species are received from sense, so that the human imago Dei has its constitutive memoria before any conscious intellectual act is elicited. To the casual reader it may seem that a presence of God which is a memory must be a known presence; but Aquinas's own explanation of his terms does not substantiate that conclusion.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Zusammenfassung Urteil, Thomas: Gegenseitigekeit von Introspektion und Metaphysik

Kurzinhalt: are above all psychological facts; inner word: insight into phantasm, expression of a reflective act of understanding

Textausschnitt: ... that Aquinas did practice psychological introspection and through that experimental knowledge of his own soul arrived at his highly nuanced, deeply penetrating, firmly outlined theory of the nature of human intellect. Hence the light of intellect, insight into phantasm, acts of defining thought, reflective reasoning and understanding, acts of judgment are above all psychological facts. The inner word of definition is the expression of an insight into phantasm, and the insight is the goal towards which the wonder of inquiry tends. The inner word of judgment is the expression of a reflective act of understanding, and that reflective act is the goal towards which critical wonder tends.
()
No doubt, as expressed by Aquinas, these psychological facts are embedded in metaphysical categories and theorems. But without first grasping in some detail the empirical content so embedded, one risks, if not emptying the categories and theorems of all content, at least interpreting them with an impoverished generality that cannot bear the weight of the mighty superstructure of trinitarian theory. Conversely, it will be found, I believe, that our preliminary concern with psychological fact will lend a sureness, otherwise unattainable, to the interpretation of the metaphysical categories; for ...

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: processio bei Thomas: processio operationis, processio operati

Kurzinhalt: verschiedene Formulierung von processio bei Thomas; Unterschied zw. Wille und Verstand

Textausschnitt: Is there any notable significance to be attached to the foregoing variations? I do not think so. In all cases the same term is reached, namely, opposed relations of origin.
()
On the contrary, it seems a plain matter of fact that for Aquinas the second procession grounding real relations is not the procession of the act of love from the will, nor the procession of something else from the act of love within the will, but the procession in the will of the act of love from the inner word in the intellect. Advertence to this repeatedly affirmed dependence of love on inner word puts an end, very simply and very clearly, I think, to an exceptional amount of labored interpretation.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Aristoteles, Thomas; actus perfecti - imperfecti -> operatio - motus (energeia - kinesis); actus existentis in actu

Kurzinhalt: The substance of what Aquinas meant by actus perfecti and actus imperfecti is contained in the foregoing account of Aristotle. He referred to this contrast variously as a difference between operatio and motus?

Textausschnitt: 8/3 Excessive attention to the metaphysical framework with insufficient attention to the psychological content of the Thomist concept of verbum has led to a good deal of obscure profundity on the meaning of Aquinas's actus perfecti. It is necessary for us to set forth the evidence on the meaning of the phrase, and in doing so it will be well to begin from Aristotle, first because it is only a translation of Aristotle's energeia ton tetelesmenou,1 and secondly, because Aquinas, when first he uses it,2 takes it for granted that the reader knows his Aristotle and so knows what it means. Our account of Aristotle may be divided into three parts: general contrasts between operation (energeia) and movement (kinesis); the analysis of movement in the Physics; and the recurring embarrassment in the De anima occasioned by the specialization of terms in the Physics. (110f; Fs)

9/3 In the Ethics >ARNE_09_10> there is considered a Platonist argument to the effect that pleasure is not the good because pleasure is a movement and so incomplete, while the good must be complete and perfect. It is met with the observation that all movements have velocities, that pleasure has no velocity, and so pleasure cannot be a movement nor be incomplete.3 On a later page the incompleteness of movement and the completeness of operation are described at greater length. A movement becomes in time; one part succeeds another; and a whole is to be had only in the whole of the time. On the other hand, an operation such as seeing or pleasure does not become in time but rather endures through time; at once it is all that it is to be; at each instant it is completely itself. In a movement one may assign instants in which what now is is not what later will be. In an operation there is no assignable instant in which what is occurring stands in need of something further that later will make it specifically complete.4 (111f; Fs) (notabene)

10/3 A similar general contrast occurs in the Metaphysics. There is a difference between action (praxis) distinct from its end and action coincident with its end. One cannot at once be walking a given distance and have walked it, be being cured and have been cured, be learning something and have learned it. But at once one is seeing and has seen, one is understanding and has understood, one is alive and has been alive, one is happy and has been happy. In the former instances there is a difference between action and end, and we have either what is not properly action or, at best, incomplete action - such are movements. In the latter instances action and end are coincident - such are operations.5 (112; Fs)

11/3 The characteristics of movement, described in the Ethics and the Metaphysics, are submitted to analysis in the Physics. The nature of movement is difficult to grasp because it is a reality that, as reality, is incomplete and so involves the indeterminate.6 Still, movement may be defined as the act of what is in potency inasmuch as it is in potency, or as the act of the movable just as movable.7 Again, one may say that what is about to be moved is in potency to two acts: one of these is complete and so admits categorial specification; but this act is the term of another which is incomplete and so does not admit categorial specification; movement is the latter, incomplete act.8 Since this definition does not presuppose the concept of time, it is employed in defining time.9 Next it is shown that the incomplete act, movement, can occur in only three categories, namely, place, sensible quality, and physical size.10 It is insisted that movement can be had only in a corporeal, quantitative, indefinitely divisible subject.11 From the indefinite divisibility of distance and time it is concluded that in a local movement not only is there a moveri prior to every assignable motum esse but also there is an assignable motum esse prior to every assignable moveri;12 thus analysis pushes to the limit the descriptive contrast between the specific completeness of operation and the specific incompleteness, the categorial indeterminacy, of movement.13 But just how the demonstrable paradox of local movement was to be extended to alteration, growth, generation, and illumination was for the commentators an obscure and disputed point.14 (112f; Fs)

12/3 As the Physics analyzes movement, so one might expect the De anima to analyze operation. But if that expectation is verified substantially,15 there is a far more conspicuous embarrassment caused by the specialization of terms in the Physics. For in the De anima, despite the alleged wealth of the Greek language, Aristotle needed such words as kinesis, alloiosis, pathesis, in a fresh set of meanings; but instead of working out the new meanings systematically, he was content, in general, to trust his reader's intelligence and, occasionally, to add an incidental warning or outburst. Three examples of this may be noted. First, there is the remark that, because movement (kinesis) is an act (energeia) even though it is an incomplete one, we may take it that undergoing change (paschein) and being moved (kineisthai) and operating (energein) are all the same thing.16 Again, there is the explanation that the phrase 'undergoing change' (paschein) is not univocal: when the scientist's science becomes actual thought, the becoming is not an alteration or, if it is, then it is alteration of a distinct genus.17 In similar vein the third book of the De anima contains the statement to which Aquinas regularly referred18 when contrasting actus perfecti and actus imperfecti: the movement of a sense is movement of a distinct species; for movement has been defined as the operation or act (energeia) of the incomplete, but operation simply so called is of the completed.19 (113f; Fs)

13/3 The substance of what Aquinas meant by actus perfecti and actus imperfecti is contained in the foregoing account of Aristotle. He referred to this contrast variously as a difference between operatio and motus?20 or as a twofold operatio21 or finally as a twofold motus.22 Actus imperfecti was explained by noting that what is moved is in potency, that what is in potency is imperfect, and so that movement is the act of the imperfect.23 Both early and late works testify to a full awareness that movement is intrinsically temporal and specifically incomplete.24 In contrast the actus perfecti is defined as 'actus existentis in actu,'25 and even as 'actus existentis in actu secundum quod huiusmodi';26 it is specifically complete, an 'operatio consequens formam,'27 the 'operatio sensus iam facti in actu per suam speciem,'28 without need or anticipation of any ulterior complement to be itself,29 and intrinsically outside time.30 (114f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: actus perfecti (Definition: actus existentis in actu) u. imperfecti; Negation: Essentialismus: die Realität erschöpft sich nicht in Wesenheiten; Hoffnung: 'quasi quidam motus' u. 'sicut actus imperfecti'

Kurzinhalt: There are elements in reality that correspond to what we know by defining; they are called essences; but they are not the whole of reality. There are also elements of reality that are less than essences ...

Textausschnitt: 14/3 What, I may be asked, does this all amount to? In current terminology, then, it is a brilliant and penetrating negation of essentialism. There are elements in reality that correspond to what we know by defining; they are called essences; but they are not the whole of reality. There are also elements of reality that are less than essences, that are, as it were, essences-on-the-way; they are movements, acts that actualize incompletely, acts intrinsically in anticipation of completion and so intrinsically in time. But there also are elements of reality that are over and above essence; sight is an essence, but seeing is more than that essence; still, seeing is not a further essence, for seeing and sight have the same definition, which they share as act and potency; this more-than-essence is act, act of what already is completely in possession of essence, act that does not need or anticipate something further to become what it is to be, act that intrinsically stands outside time. (115; Fs) (notabene)

15/3 Such is the substance of what Aquinas meant by actus perfecti and actus imperfecti. But there are also accidental variations; for, so far was Aquinas from the stereotyped terminology that sometimes is attributed to him that he could write 'sapienus enim est non curare de nominibus.'1 A first variation is had inasmuch as the term 'operatio' is suggestive of efficient causality; hence the contrast between operation and movement is taken as ground for denying that divine activity presupposes an uncreated matter.2 A second variation arises by a natural transition from the imperfection of the material continuum with its indefinite divisibility to the imperfection of anything that has not, as yet, attained its end; in this transferred sense the Sentences speak of an actus imperfecti,3 where also one may read the more cautious statement that the act of hope is 'quasi quidam motus' and 'sicut actus imperfecti.'4 A third variation arises from the fact that what exists in act is a ground of efficient causality; thus, an angel moves locally by an application of his virtue to a continuous series of places; this local movement is described as 'motus existentis in actu.'5 I believe that only poor judgment would desire to take such instances as these, not as incidental variations, but as key passages to the meaning of the repeated statement that sensation, understanding, and willing are actus perfecti. (115f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Erleiden, pati; pati proprie - pati communiter; "actus perfectus" als "pati"; operatio und actio im Sinne von Seinsakt; pathesis, pathos - poiesis , poiema

Kurzinhalt: ... the influence of Aristotle did lead Aquinas to use operatio and actio in the sense of act or of being in act; and in that sense there is no absurdity - on the contrary, there is a necessity - in saying that such act in a creature is a patii communiter

Textausschnitt: 3. Pati

16/3 There is no difficulty in thinking of movement in the strict sense of actus imperfecti as a pati. But there appears to be enormous difficulty in thinking of movement in the broad sense, which includes the actus perfecti, as a pati. Since that difficulty necessarily tends to the substitution of what someone else thinks for what Aquinas said, we must endeavor to surmount it at once. We begin from the variety of meanings of the term pati in Aquinas's source. (116; Fs)

17/3 In the Ethics Aristotle recognizes in the soul three things: potencies, habits, and pathê. The last are illustrated by desire, anger, fear, boldness, envy, joy, friendliness, hate, longing, rivalry, pity, and in general the feelings accompanied by pleasure or pain.1 Secondly, in a logical context Aristode will speak of idia pathê, which are attributes or properties, even of ideal numbers.2 Thirdly, and this is the fundamental usage, pathos is connected with the species of movement called alteration. In general, alteration is defined as change of quality,3 but the quality subject to such change is restricted to the sensibilia per se et propria such as the white and black, the heavy and light, the hot and cold, the hard and soft, and so forth.4 Pathê are such qualities as such; they are also the process of change of such qualities; especially, they are such change when it is for the worse.5 Fourthly, in close connection with the foregoing there is the account of the affective qualities in the Categories?6 though the feelings of the Ethics are also relevant here.7 Fifthly, with reference to any movement in the strict sense Aristotle distinguishes the passive process (pathêsis) and the received term (pathos) of the incomplete act, and these he maintains to be really identical with the production (poiêsis) and the effected term (poiêma) respectively of the same incomplete act.8 Sixthly, in an extended sense already noted, paschein is employed to denote sensation which is an act of the completed;9 it is to be observed that the theorem of the identity of action and passion is extended to this usage on the ground that without such an identity it would be necessary for every mover to be moved.10 (116f; Fs)


183 The complexity of Aristotelian usage pours into the writings of Aquinas. In the Sentences some nine meanings of pati are distinguished; the basic meaning is considered to be 'alteration for the worse,' and other meanings are allowed greater or less propriety according to their approximation to what is considered basic.1 In later works this jungle growth is cut through with a distinction between pati proprie and pati communiter?"2 To pati proprie is assigned the province of Aristotelian physics and, as well, the linguistic associations of pati with suffering and of passio with human passions. On the other hand, pati communiter is a purely metaphysical idea; it is somewhat less general than 'being an effect,' for it presupposes a subject; it is described as recipere, as something found in every creature, as something following necessarily from the potentiality involved in every creature However, there seems to be a concentration on the moment of reception,3 and it is pointed out that, since this pati involves no diminution of the recipient, it might be better named a perfici.4 (117f; Fs)

184 The question before us is whether operation or action as actus perfecti can be called a pati in the sense of a received perfection. The difficulty here, insofar as I have been able to grasp it, lies in distinguishing between the grammatical subject of a transitive verb in the active voice and, on the other hand, the ontological subject of the exercise of efficient causality.a When it is true that 'I see,' it is also true that "I" is the grammatical subject of a transitive verb in the active voice. But it is mere confusion to conclude immediately that "I" also denotes the ontological subject of the exercise of efficient causality. Further, it may or may not be true that one must conclude mediately from the transitive verb to the efficient cause; with such abstract questions I am not concerned. But it is false to suppose that either Aristotle or Aquinas acknowledged or drew such a conclusion. I quote: (118; Fs)

Videbatur enim repugnare, quod sentire dicitur in actu, ei quod dictum est, quod sentire est quoddam pati et moveri. Esse enim in actu videtur magis pertinere ad agere. Et ideo ad hoc exponendum dicit [Aristoteles], quod ita dicimus sentire in actu, ac si dicamus, quod pati et moveri sint quoddam agere, idest quoddam esse in actu. Nam motus est quidam actus, sed imperfectus, ut dictum est in tertio Physicorum. Est enim actus existentis in potentia, scilicet mobilis. Sicut igitur motus est actus, ita moveri et sentire est quoddam agere, vel esse secundum actum.5

185 The question is, How can one speak of sensing in act, when one has maintained that sensing is a matter of undergoing change and being moved? For sensing in act seems to be just the opposite of being changed and being moved, namely, acting. The answer is that there is an acting which is simply being in act, and simply being in act is not opposed to being changed and being moved. On the contrary, movement itself is defined as an act. If there is no difficulty about defining movement as an act, though it is an imperfect one, there is no difficulty in saying that the pati of sensation is an act and in that sense an acting. (119; Fs) (notabene)

186 Next, one may ask whether this Aristotelian viewpoint is to be found in Aquinas's independent writings. Let us begin by noting two senses of the term 'operatic.' In many contexts it denotes the exercise of efficient causality, for example, 'Deus operatur in omni operante.' But such usage certainly is not exclusive, and, I believe, it is not the most fundamental. For operatio also means simply 'being in act,' as does the etymologically parallel energeia; and in this sense it is a perfection which, in a creature, is received and so is a pati or a passio of the operating subject. Thus, Aquinas spoke of an 'operatio non activa sed receptiva.'6 He urged that the fact that sense had an operation did not make sense an active potency; for all powers of the soul have operations but most of them are passive potencies.7 He pointed out that nature provides suitable principles for operations; when the operation is an action, the principle is an active potency; and when the operation consists in a passion, the principle is a passive potency.8 He distinguished the operation of a mover, such as heating or cutting, the operation of what is moved, such as being heated or being cut, and the operation of what exists in act without tending to effect change.9 He defined potency as just the principle of operation, whether that be action or passion.10 (119; Fs)

187 Finally, so familiar to Aquinas was the notion of operation as passive, as something to be predicated not of the mover but of the moved, that in speaking of operative grace he found it necessary to explain that in this instance operation was to be attributed to the mover because it was the operation of an effect: 'operatio enim alicuius effectus non attribuitur mobili, sed moventi.'11 That explanation would seem to be rather superfluous today when people think it a contradiction in terms to speak of the operating subject as being moved. (119f; Fs)

188 What is true of operatic also is true of actio. In an early period these terms are contrasted,12 but later they are juxtaposed in opposition to factio,13 and such equivalence subsequently seems to be maintained. Frequently enough, then, actio means the exercise of efficient causality. But this meaning is not the only meaning. It also means simply actus. It is actio in the sense of actus that is the actuality of virtue, as being is the actuality of substance.14 It is actio in the sense of actus that is the complement of potency and stands to potency as second act to first.15 It is actio in the sense of actus that pertains to an active potency or to a passive potency.16 It is actio in the sense of actus that makes it possible to define passion as the actio of alterable quality,17 and as the actio of the patient.18 Finally, the action that goes forth into external matter would seem to have a prescriptive claim to denoting the exercise of efficient causality; but in an earlier work one may read that transient action is the act and perfection of the patient;19 and in later works one may read that transient action is the action and perfection of the patient,20 and the action and perfection of the transformed matter.21 Presumably, passive potencies and patients and transformed matter have an actio not in the sense that they are exercising efficient causality but in the sense that they are in act. (120; Fs)

189 To conclude, the influence of Aristotle did lead Aquinas to use operatio and actio in the sense of act or of being in act; and in that sense there is no absurdity - on the contrary, there is a necessity - in saying that such act in a creature is a pati communiter. However, before making any applications to the act, the action, the operation of understanding, it will be necessary to consider the notion of active potency. (120f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Duplex actio; Unterschied zw. 'processio operati' und 'processio operationis'; Wirkursache benötigt keine materia; Unterschied zw. Der Wirkursache, die im Tätigen bleibt und jener, die von der From seinen Ausgang nimmt; operatio ist mehr als Form

Kurzinhalt: ... actio that remains in the agent does not involve efficient causality inasmuch as it proceeds from form, species, or informed potency; for that procession is not 'processio operati' but 'processio operationis' ...

Textausschnitt: 5. Duplex Actio

202 Frequently Aquinas distinguished two types of actio, one which remains in its subject, another which goes forth into external matter to effect its transformation. This distinction has led subsequent writers to make metaphysical ultimates of what they term immanent and transient action, and, as not rarely happens, such speculative constructions are a barrier rather than a help to a grasp of St Thomas's thought, for they give an air of finality and completeness to what, in point of fact, contained not a little of the incidental and was not complete. (128; Fs)

203 Aquinas alleges two different sources in Aristotle for his duplex actio. Contrasts between actio and factio, and so between agere and facere, activum and factivum, agibile and factibile stem from Aristotle's Ethics.1 In the relevant passage Aristotle was distinguishing art, science, prudence, wisdom, and intellect; three of these (science, wisdom, and intellect) regard the necessary; the other pair (art and prudence) regard the contingent; the distinction between them is set forth by a parallel distinction between production (poiesis) and moral conduct (praxis).2 Now in medieval Latin both poiesis and praxis might be rendered by actio, and in such cases Aquinas's distinction was between the actio of moral conduct, which is a perfection of the agent, and the actio, more properly factio, which transforms external matter. (128f; Fs)

204 A corollary may be noted. When Aquinas restricts actio to beings that have dominion over their acts, actio has at least an association with moral conduct. 'Bruta aguntur et non agunt,' because St John Damascene said so;3 but also because Aristotle remarked that sense is not a principle of moral conduct, since brutes have senses yet have no part in moral conduct.4 The 'non agunt' does not mean that brutes do not act in the sense of 'aliquam actionem exercere,' which may mean simply being in act;5 it does not even deny that brutes move themselves locally inasmuch as one part in act moves another part in potency. (129; Fs)

205 Evidently this source in the Ethics lacks generality.6 But the other source in the ninth book of the Metaphysics is so general that it deals not with action but with act. The problem under discussion is the essential priority of act over potency, because act is the end of potency, the end is a cause, and a cause is prior.7 The point was evident in cases in which only potency and act existed; but when besides potency and act there was also an ulterior product, the apparent difficulty was met by noting that then the act was in the thing produced and that it emerged simultaneously with the product.8 There followed the familiar corollary on the twofold subject of the act (energeia).9 (129; Fs)

206 The medieval translator laid no stress on actio: the energeia that is in the agent was translated by actio; the one that is in the product was translated by actus.10 The opposite usage may be found in the Prima pars.11 General Thomist usage is variable. In the Sentences and in the De veritate an attempt is made to reserve operatio for the act that remains and actio for the act that goes forth.12 In the Contra Gentiles, factio is proposed for the act that goes forth and operatio or even actio for the act that remains.13 (130; Fs)

207 In the Depotentia, the Contra Gentiles, and the Prima pars, the distinction is drawn with respect to a duplex operatio.14 However, it is duplex actio that is regular in the Prima pars.15 Still, in the De potentia mention was made of a duplex actus secundus16 and this viewpoint returns in the Prima secundae,17 where also one may find an identification of the act that goes forth with the actio in passo of the Physics.18 As a final observation, one may note that Aquinas did not keep his two sources distinct; in both the Contra Gentiles and the Prima secundae he refers to the ninth book of the Metaphysics and proceeds to speak of factio, a term that implicitly is present in the Metaphysics but explicitly only in the Ethics.19 (130; Fs)

208 This fluidity of terminology is not surprising unless one indulges in an anachronistic projection of present usage upon the past. On the other hand, the meaning of these passages and their significance are quite clear. There is an act that remains in the agent and is the perfection of the agent; there is another act that goes forth into external matter and effects a change of it. The pair spontaneously come together in thought - grammatically because both are expressed by transitive verbs in the active voice, and historically because both proceed from the 'principium actionis' that was Aquinas's initial definition of active potency. (130f; Fs)

209 Even though later Aquinas did manifest a preference for a different definition of potentia activa, there was a deeper root in Aristotle himself to keep the two types of act associated; for it is a form that is the principle both of the act remaining in the agent and of the act that goes forth. In the Physics it was pointed out that the mover possesses a form which is principle of movement; for it is a man in act that makes a man out of what is a man only in potency.20 In his Sentences Aquinas refers to this passage and applies it both to transient and to immanent acts: 'causa autem actionis est species, ut dicitur in III Phys.; quia unumquodque agit ratione formae alicuius quam habet [...] sicut ignis qui desiccat et calefacit per caliditatem et siccitatem, et homo audit et videt per auditum et visum.'21 (131; Fs)

210 Even in his latest works Aquinas will speak of active potency as pertaining to things because of their forms,22 and will explain differences of efficacy because of differences in the perfection of forms; thus, fire heats and illuminates; what is so heated or illuminated can do the same but only in a lesser degree, while merely intentional forms cannot have natural effects.23 But form is not only the ground of efficiency but also the principle of operation: 'propria forma uniuscuiusque faciens ipsum esse in actu, est principium propriae operationis ipsius.'24 Such operation is the end of the operator and more perfect than his form;25 it is what is last and most perfect in each thing, and so it is compared to form as act to potency, as second act to first act.26 (131; Fs)

211 But however germane to Aquinas's thought as it actually developed, duplex actio is not a capsule of metaphysical ultimates. The act that goes forth into external matter corresponds to the predicament of action as defined in the Sentences: 'actio secundum quod est praedicamentum dicit aliquid fluens ab agente et cum motu.'27 But later Aquinas wrote that there are two actions, one that involves movement (in the sense of incomplete act), and another that does not, as when God causes grace in the soul. On the latter he remarked, 'Quod quidem difficile est ad intelligendum non valentibus abstrahere considerationem suam ab actionibus quae sunt cum motu.'28 (131f; Fs)

212 This tart observation would seem to be relevant to the passage in the commentary on the Physics where, after explaining Aristotle's concept of action and passion,29 he goes on to give his own quite different and quite universal definitions of the predicament of action and passion.30 As causal efficiency does not require external matter and movement, so also it need not go forth: there is a 'processio operati' of the inner word within the intellect.31 On the other hand, actio that remains in the agent does not involve efficient causality inasmuch as it proceeds from form, species, or informed potency; for that procession is not 'processio operati' but 'processio operationis';32 as we have just seen, operation is more perfect than form, and only an instrument is less perfect than its effect. The idea that efficient causality occurs in this type of actio has, I fear, little more basis than a failure to distinguish between the two different ways in which Aquinas defined his potentia activa. (132f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: species, eidos: Begriff bei Thomas; Form als Prinzip des Verstehens und des inneren Wortes; operatio u. actio

Kurzinhalt: entsprechend d. Tätigkeit als principium actionis u. p. effectus -> Form als Prinzip d. Verstehens u. d. Gedachten; ebenso species: Aktuierung des Intellekts und inneres Wort; actio - operatio: Trinität

Textausschnitt: 6. Species, Intelligere

213 The Latin term species translates Aristotle's term eidos and shares its ambiguity. It may mean a form, and then it includes neither common nor individual matter; and it may mean a universal, and then it includes common but not individual matter.1 In cognitional contexts species occurs in both senses: 'similitude rei intellectae, quae est species intelligibilis, est forma secundum quam intellectus intelligit';2 'intellectus igitur abstrahit speciem rei naturalis a materia sensibili individuali, non autem a materia sensibili communi.'3 The former species is a form; the latter is a universal. To determine in which sense the term species is employed is not always as easy as in the above cases. However, our criteria may be extended: a form is known only by metaphysical analysis; but the universal enters into the knowledge of everyone. To the objection that intellect does not abstract species because, according to Aristotle, intellect knows species in the phantasm, Aquinas answered: (133; Fs)

Dicendum quod intellectus noster et abstrahit species intelligibiles a phantasmatibus, inquantum considerat naturas rerum in universali; et tamen intelligit eas in phantasmatibus, quia non potest intelligere ea quorum species abstrahit, nisi convertendo se ad phantasmata, ut supra dictum est.4

214 The generality of this statement, the fact that universals are being considered, the fact that the species are known in the phantasm, all favor taking species in the sense of a universal. On the other hand, to the objection that names signify things known and that, according to Aristotle, names are signs of the passions of the soul so that the things known are passions of the soul, Aquinas answered: (134; Fs)

Et utraque haec operatic coniungitur in intellectu. Nam primo quidem consideratur passio intellectus possibilis, secundum quod informatur specie intelligibili. Qua quidem formatus format secundo vel definitionem vel divisionem vel compositionem, quae per vocem significatur. Unde ratio quam significat nomen est definitio; et enuntiatio significat compositionem et divisionem intellectus. Non ergo voces significant ipsas species intelligibiles, sed ea quae intellectus sibi format ad iudicandum de rebus exterioribus.5
215 Here we have metaphysical analysis revealing the passion of the possible intellect being informed by species and its activity in forming definitions and judgments; species means form, and though the universal is referred to as the 'ratio quam significat nomen,' it is not here called a species. (134; Fs)

216 Our present purpose is to discuss the relation between species as form and the act intelligere. Our view is that this relation is expressed by Aquinas in two different manners - one according to what we have ventured to name the Avicennist definition of active potency, the other according to the Aristotelian concept of form as natural potency. (134f; Fs)

217 First, then, just as the De potentia conceives active potency as the principle of operation or action which takes place in virtue of form,6 so one may read that (intellect actuated by) species is the 'principium actus intelligendi,'7 the 'principium actionis,'8 the 'principium formale actionis,'9 the 'principium formale quo intellectus intelligit.'10 Again, just as the De potentia conceives passive potency as potency to the reception of form,11 and contrasts this passive potency with the active potency to operation and action, so one may read a parallel contrast between the reception of species, which is named a passio, and the subsequent operatio, which is an actus perfecti.12 (135; Fs)

218 Thirdly, just as the De potentia distinguishes between 'principium actionis' and 'principium effectus,13 and again between action and the term of action,14 so there is a contrast between the form which is the principle of the act of understanding and the thought-out form of a house which is the term of the act of understanding and, as it were, its effect;15 similarly contrasted are the species which is the form that actuates the intellect and is its principle of action, the action of the intellect, and the inner word which is term to the action and, as it were, something constituted by it.16 Finally, while we have seen that the terms operatio and actio sometimes mean simply act or being in act and sometimes mean the exercise of efficient causality, we now find that the precision of trinitarian theory led Aquinas to distinguish exactly between these two meanings with regard to the operation or action of intellect; when that operation is meant in the sense of act, it is termed intelligere; but when by operation is meant that one act is grounding another, it is termed dicere.17 (135f; Fs)


219 So much for a sketch of one scheme of metaphysical analysis applied by Aquinas to intellect. For it is only to be expected that there should be in his writings some evidence of another scheme of analysis that stands in more immediate conformity with Aristotelian thought. The most impressive example of such conformity occurs in the following incidental statement. (136; Fs)

... forma recepta in aliquo non movet illud in quo recipitur; sed ipsum habere talem formam, est ipsum motum esse; sed movetur ab exteriori agente; sicut corpus quod calefit per ignem, non movetur a calore recepto, sed ab igne. Ita intellectus non movetur a specie iam recepta, vel a vero quod consequitur ipsam speciem; sed ab aliqua re exteriori quae imprimit in intellectum, sicut est intellectus agens, vel phantasia, vel aliquid aliud huiusmodi.1 (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Form, species: in der 2-fachen Bedeutung in Übereinstimmung mit Lehre und Einsicht

Kurzinhalt: Beispiel: Wille aktuiert als Habitus setzt noch nicht den Willensakt zum Ziel; operatio mehr als Form; processio operationis u. p. operati; so wie die Form nicht Wirkursache des Seins ist, so die species WU des intelligere

Textausschnitt: 220 It may not be out of place to note how exactly this fits in both with general doctrine and with intellectual theory. It is in accord with the general doctrine that the efficient cause not merely produces the form but also produces the movement consequent to the form1 that what produces the species should also produce the consequent intelligere. It is in accord with the general doctrine that form is less perfect than operation2 and so not its proportionate cause, that the species should not move intellect to the act intelligere. It is in accord with the general doctrine 'quidquid movetur ab alio movetur'3 that intellect actuated by species should not produce its acts of understanding, just as the will actuated by a habit does not produce its act of willing the end; on the other hand, just as will actually willing the end moves itself to willing the means4 so intellect actually understanding is able to utter, constitute, produce its inner word of definition or judgment. (137; Fs)

221 Further, the passage before us accords with specific intellectual doctrines. It makes it quite clear why the procession of the act of understanding is only a 'processio operationis,' while the procession of the act of defining or of judging is a 'processio operati.'5 It is quite in harmony with the statement, 'sicut enim esse consequitur formam, ita intelligere sequitur speciem intelligibilem,'6 for no form is efficient cause of its esse and similarly species is not the efficient cause of intelligere. Again, it harmonizes with the parallel statement that '[...] intelligere, quod ita se habet ad intellectum in actu, sicut esse ad ens in actu';7 for the ens in actu is not the efficient cause of its esse. Finally, of course, there is no opposition between this scheme of analysis and the preceding; when (intellect actuated by) species is said to be the principle of action or the principle of operation, it is not said to be the principle of an effect; as we have seen, these two are repeatedly distinguished by St Thomas. (137f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Das Objekt der passiven Potenz ist aktiv -> auch das intelligere ist ein pati; auch der Wille als pati

Kurzinhalt: that sentire is a pati and that intelligere is a pati; he will moves itself only inasmuch as it is in act with respect to the end

Textausschnitt: 225 In the passages quoted Aquinas states that the object of the passive potency is active, not with respect to the species alone, but with respect to the act, the action, the operation of the potency. The coherence of this position with general Thomist doctrine has engaged us through considerations of actus perfecti, pati, potentia activa, and duplex actio. We may perhaps be permitted, after this somewhat lengthy preamble, to point out that Aquinas as a matter of fact actually does say that sentire is a pati and that intelligere is a pati, and then to present our daring hypothesis that perhaps Aquinas meant what he said. In the following passages the reader will note that Aquinas is speaking not of some prior condition of sensation but of sensation itself and that Aquinas does not say that sensation has a prior condition or cause in some change but that it consists in a change and is completed in a change. I quote: (140; Fs)

... sentire consistit in moveri et pati.1 ... sentire consistit in quodam pati et alterari.2 ... cognitio sensus perficitur in hoc ipso quod sensus a sensibili movetur.3 Anima igitur sensitiva non se habet in sentiendo sicut movens et agens, sed sicut id quo patiens patitur.4... si vero operatio ilia consistit in passione, adest ei principium passivum, sicut patet de principiis sensitivis in animalibus.5 ... sensum affici est ipsum eius sentire.6... sentire perficitur per actionem sensibilis in sensum.7 ... duplex operatio. Una secundum solam immutationem, et sic perficitur operatio sensus per hoc quod immutatur a sensibili.8 ... cognitio sensus exterioris perficitur per solam immutationem sensus a sensibili.9

226 With regard to external sense it would seem that the object is active, not merely inasmuch as it causes the species, but also inasmuch as it causes the act, action, operation of the sensitive potency. (142; Fs)

227 Aquinas had the habit of quoting Aristotle to the effect that 'intelligere est quoddam pati.' In the Sentences, discussing the mutability proper to creatures, he concludes that creatures are mutable both inasmuch as they can lose what they possess and inasmuch as they can acquire what they do not possess; the latter is a true mutability, though in a broad sense, as when all reception is said to be a pati and moveri, for example, 'intelligere quoddam pati est.'10 Again, discussing the meanings of pati, he urges that there is no pati proprie in the intellect because it is immaterial, but still there is there an element of passion inasmuch as there is reception; and that is the meaning of 'intelligere est pati quoddam.'11 (142; Fs)

228 Again, meeting the objection that the divine essence cannot be the object of created knowledge because the judged is to the judge as passive, he answered that on the contrary the sensible and intelligible objects are to sense and intellect as agent inasmuch as sentire and intelligere are a pati quoddam!12 Arguing against Averroes, he made an antithesis of agere and pati and then urged, 'Posse autem intelligere est posse pati: cum 'intelligere quoddam pati sit.'13 Proving that the possible intellect was a passive potency, he concluded, 'Sic igitur patet quod intelligere nostrum est quoddam pati, secundum tertium modum passionis. Et per consequens intellectus est potentia passiva.'14 (142; Fs)

229 In these passages it is quite clear that Aquinas said that the act of understanding itself, intelligere, was a pati. Such statements fit in perfectly with the general doctrine of agent object and passive potency; they fit in perfectly with the general Aristotelian scheme of analysis that distinguishes neatly between nature, which is a principle of movement in the thing moved, and efficient potency, which is a principle of movement in the other or, if in self, then in self as other; nor is there any incompatibility between them and the Avicennist scheme of analysis except the merely apparent incompatibility that arises from the blunder of confusing what Aquinas distinguished - active potency as the principle of an operation and active potency as the principle of an effect. (142f; Fs)

230 But this, the reader will perhaps say, is all impossible. I am afraid I have not here the space to discuss abstract impossibilities. I am concerned with matters of fact, with what Aquinas said; and lest there be any misapprehension about Aquinas's ideas on the actio manens in agente, I proceed to observe that not only sentire and intelligere but also velle can be a pati.b For with respect to the interior act of the will, the grace of God is operative and the will of man is 'mota et non movens.'15 Though not stated so explicitly, the same is true with respect to the act of willing the end as conceived in the De mala and the Prima secundae; for in these works the will moves itself only inasmuch as it is in act with respect to the end, but to that act it is moved by an external principle, God.16 Finally, what is true of these later works with respect to willing the end is true more generally in earlier works in which there appears no mention of self-movement in the will.17 (143; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Wille, bewegt von Gott; operatio receptiva

Kurzinhalt: what does ... the will moved by God, when it is moved by God, while it is moved by God, confer or contribute?

Textausschnitt: On the other hand, as soon as the theory of God moving the will to the act of willing the end was proposed, Aquinas immediately perceived a difficulty; that difficulty to a modern Scholastic would be in all probability that man must be the efficient cause of his own operation, action, act, willing; but to Aquinas the difficulty was that the act must be not violent but natural; he noticed it both in the De malo and in the Prima secundae, and his answers run as follows:
()
Now what does the patient, the will moved by God, when it is moved by God, while it is moved by God, confer or contribute? It operates. It wills. In this case the operation is an operatio receptiva, just as sentire is a pati of sense and just as intelligere is a pati of the possible intellect. The will operates inasmuch as it is the will that is actuated. The will contributes inasmuch as an act received in the will has to be a 'willing,' not because it is act, nor merely because of the extrinsic mover, but proximately because act is limited by the potency in which it is received.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Zusammenfassung Kap. 3; Unterscheidungen; intellectus agens - possibilis; aktive - passive Potenz

Kurzinhalt: distinction between: efficient - natural potency; agent - possible intellect (intellectus agens, possibilis); intelligere - dicere; agent - terminal - final object; habit: science, wisdom

Textausschnitt: 240 First, there seem to be no notable variations in the concept of procession, and in particular there seems no reason for supposing that the doctrine of De veritate, q. 4, a. 2, ad 7m was retracted or revised later: the act of love with respect to an end is, as proceeding from the will, 'processio operationis,' but as proceeding from the inner word, 'processio operati.' (147f; Fs)

241 Second, the actio manens in agente is act and perfection; as act, it admits no further description; for description is of limitation, and limitation is due not to act but to potency; but as act of someone, it has the characteristic of being an ulterior actuation of what already is completed and perfected by the specific essence of the act; it is act beyond essence and so is contrasted with the act of the incomplete, which is act as process towards essence. Incidentally, it was Scotus who affirmed immanent action to lie in the first species of the predicament, quality.1 I have not noticed such a statement in Aquinas, but I suggest that it would be Thomistic to affirm that, as esse is substantial, so immanent act is qualitative;2 for the essence that esse actuates is substance and the essence that immanent act actuates is a quality. (??? 148; Fs)

243 Thirdly, among the various meanings of passio, pati, many are opposed to immanent act; but pati in the metaphysical sense of receiving is opposed only to the exercise of efficient causality in an equally strict metaphysical sense; hence pati is not incompatible with immanent act or with actio or operatio in the sense of immanent act; on the contrary, inasmuch as immanent act is a perfection received in a creature, necessarily it is a pati. (148; Fs) (notabene)

244 Fourthly, a distinction is necessary between efficient potency, principle of act in the other or in self as other, and natural potency, principle of act in the selfsame; the active and passive potencies of De potentia, q. 1, a. 1, and the active and passive principles of Contra Gentiles, 3, c. 23, are subdivisions of natural potency, and so both are receptive potencies and principles; hence the apparent paradox that an active potency or principle is also receptive. This paradox is only apparent: what is opposed to receptive potency is efficient potency and not some subdivision of natural potency. On the other hand, the appearances are impressive: just as Aristotle was handicapped in writing his De anima by the technical elaborations of his Physics, so Aquinas was handicapped both by Aristotle's lack of generality in conceiving the efficient cause and by the initial strong influence of Avicenna; for him to clarify the notion of potentia activa by appealing to the notion of causal efficiency was impossible, for the latter notion was just as much in need of clarification; hence only indirectly can we observe differences that are crucial: inasmuch as 'principium motus' and even 'principium activum motus' is not the 'movens' or the 'motor'; inasmuch as 'principium operationis vel actionis' does not mean the same thing as 'principium effectus, operati, termini producti' and does not even necessarily imply it; inasmuch as form is cause of esse and operation; inasmuch as subject is cause, active principle, somehow active cause, and productive of accidents which nonetheless emanate by a natural resultance. (148f; Fs)

245 Fifthly, the foregoing clarification of Thomist usage and principles is of paramount importance in grasping Thomist metaphysics as applied to psychology; a failure to distinguish between efficient and natural potency results in a negation of the division of objects into agent and terminal, and the elimination of the agent object provides a metaphysical scheme into which Thomist psychology does not fit; further, natural potency which, though receptive, nonetheless makes a most significant contribution to its act, tends to disappear to be replaced by efficient forms and habits in need of a divine praemotio physica which, I have argued elsewhere,3 cannot be said to be a doctrine stated or implied by Aquinas; and incidentally, we may ask whether this neglect of natural potency has not some bearing on unsatisfactory conceptions of obediential potency. (149; Fs)

246 The coherence of present conclusions with the psychological data already assembled may be noted briefly. The distinction between agent intellect and possible intellect is a distinction between an efficient potency that produces and a natural potency that receives. The distinction between the possible intellect of one that is learning and the possible intellect of one in possession of a science is a distinction between the De potentia's passive potency to the reception of form and its active potency to the exercise of operation in virtue of form. (149; Fs) (notabene)

247 The distinction between intelligere and dicere is a distinction between the two meanings of action, operation: intelligere is action in the sense of act; dicere is action in the sense of operating an effect. The distinction between agent object and terminal object is to be applied twice. On the level of intellectual apprehension the agent object is the quidditas rei materialis, not to ti estin but to ti ên einai, known in and through a phantasm illuminated by agent intellect; this agent object is the obiectum proprium intellectus humani; it is the object of insight. Corresponding to this agent object there is the terminal object of the inner word; this is the concept, and the first of concepts is ens, the obiectum commune intellectus. Again, on the level of judgment the agent object is the objective evidence provided by sense and/or empirical consciousness, ordered conceptually and logically in a reductio ad principia, and moving to the critical act of understanding. Corresponding to this agent object, there is the other terminal object, the inner word of judgment, the verum, in and through which is known the final object, the ens reale. (149f; Fs)

248 Here, as is apparent, metaphysics and psychology go hand in hand, and the metaphysical analysis is but the more general form of the psychological analysis. Souls are distinguished by their potencies, potencies by their acts, acts by their objects. The final object of intellect is the real; the real is known through an immanent object produced by intellect, the true; the true supposes a more elementary immanent object also produced by the intellect, the definition. This production is not merely utterance, dicere, but the utterance of intelligence in act, or rationally conscious disregard of the irrelevant, of critical evaluation of all that is relevant, of intelligere.4 This intelligere can be what it is only if there are objects to move it as well as the objects that it produces: the intelligere that expresses itself in judgment is moved by the relevant evidence; the intelligere that expresses itself in definition is moved by illuminated phantasm. But evidence as relevant and phantasm as illuminated are not mere sensible data; hence besides the sensitive potencies and the possible intellect there is needed an agent intellect. (150; Fs)

249 Finally, as the contrast between the labor of study and the ease of subsequent mastery manifests, there are forms or habits to be developed in the possible intellect - understanding for the grasp of principles, science for the grasp of implications, wisdom for right judgment on the validity both of principles and of conclusions; they come to us through acts of understanding; they stand to acts of understanding as first act to second; and like the second acts, they are produced by agent objects which themselves are instruments of agent intellect. (150f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Analogie der materia prima bei Aristoteles; Folgen dieser Sicht: gegen Materialisten, Plato, Kant

Kurzinhalt: ... sicut se habet aes ad statuam et lignum ad lectum, et quodlibet materiale et informe ad formam, hoc dicimus esse materiam primam

Textausschnitt: 1. The Analogy of Matter

255 The old naturalists had concluded, not only from beds and tables to an underlying subject 'wood,' but also from wood and bones to an element 'earth' and from gold and bronze (they could be melted) to an element 'water.' Aristotle accepted the principle of such analysis: any change is defined for thought by stating the underlying subject and the variable determination or form; and what holds for defining thought, also holds for the real thing .1 But while he accepted the principle, he corrected the conclusion. The ultimate subject of change in the older philosophies had always been some sensible body; that was the stuff of the universe; it alone was substantial and permanent; all else was accidental and mutable.2 Against this materialism Aristotle argued that every assignable object was subject to change; the element 'air' could be changed into the element 'water'; and so he concluded that the ultimate subject of change could not be an assignable object; it could be neither quid nor quantum nor quale nor any other determinate type of reality;3 it could not, of itself, be knowable;4 its nature could be stated only by recourse to analogy. (154; Fs)

Quod igitur sic se habet ad ipsas substantias naturales, sicut se habet aes ad statuam et lignum ad lectum, et quodlibet materiale et informe ad formam, hoc dicimus esse materiam primam.5

... materia prima... se habet ad formas substantiales, sicut materiae sensibiles ad formas accidentales.6

... (materia prima) ita se habet ad omnes formas et privationes, sicut se habet subiectum alterabile ad qualitates contrarias.7

256 Such is the defining analogy of matter. In its limit it defines prime matter, which is proportionate to substantial form. And as prime matter of itself is not knowable, so substantial form has the complementary distinction of being knowable by intellect alone.8 (155; Fs)

257 The full significance of this analogy is not easy to measure. It eliminates the materialism of the old naturalists for whom the real was the sensible.9 It corrects the misguided intellectualism of Plato, for whom the intelligible was real but not of this world. One might even say that by anticipation it puts in its proper place and perspective, that of prime matter, what Kant thought was the thing-in-itself. It does all this because it places in the most material of assignable material things an intelligible component known by our intellects and identifiable in our knowledge; that intelligible component, form, species, quiddity, has as much title to being named 'cause' and 'nature' as has matter itself; and what it is is fixed by its relation to the ratio rei, the ratio definitiva rei, the ratio quidditativa rei.10 Conversely, it is only because Aristotle's real thing is not the materialists' real thing that Aristotle was able to satisfy his own epistemological law: unless particulars are identical, at least inadequately, with their quiddities, then the former cannot be objects of scientific knowledge and the latter cannot be realities.11 (155; Fs)

258 But the significance of the analogy is not confined to its metaphysical limit of prime matter and substantial form. Besides prime matter, there are sensible and intelligible matter, common and individual matter, appendages of matter, parts of the matter, material and individual conditions. What are all these? The answer is simple if one grasps that natural form stands to natural matter as the object of insight (forma intelligibilis) stands to the object of sense (materia sensibilis).12 But to convince conceptualists, a more detailed approach is necessary. Just as the correspondence between definitions and things was the ultimate ground of the analysis of change into subject, privation, and form,13 whence proceeded the notion of prime matter, so the more detailed correspondence between parts of the definition and parts of the thing should bring to light the other elements in the analogy. Accordingly we proceed to sample a lengthy and complex Aristotelian discussion.14 (155f; Fs)

259 Segments are parts of circles, and letters are parts of syllables. Why is it that the definition of the circle makes no mention of segments, while the definition of the syllable must mention letters? A typical solution is found in the contrast between 'curvature' and 'snubness': curvature is curvature whether in a nose or not; but snubness is snubness only in a nose. In general one may say that, as without proportionate matter there cannot be the corresponding material form (just as without a proportionate phantasm there cannot be the corresponding insight), so for different forms different measures of matter are necessary. There must be letters if there are to be syllables; but the necessary letters are not necessarily in wax or in ink or in stone; hence letters are de ratione speciei or partes speciei; but letters as in wax or as in ink or as in stone are partes materiae. Similarly, one cannot have a particular circle without having potential segments; but the notion of circle is prior to the notion of segment, since the latter cannot be defined without presupposing the notion of the former; and so one can appeal either to the potentiality of the segments or to the priority of the definition of circle to conclude that segments are, with respect to the circle, partes materiae.15 (156; Fs) (notabene)

260 The notion of priority is of wide and nuanced application. The right angle is prior to the acute; the circle to the semicircle; and man to hand or finger. In each of these instances the former is a whole and the latter a part; in each the definition of the former must be presupposed by a definition of the latter; in each, accordingly, the latter does not enter into the definition of the former and so is a pars materiae. But complex cases are not to be solved so simply. Parts of a living body cannot be defined without reference to their function in the whole; again, the whole itself cannot be defined without reference to its formal principle, which constitutes it as a whole; accordingly, the soul and its potencies must be prior to the body and its parts. Still, it does not follow that parts of the body are mere partes materiae, that 'man' can be defined without bothering about corporeal parts just as 'circle' can be defined without bothering whether it be made of wood or of bronze. The difference arises because the principle of priority must here be complemented by the principle of proportion between form and matter; a circle requires no more than intelligible matter; man requires sensible matter;16 and so while bronze and wood are not de ratione speciei circuli still flesh and bones are de ratione speciei hominis.17 (156f; Fs)

261 A sufficient sample has been taken from Aristotle's involved discussion to make it plain that matter is not merely prime matter but also the matter that is sensibly perceived and imaginatively represented. If further one wishes to understand why the discussion is so complex, why Aristotle warned against simple rules of solution,18 even perhaps a conceptualist might consider the hypothesis that the real principle of solution is neither one rule nor any set of rules but rather the fashioner of all rules, intelligence itself in act, determining what it takes as relevant to itself and so de ratione speciei and what it dismisses as irrelevant to itself and so pertaining to the partes materiae. (157; Fs)

262 In any case let us close this section with a summary account of the analogy of matter. In the first instance, matter is the matter of common sense, the wood of the table and the bronze in a statue. But unless corrected, that notion easily leads to materialism, whether the crude materialism of the old naturalists or the elaborate materialism of the nineteenth-century atomists, who equally considered the real to be the sensible. On the other hand, the material world is neither sheer flux, as for Plato, nor unknowable in itself, as for Kant. The higher synthesis of these opposites lies in defining matter as what is known by intellect indirectly. Directly intellect knows forms, species, quiddities; but these knowns have antecedent suppositions, simultaneous suppositions, and consequents, all of which, as such, are indirectly known. (157; Fs) (notabene)

263 Antecedent suppositions are matter in the sense that genus is named matter and specific difference is named form, and again in the sense that substance is named matter and accident is named form; such usage is Aristotelian and Thomist but still somewhat improper. Simultaneous suppositions fall into two classes: if they pertain to the intelligible unity of the form, as letters to syllable, they are parts of the form, de ratione speciei, and in Thomist usage common matter; if they do not pertain to the intelligible unity of the form yet are ever included in some fashion in the concrete presentation, they are partes materiae or material conditions or individual matter. Finally, consequents that are contingent and potential, as segments to circles, are again partes materiae. Clearly, it is the second of these three types of indirectly knowns that offers the principal meaning of the term 'matter,' and it is this meaning that the analogy of matter considers chiefly. The general analogy is the proportion of wood to tables and bronze to statues; but the specifically Aristotelian analogy is that natural form is to natural matter as intelligible form is to sensible matter,19 that is, as the object of insight is to the object of sense. (157f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: materia prima; materia: Unterscheidung; partes materiae - formae; BeispieL Kreissegment, Buchstabe; proportionale Materie

Kurzinhalt: Besides prime matter, there are sensible and intelligible matter, common and individual matter, appendages of matter, parts of the matter, material and individual conditions. What are all these?

Textausschnitt: 258 But the significance of the analogy is not confined to its metaphysical limit of prime matter and substantial form. Besides prime matter, there are sensible and intelligible matter, common and individual matter, appendages of matter, parts of the matter, material and individual conditions. What are all these? The answer is simple if one grasps that natural form stands to natural matter as the object of insight (forma intelligibilis) stands to the object of sense (materia sensibilis).1 But to convince conceptualists, a more detailed approach is necessary. Just as the correspondence between definitions and things was the ultimate ground of the analysis of change into subject, privation, and form,2 whence proceeded the notion of prime matter, so the more detailed correspondence between parts of the definition and parts of the thing should bring to light the other elements in the analogy. Accordingly we proceed to sample a lengthy and complex Aristotelian discussion.3 (155f; Fs)

259 Segments are parts of circles, and letters are parts of syllables. Why is it that the definition of the circle makes no mention of segments, while the definition of the syllable must mention letters? A typical solution is found in the contrast between 'curvature' and 'snubness': curvature is curvature whether in a nose or not; but snubness is snubness only in a nose. In general one may say that, as without proportionate matter there cannot be the corresponding material form (just as without a proportionate phantasm there cannot be the corresponding insight), so for different forms different measures of matter are necessary. There must be letters if there are to be syllables; but the necessary letters are not necessarily in wax or in ink or in stone; hence letters are de ratione speciei or partes speciei; but letters as in wax or as in ink or as in stone are partes materiae. Similarly, one cannot have a particular circle without having potential segments; but the notion of circle is prior to the notion of segment, since the latter cannot be defined without presupposing the notion of the former; and so one can appeal either to the potentiality of the segments or to the priority of the definition of circle to conclude that segments are, with respect to the circle, partes materiae.4 (156; Fs) (notabene)

260 The notion of priority is of wide and nuanced application. The right angle is prior to the acute; the circle to the semicircle; and man to hand or finger. In each of these instances the former is a whole and the latter a part; in each the definition of the former must be presupposed by a definition of the latter; in each, accordingly, the latter does not enter into the definition of the former and so is a pars materiae. But complex cases are not to be solved so simply. Parts of a living body cannot be defined without reference to their function in the whole; again, the whole itself cannot be defined without reference to its formal principle, which constitutes it as a whole; accordingly, the soul and its potencies must be prior to the body and its parts. Still, it does not follow that parts of the body are mere partes materiae, that 'man' can be defined without bothering about corporeal parts just as 'circle' can be defined without bothering whether it be made of wood or of bronze. The difference arises because the principle of priority must here be complemented by the principle of proportion between form and matter; a circle requires no more than intelligible matter; man requires sensible matter;5 and so while bronze and wood are not de ratione speciei circuli still flesh and bones are de ratione speciei hominis.6 (156f; Fs)

261 A sufficient sample has been taken from Aristotle's involved discussion to make it plain that matter is not merely prime matter but also the matter that is sensibly perceived and imaginatively represented. If further one wishes to understand why the discussion is so complex, why Aristotle warned against simple rules of solution,7 even perhaps a conceptualist might consider the hypothesis that the real principle of solution is neither one rule nor any set of rules but rather the fashioner of all rules, intelligence itself in act, determining what it takes as relevant to itself and so de ratione speciei and what it dismisses as irrelevant to itself and so pertaining to the partes materiae. (157; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Zusammenfassung: Analogie der materia: drei Arten von materia: Gattung, Buchstabe (Holz), Kreissegment

Kurzinhalt: höhere Einheit (im Ggs zu Plato und Kant): indirekte Erkenntnis der materia: antecedent, simultaneous, consequents suppositions; natural form is to natural matter as intelligible form is to sensible matter

Textausschnitt: 262 In any case let us close this section with a summary account of the analogy of matter. In the first instance, matter is the matter of common sense, the wood of the table and the bronze in a statue. But unless corrected, that notion easily leads to materialism, whether the crude materialism of the old naturalists or the elaborate materialism of the nineteenth-century atomists, who equally considered the real to be the sensible. On the other hand, the material world is neither sheer flux, as for Plato, nor unknowable in itself, as for Kant. The higher synthesis of these opposites lies in defining matter as what is known by intellect indirectly. Directly intellect knows forms, species, quiddities; but these knowns have antecedent suppositions, simultaneous suppositions, and consequents, all of which, as such, are indirectly known. (157; Fs) (notabene)

263 Antecedent suppositions are matter in the sense that genus is named matter and specific difference is named form, and again in the sense that substance is named matter and accident is named form; such usage is Aristotelian and Thomist but still somewhat improper. Simultaneous suppositions fall into two classes: if they pertain to the intelligible unity of the form, as letters to syllable, they are parts of the form, de ratione speciei, and in Thomist usage common matter; if they do not pertain to the intelligible unity of the form yet are ever included in some fashion in the concrete presentation, they are partes materiae or material conditions or individual matter. Finally, consequents that are contingent and potential, as segments to circles, are again partes materiae. Clearly, it is the second of these three types of indirectly knowns that offers the principal meaning of the term 'matter,' and it is this meaning that the analogy of matter considers chiefly. The general analogy is the proportion of wood to tables and bronze to statues; but the specifically Aristotelian analogy is that natural form is to natural matter as intelligible form is to sensible matter,1 that is, as the object of insight is to the object of sense. (157f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Identität: Erkennender - Erkanntes, actio - passio; Thomas: identity -> assimilation; intellectus possibilis (possible intellect)

Kurzinhalt: the sense in potency is unlike the sensible in potency but ...; je nach Gesichtspunkt: Potenz und Form, Immaterialität des Erkennens; immaterielle Rezeption

Textausschnitt: 264 It will be most convenient to begin from the theorem that knowing involves an identity in act of knower and known. This identity is an extension of the theorem in the Physics that affirms the identity of action and passion; one and the same real movement as from the agent is action and as in the patient is passion.1 Now in the De anima it is seen that this theorem holds no less with regard to operations (actus perfecti) than with regard to movements (actus imperfecti).2 The one operation 'sensation' is effected by the sensible object and received in the sensitive potency; as from the object, it is action; as in the subject, it is passion; thus sounding is the action of the object, and hearing the passion of the subject, and so, by the theorem of identity, sounding and hearing are not two realities but one and the same.3 (158; Fs) (notabene)

265 From this theorem Aristotle immediately deduced, first, an alternative account of sensitive empirical consciousness,4 secondly, a solution to the question whether unseen things are colored,5 and thirdly, an explanation of the fact that excessive stimuli destroy senses.6 Aquinas fails to manifest the slightest difficulty concerning this theorem in his commentary, yet rarely if ever does he employ it in his independent writings. There one may read repeatedly that 'sensibile in actu est sensus in actu, et intelligibile in actu est intellectus in actu.' But the meaning is not the original Aristotelian identity in second act7 but rather assimilation on the level of species.8 Quite probably the cause of this shift from identity to assimilation was the terminological imbroglio of 'action' to which we have referred already.9 (158f; Fs)

266 That knowing is by assimilation is a theorem offering no special difficulty. It was a matter of common consent: 'hoc enim animis omnium communiter inditum fuit, quod simile simili cognoscitur.'10 Its grounds in specifically Aristotelian theory are reached easily: as the thing is the thing it is in virtue of its form or species, so too the knowing is the ontological reality it is in virtue of its own form or species; further, unless the form of the thing and the form of the knowing were similar, there would be no ground for affirming that the knowing was knowing the thing. (159; Fs) (notabene)

267 It is a short step from a theorem of assimilation to a theorem of immaterial assimilation. If knower and known must be similar on the level of form, there is no necessity, indeed no possibility, of assimilation on the level of matter. The contrary view had been advanced by Empedocles, and against it Aristotle marshaled no less than ten arguments.11 His own view was in terms of potency and act, action and passion: the sense in potency is unlike the sensible in potency;12 but the sense in act is like the sensible object on the general ground that effects are similar to their causes;13 it followed that the senses were receptive of sensible forms without the matter natural to those forms, much as wax is receptive of the imprint of a seal without being receptive of the gold of which the seal is made.14 (159f; Fs) (notabene)

268 In human intellect immaterial assimilation reaches its fulness in immaterial reception: not only is the matter of the agent not transferred to the recipient, as the gold of the seal is not transferred to the wax; not only is the form of the agent not reproduced in matter natural to it, as in sensation; but the form of the agent object is received in a strictly immaterial potency, the possible intellect. Thus the structures of sense and intellect differ radically. The sensitive potency, such as sight, is form of the sensitive organ, the eye; just as soul is the form of the body.15 Sensation itself is the operation not merely of the organ nor merely of the potency but of the compound of organ and potency.16 Directly, the sensible object acts on the sensitive organ;17 but since matter and form, organ and potency are one, the movement of the organ immediately involves the operation of its form, the sense.18 (160; Fs) (notabene)
Kommentar (19/05/2007): da wäre ein Ansatzpunkt von Rahners Theorie ...

269 On the other hand, the possible intellect is not the form of any organ;19 it has no other nature but ability to receive;20 it stands to all intelligible forms as prime matter stands to all sensible forms;21 and precisely because it is in act none of the things to be known, it offers no subjective resistance to objective knowing.22 Thus possible intellect stands to its first act, which is science, as the sensitive organ stands to its first act, which is the sensitive potency;23 both sensation and understanding are the operations of compounds, but sensation is the operation of a material compound, while understanding is the operation of an immaterial compound; since, then, operari sequitur esse, the substantial form of man must be subsistent but the substantial form of a brute cannot be subsistent.24 (160f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Theorem: Wissen ist durch Immaterialität und Assimilation; Immaterialität -> intentionale Existenz

Kurzinhalt: general theorem that knowledge is by immateriality; the knower need not be the known; Form unterschiedlich je nach Rizipient

Textausschnitt: But if the object does not have to be material, nor the subject immaterial, and the action of the object on the subject has no particular claim to immateriality, what can be the meaning of the general theorem? In the first place, its meaning is negative; the knower need not be the known; assimilation indeed is necessary, but it is on the level of form and not that of matter; complete assimilation, both material and formal, would make the knower be the known but would give no guarantee of knowledge. Out of this negative and anti-Empedoclean meaning there arises a positive meaning. The form of the knowing must be similar to the form of the known, but also it must be different; it must be similar essentially for the known to be known; but it must differ modally for the knower to know and not merely be the known. Modal difference of forms results from difference in recipients: the form of color exists naturally in the wall but intentionally in the eye because wall and eye are different kinds of recipient; similarly, angels have a natural existence on their own but an intentional existence in the intellects of other angels. Thus the negative concept 'immateriality' acquires a positive content of intentional existence; and intentional existence is a modal difference resulting from difference in the recipient.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Warum Formen 2 Arten der Existenz haben: natürlich und intentional: Vollkommenheit als Totalität

Kurzinhalt: Thomist system conceives perfection as totality: if finite things which cannot be the totality ...;

Textausschnitt: There remains a still further step to be taken. Why have forms two different modes of existence, natural or intentional, according to difference in recipients? It is because Thomist system conceives perfection as totality: if finite things which cannot be the totality are somehow to approximate towards perfection which is totality, they must somehow be capable not only of being themselves but also in some manner the others as others; but being themselves is natural existence, and being the others as others is intentional existence. Moreover, if potency and especially matter are the principles of limitation, tying things down to being merely the things they are, it follows that the intentional mode of existence results from the negation of potency and specifically from the negation of matter. It is only in the perspective of such systematic principles that the general theorem `knowledge is by immateriality' can be understood.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Apprehensive Abstraction; Identität: forma intelligibilis, quidditas rei (species intelligibilis), object of intellect

Kurzinhalt: quidditas rei materialis, primo et per se cognitum, human intellect: potency of a form that actuates matter; the agent object of apprehensive abstraction (insight)

Textausschnitt: In the universal hierarchy of cognoscitive potencies human intellect holds an intermediate place. Sense is the first act of a material organ, and so its object is a form existing in matter as it exists in matter. Angelic intellect is the potency of a pure form, and so its object is a pure form. But human intellect is neither the act of an organ, as sense, nor the potency of a pure form, as angelic intellect; it is the potency of a form that actuates matter, and so its object must be a form, existing indeed in matter, but not as it exists in matter.
()
one must first distinguish conversion to phantasm from reflection on phantasm, and secondly, settle precisely what is meant by conversion. Now conversion and reflection are quite distinct both in themselves and in their consequents. They are distinct in themselves:
()
But plainly there is no difficulty in reconciling the necessity of sight converting to color with the fact that color is what sight first and directly knows; similarly, there is no difficulty in reconciling the necessity of possible intellect converting to phantasm to know the quiddity with the statement that possible intellect first and directly knows the quiddity in the phantasm.
()
In the Contra Gentiles the actual intelligibility of phantasm is clarified: in the dark colors are visible in potency; in daylight they are visible in act but seen in potency; they are seen in act only inasmuch as sight is in act; similarly, prior to the illumination of agent intellect, phantasms are intelligible in potency; by that illumination they become intelligible in act but understood only in potency; they are understood in act only inasmuch as the possible intellect is in act. Moreover, there occurs a description of the intelligibility in act of phantasm: the species intelligibilis is said to shine forth in phantasm as the exemplar does in the example or image.
()
As has been already explained, the object of insight into phantasm is preconceptual, so that any expression of it is as conceived and not as such, just as any expression of the object of sight is of it as conceived and not as such. It is this fact that accounts for the variety of the descriptions one finds.
()
In the In Boetium De Trinitate there occurs an identification of
(1) 'forma intelligibilis,'
(2) 'quidditas rei,' and
(3) object of intellect. Since 'species' translates Aristotle's eidos, which regularly means form, it is not surprising that the object of insight should be named not only 'forma intelligibilis' but also 'species intelligibilis.' Thus, the species that shines forth in phantasm is an object of intellectual knowledge; again, the species that intellect understands, knows, apprehends in phantasm, plainly is an object; and in such statements not only the thought but also the expression is Aristotelian.
()
Finally, the object of insight, besides being 'quidditas sive natura rei materialis,' 'forma intelligibilis,' and 'species intelligibilis,' also is the universal which is not posterior but prior, not with, but without the 'intentio universalitatis,' and concretely though inadequately identical with the particular material thing, just as the Aristotelian quiddity is concretely though inadequately identical with the particular.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: apprehensive abstraction as second act, actus perfecti; species intelligibilis quae, qua, in qua

Kurzinhalt: the act of apprehensive abstraction (insight), an immaterial similitude of the form that is received materially in the known thing

Textausschnitt: But though apprehensive abstraction is itself cognitional and abstracts from sensibly known individual or sensible matter, still it may be considered insofar as it enters under metaphysical categories. From that viewpoint it is an operation, a second act, an actus perfecti. Because it involves psychological necessity and universality, metaphysically the form whence it proceeds must be received universally, immaterially, and immovably ... Such a form is not the essence itself of the soul but an immaterial similitude of the form that is received materially in the known thing. It is not innate, nor derived from separate substances out of this world, nor consisting exclusively of intellectual light; but it is received from material things inasmuch as phantasms are made intelligible in act by agent intellect; hence neither the acquisition nor the use of science can occur without conversion to phantasm; nor can we even judge properly unless sense is functioning freely.
()
Now this form also is called a 'species intelligibilis'; obviously it is quite different from the species of our preceding paragraph, which is an object. If the latter be named 'species quae,' then this form is 'species qua intelligitur'; the 'species quae' is one of various attempts to characterize the preconceptual object of insight; the 'species qua' is not a direct object but a conclusion of metaphysical reflection. When the possible intellect is actuated by the 'species qua,' it is constituted in the first act of apprehensive abstraction; this first act of apprehensive abstraction stands to the second act as does form to esse and as principle of action to action.
()
the reception of the 'species qua' is a passion, and the consequent second act is similarly a pati in the general sense of that term; by that second act the preconceptual 'quidditas rei materiallis' or 'forma intelligibilis' or 'species quae' or universal in the particular is known; but in virtue of that second act there is formed the definition, the act of defining thought, the act of meaning; and this, at times, is said to be or to contain a third 'species intelligibilis,' which may be distinguished from the 'species quae' and the 'species qua' by being called a 'species in qua.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Zwei Arten von Intelligibilia, Weise des Erkennens nur im Modus verschieden

Kurzinhalt: Divine substance: wie ein zu starkes Licht; actuated intelligibility of sensible things: abstracts from space and time, spiritual substances: outside space and time

Textausschnitt: As the sensible is the object of sense, so the intelligible is the object of intellect. The sensible is confined to material reality, but the intelligible is coextensive with the universe: whatever can be can be understood. The supreme intelligible is the divine substance, which lies beyond the capacity of human intellect, not as sound lies outside the range of sight, but as excessive light blinds it.
()
Further, there are two classes of intelligibles and two modes of understanding: ... But while the difference between the two classes of intelligible is real and intrinsic, the difference between the two kinds of understanding is only a difference in mode; hence, whether the soul is in or out of the body, it is the same human intellect, specified by the same formal object, but operating under the modal difference that actual intelligibility is presented or is not presented in phantasms. Again, just as understanding the actuated intelligibility of sensible things abstracts from space and time, so the spiritual substances that are in themselves actually intelligible exist outside space and time.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: 3 Fragen hinsichtlich des phantasmas; Plato: kein intellectus agens?

Kurzinhalt: was wird erhellt; worin besteht die Erhellung / Immaterialisierung; wie kann das ein Objekt im intellectus possibilis hervorrufen?

Textausschnitt: How can the act existing in a material organ, such as the phantasm, be the agent object of immaterial intellect? Now Aquinas himself was concerned with this possibility. He pointed out that, since the objects of Platonist science were immaterial ideas, Platonist doctrine had no use for an agent intellect; on the other hand, since the objects of Aristotelian science were material things and only potentially intelligible, there had to be a power of the soul to illuminate phantasms, make them intelligible in act, make them objects in act, produce the immaterial in act, produce the universal, by way of abstracting species from individual matter or from material conditions. (182; Fs) (notabene)

317 Such statements raise three questions: what precisely is illuminated, immaterialized, universalized; in what does the illumination, immaterialization, universalization consist; and how can that provide an object in act for the possible intellect?
()
More precisely, it is phantasm, not in the sense of act of the imagination, but in the sense of what is imagined, that is illuminated; for what is illuminated is what will be known; and certainly, insights into phantasm are not insights into the nature of acts of imagination but insights into the nature of what imagination presents; as Aquinas put it, insight into phantasm is like looking in, not looking at, a mirror.
()
As to the second question, there is an interesting Thomist objection against a possible Averroist alternative that would account for our knowing by a separate possible intellect on the ground that species in the separate intellect irradiate our phantasms. The objection runs:
()
The foregoing is negative. On the positive side there is a list of four requirements: the presence of agent intellect; the presence of phantasms; proper dispositions of the sensitive faculties; and, inasmuch as understanding one thing depends on understanding another, practice. The first two requirements recur in ...
()
The imagined object as merely imagined and as present to a merely sensitive consciousness (subject) is not, properly speaking, intelligible in potency; but the same object present to a subject that is intelligent as well as sensitive may fairly be described as intelligible in potency. Thus, pure reverie, in which image succeeds image in the inner human cinema with never a care for the why or wherefore, illustrates the intelligible in potency.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Abstraktion; 3 Stufen: objektive, apprehensive, formtive

Kurzinhalt: There are three stages to physical and mathematical abstraction: the objective, the apprehensive, the formative.

Textausschnitt: 330 There are three stages to physical and mathematical abstraction: the objective, the apprehensive, the formative. Objective abstraction is the illumitiation of phantasm, the imagined object; it consists in treating the imagined object as something to be understood as far as its specific nature goes; like action and passion, it is one reality with two aspects; as effected by agent intellect, it may be named efficient; as affecting the imagined object, it may be named instrumental. Next, with regard to apprehensive abstraction, one has to distinguish between first act and second act: first act is the possible intellect informed and actuated by a species qua; second act proceeds from first as esse from form and action from principle of action; accordingly, the procession is processio operationis; the second act consists in grasping, knowing, considering an intelligible species quae in the imagined object. Per se this second act is infallible; consequent to it by a sort of reflection, there is indirect, intellectual knowledge of the singular, that is, a reflective grasping that the universal nature understood is the nature of the particular imagined. Thirdly, there is the act of formative abstraction; this consists in an act of meaning or defining; but whenever there is an act of meaning or defining, by that very fact there is something meant or defined; accordingly, formative abstraction may also be described as positing a universal ratio or an intentio intellecta. (187f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Critical Point in philosophy; Hauptunterschied zw Realismus, Idealismus und Lonergan

Kurzinhalt: For a materialist the terms are real, the intelligible unification subjective; for an idealist the terms cannot be reality, and ...

Textausschnitt: This is the critical point in philosophy. For a materialist the terms are real, the intelligible unification subjective; for an idealist the terms cannot be reality, and the intelligible unification is not objective; for the Platonist the terms are not reality but the intelligible unifications are objective in another world; for the Aristotelian both are objective in this world; Thomism adds a third category, existence, to Aristotelian matter and form. (Fußnote zu Absatz 333)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Wissen als Bewegung (Plato) u. Vervollkommnung (Aristoteles); menschl. Intellekt erkennt sich selbst

Kurzinhalt: For the Aristotelian confrontation is secondary. Sense in act is the sensible in act. Intellect in act is the intelligible in act; Potenz, Habitus und Akt

Textausschnitt: The conception of knowing as movement appears in Plato's dilemma that the subsistent Idea of Being either must be in movement or else must be without knowing. The same dilemma forced Plotinus to place the One beyond knowing; Nous could not be first, because Nous could not be simple. In St Augustine the notion that knowing is by confrontation appears in the affirmation that we somehow see and consult the eternal reasons. ...
()
For the Aristotelian, on the other hand, confrontation is secondary. Primarily and essentially, knowing is perfection, act, identity. Sense in act is the sensible in act. Intellect in act is the intelligible in act. In this material world, of course, besides the knower in act and the known in act, there are also the knower in potency and the known in potency; and while the former are identical, still the latter are distinct. Nonetheless, potency is not essential to knowing, and therefore distinction is not essential to knowing. It follows that in immaterial substances, as one negates potency, so also one negates distinction: 'In his quae sunt sine materia, idem est intelligens et intellectum.' A Platonist subsistent Idea of Being would have to sacrifice immobility to have knowledge; but Aristotle, because he conceived knowing as primarily not confrontation but identity in act, was able to affirm the intelligence in act of his immovable mover.
()
Unlike the natures of material things, which can be known only by what they do, human intellect can be known by what it is. Efficiently, it is the light of intelligence within us, the drive to wonder, to reflection, to criticism, the source of all science and philosophy. Receptively, it offers the three aspects of potency, habit, and act. As potency, human intellect is the capacity to understand; it is common to all men, for even the stupidest of men at least occasionally understand. As habit, human intellect is fivefold:
()
For intellectual habit is not possession of the book but freedom from the book. It is the birth and life in us of the light and evidence by which we operate on our own. It enables us to recast definitions, to adjust principles, to throw chains of reasoning into new perspectives according to variations of circumstance and exigencies of the occasion.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Von der Identität zur Konfrontation; Notwendigkeit des inneres Wortes beim Menschen; Unmöglichkeit d. Beweises bei Gott

Kurzinhalt: quidditas rei -> res: humantias -> homo; understanding moves from identity with its preconceptual object to confrontation with its conceived object

Textausschnitt: The essential necessity of inner words in our intellects is the necessity of effecting the transition from the preconceptual quidditas rei materialis, first to the res, secondly to the res particularis, thirdly to the res particularis existens. The transition from quidditas rei to res, say from humanitas to homo, occurs in conception, in which there emerges intellect's natural knowledge of ens. In virtue of this step, understanding moves from identity with its preconceptual object to confrontation with its conceived object;b but as yet the object is only object of thought. The second step is a reflection on phantasm that enables one to mean, though not understand nor explanatorily define, the material singular. In this step intellect moves from a universal to a particular object of thought. Finally, by a reflective act of understanding that sweeps through all relevant data, sensible and intelligible, present and remembered, and grasps understanding's proportion to the universe as well, there is uttered the existential judgment through which one knows concrete reality.
()
We turn to our second question. Why cannot natural reason demonstrate the existence of the divine Word from the premise of divine selfknowledge? First, the demonstration cannot be effected by contrasting the proper object of understanding with the divine essence. God is simply intelligible. He is pure form identical with existence. There is no distinction between his essence or his existence or his intellect or his understanding. There is not even a distinction' between his esse naturale and his esse intelligibile. Secondly, the demonstration cannot be effected by arguing that without an inner word there would be no confrontation between subject and object. For one cannot demonstrate that such confrontation is essential to knowledge. Primarily and essentially, knowing is by identity. The natural light of reason will never get beyond that identity in demonstrating the nature of self-knowledge in the infinite simplicity of God.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: verschiedene innere Wörter als das esse intelligibile (intentionale) im Gs. zum esse naturale

Kurzinhalt: one act of understanding expresses itself in many inner words ... these inner words are the esse intelligibile or the esse intentionale of soul as distinct both from the esse naturale of soul itself and from the esse intellectum ...

Textausschnitt: Further, once understanding of the human soul has developed, there are not two acts of understanding but one, which primarily is of intellective soul and secondarily, in the perfection of intellective soul, is of the sensitive and vegetative souls. Finally, our one act of understanding expresses itself in many inner words, in which are defined intellective, sensitive, and vegetative souls and the relations between them; further, these inner words are the esse intelligibile or the esse intentionale of soul as distinct both from the esse naturale of soul itself and from the esse intellectum, which is an extrinsic denomination from an intelligere of soul whether real or intentional.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Wort Gottes, inneres Wort, inner word: natürlich Vernunft reicht nicht aus; Psychological trinitarian theory; Trinität, Augustinus

Kurzinhalt: hat divine knowledge of the other provides no premise whence the procession of the divine Word could be established by natural reason; Psychological trinitarian theory

Textausschnitt: Now on Thomist analysis the divine essence formally is itself but eminently it contains all perfection. The divine act of understanding primarily is of the divine essence but secondarily of its virtualities. The divine Word that is uttered is one, but what is uttered in the one Word is all that God knows. Moreover, the divine essence, the divine act of understanding, and the divine Word considered absolutely are one and the same reality; hence there can be no real distinction between 'contained eminently in the essence' and 'secondary object of the understanding' or between either of these and 'uttered in the one Word.' Further, utterance in the one Word does not confer on the ideas an esse intelligibile that otherwise they would not possess; for in God esse naturale and esse intelligibile are identical. It remains, then, that divine knowledge of the other provides no premise whence the procession of the divine Word could be established by natural reason. The plurality of divine ideas within divine simplicity is accounted for by an infinite act of understanding grasping as secondary objects the perfections eminently contained in the divine essence and virtually in divine omnipotence. As we can understand multa per unum all the more so can God.
()
Hence, though our intelligere is always a dicere, this cannot be demonstrated of God's. Though we can demonstrate that God understands, for understanding is pure perfection,d still we can no more than conjecture the mode of divine understanding and so cannot prove that there is a divine Word. Psychological trinitarian theory is not a conclusion that can be demonstrated but a hypothesis that squares with divine revelation without excluding the possibility of alternative hypotheses. Finally, Aquinas regularly writes as a theologian and not as a philosopher; hence regularly he simply states what simply is true, that in all intellects there is a procession of inner word.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: processio operati u. operationis; inner word (inneres Wort) Analogie zu Gott

Kurzinhalt: the inner word is to our intelligence in act as is act to act ...: processio operati; inasmuch as dicere does not involve the imperfection of processio operationis: analogy to the divine procession

Textausschnitt: Secondly, Aquinas developed a more general notion of efficient causality than that defined by Aristotle. Thus principium operati, principium effectus, processio operati include the idea of production but do not include the Aristotelian restrictions of in alio vel qua aliud. The act of understanding is to the possible intellect, the act of loving is to the will, as act to potency, as perfection to its perfectible; the procession is processio operationis and cannot be analogous to any real procession in God. But the inner word is to our intelligence in act as is act to act, perfection to proportionate perfection; in us the procession is processio operati; in us dicere is producere verbum, even though it is natural and not an instance of Aristotelian efficient causality. Inasmuch as dicere does not involve the imperfection of processio operationis it offers an analogy to the divine procession. (205f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: inneres Wort in uns: zugleich processio operati und processio intelligibilis; reale Distinktion; intentio, res intelleca

Kurzinhalt: our inner word and act of understanding are two absolute entities really distinct; inner word in God: also natural generation

Textausschnitt: In us inner word proceeds from act of understanding by a processio intelligibilis that also is a processio operati, for our inner word and act of understanding are two absolute entities really distinct. In God inner word proceeds from act of understanding as uttering by a processio intelligibilis that is not a processio operati, at least inasmuch as divine understanding and divine Word are not two absolute entities really distinct.
()
It may be doubted that a pure processio intelligibilis is a real procession. If A is because of B without being caused by B, the dependence of A on B seems to be merely mental. It is true that a processio intelligibilis cannot be real except in a mind. On the other hand, in a mind it necessarily is real; just as the mind itself and its operation are real, so the intelligible procession within the mind and the consequent relations of origin are all real. 'Mental' is opposed to 'real' only inasmuch as one prescinds from the reality of mind.
()
Indeed, the divine procession of the Word is not only real but also a natural generation. In us that does not hold. Our intellects are not our substance; our acts of understanding are not our existence; and so our definitions and affirmations are not the essence and existence of our children. Our inner words are just thoughts, just esse intentionale of what we define and affirm, just intentio intellecta and not res intellecta. But in God intellect is substance, and act of understanding is act of existence; it follows that the Word that proceeds in him is of the same nature and substance as its principle, that his thought of himself is himself, that his intentio intellecta of himself is also the res intellecta. As there is an analogy of ens and esse, so also there is an analogy of the intelligibly proceeding est. In us est is just a thought, a judgment.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Sünde als Unterlassung; Notwendigkeit der Bewegung vom Intellekt zum Willen; Sünder; Unruhe, Umkehr

Kurzinhalt: necessity: intelligible procession from intellect to will -> sin is failure to act; ontologische Begründung der Rationalisierung der Fehler einer Person oder Gesellschaft

Textausschnitt: Evidently so, for without an intelligible procession of love in the will from the word of intellect, it would be impossible to define the will as rational appetite. Natural appetite is blind; sensitive appetite is spontaneous; but rational appetite can be moved only by the good that reason pronounces to be good. Because of the necessity of intelligible procession from intellect to will, sin is not act in the will but failure to act; it is failure to will to do the good that is commanded, or it is failure to will to inhibit tendencies that are judged to be wrong. Because of the same necessity of intelligible procession from intellect to will, the sinner is driven by a fine disquiet either to seek true peace of soul in repentance or else to obtain a simulated peace in the rationalization that corrupts reason by making the false appear true that wrong may appear right. Finally, however much it may be disputed whether there is any processio operati from the word of our intellects to the act in our wills, it cannot be denied that there is a processio intelligibilis from the word of intellect to the act of rational appetite.
()

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Procession (Hervorgang) des Wortes - aber nicht der Liebe: generatio; Identität zw. Akt d. Liebens und d. Geliebtem

Kurzinhalt: the amari of the beloved in the lover is one and the same act as the amare of the lover for the beloved; the object of intellect is in intellect 'per similitudinem speciei -> generatio

Textausschnitt: Similarly, by final causality there results from the beloved the amari of the beloved; and this amari of the beloved is not in the beloved but in the lover. Next, the appeti of the term in the motive principle is one and the same act as the appetere of the motive principle for the term; similarly, the amari of the beloved in the lover is one and the same act as the amare of the lover for the beloved ... Finally, if the presence of the beloved in the lover is exactly the same entity as the act of love in the lover, why does Aquinas bother about it? Obviously because he wishes to determine the nature of love and so to show that, while the procession of the Word is a generation, still the procession of Love is not. The object of intellect is in intellect 'per similitudinem speciei,' but the object of will or love is in the will not by reproduction but as a goal is in tendency to the goal.
()
There cannot be the dynamic presence of the beloved in the lover's will, unless there first is intellectual conception. Further, it is not the concept but the conceived that is loved; hence divine love necessarily is related both to the Word and to God from whom the Word proceeds.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Trinität, psychologische Analogie, Vergleich: Physiker, Quantentheorie

Kurzinhalt: the psychological analogy truly gives a deeper insight into what God is. Still, that insight stands upon analogy ... Just as an experimental physicist may not grasp ...

Textausschnitt: By natural reason we know that God is absolute being, absolute understanding, absolute truth, absolute love. But natural reason cannot establish that there are in God processiones intelligibiles, that the divine Word is because of divine understanding as uttering, that divine Love as proceeding is because of divine goodness and understanding and Word as spirating. Such further analogical knowledge of quid sit Deus pertains to the limited but most fruitful understanding that can be attained when reason operates in the light of faith. Thus, the Augustinian psychological analogy makes trinitarian theology a prolongation of natural theology, a deeper insight into what God is.
()
In other words, the psychological analogy truly gives a deeper insight into what God is. Still, that insight stands upon analogy; it does not penetrate to the very core, the essence of God, in which alone trinitarian doctrine can be contemplated in its full intelligibility; grasping properly quid sit Deus is the beatific vision. Just as an experimental physicist may not grasp most of quantum mathematics, but under the direction of a mathematician may very intelligently devise and perform experiments that advance the quantum theory, so also the theologian with no proper grasp of quid sit Deus but under the direction of divine revelation really operates in virtue of and towards an understanding that he personally in this life cannot possess.
()
Hence it is that the psychological analogy enables one to argue that there are two and only two processions in God, that the first is 'per modum intelligibilis actionis' and a natural generation; that the second is 'per modum amoris' and not a generation; that there are four real relations in God and three of them really distinct; that the names verbum and imago are proper to the Son, while the names amor and donum are proper to the Holy Spirit. But do not think that Aquinas allows the psychological analogy to take the place of the divine essence as the one sufficient principle of explanation. The psychological analogy is just the side door through which we enter for an imperfect look.
()
Thus, though the generation of the Son is 'per modum intelligibilis actionis,' though a proper name of the Son is the Word, still Aquinas did not conclude that the principle by which the Father generates is the divine intellect or the divine understanding. In us the inner word proceeds from understanding, and our understanding is really distinct from our substance, our being, our thought, our willing. But in God substance, being, understanding, thought, willing are absolutely one and the same reality. Accordingly, ...

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Konzeptualist: Sicherheit des Denkens; Verstehen d. Trinität

Kurzinhalt: Remove the effort to understand, and understanding will decrease. Imperfectly we grasp why God is Father, Word, and Spirit ...

Textausschnitt: ... for one can be certain only because one understands, or else because one believes someone else who certainly understands. It is only inasmuch as different concepts proceed from one act of understanding that different concepts are seen to be joined by a necessary nexus. Remove the effort to understand, and understanding will decrease; as understanding decreases, fewer concepts are seen to be joined by a necessary nexus; and as this seeing decreases, certitudes decrease. To stop the process, either one must restore the effort to understand or one must appeal not to intellect but to some higher or lower power.
()
Imperfectly we grasp why God is Father, Word, and Spirit, inasmuch as we conceive God, not simply as identity of being, understanding, thought, and love, but as that identity, and yet with thought because of understanding, and love because of both, where 'because' means not the logical relation between propositions but the real processio intelligibilis of an intellectual substance. What is truly profound is also very simple.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Erziehung; Position: Modernisten - Traditionalisten; Zusammenfassung

Kurzinhalt: f the modernist position. There were five points: first, nothing is to be taken for granted or accepted on blind faith; secondly, there is no fixed reality to be known - knowledge is a component in an ever changing process; thirdly,

Textausschnitt: 13/1 So much for the philosophy of the modernist position. There were five points: first, nothing is to be taken for granted or accepted on blind faith; secondly, there is no fixed reality to be known - knowledge is a component in an ever changing process; thirdly, the methods of empirical science are the only valid methods; fourthly, these are to be applied to the whole of traditional wisdom, which is simply the product of a prescientific, preindustrial, predemocratic age and society, and consequently is notto be expected to be very relevant to our quite different times; and finally, the great appeal is to be to experience. (8f; Fs)

14/1 The traditionalist position is set out at greater length by Adler and Mayer.1 They urge that the traditionalist would say that things exist prior to changing, and change does not eliminate all previous properties; some are permanent. Within the field of science methods differ widely, and there are still greater differences between these scientific methods and the methods proper to mathematics or philosophy or ethics.2 Finally, there are certain truths accessible to a prescientific, preindustrial, and predemocratic age, and these truths hold for any age. (9; Fs)

15/1 You can see that there is a weakness in that answer, at least in the way I have summed it up. An educational philosophy that appeals to the immutable elements in things, to their eternal properties, to the truths that hold in any age, and simply urges that empirical methods are not the only methods, really is defending a negative position. It is not offering a vision, an understanding, a principle of integration and judgment, and the great power that are offered on the modernist side by their close correlation between fundamental philosophic notions and educational theory.3 If one appeals simply to what is immutable, then one appeals to what holds equally for the education of primitives, ancient Egyptians, Greeks and Romans, medieval and Renaissance men, people at the time of the Enlightenment of the eighteenth century, and people today. And that is not meeting the challenge. It grounds an abstract education for abstract human beings.4 (9; Fs)

16/1 It will not do, then, to ascribe a merely negative value to the philosophy of education.5 Let us attempt, then, to grasp the idea of a philosophy of education as something positive, as providing the vision missing in the traditionalist response.6 (9f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Philosophie der Aufklärung als absolute Norm > Philosophie der Erziehung; Descartes, Newton, Husserl

Kurzinhalt: Drei Stufen in Philosophie: Unterschied zwischen Theologie und Philosophie, Philosophie und Wissenschaft; Philosophie als Nachfolgerin von Religion

Textausschnitt: 17/1 At the beginning of his posthumously published work Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften and die transzendentale Phänomenologie,1 Edmund Husserl made a point that I think will be helpful to us. He urged that 'Western man'2 can be conceived simply as an anthropological classification, a technical term in anthropology, a geographic designation of a civilization; or, on the other hand, it can be conceived as the Renaissance conceived man. The Greeks of fourth-century Athens took current words in their culture - epistêmê, sophia, alêtheia - and gave them a meaning, imposed upon them an Umdeutung; a shift of meaning, with the result that the words came to signify something of which the average Athenian had no notion whatsoever. The Renaissance discovery of the ancients retrieved an idea of man that involved the negation of merely traditional power and merely traditional norms, and the affirmation of human reason and human freedom as the ultimate principles in individual life and in human society. According to Husserl, the ideal of man as endowed with reason and freedom, and as destined to base his life and the life of human society upon reason and freedom - upon reason as opposed to merely traditional norms, and upon freedom as opposed to merely traditional power - was the ideal that captured the Renaissance. (10f; Fs)

18/1 The implement and carrier of that ideal was philosophy. But since the Middle Ages philosophy has been understood in any of three quite different manners, and, I submit, none of them is satisfactory for our purposes.3 (11; Fs)

First, there was philosophy as it functioned in the context of the medieval symbiosis of theology, philosophy, the liberal arts, and the sciences.4 (11; Fs)

Second, there was philosophy as a distinct discipline and department, completely autonomous, recognizing the right and the truth of a revealed religion, but still proceeding exclusively in the light of its own criteria and its own methods. From about the year 1230,5 the distinction between philosophy and theology was clearly drawn, but the separation of philosophy and theology emerges in full clarity in the work of Descartes. What is not clear in Descartes, of course, is the distinction between philosophy and science. He proves the conservation of momentum, for example, from the immutability of God. And while there is effectively the distinction between philosophy and science in Newton, there is not yet the verbal distinction. Newton named his great work Philosophiae naturalis principia mathematica - The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. He thought he was doing philosophy in presenting his theory of universal gravitation. (11; Fs) (notabene)

19/1 So first, you can conceive philosophy in the sense of the medieval living together with theology, and secondly you can conceive philosophy as a totally distinct and independent department that appeals to reason and acknowledges the existence of revealed truth, but that itself is something different and separate. A third conception of philosophy regards philosophy as the successor to religion, as the supreme arbiter in all things. The philosophy of the philosophes, the thinkers of the Enlightenment,6 was philosophy in this third sense, philosophy as an affirmation of human reason and human freedom as the ultimate basis of human life. It emphasized in particular the negation of merely traditional norms and merely traditional power, the negation that in the French Revolution dispossessed the king, the feudal nobility, and the church. The fertility of this idea, ramifying into countless fields of thought and activity, steadily promoted individualism, democracy, and state-controlled secularist education. It did so both directly and indirectly, though of course with varying degrees of consistency and efficacy. Philosophy, not merely in the sense of something distinct and separate from theology, but as the ultimate norm, an absolute self-affirmation by man, has been the inspiration of philosophies of education, as of the whole modern movement. (11f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: 2 Formen der Philosophie im 3. Sinn: in d. englisch-sprachigen Welt u. in Deutschland: naturwissenschaftliche Orientierung u. Historizismus

Kurzinhalt: Unterschied in der säkularistischen Tradition zwischen Frankreich, England u. USA und Deutschland; säkularistische Philosophie führt zu einer säkularistischen Erziehung

Textausschnitt: 20/1 Philosophy in this third sense has taken two main forms: naturalism in the English-speaking world and to a large extent in France, and historicism in Germany. For the naturalists, the model of science and of all human knowledge is natural science. Specifically at the time of the Enlightenment, it was Newton's mechanics. Later the evolutionary doctrine of Darwin would replace this model. But historicism differs fundamentally from both. Here the human spirit is to be distinguished from nature. The basic category is not mechanical nor evolutionary law, but meaning. Meaning is the vehicle that brings men together, that guides their enterprises, that provides the field in which the human spirit develops and human freedom is exercised. There is a radical difference, then, between secularist thought in the German tradition and secularist thought in France, England, and the United States.
()
21/1 Secularist philosophy, of course, led spontaneously to a secularist education. If the basis of human life is human reason and human freedom and nothing else, if we are to have in 'Western man' a fundamental affirmation of human dignity as the basis of the whole of human life and society, then education simply has to be secularist. It is not quite consistent, of course, that it also be state-controlled. After all, state control is just the opposite of human freedom, since it sets up a machine. State control seems

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: 2.1 The Masses

Kurzinhalt: Is it possible to extend higher civilization to the lower classes without debasing its standard and diluting its quality to the vanishing point?

Textausschnitt: 25/1 The first new factor is the masses. In 150 years the population of the earth has increased by 1,000 million. The increase has been possible in virtue of modern commerce, industry, and technology. To think of liquidating our industrial and technological societies is to think of liqudating the greater part of the earth's present population.
()
... Is it possible to extend higher civilization to the lower classes without debasing its standard and diluting its quality to the vanishing point? Is not every civilization bound to decay as soon as it begins to penetrate the masses?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: das Gute; 2.1 Not Abstract; ens et bonum convertuntur

Kurzinhalt: For example, it is not true to say that only substances are good

Textausschnitt: 7/2 We will start from the well-known tag ens et bonum convertuntur, being and the good are convertible. The good exists, and what exists is good. Philosophy speaks of the good as a transcendental. That is to say, the good is not confined to one of Aristotle's ten predicaments. For example, it is not true to say that only substances are good and accidents are not, or that, among the accidents, only quantity or quality or relation is good. Rather, the good is found in all of the descriptive categories. The good is not an abstract notion. It is comprehensive. It includes everything. When you speak of the good, you do not mean some aspect of things, as though the rest of their reality were evil. The good is a notion that is absolutely universal, that applies to whatever exists; and at the same time it is totally concrete. This is what I mean by saying it is a comprehensive term.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Aspekte des Guten; human good, good of order

Kurzinhalt: 2.2 Not an Aspect; 2.3 Not Negative; 2.4 Not a Double Negation; 2.5 Not Merely an Ideal; 2.6 Not Apart from Evil; 2.7 Not Static; 2.8 The Good Known Analogously; 2.9 The General Notion of the Human Good

Textausschnitt: Siehe Word-Text

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Augustinus über das Böse: Gott hätte eine andere Welt erschaffen können

Kurzinhalt: 2.6 Not Apart from Evil; God could have created a world without any evil whatever, but thought it better to permit evil and draw good out of the evil

Textausschnitt: 12/2 Again, as I have already remarked, the good is not apart from evil in this life. In his Enchiridion ('Handbook') St Augustine made perhaps one of the most profound remarks in all his writings, and for that matter in the whole of theology, when he said that God could have created a world without any evil whatever, but thought it better to permit evil and draw good out of the evil. We must not forget that what God wants, the world God foreknew from all eternity in all its details and freely chose according to his infinite wisdom and infinite goodness, is precisely the world in which we live, with all its details and all its aspects. This is what gives meaning to a phrase that might at times be considered trite: resignation to the will of God.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Mt, Mk: Einer ist der Gute; Plato - Aristoteles: Erkenntnis reicht - Aneignung von Habitus

Kurzinhalt: 2.8 The Good Known Analogously; contrast between Plato and Aristotle; Tillich

Textausschnitt: 'What is good by its essence?' 'What is good?' asks for the essence, and there is only one thing that is good by its essence, and that is God. Everything else is good by participation; just as there is only one thing that exists by its essence, and everything else exists by participation. That good, that being, is known properly, as opposed to analogously, only in the beatific vision. You know what is the good, what is being, by its essence, when you have the beatific vision. Otherwise you know them only analogously. In other words, ... Consequently, as one's knowledge of finite beings and finite goods becomes more full, more perfect, more adequate, in the same proportion one has a fuller, more adequate, more perfect basis for forming an analogous notion of what the good is. (30f; Fs) (notabene)
()
15/2 Perhaps this will help us see what lies behind the profound contrast between Plato and Aristotle. In the Republic Plato wants to find out what the good man would be, and seeks to answer this question by describing the good society. At the term of the argument, he says that, if the good society is to exist, the guardians will have to know the Idea of the good. Knowing the Idea of the good is the ultimate solution to all human problems. But Aristotle said in his Ethics that whatever may be the case with regard to the Idea of the good, obviously it cannot make much difference to the goodness of concrete human living. That is a matter of acquiring the right habits. Aristotle studies things in the concrete. (31; Fs) (notabene)
()
Now there is a sense in which both Plato and Aristotle are correct. The Idea of the good really is God himself. The divine essence is the essence of the good, and the only essence of the good, the only place where the essence of the good is found. And that is the measure of all other good. And the good is mysterious because God is mysterious. As Isaiah says, 'My thoughts are above your thoughts, and my ways are above your ways' (Isaiah 55:8). On the other hand, anything that exists and is good by participation is finite, and because it is finite it is not perfect in every respect; it can be criticized. The possibility of noting that it is not good in every respect, that it can be criticized, is for St Thomas the basis of human freedom. One cannot choose between God and anything else, but one can always choose between finite things, because they are finite in their being and in their goodness. They are not good from every possible viewpoint. Criticism is possible. Hence one can say that what is beyond criticism is either God or an idol,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: das menschliche Gute - Zusammenfassung: Wahl und Verstehen

Kurzinhalt: 2.9 The General Notion of the Human Good; The good is human insofar as it is realized through human apprehension and choice;

Textausschnitt: 16/2 Now, while most of my illustrations thus far have been from the human good, we have not yet attended to what is specific in the human good. The good is human insofar as it is realized through human apprehension and choice. Without human apprehension and choice we would not exist - we are children of our parents. We would not have our cities, and so on. Everything in human life that we know about, apart from 'the forest primeval, the murmuring pines and the hemlocks' depends upon human apprehension and choice. That is the distinctive feature of the human good - it is what comes out of human apprehension and choice. Furthermore, human apprehension develops, so that one age understands things better and knows more than the preceding age; and human choice is good or evil; and so the human good is a history, a cumulative process where there is both advance of apprehension, and distortion, aberration, due to evil. (32; Fs)
()

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: The Good of Order; Ordnungsgut; Zusammenarbeit, Voraussetzungen (Habitus, Institutionen, Material, Status)

Kurzinhalt: Now what are the general characteristics of a human good of order? It includes a number of things. We will discuss four: ...

Textausschnitt: 3.1.2 The Good of Order

20/2 The good of order is the setup. The family, for instance, is not a particular good, but a flow of particular goods for father and mother and children. Another instance of the good of order is technology-economy-polity. The most obvious aspect here is the economy. There can be a depression, and it is not for lack of raw materials, nor for lack of factories and railways, nor for lack of capital - money is going begging. Nor is it for lack of people willing to work or for lack of people willing to invest. It is just that the whole setup has simply gone awry; it just will not work. That is a case of the evil in the depression. You can see the absence of the good of order. (34; Fs)

21/2 Again, an educational system is a good of order. An educational system is not the education of this child or this young man or this young lady. It is a flow of educations. It determines what flows and the direction in which it will flow. The church, too, is a good of order. It gets people to heaven - not just one, but a flow of people into heaven. The world of art, letters, sciences, philosophy - the world of learning - is a setup, a good of order. (34; Fs)

22/2 Now what are the general characteristics of a human good of order? It includes a number of things. We will discuss four: a regular recurrence of particular goods, coordinated human operations, a set of conditions of these operations, and personal status.1 (34; Fs) (notabene)

23/2 The most conspicuous aspect of a good of order is a regular recurrence of particular goods. If X is a good thing and occurs, it will recur when there is a good of order. If breakfast is a good thing, and if there is a good of order, you will have breakfast every morning. A theoretical analysis of the notion of recurrence can be found in Insight.2 The good of order is not a matter of mechanist planning. Planning has to work in every single detail or everything goes awry. But the good of order is a matter of sets of alternative schemes of recurrence.3 It is something like the way the water circulates on the surface of the earth: it goes up from the sea in water vapor and forms clouds that are carried over the land; the water then falls down in rain, which flows into brooks and streams and rivers, and finally returns to the sea. The circulation of water does not work like a machine, according to some set of rules. Rather, all along it works according to sets of probabilities. Thus, there are spots that are deserts, and others that have too much rain, and still others that have too much humidity. The regular recurrence of particular goods is a fundamental aspect of the good of order. When there is a regular recurrence of particular goods, there is a good of order behind it. (34f; Fs)

24/2 Next, that regular recurrence occurs through coordinated human operations. There is a recurrence of particular goods because men operate, and operate in some sort of coordinated fashion, with a certain interdependence. So the second element in the good of order consists in coordinated human operations. (35; Fs)

25/2 Thirdly, you can have the coordination and the operations only if certain conditions are fulfilled. We will distinguish three parts in this third element. First, there are the habits in the subject. What do I mean by a habit? A person has a habit of mind when he does not have to learn, when he already knows, when he can operate on his own, when you do not have to take the time to teach him. A person has a habit of will when you do not have to persuade him - 'Barkis is willin'.'4 A person has a habit of dexterity, of manual skills, when he does not have to learn how to do something. If he had to learn how to drive a car, there would be no use asking him to drive you downtown; you ask a person who already has the skill. Thus we can distinguish three kinds of habits: cognitional habits, volitional habits, and skills; not having to learn, not having to be persuaded, not having to acquire the skill. Habits are a condition of coordinated human operations. If every time something had to be done people had to take a year off to learn, or to be persuaded, or to acquire the skills, nothing would ever be done. (35; Fs)

26/2 The second condition of effective coordination lies in institutions. Institutions are like habits, but in the objective order. Everyone in the United States comes to an agreement about a way of doing things when the governruent passes a law. An institution is a mechanism set up for making decisions. There are many such mechanisms - not only governmental, but social institutions in general. Such institutions are objective conditions that result from human apprehensions and choices and facilitate the flow of coordinated operations. But you can count on the other fellow doing it: through these institutions individuals are socialized. For example, if every time you went out for a drive you were not sure whether there might be some lad driving around with the purpose of running into people, it would be a more hazardous enterprise; but because of socialization, we can count on no one but a madman doing that. (35f; Fs)

27/2 The third condition of coordinated operation is material equipment, the material means of facilitating cooperation.5 For example, a university without any buildings does not have the material equipment that is one element in an educational system. (36; Fs)

28/2 The final element in the good of order is personal status. When you have coordinated operations resulting in a flow of particular goods, there arise personal relations that are congruent with the structure of the good of order. Such personal relations give rise to status. Thus, the family is a good of order; a mother fulfils certain functions within the family; she plays a determinate role in the good of order that is the family, and by playing that role, fulfilling that part, she enters into certain relations with the other members of the family. Being in those relations with other members of the family is having a status in the family, a status that arises from the personal relations that result from coordinated human operations. Similar conditions obtain for pupil and teacher, doctor and client, and so on right along the line.6 The human good gives rise to determinate structures of interpersonal relations that result in status. (36; Fs)

29/2 So the good of order involves four aspects: a regular recurrence of particular goods, coordinated human operations, the triple condition of these coordinated human operations - habits, institutions, and material equipment - and finally, the personal status which results from the relations constituted by the cooperation. (36; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Value; ästhetischer, ethischer und religiöser Wert

Kurzinhalt: three kinds of value: aesthetic, ethical, and religious

Textausschnitt: 30/2 The third element in the invariant structure of the human good is value. Not only are there setups, but people ask, 'Is the setup good?' They say, 'There is nothing wrong with him, it's the setup.' Children fight about particular goods, but men fight about the value of a good of order.
()
32/2 Aesthetic value is the realization of the intelligible in the sensible: when the good of order of a society is transparent, when it shines through the products of that society,
()
33/2 Secondly, there is ethical value. It swings us beyond discussion of the good as developing object to the good that is the subject. Ethical value is the conscious emergence of the subject as autonomous, responsible, free

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Kennzeichen der invarianten Struktur des Guten: open structure, Interlocking Aspects, A Synthetic Structure

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 36/2 I wish now to emphasize certain aspects of the general invariant structure of the human good. It is open; its three aspects are related to one another in an interlocking fashion; it is synthetic; and it is isomorphic with several other structures. (38f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Thomas: Problem zwischen Individuum und Gemeinschaft; Status; das Ordnungsgut repräsentiert in Menschen

Kurzinhalt: Thomas: einmal: das Weltgute als Ausdruck des schlechtnis Guten, dann die Ordnung der Seele; Lösung: the person emerges with personal status within the order

Textausschnitt: In one place in the first part of the Summa theologiae (q. 47, a.1), he states that the good of order found in the whole universe is the closest approximation to divine perfection. But in another place (q. 93, a. 2, ad 3m), he states that the order in the soul, on which is based the Trinitarian analogy, provides the most intense, concentrated image of divine perfection. There is a conflict between order and person. Are we interested in the order that helps persons, or in persons simply? Do you sacrifice persons for the order? The law does so when people are executed and wars are fought. But the order can also be sacrificed for persons. And the two can also be united insofar as the person emerges with personal status within the order. Then the order is an order between persons, and the good of order is apprehended, not so much by studying the notion of schemes of recurrence and determining the schemes in which human goods occur, but by apprehending human relations. The most efficacious example of the human good of order is the family, and the family subsists on personal relations. It is in their personal relations with one another that the members of the family concretely perceive their good of order. Through personal relations there is a concrete, immediate apprehension of what the good of order concretely is. It is useful to have a theoretical structure, to be able to speak of the good of order generally, but the simplest and most effective apprehension of the good of order is in the apprehension of personal relations. (40f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Kennzeichen der invarianten Struktur des Guten: Isomorphic with Other Structures

Kurzinhalt: Isomorphie zwischen dem Guten und den drei Stufen: Erfahrung ...;

Textausschnitt: The first parallel is with the structure of cognitional activity. We have distinguished particular goods, the good of order, and value. Our acquaintance with the particular good is mainly a matter of experience. But to know about the good of order, you have to understand. It is intelligence, understanding, insight, that is chiefly relevant to knowing the good of order. And it is when one reflects on different orders, different possible setups and systems, that one comes to the notion of value, and such reflection is on the level of judgment. You will recall from Insight that experience, understanding, and judgment are three fundamental levels of consciousness. They run parallel to a fundamental division in metaphysics, according to which finite being is composed of potency, form, and act, whether substantial or accidental. (41; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Differentiale des Guten: intellektuelle Entwicklung, Sünde, Erlösung; i. E.: Kultur, Zivilisation (Hutchins, Toynbee)

Kurzinhalt: Fortschritt der Technik: Vergleich mit Rad; The process functions as a wheel: situation, insight, counsel, policy, common consent, action, new situation, new insight, new counsel,

Textausschnitt: 1/3 The differentials of the human good are of three kinds.1 The first is intellectual development. Man's intellect is potens omnia facere et fieri: it is infinite potentially. Moreover, it moves through incomplete acts towards more complete actuation. The angel from the first moment of its existence knows naturally all that it will ever know, but the human race exists in time, and through time acquires its knowledge. It is natural to man to have an intellect that develops in time. That intellectual development, which is accountable for progress, is a first principle differentiating human societies.2. (49; Fs)

2/3 The second principle differentiating human societies is sin. In sin, man is the first cause. Whenever we do good, we are just God's instruments, but with respect to the radical element in sin man is the initiator, the first cause. Sin is nothing, a negation, but that is man's originality; and that makes a difference: sin is the basis of decline in human society.3 (49f; Fs) (notabene)

The third differential is redemption, victory over sin, the restoration of the order destroyed by sin.4 (50; Fs)

1.1 Intellectual Development5

1.1.1 The Development of Intelligence

3/3 As we distinguished insight or intelligence and judgment, so we shall distinguish two levels of development in the first differential. There is intellectual development, and there is reflective development. Intellectual development corresponds to civilization, reflective development to culture - if you want to distinguish between civilization and culture. Again, Hutchins in The University of Utopia distinguishes between the methods of discovery and the methods of discussion6? His distinction is approximately the same as the one I am making. Methods of discovery are scientific methods pertaining more to insight or intelligence, while methods of discussion are concerned with aims and values, educational purposes, and so on, and pertain more to the reflective level. (50; Fs)

4/3 With regard to the first level, then, we can see the structure of civilizational development from our account of insight. The act of understanding occurs with respect to imagined or sensible data. The human situation at any time includes a set of data; someone understands something, gets a bright idea, and figures out what would happen if this idea were put into effect. He takes counsel with others or with the influential people; a policy is devised; consent is won; and human action changes in the light of the new idea. The change in human action brings about a new situation, and the new situation suggests further acts of understanding. The process functions as a wheel: situation, insight, counsel, policy, common consent, action, new situation, new insight, new counsel, new policy, and so on.7 The wheel can turn indefinitely. Such an analysis of process is mainly in terms of experience and insight, and also choice. The analysis can be illustrated by what Toynbee's Study of History says about 'Challenge-and-Response.'8 Challenge is the situation, and response is guided by an insight into the situation. The response creates a new situation, which brings forth a further challenge, and so on as the process keeps going. (50f; Fs)

5/3 Now this process of new ideas can spread through the whole good of order. You start changing the situation at one point, but that change in the situation will involve repercussions all through the good of order. New ideas will start popping up everywhere. There will result augmented well-being, and it affects each of the aspects of the human good:9 the flow of particular goods becomes more frequent, more intense, more varied; new equipment is produced; institutions are remodeled; new types of goods are provided; the society enjoys more democracy and more education; new habits are formed to deal with the new equipment in the new institutions; there is status for all, because everything is running smoothly; everybody is too busy to be bothered with knifing other people; there are happy personal relations, a development in taste, in aesthetic value and its appreciation, and in ethics, in the autonomy of the subject; finally, there is more time for people to attend to their own perfection in religion. (51; Fs)

6/3 This process of change moves the situation away from the roots of chronic evils. The old evils cannot function in the new setup, simply because they pertain to the old situation, and that old situation has been changed. This process of development has no fixed frontiers. It radiates, as it were, from a center. The people in the next town, the next state, the next country start doing likewise. They can see that the new situation is good, and so they too have to change. (51; Fs)

7/3 Secondly, who are the agents? I have spoken simply of the process - situation, insight, counsel, policy, new type of action, new situation, new insight, and the snowball effect of the entire cycle. The agents may be called a succession of creative personalities. The situation can be wholly transformed if there is a succession of personalities who are not simply sunk into the existing situation, immersed in its routines, and functioning like cogs in a wheel, with little grasp of possibilities, with a lack of daring.10 They withdraw, perhops even physically, but at least mentally.11 They are detached; it is because of their detachment that they can see how things could be different. They may be accounted as nobodies while they are withdrawn, but when they return, they transform the world. In their withdrawal they become themselves, and they return with a mission.12 The return, of course, may not occur in their own lifetime. The most influential man in the twentieth century - the strongest candidate at least - is Karl Marx,13 and he spent years in the British Museum writing books that everyone else laughed at. Toynbee accounts for the process of such influence in terms of a creative minority. To begin, a creative personality influences a small group, which in turn influences other groups. Plato speaks of a spark that leaps from soul to soul.14 (51f; Fs) (notabene)

8/3 Toynbee distinguishes four periods in such a process. The first is marked by enthusiasm. In the second period people are more sedate. The third period is one of disillusion, of storm and stress. And in the fourth period, people acquiesce, and the prophets are honored by the sons of those who had stoned them.15 Thus, insights occur to individuals; these individuals have to communicate their ideas to a minority; and the minority passes through the four periods. Others then will follow, but with limited understanding and devotion, and no initiative - Toynbee calls this 'mimesis.' They are charmed, they feel something is afoot, but they need a leader, they need to be organized, and so there develop a functional hierarchy, rule, law, loyalty.16 The major weakness in Toynbee's analysis is that he presented himself as an empirical scientist. On this point he has been severely criticized. But I find his work superb at another level, as an illustration of how human intelligence works in history.17 (52f; Fs)

9/3 The first of the differentials,18 then, is intellectual development, and we are considering it first on the level of intelligence. Aristotle divided all questions into four, and the four again into two: Quid sit? and, An sit? What is it? and, Does it exist? The answer to the question Quid sit? is on the level of intelligence. We have considered intellectual development in its social aspect, that is, in the sense of civilizational order, the development of society. A concrete illustration of this type of development is provided in Schumpeter's business cycles.19 Schumpeter divides business cycles into three types, the third and longest of which lasts about sixty years. An example is the age of the railroad. The discovery of the idea of the railroad and the subsequent building of the railroads transformed the entire economy of the United States - consider what things could not exist without the railroads, and what things came into existence because of them. The idea of having railroads involved numerous concrete implications and made possible things that before were not possible. In similar fashion, we live at the present time in an age of electronics. All sorts of developments stem from the single idea of electronic devices and appliances. It is a fundamental idea that, when put into practice, releases the possibility of a whole series of other ideas. Another illustration lies in motorcars and the transformation of the roads. The roads that we have now did not exist fifty years ago, and one of the main reasons they exist now is the existence of the motorcar. The existence of roads followed the existence of the motorcar, and all sorts of other things have followed from both. One idea leads to another and makes the realization of other ideas possible. One can see this very clearly in concrete instances of the technological order, although the same sort of thing , exists, though more obscurely, in ideas of a more immaterial character. (53f; Fs)

10/3 I have used Toynbee's analysis largely, in treating the development of social intelligence, that is, of intelligence with respect to the technology-economy-polity: the process from situation, insight, counsel, policy, new action, changed situation giving rise to, making possible and significant, further insights. The cycle is ongoing, and the entire good of order of a culture or civilization can be transformed in that manner. That is just the analysis of the process, however. There are also the agents. The prime agents of such a process are creative personalities. The immediate agents Toynbee calls the creative minority, the people who catch on to the idea, and with considerable risk and sacrifice devote themselves to its realization. Finally, the rank and file, who have some notion of the idea, are led, carried on in the stream. (54; Fs)

11/3 The more specific developments of intelligence in a pure sense - the development of science, mathematics, and so on - are a little too technical for us to treat at this point without digressing too far from our present topic. We will come back to these developments later when we consider the implements at the disposal of the educator to help him realize his purposes, and ask about the good of different subjects in education. But at present we are simply trying to form some notion of our ends. So we are thinking of the good in general, in order to arrive at both a determination of what the aims of education might be or should be and a criticism of what in fact they are. (54; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Differentiale des Guten: intellektuelle Entwicklung 2; Zivilisation, Kultur: die reflektive Entwicklung; Fortschritt in Kultur durch Verschiedenheit der Kompaktheit

Kurzinhalt: The accumulation of insights results in a new civilizational order. But the structural invariants do not change; Mircea Eliade (Jung), Voegelin;

Textausschnitt: 12/3 Now, besides this first level of intellectual development, which is a development in intelligence, in the question Quid sit? What is it? there is also a reflective level of development, a development of culture as opposed to civilization. Civilization is connected with technology, economy, and the polity or state.
()
The accumulation of insights results in a new civilizational order. But the structural invariants do not change. They are not the object of a new discovery. They are always there, operative though they are not noticed. You can stop the man on the street and ask him what he thinks of the distinctions among particular goods, the good of order, and values, and he will simply gape at you. Still, the structural invariants are operative in his life, in his ways of thinking and doing things, even though he does not advert to them explicitly. They are implicit in all human acts -in experience, understanding, reflection, freedom and responsibility. They are given some expression in the customs, the laws, the stories, the traditional wisdom of every society. (55; Fs)
()
13/3 Nonetheless, there is a progress in the apprehension of the structural invariants. That progress is from the compactness of the symbol to the differentiation of philosophic, scientific, theological, and historical consciousness. (55; Fs) (notabene)
()
17/3 A similar sort of work on a different level is being done by Eric Voegelin in Order and History. Voegelin's study reveals how the symbols of Babylonian and Egyptian thought were countered in the revelation given to Israel, and how the symbols of the Homeric age were transformed, upset, transcended by such philosophers as Heraclitus, Parmenides, and Xenophanes, and by the movement into explicitly rational consciousness that appears with the Sophists and particularly with Plato and Aristotle. Voegelin understands cultural development in terms of the movement away from the compactness of the symbol to differentiated consciousness. (57; Fs) (notabene)
()
21/3 Our first differential, then, is intellectual development. Man grows in understanding of nature and himself, and there is a consequent development in civilizational order. Intellectual development explains the conspicuous difference between the Stone Age and successive periods of human life and history. But at the same time, arising in and because of this change in civilizational order, there is an enucleation, a development, in the apprehension and the realization of the structural invariants of the human good itself. (58; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Sünde: als Verbrechen, als Komponente im sozialen Prozess; Marx, Nietzsche: Hass d. Sünde;

Kurzinhalt: ... there can arise the vertical invasion of barbarians, of people who do not understand the society as it exists and are in revolt against it. Such people come from within the society. The society has failed to bring them up to its own level ...

Textausschnitt: 1.2 Sin

21/3 The second differential is sin. Sin is a category not only of theological and religious thought. One of the fundamental inspirations of Karl Marx is perhaps his hatred and critique of the sins of the bourgeoisie in the nineteenth century. There is a terrific hatred in Marx, and it is a hatred of sin. Again, in Nietzsche there is a hatred and critique of the sins of the masses, of what is all too human, of their resentment against human excellence of any kind, of their desire to bring everything down to their own level. It was against this that Nietzsche was reacting in affirming his transvaluation of values and his 'Superman,' and so on. For Nietzsche, of course, the fundamental expression of the resentment of the masses against human excellence was Christianity. Nietzsche lived fully the secularism of the modern time. For him God was dead, in the sense that God no longer exerted any influence upon human social, political, and economic life. Nietzsche wanted to think things out in full coherence with that fact. His explanation of Christianity as a resentment against excellence is, of course, a tool that can be turned against him. In Max Scheler's analysis the notion of resentment is given a twist, another application. For a while Scheler was a Catholic, and at that time he upheld the thesis that Protestant, bourgeois, capitalist society was the product of resentment against Catholicism and the feudal aristocratic hierarchy. The notion of resentment, it seems, can be used in all sorts of ways. (58; Fs; tblVrw bis 32/3)

22/3 These examples indicate that sin is a preoccupation not merely of religious and theological thought. Sin is an evident fact in human life, something one has to think of, something that accounts for the differences.

We will consider sin under three headings: sin as crime, sin as a component in social process, and sin as aberration. (59; Fs)

1.2.1 Sin as Crime

23/3 Sin as crime is, as it were, a statistical phenomenon. Everything is not going to be perfect. Sin as crime is more or less an incidental, statistical, and relatively small departure from accepted norms. It gives rise to laws, the police, law courts, tribunals, prisons. At the same time, it generates the notion of the good as 'keeping out of jail' - You're a good man if you're not in jail; that's all we can ask of you. It brings out the further notion that to attain further good is a matter of having more laws, more policemen, more courts. Against sin as crime, then, there is the law, and the law is a fundamental element in the apprehension of the good. As St Paul states in Romans 3.20, 'Through the law there is knowledge of sin.'1 And again in Romans 5.13 he writes, 'Before the law there was sin in the world, but the sin was not counted as sin since there was no law'2 (59; Fs)

24/3 Sin as crime is a matter of the crimes of passion, of moral failure, of bad will, of incomprehension. The criminal class to a greater or lesser extent is a class of those who do not understand the social setup. Criminals establish another society of their own with its own moral standards. There is a story of a gangster who shot a policeman, and when asked why he did it said he did it in self-defense3 he had moral standards of his own that gave evidence of an entirely different society, with criteria and laws of its own. In any society there can arise the vertical invasion of barbarians, of people who do not understand the society as it exists and are in revolt against it. Such people come from within the society. The society has failed to bring them up to its own level, or they have refused to ascend to the level of the society. The annual crop of infants is a potential invasion of barbarians, and education may be conceived as the first line of defense. (59; Fs)

1.2.2 Sin as a Component in Social Process

25/3 Secondly, there is sin as a component in social process, as the opposite to the development of civilizational order. Our Lord remarks in Matthew 18.7 that it is necessary that scandals come. In fact, the good of order does not develop in the glorious fashion I outlined yesterday. It develops under a bias in favor of the powerful, the rich, or the most numerous class. It changes the creative minority into a merely dominant minority. It leads to a division of classes not merely by their function, but also by their well-being. This division of classes gives rise in the underdogs to suspicion, envy, resentment, hatred, and in those that have the better end of the stick, to haughtiness, arrogance, disdain, criticism of 'sloth,' of 'lack of initiative,' of 'shortsightedness,' or in earlier times, of 'lowly birth.' Thus in the very process of the development of civilizational order, there result from sin a bias in favor of certain groups and against other groups, class opposition, the emotional charging of that opposition, and the organization of those emotions and that opposition in mutual recriminations and criticism. In time the pendulum swings from dominance by force and class law, through palliatives and concessions, to a shift of power and to punitive laws. Income tax in England at the present time seems to be an instance of punitive law. We find a great emigration of the best young brains from England, because they foresee no possibility of getting anywhere in their own country, where there is discrimination against what once was the leading class.4 Such a state of affairs interferes with creativity. It is not enough just to have a new idea, even if the idea is justwhat is wanted. The idea has to combine with power, with wealth, with popular notions, before it can be realized. It cannot simply emerge from the man on the spot, diffuse, give rise to new potentialities in a chain reaction. Developments become lopsided, curtailed. Completion of the development is demanded by disaffection, but it cannot emerge in the normal fashion of the spread of an idea. It has to come by management, from above downward, not from below upward. Management always needs more power. Without a constant increase in power, management is not able to control all the outside5 factors that might interfere with its plans. If it cannot exclude those factors, it cannot achieve its results. And so there occurs the rise and growth of a bureaucratic hierarchy. (60; Fs)

26/3 In spontaneous developments, the new ideas come where they may to the man on the spot who is intelligent, sees the possibilities, and goes ahead at his own risk. But in the bureaucracy the intelligent man ceases to be the initiator. He does not have the power, the connections, the influence, to put his ideas into practice. He becomes a consultant, an expert, called in by the bureaucracy. Activity is slowed down to the pace of routine paperwork. Style and form, that are inevitable when the man who has the idea is running things, yield to standardization and uniformity. Wisdom and faith yield to eclecticism and syncretism: Pick the best ideas, and the ideas that will suit everybody, or some of those that will suit everybody. The process of mimesis, of the people who were carried on in the movement even though they did not quite understand it, changes into drudgery and routine, with no understanding of what is going on.6 They keep on doing it because they have to live. Creativity has fewer and fewer opportunities for significant achievement. The lone individual is more and more driven onto the margin of the big process, of what is really going on.7 The masses demand security, distraction, entertainment, pleasure, and they have a decreasing sense of shame. (60f; Fs)

27/3 In this regard, I relate a story told me by a man in Montreal. His mother came from Germany and his uncles went to Detroit. His uncles put their sons through college by spending their lives working in factories. When they retired from the factories they could not just be idle, so they set up small machine shops where they worked on their own time. Their sons with the college educations were quite content to work in the factories just as their fathers had done, and they spent their spare time watching baseball games on television. Now that is not simply an individual matter. The older men belonged to a different time, when opportunities existed for the individual that do not exist today. The supermarkets have pushed out the corner grocery store, and so on all along the line. You have to be in big business to be in business at all, and in big business you have nothing to say. Thus there is a spread of frivolity. (61; Fs)

28/3 There is also esotericism: people retire into the ivory tower, and they have no intention of returning to the transformation of the situation. There is archaism: people preach the revival of the ancient virtues, but the ancient virtues are no longer relevant to the present situation; they were virtues once, but they are not what is needed now.8 There is futurism: achieve utopia by a leap; forget that the good is concrete - bonum et malum sunt in rebus: good and evil lie in the concrete, and the real ideal, the true ideal, is the potentiality in the concrete. There are what are called 'times of troubles,' wars to arouse social concern, to give people a stake in the nation, to give them the feeling that they belong together in one nation. There are the outer and inner barbarians growing to ever larger proportions. And finally, there is the universal state as an outward peace to cover over inner emptiness. Sin as a component in the social process lets the material development go ahead, and at the same time takes out of it its soul. (61f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Sünde als Abweichung; das Böse als Gegenteil zu kultureller Entwicklung; Geschichte - menschliches Bewusstsein; Zeitgeist

Kurzinhalt: And just as consciousness floats according to the orientation of the subject ... so also history has its orientation... There is such a thing as the spirit of an age, and that spirit of an age can be an aberration, it can be folly

Textausschnitt: 1.2.3 Sin as Aberration

29/3 Thirdly, there is sin as aberration, as the evil that is opposite to cultural development, to development on the reflective level, that is, to development in the apprehension of the invariants of the human good. On sin as aberration, the New Testament is rather abundant. See Romans 1:8-32, 2:2-24. Romans 5:1 tells us; 'Sin reigned in the world.'1 John 1.92 has: 'He came unto his own, and his own received him not.' In John 3:9-21, we read, 'All that love the light come to the Son, but those whose works are evil refuse to come to the light, because they do not wish their works to become manifest.'3 Again, in John 8.42-47 and 12,37-41, there is word of the blindness of Israel.4 (62; Fs)

30/3 Now how can sin be aberration? What does that mean? Human history is like human consciousness: if I may use a metaphor, both of them float. Human consciousness is not a fully determined function of sensitive impressions and hereditary equipment. Consciousness also depends upon an orientation within the subject that is accepted and willed by the subject. There is such a thing as freedom of consciousness - principally, of course, in the sense that acts of will are free, but also and by way of a precondition in the sense that consciousness itself is not something determined uniquely by external objects or internal objects, by biological or sensitive conditions and determinants. You think of what you please. In that sense, consciousness floats. It selects. What comes to your attention depends not merely upon the thing's being there to be attended to, but much more upon your being interested. And just as consciousness floats according to the orientation of the subject - these are points on which we shall have to go into more detail later - so also history has its orientation. There is such a thing as the spirit of an age, and that spirit of an age can be an aberration, it can be folly. Whom the gods destroy they first make blind.5 As aberrant consciousness heads to neurosis and psychosis, similarly aberrant history heads to cataclysm6 (62f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Geschichte, Bewusstsein - Sünde, Abweichung; moralische Impotenz, Gnade, Rationalisierung; Sprung (leap) - Gnade

Kurzinhalt: The moral impotence of man creates in man a demand for false philosophies in our day, for a high-level rationalization, just as it created a demand for degrading myths in ancient times

Textausschnitt: In what consists the aberration of consciousness and of history? We will deal with this in more detail later, but for the moment it will suffice to distinguish between the ideal tendencies of the human spirit to what is true, to what is right, to what is good, and on the other hand, what in the concrete individual is conjoined with these spiritual aspirations, that is, his concern. His total concern includes his ideal aspirations, but it includes more as well; and it can deform, misdirect, those aspirations. Every closing off, blocking, denial of the empirically, intelligently, rationally, freely, responsibly conscious subject is also a closing off, a blocking, of the dominance of the higher aspirations of the human spirit and the human heart. Again, historically, every failure to unblock is () That incapacity to avoid sin without grace is moral impotence. The moral impotence of man creates in man a demand for false philosophies in our day, for a high-level rationalization, just as it created a demand for degrading myths in ancient times. The objectification of sin in social process provides the objective empirical evidence for the false philosophy or degrading myth. The incomplete development and the sins of the philosopher or the bard make them incapable of conceiving and expressing a true philosophy or a true symbolic vision of life. Moreover, those who do uphold what is true give scandal by acting and writing unworthily. Again, the refutation of n false philosophies, where n is as big as you please, does not exclude - in fact it invites - the creation of the (n + 1)th false philosophy. There is in man a demand for false philosophy, for degrading myths, because of his moral impotence. What is needed in man to break away from the aberration of sin is a leap - not a leap beyond reason, as irrationalist philosophers would urge, but a leap from unreason, from the unreasonableness of sin, to reason. That leap is not simply a matter of repeating, pronouncing, affirming, agreeing with the propositions that are true, while misapprehending their meaning and significance. That is just what lies behind the decadence of philosophic schools. The leap is rather really assenting to, really apprehending - Newman's distinction between real and notional apprehension and real and notional assent. What is wanted is something existential - real apprehension and real assent to the truth. (63f; Fs) (notabene)

Now what I have said of philosophy and myth is true of all departments: of human science, of natural science, of arts and letters. All are expressions of the orientation of the human soul and the social situations produced by souls and expected in the future from souls. All are determinants of, and determined by, the social situation, which is simply the result of the influence of the group on the individual, and of each individual on the group. To surrender to this aberration produces a series of lower syntheses. Hegel spoke of the series of ascending syntheses, but one can design without any great difficulty a series of descending syntheses as well: medieval unity shattered at the Reformation on the struggles between church and state; the wars of religion disgusted men with all supernatural religion, and led to rationalism, the guidance of life not by any divine revelation but simply by man's own reason; the fact that men could not agree effected the transition from rationalism to liberalism and tolerance; and the fact that, when people merely tolerate one another's views, they cannot have any common view, and they cannot act effectively to deal with social evils, gives rise to totalitarianism. And so we can discern in that progress, which is the progress of modern thought in one of its aspects, a succession of lower syntheses. In the face of that succession of lower syntheses, the Catholic can wish to retire into an ivory tower, to condemn the new good because it is associated with new evils; but that is just another form of the aberration. (64f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Erlösung 1: Neuanfang, neue Erde (Toynbee), Christus (keine eschatologische Transformation der Welt); Sinngebung des Leidens

Kurzinhalt: The redemption in Christ Jesus does not change the fundamental fact that sin continues to head for suffering and death. However, the suffering and death that follow from sin attain a new significance in Christ Jesus.

Textausschnitt: 1.3 Redemption

33/3 The third differential, redemption, can be conceived in various ways.

It is a break with the past, the dead hand of the past, its institutions, the mentalities it produced, the resentments and hatreds it accounted for. Mircea Eliade, in The Myth of the Eternal Return,1 sees in the rites of the vegetation cults, the Dionysian cults, the Roman Saturnalia, a symbolic wiping out of the past. The orgies connected with these rites were given the significance of wiping out the enmities, the resentments, the debts, the obligations to which the past had given rise, and making possible a new start. That idea of a new start is an element in confession, in the sacrament of penance. It involves the emergence of new men in a new situation.2 Eliade criticizes these rites as a flight from history, but one can also think of them as a primitive means on the symbolic level to deal with and dominate history. It is true that man is historical, but he is historical in the sense that his apprehensions and choices form a cumulative process; and there is no contradiction between the historical and the use of apprehension and choice to dominate and control that process in some manner. In that sense the myth of the eternal return, the return to the new situation, to starting afresh, can be thought of as a symbolic technique on a rather primitive level for dealing with the fundamental problem of history. History dominates man enough without his attempting to free himself from it. (65f; Fs)

34/3 Another type of redemption is what Toynbee calls 'New Soil'.'3 A corrupt civilization disintegrates. New people take over the achievements of the past without the memories and hatreds, the false ideas and degrading myths. Or again, there can be new soil in the more literal sense of immigration to new lands. When such an immigration occurs the society begins afresh. The cumulative problems created by sin as a component in social process and as aberration are undercut. There is a new start. (66; Fs)
35/3 There is a redemptive aspect in revolution, the violent destruction of existing institutions, existing habits, existing material equipment, and the persons that are the carriers of the institutions and the habits of a culture. Thucydides provides a terrifying description of the revolution at Corcyra,4 where the people were divided into the rich and the poor, and the rich were simply wiped out, mercilessly and completely. The French and Russian revolutions were more or less complete liquidations of the past of a country. In Marxism there is a Jewish eschatological element combined with the idea of revolution, a sudden, quasi eschatological5 transformation of the situation, produced by the revolution. (66; Fs)
36/3 There is an element of the notion of redemption that is illusory, in archaism with its revival of ancient virtues, in futurism with its leap to utopia, in esotericism with its attitude of 'Let the world go by, at least we shall live our well-regulated and happy lives by ourselves,' and, of course, in the more recent illusion of automatic progress, which is simply a denial of the problems created by sin. (66; Fs) (notabene)

37/3 However, when I spoke of redemption, what you all first thought of was redemption in Christ Jesus. That redemption was not what was expected: an eschatological transformation of this world, a complete destruction of the unjust, and a millennium of peace and prosperity for the just. The redemption in Christ Jesus does not change the fundamental fact that sin continues to head for suffering and death. However, the suffering and death that follow from sin attain a new significance in Christ Jesus. They are no longer the sad, disastrous end to the differential of sin, but also the means towards transfiguration and resurrection. Beyond death on the cross, there is the risen Savior. The antithesis between death and resurrection runs through the writings of St Paul in a series of different forms. There is the symbolic death of baptism and the symbolic life of the Eucharist; there is the ascetic death of mortification, of dying to sin, and the ascetic resurrection of the exercise of virtue. They are all spoken of by St Paul with the compactness of the symbol. (66f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Erlösung 2: Glaube, Hoffnung, Liebe; G. (Beibehaltung der Wahrheit); H. (Kraft des Widerstehens); Sünde (zwei Wurzeln)

Kurzinhalt: ... faith reestablishes truth as a meaningful category ... there arises hope ... which enables us to resist the pressures and the determinisms ... Redemption in Christ Jesus is the answer to the problem created by sin as a component in social ...

Textausschnitt: 38/3 Faith is the fundamental answer to the problem of sin not only in the next life but also in this life. Against sin as aberration, that is, the sin that verifies the old Greek proverb 'Whom the gods would destroy they first make blind,' faith reestablishes truth as a meaningful category. Pilate asked our Lord, 'What is truth?' The modern human scientist does not ask that question if he is preoccupied with imitating the techniques of the natural sciences. For then knowledge is science only in the measure that it can verify and enable one to predict. The reestablishment of truth as a meaningful category is also a liberation of intelligence and reason. (67; Fs)

39/3 Again, against sin as a component in the social process, sin as changing social process from a matter of freedom and creativity to routine and drudgery with all its determinisms and pressures and in the limit violence, there arises hope, which liberates the pilgrim in us,1 and which enables us to resist the pressures and the determinisms that are, as it were, the necessity of sinning further. Pius XII spoke of the fact that the modern world creates situations in which people have to be heroic to avoid mortal sin. To have that heroism there is needed the virtue of hope; and without that heroism there is no victory over the cumulative effects of sin as a component in social process. (67; Fs)

40/3 Finally, against sin as self-perpetuating, as a chain reaction, there is love of one's enemies and the acceptance of suffering. Sin as a chain reaction has two bases. It has a basis first in the hearts of men, where sin leads to ever further sin insofar as hatred arises. But Christ teaches us, 'Love your enemies, do good to them that hate you.' Secondly, there is a chain reaction of sin in the logic of the objective situation,2 and against that aspect Christianity teaches the acceptance of suffering. 'The servant is not better than his master.' 'Do not resist evil, but overcome evil with good.' The acceptance of suffering puts an end, at least at one point, to the chain reaction of sin that spreads throughout a society. When everyone is dodging suffering, when no one accepts it, the burden is passed ever further on. (67f; Fs)

41/3 Redemption in Christ Jesus is the answer to the problem created by sin as a component in social process and as fundamental aberration, but it has not merely a negative office. It comes through the grace of our Lord Jesus Christ, through a personal communication of the life of the ever Blessed Trinity to mankind. 'In the fulness of time, God sent his Son, born of woman, made under the law, that those who were under the law might be redeemed and receive the adoption of sons. And now that you are sons, to show that you are sons, he sent the Spirit of his Son into our hearts, crying, "Abba, Father!"' (Galatians 4: 4-6).3 The mission of the Son and the mission of the Holy Ghost is the basis of a new society in Father, Son, and Holy Ghost, in which there is communicated to us personally, through the person of the Son and through the person of the Spirit, a participation of divine perfection, a participation of the order of truth and love that binds the three persons of the Blessed Trinity.4 Sin, suffering, and death remain, but in Christ they have become transition points to an ever fuller life on this earth with God the Father and the Son and the Holy Ghost, with whom we aspire to live in eternal life. The process of redemption, then, as conceived by the Catholic, is first of all the radical answer to sin - not the answer to sin that eliminates sin, but the answer to sin that endures its consequences and nullifies them and transforms man into a child of God, with a participation in the sonship that God the Father acknowledged when Jesus was baptized at the Jordan: 'This is my beloved Son. Hear ye him.'5 In baptism we become adopted sons as Christ was the natural Son of the Father.6 (68; Fs) (notabene)

42/3 So much for the three differentials of the human good. We set up an invariant structure, and then we noticed that the structure was realized differently at different times, and we distinguished three differentials: intellectual development on the two levels of civilization and culture; sin contradicting, deforming both those types of development; and finally, redemption. That analysis of the good, of course, makes it obvious why we want Catholic education. The fact of sin is not any private opinion of Catholics, but something to be noted by all. Our notion of the good cannot prescind from the tension between the good and evil. If we have an answer to the problem of evil, it will influence our education in all its aspects, because it influences our very notion of the good. (69; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Common Sense - Grammatik, Ichbezogenheit

Kurzinhalt: Again, common sense is egocentric. It is not concerned with the general question of how anyone is to behave, but with how I am to behave

Textausschnitt: 53/3 Again, common sense is egocentric. It is not concerned with the general question of how anyone is to behave, but with how I am to behave; not with' what anyone is to say, but with what I am to say; not with what is to be done by so and so, but with what I am to do and how I am to do it. It is like grammar. In grammar, place is always relative to my place -'here' is my 'here' - and time is always relative to my time - I 'am,' and what is not at the same time 'was' or 'will be.' Persons, too, are relative to the first person. What is the second person? Not myself but the one I am talking to. And what is the third person? Somebody else. Common sense is egocentric in the same fashion. (72f; Fs)

54/3 Finally, common sense is the mode of all concrete understanding and judgment. When you get really down to the concrete, you are in the situation, and the situation is before you, and to deal with the situation you do not want some universal science; and in fact complete analysis is impossible and undesirable.1 You want to make the ultimate adjustments to the concrete, beyond the generalities of science. In a way, common sense is prelogical. Lévy-Bruhl, the French sociologist, introduced the term 'prelogical' in describing primitives.2 I do not wish to use the term in that sense, but rather to mean that common sense does not use terms, propositions, and syllogisms as a technique for the clarification and development of intelligence.3 It proceeds in a much more direct fashion. The Greek discovery of the logos was the discovery of language, and consequently of concepts and judgments, and attention was drawn to the words, to the propositions, to the arguments, as a means, a tool, to make intelligence more complete and more adequate. (73; Fs)





53/3 Again, common sense is egocentric. It is not concerned with the general question of how anyone is to behave, but with how I am to behave; not with' what anyone is to say, but with what I am to say; not with what is to be done by so and so, but with what I am to do and how I am to do it. It is like grammar. In grammar, place is always relative to my place -'here' is my 'here' - and time is always relative to my time - I 'am,' and what is not at the same time 'was' or 'will be.' Persons, too, are relative to the first person. What is the second person? Not myself but the one I am talking to. And what is the third person? Somebody else. Common sense is egocentric in the same fashion. (72f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: 4 Stufen der Integration; Common Sense, geschichtliches Bewusstsein

Kurzinhalt: Unterscheidung

Textausschnitt: 2.2.1 Undifferentiated Common Sense
2.2.2 Differentiated Common Sense
2.2.3 Classicism and the Differentiation of Consciousness
2.2.4 Historical Consciousness

2.2 Four Levels of Integration

By my formulation of common sense I have provided myself with a general basis for distinguishing four levels of integration. (73; Fs)

2.2.1 Undifferentiated Common Sense

54/3 The first level of integration is undifferentiated common sense. Undifferentiated common sense characterizes the primitive. Here there occurs the same development of intelligence in all the members of the tribe or clan. Thinking is a community enterprise. The clan or the tribe may be fruit gatherers or gardeners or hunters or fishers. They will have developed skills, a language, some tools. They will have their art and their myths and their taboos. Tribes will differ from one another - there are enormous differences between the Eskimos and the pygmies or the bushmen - but in any given group there is a common intelligence. Common sense is common in the sense that it is common to many. (73f; Fs)

55/3 The relation between undifferentiated common sense and the idea that thinking is a community enterprise may have some connection with a phenomenon at the present time, the tendency of teenagers to conformism. An education whose ideal is adjustment does not proceed much beyond undifferentiated common sense. Conversely, if one's development is merely an undifferentiated common sense, people will have to conform.1. (74; Fs) (notabene)

2.2.2 Differentiated Common Sense2

56/3 The second level of integration is differentiated common sense, differentiation of common sense by the division of labor. We may associate this level of integration with Egypt, Crete, Sumer, Babylon, Assyria, the ancient high civilizations of the Indus Valley and the Hwang Ho Valley, of the Mayas of Central America and the Incas of Peru. In those civilizations there existed large-scale agriculture, there was a great differentiation of arts and crafts, there were writing, arithmetic, bookkeeping, engineering, surveying, astronomy. There was a social hierarchy and law. There was what Voegelin calls the 'cosmological myth.'3 The divine order, the ultimate realities, the gods, were, as it were, incarnated in the social order, so that at least in Egypt and to some extent in Mesopotamia - I don't know about the others - the king was the god or the son of god. In later stages in these civilizations there emerged another aspect of differentiated common sense in the form of a wisdom literature. This stage is illustrated, for example, in the book of Proverbs. And in the breakdowns of these civilizations there occurs the emergence of individualism. (74; Fs) (notabene)

57/3 So there is a differentiation of common sense by the division of labor; there are different kinds of common sense for people in different walks of life. This specialization leads to a high development of arts and crafts and practical sciences such as astronomy, engineering, and surveying. Building the pyramids, for example, was an extraordinary achievement in engineering. (75; Fs)

2.2.3 Classicism and the Differentiation of Consciousness

58/3 The third level of integration involves the differentiation of consciousness, the emergence of the intellectual pattern of experience. We will name it the pure development of human intelligence.4 This is what is meant by classicism in its best sense, the Greek achievement. (75; Fs)

59/3 We will consider first the general characteristics of this level of integration. The individual appeals to immanent norms, to what is true against the false, to what is right against the wrong, to what is good against the evil. The autonomy of the human spirit emerges. There is a development of argument, definition, science, the critique of gods, of myths, of magic, of taboos, of institutions and manners, of aims and values. These features are all exhibited in the Sophist movement of the fifth century B.C. and the philosophic movement of the fourth century B.C. in Greece. The individual asserts his freedom to be himself. He liberates aesthetic, intellectual, scientific, moral, and religious activity from traditionally restricted functions within the collectivity.5 Prior to this pure development of intelligence all of these features existed except science, but they were functional parts within the concrete totality. In the ancient high civilizations such as Egypt or Crete, there was differentiated common sense, where the integration comes through the concrete integration of the members of society. But there was not a theoretical integration beyond the differentiated common sense of individuals engaged in different tasks and leading different kinds of lives. (75; Fs)

60/3 The emergence of individualism, of critical thought,6 gives rise to what Marx called the superstructure. There are discussion groups, wandering teachers, the formation of academies, schools, libraries, universities, universalist tendencies in intellectual, political, and religious fields. There is the pursuit of wisdom and culture for their own sake. This pure development of intelligence is not practical; it is7 proudly useless; it is the enrichment of mind, the advance of knowledge, the ennobling of will, the rationalization of manners, all for their own sake. But it involves a tendency as well to be limited to a particular class, to classical models, the depiction of ideals, the per se, the legal. It offers tables of virtues and vices, settled art forms and literary genres, types of polity, all in static concepts, principles, systems. (75f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: das historische Bewusstsein

Kurzinhalt: Geschichte als Produkt des Menschen wurde weitgehend der säkularen Welt überlassen

Textausschnitt: We have come to realize that we are more the masters of our own destiny than we had thought. The self-assertion of modern man contains a notable measure of truth: man is responsible for his history; man is largely what man has made of man. But this self-assertion has been left largely to the initiative of the secularists, and the result has been the de-Christianization of the modern world. Even so-called Catholic countries are to a great extent either backward or de facto non-Catholic. This should not surprise us: it is not merely the Bourbons who forget nothing, learn nothing, and like things that way. But also, Christianity is a wisdom, and wisdom enters on the scene only when what is going forward becomes clear. The idea of historical consciousness arose outside the church and produced disasters, but we have to consider it seriously. In Hegel's words, 'Only with the fall of twilight does the owl of Minerva take wing.' The church moves slowly but surely. (76f; Fs)
62/3 The self-assertion of modern man has been implemented by philosophy, or, where philosophy deserted the scene, by empirical human science. There has developed a philosophy of human science, a philosophy of politics
()
There is a philosophy of history, as in Vico, who began a new phase different from that which held from Augustine to Bossuet. There is the move from Vico, with his insistence on the priority of poetry and the compact symbol, vis-à-vis differentiated consciousness, to Hegel, Marx, and Troeltsch, Through Marx, there is the influence of the philosophy of history on later Russians and Chinese. There is the philosophy of education - already we have mentioned Dewey's influence not only in the United States but worldwide. And today there is the rediscovery of the symbol in depth psychology, in the work of Eliade and the history of religions, in Cassirer's Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, in Voegelin's interpretation of the ancient Near East, Israel, and Greece, and in the phenomenologists and existentialists. But there are also the social engineers and the hidden persuaders, the propaganda ministries and the advertising industry. (77; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: von der Natur zum Ideal: animal rationale, das man sein soll; der Mensch als symbolisches Wesen (Cassirer)

Kurzinhalt: THE DEVELOPING SUBJECT; 1.1 'Being a Man': From Essence to Ideal; The man that one has to be is not what one necessarily is. It is something that follows,

Textausschnitt: ... You can see from the fact of sin, which is an irrationality, that there is reason for doubting the rationality of man. On the other hand, all men use symbols, and so 'man as a symbolic animal' provides a universally true definition. (79; Fs)
()
When we defend the notion of man as rational animal we appeal to what man is potentially. The Greeks defined man as zôon logikon, animal rationale, the animal that is a logical animal. If the logical, rational part of the definition is regarded as something in potency, then it is something that is common to mewling infants, to people that are asleep or unconscious, ...
()
... The man that one has to be is not what one necessarily is. It is something that follows, not from having a birth certificate or citizenship, but from a decision, from the use of one's freedom, from a use of freedom that occurs despite a measure of uncertainty. We do not know all about everything,
()
... Moreover, once one makes a decision, one has not exhausted the content of being a man. One has done so just for that occasion. The challenge remains with us perpetually. There are decisions and choices that have to be made all along the line, and at any time we can fail. We can be 'the man', today and fail tomorrow. Being a man is something that, if we are it, we are so only precariously. It is a continuous challenge.
()
... If you consider man as a rational animal, where the word 'rational' is understood potentially, then there is no development; it is eternally true of every man no matter what he does, how intelligent or stupid he is, how wise or silly, how saintly or wicked - he is a rational animal in that sense. But there is another sense, being actually rational, that carries the implications emphasized by the contemporary group of philosophers known as existentialists Their reasons for doing so are, first of all,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Von der Substanz zum Subjekt; Bewusstsein (Präsenz in drei Bedeutungen)

Kurzinhalt: THE DEVELOPING SUBJECT

Textausschnitt: Who is a man? Who is to be a man? The answer is 'I,' 'We.' That use of the first person supposes consciousness. What has to be a man is not just any instance of rational animal. It is one that is awake. Moreover, insofar as he is concerned with being a man, he is aware of potential triumph or potential failure, and aware of his own freedom and responsibility. (81; Fs)
()
7/4 Such awareness is consciousness, and that consciousness is not to be thought of as thinking about oneself. One is conscious no matter what one is thinking about. Consciousness means that one is doing the thinking. Cognitional and volitional activity not only deals with objects, but also reveals the subject and his activity. To get hold of the notion of consciousness it is well to begin from the word 'presence.'
()
8/4 There are, of course, different levels of consciousness. First, there is merely empirical consciousness: you hear the sounds but you are not worried about any meaning in them. Next, there is intellectual consciousness. Aristotle remarks that wonder is the beginning of all science and philosophy. One asks, What is it? Why? What does he mean? Where is he going? What is he up to? Then not just anyone is present, but someone intelligent is present. Empirical consciousness is simply presence in the third sense, but in intellectual consciousness, someone intelligent is present, actually intelligent, actively intelligent, wondering why and what and how and whither. Thirdly, there is rational consciousness.
()
8/4

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Von der Regionalpsychologie zum Bewusstseinsstrom; Horizont - Profi (Abschattung - Horizont, Husserl), Welt

Kurzinhalt: THE DEVELOPING SUBJECT; From Faculty Psychology to Flow of Consciousness; What is this world? We will begin with a distinction between profile and horizon; eg: Horizont = die hinreichende Zahl von Profilen

Textausschnitt: 10/4 Now the flow of consciousness has a fundamental autonomy. Consciousness is not a market place into which there enters anything whatever, according to its own laws, and from which there departs anything whatever, according to its own laws. Consciousness is a structured unity. It is true that things force themselves upon us, upon our consciousness. The well into which Thales tumbled forced itself upon his consciousness. Again, it is true that consciousness is not completely autonomous, that it cannot run off in any direction it pleases. The limits to the autonomy or freedom of consciousness are exhibited in psychic illness. The orientation of consciousness can get out of touch with the demands of the nervous system. So there are two extremes: things can be forced upon consciousness, and consciousness cannot run off in any direction whatever. But normally consciousness is a directed organization of selected data. And governing that direction and selection is our concern, what we care about, care for, are interested in, aim at. Heidegger's term is Sorge, care; 'concern' is the ordinary English translation. The same notion reappears in such words as 'attention' and 'interest.' One can walk along the street with a friend and in the midst of all sorts of street noises hear just that thin trickle of sound that are his words. Meaning makes his voice audible. That is an example of the selectivity of consciousness. There are all sorts of impressions made upon our sensitive apparatus, our sense organs, but not all of them get into consciousness. It is what you are interested in that gets into consciousness. Consciousness selects; it floats upon the series of demands for attention. (83f; Fs)
()
11/4 In the flow of consciousness there is not only the subjective side, the concern, what concerns me, but also its correlative, the world - not the world but one's world. There is the world of teachers,
()
13/4 The distinction I have just drawn is Husserl's distinction between Abschattung and Horizont. Abschattung is, as it were, the shadow; 'horizon' will do for Horizont. But now we want to think of a horizon of the second degree. We have spoken of a horizon of Brockman Hall, or of any object that you cannot see the whole of in a single look. But what is one's world? It is a horizon of horizons. It is the totality of objects like Brockman Hall, the organized whole of intelligibly varying objects in which I happen to have any interest, for which I have any concern. And that totality is a totality that we construct out of our experience, where the construction is governed by our concern. Just as one does not see the horizon of Brockman Hall, so one never sees one's world. What is his world? Well, you don't see it. It is a construction of constructions. What you see is the profile. The horizon is an envelope containing all possible profiles, and also the knowledge of how many profiles you need in order to recognize the object. (This is an analytic account, of course, a simpler statement of the things that go on.) One's world is a horizon of horizons, a horizon of the second degree, the totality of objects for which one has any concern. Again, one can say that my world is the part of the universe determined by the horizon of my concern. (84f; Fs) (notabene)
()
14/4 Thus we have four terms, four moments in concrete existence subject, concern, horizon, world. The subject's concern determines his horizon, and his horizon selects his world. With that notion of subject-concern-horizon-world, one can move from the child's world to the world of the man. These notions thus give us something that we can deal with when we speak of the developing subject. (85; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: das intellektuelle Erfahrungsmuster: pure desire to know - Universum; that intellect is potens omnia facere et fieri

Kurzinhalt: The Intellectual Pattern of Experience: consciousness is dominated by wonder, by the pure desire to know; the correlative becomes the universe

Textausschnitt: 17/4 When consciousness moves into the intellectual pattern of experience, one's concern becomes the wonder that Aristotle spoke of as the beginning of all science and philosophy. In the measure that that wonder is the dominant concern in consciousness, experience takes on a pattern of its own that is dictated by the exigences of that wonder. ... you can see that this pattern is an organized whole that has its own characteristics, and that it is quite distinct from the ordinary pattern of experience in which we are dealing with persons and mastering things. In the intellectual pattern of experience, consciousness is dominated by wonder, by the pure desire to know, by intellectual detachment and impartiality. One wants to know, What is it? and whether one's answer to that question is true. (86f; Fs)
()
Still, the significance of moving into the intellectual pattern of experience is that, when concern is purely intellectual wonder, the correlative becomes the universe. As long as consciousness is directed by whatever concerns one may have, one is in one's world, but insofar as the intellectual pattern of experience is dominant, one is concerned, not with any private world, but with the universe. This is the meaning of the traditional notion that intellect is potens omnia facere et fieri. The object of intellect is omnia, everything, and an object that includes everything is not restricted to any genus of things. That object must be being. And so, while concern has as its correlative a private world, the intellectual pattern of experience has as its correlative the one universe, everything. (87f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Erkenntnis bei Thomas: intellectus agens, i. possibilis, species intelligibilis, inneres Wort - Scotus

Kurzinhalt: The ontological structure of intellect in the writings of St Thomas may be represented schematically as follows; Scotus: kein intelligere (durchdringen des phantasmas); kein 2. inneres Wort

Textausschnitt: 1.1 Scholastic Theories

3/5 The ontological structure of intellect in the writings of St Thomas may be represented schematically as follows.1 There is an intellectus agens, on the one hand, and there are senses, imagination, phantasms, re-presentations of the data of sense, and an intellectus possibilis, on the other hand. The agent intellect illuminates the phantasm and uses it as an instrument to impress upon the possible intellect an intelligible species. The possible intellect, determined by the species, has an act, intelligere, understanding,2 and from that act there proceeds an inner word. It is a simple inner word, not a judgment, since in itself it is neither true nor false. The standard illustration of such an inner word is the definition. This simple inner word is followed by a reflective process, an activity named reductio ad principia, a reduction of the definition to its principles in intellectual light (intellectus agens) and in sense whence the phantasms were withdrawn. From that reflective process there proceeds a second inner word, the composition or division by affirmation or negation. (108; Fs) (notabene)

4/5 Such is the Thomist structure of intelligence. It can be established beyond any doubt or question from the writings of St Thomas that this is what he meant when he spoke of intellect. He gives, however, a strictly metaphysical account of the psychological process, that apparently does not appeal to data of consciousness.3 (108; Fs)

5/5 In the thought of Duns Scotus, of course, there is presented a different setup, first from the ontological point of view. Scotus speaks of the intellective power, and he does not wish to determine whether or not it is to be divided into agent and possible intellect. He also recognizes the existence of the phantasm and the use of the phantasm by the intellective power to impress upon intellect - whether agent intellect is really distinct from possible intellect or not is not settled - an intelligible species. But that intelligible species corresponds, not to the Thomist intelligible species, but to the Thomist simple inner word. Intellect takes a look at that species, and when it does so it is knowing a concept. It can form several species, take a look at two at a time, compare them, see whether they are compossible, compatible or incompatible, or necessarily connected. (108f; Fs)
(notabene)
eg: Also, Scotus' species intelligibilis entspricht dem ersten inneren Wort bei Thomas (folglich lässt er den Prozess des intelligere aus und hat die Auffassung eines Erkennens durch "Sehen"), dann verquickt er dieses innere Worte, indem er es zugleich als Begriff auffasset, mit dem, was bei Thomas das zweite innere Wort ist.

6/5 Clearly we have here two quite different ontological accounts of the structure of intellect. But there is also a difference in the psychological content. There is abundant evidence in the writings of St Thomas that the act of understanding, intelligere, regards not only the inner word but also the phantasm. Scotus denies the possibility of that. What understanding would see in the phantasm either is universal or it is particular. If it is particular, then we have not understanding, but sense, for sense knows the particular. If it is universal, then understanding is suffering from an illusion, because there is no universal in the phantasm. The traditional or regular Thomist answer to that, of course, is the distinction between the potential and the actual. The phantasm is potentially intelligible, but the intelligible in act is identical with the intellect in act. (109; Fs) (notabene)

7/5 Another difference is that the Scotist analysis leads to a conceptualized universe. Scotus saw the need for a further intellectual intuition of the existing and present as existing and present, if one is to know whether or not this conceptualized network exists. That is not the case with St Thomas. For St Thomas judgment proceeds from the reductio ad principia of reflection. (109; Fs)

8/5 We have two presentations, then, and the difference between them raises a question of fact. Does understanding regard phantasms or does it not? In general, I believe there is no possibility of doubt that understanding does occur with respect to phantasms. However, it is very difficult to get some people to admit that this is the case because, if they do, they have to face epistemological questions that otherwise they could dodge. It is the existence and the dodging of those epistemological questions that, to my mind, accounts for the fact that what Aristotle and Thomas were talking about when they spoke about the intelligible in the sensible has been totally disregarded for a number of centuries by people proclaiming themselves to be Aristotelians and Thomists.4 (109f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Horizont: abhängig vom Streben; Widerstand gegen Horizonterweiterung; Liebe (charity)!!; übernatürlich - natürlich

Kurzinhalt: Heraklit: Logion vom Schlaf (Sorge); the known, the known unknown, the unknown unknown; docta ignorantia - indocta ignorantia; an organized resistance to going beyond one's horizon

Textausschnitt: Weiter unten!!.
Liebe / charity: To move into the practical pattern of experience without contracting one's horizon presupposes perfect charity.


21/4 There is, then, a deeper meaning to Heraclitus's statement that when men sleep each lives in a private world of his own, in his dreams, but when they wake up they live in the common world settled by the logos, by reason. Insofar as one lives in one's own world that is settled by one's own concern, by the Sorge at the root of one's flow of consciousness, one is in something of a private world,
()
25/4 The horizon, is the boundary, the frontier, between docta ignorantia and indocta ignorantia. What is beyond my horizon is meaningless for me, though it may not be meaningless in itself. It is not worth while for me, but it may be worth while in itself. One's horizon, the boundary between one's docta and indocta ignorantia, corresponds to one's concern, and one knows about one's horizon only indirectly. To know about a horizon one has to have a larger horizon within which one can define the smaller one. But if this is one's horizon one does not have the larger horizon within which one can grasp where the limits lie for the individual. One's own horizon is the limit, the boundary, where one's concern or interest vanishes....
()
In the general case, the subject and his concern determine a horizon that selects out of the universe a world. But there is also an intellectual pattern of experience, and correlative to it is the universe, all that exists. The intellectual pattern of experience that corresponds to the universe is beyond any particular horizon. As long as it exists, it is orientated upon totality, upon being, upon everything. But the moment the intellectual pattern of experience ceases to be dominant, then one can shift back to a narrow concern. To move into the practical pattern of experience without contracting one's horizon presupposes perfect charity. There is an intimate correlation between the natural and the supernatural, according to the doctrine of St Thomas. According to St Thomas, there is a natural desire for the beatific vision, a desire to know God by his essence. When consciousness
()
In the general case, the subject and his concern determine a horizon that selects out of the universe a world. But there is also an intellectual pattern of experience, and correlative to it is the universe, all that exists. The intellectual pattern of experience that corresponds to the universe is beyond any particular horizon. As long as it exists, it is orientated upon totality, upon being, upon everything. But the moment the intellectual pattern of experience ceases to be dominant, then one can shift back to a narrow concern. To move into the practical pattern of experience without contracting one's horizon presupposes perfect charity. There is an intimate correlation between the natural and the supernatural, according to the doctrine of St Thomas. According to St Thomas, there is a natural desire for the beatific vision, a desire to know God by his essence. When consciousness is rooted in the pure desire to know, and when one knows of the existence of God, one asks what God is. To ask, What? is to desire to know something by its essence, and to know God by his essence is something that is attained only through the beatific vision. Thus the pure desire to know includes in its range the supernatural goal to which de facto we are destined in this life. St Thomas's doctrine causes difficulty chiefly, I believe, to those whose presuppositions are not Thomist but Scotist. I cannot go into that question here and now, except to say that there is no doubt that this is St Thomas's position. He develops it over thirty-five chapters or so in the third book of the Summa contra Gentiles, and it recurs at all the key points in the Summa theologiae. 'The natural moves into the supernatural; grace is the perfection and completion of nature. Such is the position in the Thomist analysis, where 'Thomist' means'of St. Thomas,' not the Thomistic school, which has various opinions on the matter. And that supernatural end correlative to the desire to know is charity. Thus it is by charity that we can move into the practical pattern of experience without contracting our horizon. (90f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Entwicklung; Newman (Beispiel: Matrose);

Kurzinhalt: development: the orientation of one's living, of one's concern; it eliminates previous evils by finding a higher integration

Textausschnitt: ... Development depends upon, and is measured by, not so much the external objects with respect to which one operates as the organization of one's operations, their reach, their implications, the orientation of one's living, of one's concern. Development retains all that was had before and adds to it, and it can add to it enormously. It eliminates previous evils by finding a higher integration in which the problems solve themselves. It finds this higher integration by working, not at the periphery but at the root, at the Sorge, at the concern, and by effecting the shift from the concern that is all too human to the spiritual aspiration of man that has its fundamental and first appearance in the pure desire to know that grounds the intellectual pattern of experience and sets the standards for one's morality. (91f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Philosophische Entwicklung - Ggs zum technischen Fortschritt

Kurzinhalt: Linie: Parmenides - Herakli t- Plato - Aristoteles - Thomas; Arianismus, Nestorianismus; philosophic develpment: the subject is also one of the objects

Textausschnitt: 29/4 Philosophic development is different. By philosophic development I mean developments in philosophy, in human science, in theology. In those fields there occur crises and developments of the same type as in the scientific field. Parmenides' attention to being was such a development; Heraclitus's attention to the logos was such a development; Plato's distinction between sensible and intelligible, aisthêta and noêta, was such a development. Aristotle's characterization of the intelligible as the causa essendi in the sensible - the noêton is the aition tou einai immanent in the sensible, form immanent in matter - was going beyond Platonic modes of thought. When Aquinas went beyond hylomorphism, the composition of substantial form with prime matter, to posit a third metaphysical entity - esse, existence - he was going beyond Aristotle in a profound and radical fashion. (94; Fs) (notabene)
()
32/4 So there are crises and real developments within the philosophic field, just as there are in mathematics and science. However, the difference in the philosophic field is that the recession of the horizon does not result in a universal and permanent difference. The new horizon is accepted by some and not by others, ... The definition of the consubstantiality of the Son was accompanied by Arianism. The affirmation of one person in two natures in Christ was accompanied by Nestorianism and Monophysitism. The working out of the doctrines of the sacraments, grace, and the church in the medieval period was followed by the Protestant negation of all of these developments at the time of the Reformation. The moments of development within this field do not result in universal and permanent achievement. (95; Fs)
()
33/4 Not only is the new development accepted by some and rejected by others - there is the formation of schools - but the new schools then tend to splinter, to have periods of decay and revival. What is happening in a period of decay within a school? The words of the master are faithfully repeated, but the meaning has been devaluated and contracted to fit into a narrower horizon, a lower stage of development. These periods of decay are followed by periods of revival, a restoration of the original meaning. What is happening is a revival in subjects who have horizons large enough to follow the thought of the original inspiration. And so we have neo-Platonism as well as Platonism, neo-Aristotelianism ...
()
34/4 The ground of this difference between the scientific and the philosophic developments is not hard to find. The scientific development involves a transformation of the object, a rethinking of basic categories, postulates, and axioms. Similarly in the philosophic field. However, the difference between the scientific and the philosophic is that in the case of the philosophic the subject is also one of the objects. The subject can accept the transformation in the conception of the object only if he effects a transformation in his own living. Because the subject is one of the objects, there can occur the transformation of the object only on the condition that there occurs a radica1 conversion, a real development, in the subject. That real development in the subject is something that every subject dreads. Because of that dread of subjects there can be found down the centuries a family resemblance between materialists, between idealists, between realists, that is independent of the purely intellectual development that has been occurring. There is a fundamental philosophic difference of subjects themselves, of the capacity of subjects to broaden their horizon to the point where it includes the universe. (96; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Komplexität: Moralische Entwicklung

Kurzinhalt: Verschiedene Arten und Organisationen von "good";

Textausschnitt: 36/4 Moral development is development in the good that is one's concern. But one's emphasis or concern can fall upon particular goods, 'what's good for me'; it can fall upon the good of order; and it can fall upon values. And one's apprehension of values can be aesthetic or ethical or religious. These differences give rise to the possibility of a great variety of modes of organization of the moral subject, the possibility of different bases of moral orientation. (97; Fs) (notabene)
()
37/4 Moreover, it is very difficult to draw sharp distinctions. There is a natural line of development in man. The child has to develop not only spiritually but also as an animal. The two developments are required, and both are good, both are natural.
()
41/4 So what I have been saying is that the question of moral development is very complex, and one must not jump to conclusions about particular individuals. A person may be apprehending symbolically a very high morality even though he seems to be apprehending nothing but the particular good; he may be living according to

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Beispiel Kreis und die vier Ursachen

Kurzinhalt: If you examine a wheel, you can ask, 'Why is it round?'and then you are asking about its immanent intelligibility ...

Textausschnitt: ... If you examine a wheel, you can ask, 'Why is it round?'and then you are asking about its immanent intelligibility. You can ask, 'Who made it?' and 'What kind of tools did he use?' and then you are asking about the agent, the efficient cause. Or you can ask, 'What did he make it for?' and then you are asking about the final cause. You can ask, 'What did he make it out of?' and then you are asking about the material cause. But the formal cause is the immanent intelligibility, and that is what pure science is concerned with. It is applied science that is concerned with agent, end, and material. (143; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Bedingungssatz und das Unbedingte; Grund - Syllogismus

Kurzinhalt: Ableitung des modus ponens (wenn A -> dann B) aus dem virtuell Unbedingten; the major premise -> the link between the conditioned and the conditions; : ... we know that there are no further relevant questions

Textausschnitt: 24/7 There is also the virtually unconditioned, and every human judgment in this life depends, not on the vision of God, but upon the attainment of a virtually unconditioned. A virtually unconditioned is a conditioned whose conditions are fulfilled. Its formal expression is the syllogism. Where A and B stand for one or more propositions, the form is
If A, then B.
But A.
Therefore B.
The major premise is a link between the conditioned and its conditions; the minor expresses the fulfilment of the conditions; the conclusion presents the conditioned as virtually unconditioned. It is a conditioned whose conditions are fulfilled. (148; Fs) (notabene)
()
25/7 On that analysis, then, syllogism is not, as Kant and sceptics generally conceive syllogism, the occasion for an infinite regress: () In general, the major premise must express explicitly the link between the conditioned and the conditions: if the series of conditions, then the conditioned. The link is grasped when one grasps that one's insight is invulnerable, that there are no further relevant questions. If A, then B. A link, a nexus between conditions and conditioned, is, in a general case, what is grasped in some insight as a possibility or a necessity. Is that connection correct? We know it is correct when we know that there are no further relevant questions. An insight is corrected insofar as one asks further questions and sees that one needs a further insight that qualifies or corrects, fills out or complements in some fashion, the insight one previously had. When one sees that there are no further relevant questions, one is sure of the link. (148; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Weisheit als 1. Gabe des Geistes; Weisheit und Naturwissenschaft

Kurzinhalt: a man who has the wisdom to know when there are no further relevant questions, when the matter can be settled,

Textausschnitt: 30/7 As you know, there is no rule of thumb for producing men of good judgment. A man of good judgment is a man who has the wisdom to know when there are no further relevant questions, when the matter can be settled, when he can say, 'Yes' or 'No.' Moreover,
()
So wisdom, while it is necessary for good judgment, for knowing whether or not there are any further relevant questions, still is a foundation that lies ahead. It is not the sort of foundation that we have at the start and on which we build; it is the goal towards which we move. And we can always grow in wisdom. Complete wisdom is God's knowledge.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Weisheit, wisdom;Wahl des richtigen Verständnisses von Sein (being)

Kurzinhalt: There is no first principle that does not attain a different meaning according to the different meaning you give being; Why do you prefer Aristotle to Plato and Aquinas to Scotus?

Textausschnitt: What is the step, then, from the analytic proposition to the real world? In the Prima secundae of the Summa, question 66, article 5, ad 4m, St Thomas asks why wisdom is the highest of the intellectual virtues. He distinguishes three speculative virtues of intellect: ...
()
49/7 What does that mean in language familiar to nonscholastics? It means that there is no knowledge of truth contained on the second level of consciousness, or on the first and second combined. Wisdom's selection of terms is the selection of one meaning of the term 'being' rather than another, and once that selection has been made, the rest is settled. For example, there is Parmenides' notion of being, Plato's, Aristotle's, Avicenna's, Averroes', St Thomas's, Scotus's, and Hegel's. They all differ. There is no first principle that does not attain a different meaning according to the different meaning you give being. How do you pick out which is the correct notion of being? Picking out the correct notion of being is putting in a fundamental determinant in the meaning of all possible principles you may ever appeal to. Why do you prefer Aristotle to Plato and Aquinas to Scotus? That is the function of wisdom. Wisdom governs the selection of basic terms, the selection of basic terms governs first principles, and first principles govern conclusions. Because we move up to wisdom, because wisdom is not a foundation from which we start but towards which we tend, it is by studying different philosophic systems, comparing them, and seeing the different consequences of the different systems that one arrives at the wisdom of one's own that entitles one to prefer one notion of being to another. That preferring one notion of being to another is a strategically very important judgment, and it is a judgment of fact. Which notion of being is the real? To select the notion of being that is the notion of real being as opposed to false conceptions of being is the fundamental wisdom of the philosopher. It is de facto true, and he makes it in a particular judgment in which he grasps a virtually unconditioned. Just what that judgment is, is a further question. (156f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Ursache für philosophische Differenzen

Kurzinhalt: ... unless the conversion of the subject follows, there will be a conflict between object and subject. The subject will feel that the new theory cannot be true; the root cause of philosophic differences

Textausschnitt: 8/7 But there is a third level of development. The subject of a human science is also one of its objects; and a higher viewpoint on the object, a reformulation of the concepts expressing a fuller understanding of the objects, has implications with regard to the subject himself. A transformation of physics or chemistry, a totally new viewpoint in such a science, involves no change in human living. But in a human science such a transformation has implications for the subject himself. There is not merely transformation in the objects, but also conversion of the subject; and unless the conversion of the subject follows or has been prepared, there will be a conflict between object and subject. The subject will feel that the new theory cannot be true. This third type of development is, I believe, the root cause of philosophic differences. The subject is unprepared to be converted, to transform himself in accord with the corresponding transformation of the human object that has resulted from the development of the human science. (161; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Tertullian: Beispiel für infantile Auffassung von Realität: nur Körper sind real; Augustinus: veritas, Piaget

Kurzinhalt: Tertullian: God has to be a body-not a body such as we see and feel, but still a body; Augustine: discovery of the limitations of the infantile apprehension of reality

Textausschnitt: 29/7 Now the notion of reality formed in that manner is of the same elementary order as the kinesthetic-tactile notion of space. And quite clearly, if one holds that that is reality, then the operations of the mathematician and of the natural scientist that arise within the intellectual pattern of experience and form the enormous structures that refer to a world quite different from the world for us, a world rather of things in their relations to one another, give rise to an unreal world. Such knowing is just hypothesis. It becomes knowledge of reality insofar as you can get back to what you can deal with, what you can see with your eyes, handle with your hands, feel to be hot or cold, rough or smooth, wet or dry, heavy or light. Then the real is simply the aisthiton, the sensibile, what is given to sense. All the rest is instrumental, as Dewey would say. It is immanent, an activity of the subject. It is not knowing reality. It may help you to deal with the reality that is given to sense, but in itself it is not knowing. Activities of understanding help one, they are useful, but they are not knowing. And still less is judgment knowing. Judgment is just putting a rubber stamp upon these activities of understanding. When the scholastics held that the real, ens, is id quod est, where est is said of what you know when you make the judgment 'It is,' they were not talking about reality at all. They were caught up in a verbalism. To throw any doubts upon the convictions about reality formed in infancy is to be an idealist, a Platonist, a Kantian, a relativist, or God knows what. In any case, it is certainly getting out of this real world. (169f; Fs)
()
30/7 We have here a case in which the notion of the real develops, and we have in patristic literature two brilliant instances of this. For Tertullian, only bodies are real. God has to be a body-not a body such as we see and feel, but still a body. What is not a body is not real. This is an expression of the survival of the infantile view of reality. Similarly, StAugustine, who was a man of extraordinary intelligence, was for years a materialist. He knew he was a materialist, and he said so. But he changed. And then when he wanted to talk about the real, what is really so, what word did he use? Veritas. Augustine does not talk about realitas, but about veritas, about what is true. And the truth is known not without, non foras, and not just within, non intus, but above us, in a light that he describes as incommutable and eternal. The history of Augustine's thought is the history of the discovery of the limitations of the infantile apprehension of reality and the history of the shift to the true. (170; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: The Notion of Being; Aristotle: ousia, eidos; Augustinus: veritas; Thomas: ens dicitur ab esse

Kurzinhalt: ti estin ousia, what has the same meaning as why; eclipse (moon); what is man? -> aition tou einai, the causa essendi

Textausschnitt: 31/7 Now let us take another instance, one that ties in with the preceding: the notion of being. Parmenides was the first to insist on to on. Plato carried the matter further, but Aristotle was the one who really went to work on the issue. He argues out the meaning of the word ousia in book 7 of his Metaphysics. In the last chapter of that book, after he has considered what ousia is from a whole series of different angles, he says, Now let us begin afresh, let us take matters in another way. It is this last study that will, I think, throw a shaft of light upon what Aristotle is talking about. (170; Fs)
32/7 Aristotle is asking ti estin ousia, What is being ('entity,' in Owens's translation)? He says that to ask what something is is the same question as to ask why. What do you mean when you ask what? The difficulty of that question lies not only in the term 'being' but also in what is meant by what. Aristotle says what has the same meaning as why. This can be shown from simple examples. What is an eclipse? You can change that into a why question: Why is the moon darkened in this fashion? If you can explain why the moon is darkened in this fashion, you can explain what an eclipse is. The same answer goes for both questions. The moon is darkened in this fashion because the earth comes between the moon and the sun, and so the light from the sun does not reach the moon. What, then, is an eclipse? It is the earth blocking off the light of the sun from the moon. The questions what and why are the same. (170f; Fs) (notabene)
33/7 However, Aristotle admitted that not all cases of the question, What is it? can be reduced to questions of why in the same simple fashion. In talking about an eclipse of the moon you can ask, Why is the moon thus darkened? The eclipse is the darkening, the covering up, the leaving out. But when you ask, What is a house? or What is a man? how do you change that into a why question? There is only one term. Aristotle's answer is to distinguish between the materials and the form. Why are these pieces of timber and lumps of stone a house? Because of the form, because of the way the artificial form orders together all the stones and all the pieces of timber. And why are these materials a man? Because of the form, because of the soul; the intellective soul makes this body a man. So he concludes that when you ask the question, What? you can change it into a question, Why? by asking for the formal cause in the ultimate simple instances. And so when Aristotle in book 7 asks, What is a man? the answer is the aition tou einai, the causa essendi, the reason why the materials are something. That is the form, the eidos, the morpé. At the end of book 7, he identifies ousia with eidos, with form, with the causa essendi. Then in book 8 he moves on a step, to discuss material things, and there he says that the aition, the 'What is it?' is the essence. In material things this is the combination of form and matter. In immaterial things it is the form alone. So we have the Aristotelian answer to the question of being in terms of matter and form, or, in the immaterial order, of pure form. (171; Fs) (notabene)
34/7 Now the Aristotelian answer did not satisfy St Thomas. After all, Aristotle is not asking why this man is, but why he is a man, not why this house is, but why it is a house. St Thomas notes, ens dicitur ab esse. 'Being,' the noun, is said from 'to be.' It receives its meaning from the 'to be,' from the 'is.' And the 'is' is something that is not just the same as being something. (171f; Fs) (notabene)
35/7 St Thomas does not drop the Aristotelian notion that what means why. But he has an answer to the question, What is being? - namely, Why is being what it is? He acknowledges an ens per essentiam, a being that in virtue of its own intelligibility is. Direct knowledge of that being is the beatific vision. Any other being is a being by participation. To understand an ens per participationem is to understand, not being, but a kind of being - the being of a rose, or the being of a monkey, or the being of a man, but not being simply. To know being as being is to have the beatific vision. God knows in his essence himself and everything else that is or could be. Insofar as we participate that divine knowledge in the beatific vision, we have knowledge of what being is. But until we have knowledge of what being is, we know being only by analogy, by knowing some beings and extrapolating to the others. (172; Fs) (notabene)
36/7 Now, when St Thomas goes beyond Aristotle on the notion of being, what he is doing is bringing together Augustine and Aristotle. Augustine is the man who first insisted on veritas, on truth. The Aristotelian notion of being was, Sense and understanding correspond to matter and form. But in St Thomas, sense, understanding, and judgment correspond to matter, form, and the act of essence: esse, existence. St Augustine is the one who developed the notion of judgment as fundamental in knowing, the veritas. St Thomas added its metaphysical equivalent, the esse, in the composition of the finite being. (172; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Scotus: being is 'not nothing'; Christian Wolff, Hegel

Kurzinhalt: For Scotus, being is 'not nothing.' It is not a totality that is the whole of reality.

Textausschnitt: 37/7 However, that movement that begins with Parmenides and passes through Plato, Aristotle, and Augustine to Aquinas is not the only answer to the question, What is being? For Scotus, being is 'not nothing.' It is not a totality that is the whole of reality. You do not need the beatific vision to answer the question, What is being? Being is the concept with the minimum connotation and the maximum denotation. The implications of the Scotist notion of being appear in the order of the philosophic sciences in Christian Wolff, for whom ontology is the study of possible being, and actual being is studied in other departments. Scotus's being is also the being presupposed by Hegel. The being that is not found in anything, that is just 'not nothing,' is the sort of being that never exists. Nothing is merely 'not nothing,' and consequently Hegel's dialectic of the concept goes from being to nothing, the 'not-nothing' being. 'Not nothing' is the minimum connotation with the maximum denotation, and there is nothing that exists corresponding to that; and if there is nothing that exists corresponding to the concept, the concept is a concept of nothing. And so Hegel goes from being to nothing and reconciles both in becoming. (172f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Notion of being ; fundamental dynamism; pure desire to know; species intelligibilis; intellectus agens, possibilis

Kurzinhalt: 5 elements of the notion of being; the asking in words is an expression of that fundamental dynamism; ens quo, ens quod, judgment, being, intentio entis

Textausschnitt: 38/7 Now, if we try to put together all the elements in the notion of being, we can distinguish five points:
(1) the intention of being;
(2) the concept of being;
(3) knowing a being;
(4) knowing the notion of being; and
(5) knowing being, or knowing the idea of being. (173; Fs)
()
39/7 The intention of being is the light of intellect, the origin of wonder, the origin of all questions asking Why? How? What? and again, Is it so? It is the ground of human intelligence. It is not knowing anything or conceiving anything; it is consciously discontented ignorance. One wants to understand, one wants to know, one asks. The asking in words is an expression of that fundamental dynamism, the origin of all science and philosophy. It is in virtue of the intention of being that St Thomas concludes to a natural desire to know God. When we know the existence of God, we ask, What is God? To ask what something is is to want to know it by its essence, and the only knowledge of God by his essence is the beatific vision. Consequently, when we ask, What is God? we are expressing, not any acquired or infused habit, but something that is natural to man, namely, to ask, What is it? with regard to anything he meets with or knows about. The pure desire to know is the root of the intellectual pattern of experience and is to be contrasted with Heidegger's Sorge, concern, which is man as he ordinarily is. Man's flow of consciousness is not simply an expression of the pure desire to know, but is modified by concerns of all types. (173; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Objectivity, Objektivität,

Kurzinhalt: the first spontaneous answer is that the objective is what is out there; the dividing line between objectivity and nonobjectivity or subjectivity lies in truth and falsity

Textausschnitt: 45/7 Let us now take another notion that develops, the notion of objectivity. Presumably, at a first approximation everyone assumes that we know just what is meant by objectivity. You tell people they are not being objective, and usually all you mean, of course, is that you do not agree with them. But if you ask them what they mean by objectivity, or if you ask yourself, What do I mean by objectivity? the first spontaneous answer is that the objective is what is out there; and being objective is seeing what is out there, seeing all of it, and not seeing anything that is not out there. That is what objectivity is. If one follows out logically that notion of objectivity, one agrees with the empiricists, the positivists, the pragmatists, the sensists, the modernists. (175; Fs) (notabene)
()
46/7 One moves to a second notion of objectivity when one thinks of impartiality, detachment. We say a person is guided by his passions; his thinking is wishful; he is not thinking in the intellectual pattern of experience; he does not have ...
()
47/7 There is a third component in the notion of objectivity, and that is when one reaches the absolute, the unconditioned. One is objective when what one says is true, and one is not objective when what one says is false. The dividing line between objectivity and nonobjectivity or subjectivity lies in truth and falsity.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Philosophic differences

Kurzinhalt: act, form, and potency; basic group: differences among philosophers; one can read fruitfully all sorts of material without losing one's way

Textausschnitt: 51/7 Those operations, as a group, determine an object. There is an object proportionate to such operations. The object will be compounded of act, form, and potency, where act is the component in the reality corresponding to the is of judgment, ..
()
52/7 The basic group of operations yields the structure of material being in scholastic philosophy. We can go beyond material being by excluding potency. This leaves two possibilities:
(1) form and act, and
(2) act.
These pertain, respectively, to angels and to God. And from this basic group of operations we can go on to discuss the differences among philosophers, and so to offer a theory of philosophic differences. (177; Fs) (notabene)
()
53/7 The importance of the theory of philosophic differences is that, if one gets a sufficient grasp of it, one can read fruitfully all sorts of material without losing one's way. If one is limited in one's reading and inspiration exclusively to the works written by Catholics that have been approved as safe, one is cutting down enormously one's field of study, one's sources.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Basic levels of conscious operations; Sorokin, values; positions - counterpositions

Kurzinhalt: the 3 basic levels of conscious operations: the experiential, the intellectual, and the rational or reflective; living can be organized more on the level of experience, or more on the level of intelligence, or more on the level of rational reflection

Textausschnitt: 54/7 Let us begin with the three basic levels of conscious operations: the experiential, the intellectual, and the rational or reflective. The three basic types of philosophy are organized, respectively, about the level of experience, about the level of intelligence, and about the level of rational reflection. (178; Fs) (notabene)
()
55/7 De facto, in artistic and literary work the experiential level is most prominent, in mathematical and scientific work the intellectual is most prominent, and in philosophical work the rational and reflective is most prominent. Because rational reflection leads to saying A is, A is B, or A is not C, philosophy can be very jejune. And that is no harm. But that is the controlling level of the other two. Acts of understanding are much rarer than acts of experiencing, and acts of judging are much rarer than acts of understanding. ... You can deal with insights that are all X's, but the philosopher's emphasis is on the 'is' or 'is not.' (178; Fs)
()
56/7 However, men in their living can be organized more on the level of experience, or more on the level of intelligence, or more on the level of rational reflection; and so there arise three basic classes of philosophy. The tendency to organize on the experiential level is manifest in the materialist, the empiricist, the sensist, the positivist, the pragmatist, the modernist. These same types of philosophy recur throughout the whole history of philosophy. There are differences in the experiential philosophies due to different objects of intellectual interest, but they are all of that basic type. On the second level, there are the philosophies of the Platonist, idealist, relativist, essentialist varieties. On the third level, there are the realists, where what is meant by the real is what is known when one truly affirms, 'It is.' As St Thomas said, for example, we know the existence of God when we know the truth of the proposition Deus est, God is. (178; Fs)
()
57/7 Now these philosophic differences will radiate through the whole of life. Earlier, we considered three levels of the good: the particular good (the level of satisfactions), the good of order, and value. We distinguished aesthetic, ethical, and religious values, where the aesthetic value is apprehended by insight into the concrete, the ethical value is the individual demanding correspondence between his rationality and his activity, and the religious value is the rational individual using truth to know being, orientating himself before God within the world and history. The distinction of the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious comes, of course, from Kierkegaard. He used the three categories in speaking of three spheres of existential subjectivity. A person moves from one sphere to another only by a leap. In other words, when a person is within a given sphere of existential subjectivity, as Kierkegaard would put it, or within a given horizon, to use the terminology that we developed earlier, then it is not by arguing from that sphere that one will bring him to another sphere. That sphere becomes a closed system, and a person has to be dynamited out of it. We then related to this distinction of operations Sorokin's analysis of Western culture in terms of three types of cultures or civilizations. There are the sensate, corresponding to the experiential; the idealistic, corresponding to the intellectual; and the ideational, corresponding to the reflective, the 'It is.' Consequently, meeting those fundamental types is the approach implied in Insight in the distinction between positions and counterpositions. Fundamentally, positions are philosophic, ethical, artistic, practical views that are in harmony with the full implications of the three levels. Counterpositions are views, whether philosophic, ethical, practical, or artistic, that involve a blind spot, a limited horizon, where the limitation is either to the intellectual level or to the experiential level. The systematic formulation of the difference between positions and counterpositions is given in epistemological terms: if the real is what you know by understanding correctly, you have a position; if the real is anything but that, or if no real at all is acknowledged, you have a counterposition. (179f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Philosophic Differences: Galileo , primary and secondary qualities, geometry; Aristotle

Kurzinhalt: For Galileo the object of science was a geometrization of the world. In proposing this he had to meet the objection that ; The fundamental Aristotelian axiom is that knowing is by identity

Textausschnitt: 58/7 What I have said thus far is very general, and now we may illustrate it. I begin with the empiricist movement. (180; Fs)
Galileo did not merely discover the idea of the natural law in the instance of the law of free fall. His real inspiration was the idea of a system of laws, and his concept of that system was a ready-made system, namely, Euclidean geometry. For Galileo the object of science was a geometrization of the world. In proposing this he had to meet the objection that it is obvious to everybody that the real world is far more than is treated in geometry. To meet that objection he drew a distinction between primary and secondary qualities. Primary qualities are ...
()
59/7 Now this was a doctrine invented by Galileo to sell his theory of science. And, while his theory of science underwent subsequent revisions, the distinction between primary and secondary qualities continued to have a great influence in philosophy. Nor is this incidental. For it was the real concern of philosophers to arrive at a theory of knowledge that would ground the scientific methodology and justify how science is able to produce such results. And that aim has been attained to a great extent. But as you can see, the position of Galileo that what is really out there is the geometrical object, and the rest of it is just in the subject, is a theory about what is real. It rests upon an epistemological assumption that most people find self-evident, namely, that knowing is a matter of taking a look, that a real distinction between subject and object, and a confrontation of the object to the subject, are of the very essence of knowledge, so that Aristotle was completely wrong when he asserted that sense in act is the sensible in act, that intellect in act is the intelligible in act, and that in things that are without matter the one that understands and what is understood are identical. The fundamental Aristotelian axiom is that knowing is by identity. (181; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Kant: position (Zusammenfassung); pure desire to know, the unconditioned gets beyond the subject; Plotinus, Plato

Kurzinhalt: pure desire to know = transcendental illusion; what makes knowledge knowledge is experience, not a grasp of the unconditioned, naive assumption that knowing is taking a look

Textausschnitt: 66/7 That, very roughly, is the Kantian position. Kant dropped much of the rational level. Simply to say, 'It is,' is just to talk; it is not knowledge of anything. The pure desire to know is transcendental illusion, because it moves you beyond the level of possible experience. The Kantian criterion, the ultimate criterion that is constantly operative in the Critique of Pure Reason, is the idea of possible experience. Knowledge is possible insofar as we construct experience. When we start talking about angels and God, we are not constructing any experience, and consequently our sets of a priori forms are irrelevant. It is a fundamental Kantian assumption that what makes knowledge knowledge is experience, not a grasp of the unconditioned, not something that occurs in the judgment. (184; Fs) (notabene)
()
67/7 The Kantian position is not easily transcended. If one reflects upon one's capacity to reflect, one can see that there is a demand for the unconditioned, and this demand makes one say that science is only probable, that it has not yet reached the unconditioned. This demand for the unconditioned and obtaining of the unconditioned is something that constitutes a third level in our knowing. But if one simply speaks vaguely about evidence, it is not self-evident that one has to go beyond experience and understanding to posit a third level in which the unconditioned is reached; one ignores that reflectivity and thinks simply of the fulfilment of the conditions, of verification in the materialist sense of having the requisite sensation. One does not think of having the requisite sensation as the fulfilment of the conditions that, combined with the link between the conditions and the conditioned, introduces something new, namely, a satisfaction of the demand of rational reflection for the unconditioned, a satisfaction that through the attainment of the unconditioned gets beyond the subject. If the unconditioned is attained, then there is attained something independent of the subject, something in an absolute order, that something that we name truth. Truth is absolute, and it is the means through which we know the real. (184f; Fs)
()
68/7 In other words, in all that development there is the naive assumption that knowing is taking a look. I say the assumption is naive, but it has been held by very profound philosophers. Why are there subsistent universals in Plato? Well, you know the universal, and knowing is taking a look of some sort, or at least remembering a look, and therefore there has to be the universal. Why is it that in Plotinus the first, the One, does not know, is beyond knowledge? Because knowledge involves an imperfection. The first knower is had in the Intelligence, the Nous, that emanates from the One; but the One is beyond being and beyond knowing, because being and knowing imply a duality. (185; Fs) (notabene)
()
69/7 That is an example. There are many other criticisms that can be made of Kant, but the fundamental objection is that the issue is not placed on the rational level. His a priori is validated insofar as it is a necessary condition of possible experience. His ultimate is experience, not truth, not the unconditioned; and that is where he differs from being. Moreover, because he does not reach the unconditioned, his doctrine is an immanentist doctrine. One gets out of merely experiencing and understanding, to reality, through an absolute, through the unconditioned. In Kant there is not that unconditioned. It is implicit, of course, in that he does acknowledge simple fact - you can prove a position by introducing a virtually unconditioned; but he does not have the unconditioned as a systematic structural element in his philosophy, and he cannot introduce it into his philosophy without destroying that philosophy. As long as the unconditioned is not recognized, implicitly or explicitly, the philosophy is an immanentist philosophy. You have the experiences, you perform acts of understanding, but you cannot use true propositions as the means through which you know reality. (185; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Science, existentialists; intellectual pattern, pure reason = speculative intellect

Kurzinhalt: If your attainments in the intellectual pattern of experience are the sort of thing that you can live out, then you are being an intelligent and rational man.

Textausschnitt: If through the intellectual pattern of experience one arrives at the unconditioned, one arrives at truth and being, and that is all that can be demanded. That is the formulation, concretely, of what is meant by speculative intellect or pure reason. If your attainments in the intellectual pattern of experience are the sort of thing that you can live out, then you are being an intelligent and rational man. You are living concretely up to the level of what you know. This is the basis of the autonomy of spirit. It is the ideal of the ethical man. Religion simply places the ethical man within the broader context of God, his creator and judge, and of human history as the field within which he exercises his autonomy. So I do not believe there is anything more than an apparent argument from group theory or from the tendencies of people like Bergson, or from idealists like Croce, to belittle science and consider it as merely practical. (187f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Heidegger, What does Heidegger mean by das Seiende? das Man

Kurzinhalt: one is in the field in which the unconditioned, truth, and truth as the medium through which being is known have not been reached.

Textausschnitt: 76/7 In both Heidegger and Jaspers, one is in the field in which the unconditioned, truth, and truth as the medium through which being is known have not been reached. Heidegger speaks a great deal of das Seiende and of Sein. He aims at an ontology, but he is quite clear that he has not got there yet, and he does not see how one can. He deals with the ontic in the hope of being able to arrive at an ontology. (Ontology means an account of being; ontic is just being.) What does Heidegger mean by das Seiende? He means the given as merely given, as stripped of all intelligibility, which, after all, comes from the intelligence of the subject. To know das Seiende one needs a breakdown of consciousness, because consciousness intellectualizes, makes intelligible the whole flow of experience. You need a breakdown of consciousness to know what das Seiende is.
()
... Das Seiende is the merely given without any intelligible embellishment attributed to it by human consciousness. And Sein is the contribution of human intelligence, what is added to das Seiende by insight.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Jaspers: existence and transcendence; set of ciphers

Kurzinhalt: fundamental concepts: Existenz and Transzendenz, existence and transcendence; for him, there is no way of breaking the Kantian immanence; to think we are knowing anything would be metaphysics

Textausschnitt: ... Jaspers's concern is also with the subject. He has a first-hand acquaintance with science because of his professional studies. His idea of science is empiricist and pragmatist. He can give you magnificent descriptions and analyses of the experiencing, intelligent, rational subject. His philosophy is mostly worked out by explanations of the meanings of German words, but it is brilliant in its nuances. (190; Fs)
()
81/7 Jaspers's two fundamental concepts are Existenz and Transzendenz, existence and transcendence. As he states in his Philosophie, these words mean what is expressed by mythical consciousness with the names 'soul' and 'God.' Why is it that Jaspers uses these two terms and says that their meaning is equivalent to what the mythmaker named soul and God? It is because he sees no answer to Kant. He is in line with Kant's Critique of Practical Reason, the moral side of Kant, as well as with Nietzsche and Kierkegaard, and he made them much more profound and far-reaching. He has no idea of rational consciousness reaching the unconditioned and using truth as a medium through which reality is known. Because he does not have that idea, the only knowledge he can have is of two kinds: the knowledge you can have from pragmatic science - it works - and the experience one can have of oneself as experiencing, intelligent, reasonable, free, and responsible. In one's experiencing oneself, above all as free and responsible, one has an experience of soul. But one must not speak of soul as though one were knowing a reality through that experience. For him, there is no way of breaking the Kantian immanence. If you could break the Kantian immanence, then you could use the word 'soul' and be talking about a reality; but you cannot break it, and so to talk about soul as though it were a reality is myth. In this experience his philosophy is aimed at an illumination of Existenz. It is a matter of self-appropriation. Self-appropriation is, of course, essential to Jaspers, because he has no way of saying anything that is true, that corresponds to reality. That is blocked off by his Kantian assumptions, his failure to get beyond Kant. His philosophy aims at an illumination of Existenz, and in selfawareness, in the illumination that self can have in experiencing itself, there emerges an awareness of Transzendenz in the exercise of freedom, especially in the exercise of freedom in limiting situations, situations involving guilt, struggle, suffering, and death. (190f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Piaget: Unterschied zu verschiedenen anderen Theorien: Gestaltstheorie

Kurzinhalt: his position explicitly differs from the associationist position, from the theory of the conditioned reflex, from Gestalt theory

Textausschnitt: As a psychological theory his position explicitly differs from the associationist position, which is in terms of images and the similarity between images. It differs, too, from a psychology of needs. Piaget has no doubt of needs, but he considers a need as simply an introspective aspect of the scheme. Again, his theory differs from the theory of the conditioned reflex. The conditioned reflex is simply an accidental elaboration of a scheme, one that lasts just as long as it gives satisfactory results. According to Piaget, conditioned reflexes do not produce permanent differences. Finally, his position differs from Gestalt theory. They are similar insofar as in each case the scheme has a structure, a form. But the structure for Piaget is an operational structure, whereas the structure in Gestalt theory is within the percept. (198; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Piaget, Group Theory (Gruppentheorie); a stage in development

Kurzinhalt: Moving up to the group, the child is able to perform a number of the operations, but not the whole system

Textausschnitt: 16/8 Some knowledge of group theory is necessary if one is to understand what Piaget is doing. He is using the idea of the group of operations. When the group or rounded whole is attained, there occurs what Piaget calls a stage in development. Moving up to the group, the child is able to perform a number of the operations, but not the whole system. Consequently, there will be points where he will be blocked, where he will not be able to do things or figure things out. Piaget is able to discern where the group of operations will be lacking. He gives the child things to do and finds that the group has not yet been attained. The child reaches an equilibrium, a capacity to act on a given level, when the group is attained. Development is occurring along a certain line, and the development is attained when the group is attained. From the notion of the group Piaget derives a theoretical structure that defines when development is still occurring and the group has not yet been attained, and again when development is attained. So his theoretical structure gives a precise meaning to stages and to the 'not yet attained' of stages. (199f; Fs) (notabene)

17/8 Piaget thinks up very implausible types of experiments. For example, he will have two large bottles full of water, and he will pour the water from one into a series of smaller bottles. He will then put the empty bottle aside and ask the children, Is there more water in the big bottle or in the series of little ones? Now the children just look; they will not know. It is only at a certain stage, when, instead of comparing the end results, they think of the process and realize that no more water was added and none was spilt, that they will know there is the same amount of water in the series of smaller bottles as in the larger bottle. And only two years later will they be able to apply the same sort of thing to another problem - if we cut something up, does the whole weigh more than the sum of the parts? Again, it is a matter of thinking of and understanding the process, not of comparing the end results. Piaget constructs endless experiments and gives surprising tests to children, but his fundamental inspiration is the idea of the group. And, of course, the notion of the group of operations is used here in a sense that is merely analogous to the use in mathematics. He is not talking about mathematical operations, but about the operations of the child in looking, grabbing, and so on. (200; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Kunst: Gefühl, Einsicht als konkrete Einsicht, Urteil als freie Wahl, verantwortliche Tätigkeit

Kurzinhalt: Art mirrors that organic functioning of sense and feeling, of intellect not as abstract formulation but as concrete insight, of judgment that is not just judgment ...

Textausschnitt: 4/9 One can put this point in a different manner and by putting it in a different manner see how the problems of apprehending the concrete can be turned to some extent by thinking about art and history. Any type of differentiated intellectual consciousness, such as mathematics, science, and philosophy, can express more or less adequately precisely what it is. But any such type of differentiated consciousness is simply a withdrawal for a return. Just as development occurs now in one direction, now in another, and then in a third, and it is only at the end of the whole spiraling process that one has the finished product, so differentiated consciousness is, as it were, a stage in the development. It is a withdrawal from total activity, total actuation, for the sake of a fuller actuation when one returns. What one returns to is the concrete functioning of the whole. In that concrete functioning there is an organic interrelation and interdependence of the parts of the subject with respect to the whole, and of the individual subject with respect to the historically changing group.1 Art mirrors that organic functioning of sense and feeling, of intellect not as abstract formulation but as concrete insight, of judgment that is not just judgment, but that is moving into decision, free choice, responsible action.2 (209; Fs) (notabene)


, so differentiated consciousness is, as it were, a stage in the development. It is a withdrawal from total activity, total actuation, for the sake of a fuller actuation when one returns. What one returns to is the concrete functioning of the whole. In that concrete functioning there is an organic interrelation and interdependence of the parts of the subject with respect to the whole, and of the individual subject with respect to the historically changing group. Art mirrors that organic functioning of sense and feeling, of intellect not as abstract formulation but as concrete insight, of judgment that is not just judgment, but that is moving into decision, free choice, responsible action. (209; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Topics in Education

Titel: Topics in Education

Stichwort: Binswanger: Traum der Nacht u. d. Morgens (Dasein)

Kurzinhalt: Binswanger distinguishes between the dreams of night and the dreams of morning. The dream of night is influenced organically, ... But the dream of morning is the Dasein, the existential subject beginning to posit himself in his world.

Textausschnitt: 5/9 Let us recall by way of a preface to what I am going to attempt to say about art what we said about the good as the developing subject. We must pass from the logical essence of man, something that is common to heroes and scoundrels, mewling infants and saints, something that is verified in everyone equally, to man as concrete potentiality and concrete duty; from man as substance to man as conscious subject; from thinking of a set of faculties and their actuation to thinking of a concrete flow of consciousness, and to thinking of that concrete flow in terms of the subject and his concern that defines the horizon of his world. The subject is not only in his world, but by his intersubjectivity, which we indicated by the phenomenology of the smile, he has a Mitwelt, a world-with-him of other persons with whom he is aware of living. Again, he has a world about him of tools, artifacts, buildings, and so on — an Umwelt.1 That flow of consciousness is captured by Ludwig Binswanger, who used Heidegger's thought to give a new angle to depth psychology.2 Binswanger wrote a little essay entitled 'Traum und Existenz.'3 There is a French translation of this essay, Le réve et l'existence,4 the advantage of which is that Binswanger's rather short essay is prefaced by a long introductory essay by the translator that runs to about 130 pages and helps one get the point. Binswanger distinguishes between the dreams of night and the dreams of morning. The dream of night is influenced organically, for example by the state of one's digestion, and is of no great significance. But the dream of morning is the Dasein, the existential subject beginning to posit himself in his world. He is doing so symbolically, but it is the first movement towards being awake. The subject with his concern will be in his world; the world and the subject are simultaneous. The reason Heidegger speaks of Dasein is that he does not want any split between subject and object. Dasein means the subject and his world; both are simultaneous and correlative. If we think of ourselves that way, we realize that if we know anything about anything it is through meaning, through the intentional order. The stuff of our lives is intentional insofar as we have any consciousness of it at all. Consciousness is not the whole of reality; there are such sciences as biology and neurology, physics and chemistry; but anything that we are above the biological level, and anything that we know, is contained within a field of intentionality, a field that includes the sensitive, intellectual, judicial, and voluntary. These transitions from logical essence to concrete potentiality, from substance to subject, and from faculty psychology to the flow of consciousness are a helpful background to what I want to say about art. And Binswanger's distinction will soon prove helpful in speaking about experiential patterns.5 (209f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Macht, Autorität, Gemeinschaft; keine Gemeinschaft ohne: Erfahrung, Einsicht, Urteil

Kurzinhalt: Community means people with a common field of experience, with a common or at least complementary way of understanding people and things, with common judgments and common aims

Textausschnitt: 4/1 As the source of power is cooperation, so the carrier of power is the community. By a community is not meant a number of people within a frontier. Community means people with a common field of experience, with a common or at least complementary way of understanding people and things, with common judgments and common aims. Without a common field of experience people are out of touch. Without a common way of understanding, they will misunderstand one another, grow suspicious, distrustful, hostile, violent. (5; Fs) (notabene)
5/1 Without common judgments they will live in different worlds, and without common aims they will work at cross-purposes. Such, then, is community, and as it is community that hands on the discoveries and inventions of the past and, as well, cooperates in the present, so it is community that is the carrier of power. (6; Fs)
6/1 The exercise of power is twofold. For men live in two worlds. From infancy they live in a world of immediacy, a world revealed by sense and alive with feeling. Gradually they move into a world mediated by meaning and motivated by values. In this adult world the raw materials are indeed the world of immediacy. But by speech one asks when and where, what and why, what for and how often. Answers cumulatively extrapolate from what is near to what is ever further away, from the present to one's own and to others' memories of the past and anticipations of the future, from what is or was actual to the possible, the probable, the fictitious, the ideal, the normative. (6; Fs)
7/1 As exercised within the world mediated by meaning and motivated by values, power resides in the word of authority. It is that word that brings the achievements of the past into the present; it is that word that organizes and directs the whole hierarchy of cooperating groups in the present; it is that word that distributes the fruits of cooperation among the cooperating members; it is that word that bans from social intercourse those that would disrupt the cooperating society. In brief, the word of authority is the current actuality of the power generated by past development and contemporary cooperation. (6; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Authorität, Authentizität; transzendentale Gebote; Gemeinschaft, Sinn, Werte: authentisch, nicht-authentisch

Kurzinhalt: Such meanings and values may be authentic or unauthentic. Be attentive, Be intelligent, Be reasonable, Be responsible

Textausschnitt: 12/1 Such meanings and values may be authentic or unauthentic. They are authentic in the measure that cumulatively they are the result of the transcendental precepts, Be attentive, Be intelligent, Be reasonable, Be responsible. They are unauthentic in the measure that they are the product of cumulative inattention, obtuseness, unreasonableness, irresponsibility. (7; Fs) (notabene)
()
13/1 Authenticity makes power legitimate. It confers on power the aura and prestige of authority. Unauthenticity leaves power naked. It reveals power as mere power. Similarly, authenticity legitimates authorities, and unauthenticity destroys their authority and reveals them as merely powerful. Legitimated by authenticity authority and authorities have a hold on the consciences of those subject to authority and authorities. But when they lack the legitimating by authenticity, authority and authorities invite the consciences of subjects to repudiate their claims to rule. However, subjects may be authentic or unauthentic. Insofar as they are authentic, they will accept the claims of legitimate authority and legitimate authorities, and they will resist the claims of illegitimate authority and illegitimate authorities. On the other hand, insofar as they are unauthentic, they will resist legitimate claims, and they will support illegitimate claims. (7; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Dialektik, Authentizität

Kurzinhalt: unauthenticity is realized by any single act of inattention, obtuseness, unreasonableness, irresponsibility. But authenticity is reached only by long and sustained fidelity

Textausschnitt: 14/1 Dialectic has to do with the concrete, the dynamic, and the contradictory. Cooperation, power, and authority have to do with the concrete and the dynamic. Authenticity and unauthenticity add a pair of contradictories. The resulting dialectic is extremely complicated. Authenticity and unauthenticity are found in three different carriers:
(1) in the community,
(2) in the individuals that are authorities, and
(3) in the individuals that are subject to authority.
Again, unauthenticity is realized by any single act of inattention, obtuseness, unreasonableness, irresponsibility. But authenticity is reached only by long and sustained fidelity to the transcendental precepts. It exists only as a cumulative product. Moreover, authenticity in man or woman is ever precarious: our attentiveness is ever apt to be a withdrawal from inattention; our acts of understanding a correction of our oversights; our reasonableness a victory over silliness; our responsibility a repentance for our sins. To be ever attentive, intelligent, reasonable, responsible is to live totally in the world mediated by meaning and motivated by values. But man also lives in a world of immediacy and, while the world of immediacy can be incorporated in the world mediated by meaning and motivated by values, still that incorporation never is secure. Finally, what is authentic for a lesser differentiation of consciousness will be found unauthentic by the standards of a greater differentiation. So there is a sin of backwardness, of the cultures, the authorities, the individuals that fail to live on the level of their times. (8; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Authentizität; Nicht-Authentizität: Fortschritt, Niedergang (decline); Erlösung

Kurzinhalt: The fruit of authenticity is progress; the fruit of unauthenticity is decline; redemption

Textausschnitt: 16/1 A more effective approach is to adopt a more synthetic viewpoint. The fruit of authenticity is progress. For authenticity results from a long-sustained exercise of attentiveness, intelligence, reasonableness, responsibility. But long-sustained attentiveness notes just what is going on. Intelligence repeatedly grasps how things can be better. Reasonableness is open to change. Responsibility weighs in the balance short- and long-term advantages and disadvantages, benefits and defects. The longer these four are exercised, the more certain and the greater will be the progress made. (9; Fs) (notabene)
()
17/1 The fruit of unauthenticity is decline. Unauthentic subjects get themselves unauthentic authorities. Unauthentic authorities favor some groups over others. Favoritism breeds suspicion, distrust, dissension, opposition, hatred, violence. Community loses its common aims and begins to operate at cross-purposes. It loses its common judgments so that different groups inhabit different worlds. Common understanding is replaced by mutual incomprehension. The common field of experience is divided into hostile territories. (9; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Toynbee; kreative, herrschende Minderheit; inneres, äußeres Proletaritat

Kurzinhalt: Toynbee: creative minority, dominant minority, internal and external proletariat;

Textausschnitt:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Finalität: absolute, horizontal, vertikal; Evolution

Kurzinhalt: finality: absolute, horizontal, vertical;

Textausschnitt: 4/3 By "finality" I would name not the end itself but relation to the end, and I would distinguish absolute finality, horizontal finality, and vertical finality. (24; Fs)
Absolute finality is to God. For every end is an instance of the good, and every instance of the good has its ground and goal in absolute goodness.
Horizontal finality is to the proportionate end, the end that results from what a thing is, what follows from it, and what it may exact.
Vertical finality is to an end higher than the proportionate end. It supposes a hierarchy of entities and ends. It supposes a subordination of the lower to the higher. Such subordination may be merely instrumental, or participative, or both, inasmuch as the lower merely serves the higher, or enters into its being and functioning, or under one aspect serves and under another participates. (24; Fs)
()
5/3 The classicist view of the universe acknowledged hierarchy and the instrumental type of vertical finality. An evolutionary view adds the participative type:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Vorsehung und Wahrscheinlichkeit, Evolution (PROBABILITY AND PROVIDENCE)

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 7/3 A theologian, if he thinks of evolution, turns to divine providence. A contemporary scientist that does so thinks of probabilities. Darwin's accumulations of chance variations have gained respectability as probabilities of emergence. His survival of the fittest becomes probabilities of survival. What holds for living things, also holds in inanimate nature. Quantum theory has ended the long reign of mechanist determinism and has enthroned statistical law. (24f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Das Übernatürliche (Finalität); THE SUPERNATURAL; vertikale Finalität

Kurzinhalt: the infinite absolutely transcends the finite; it regards man's vertical finality to God

Textausschnitt: 11/3 Contemporary English usage commonly associates the supernatural with the spooky. But the term has a far older meaning, to which we have already adverted in speaking of vertical finality. For in a hierarchy of beings, any higher order is beyond the proportion of lower orders and so is relatively supernatural to them. But the infinite absolutely transcends the finite. It follows that the divine order is beyond the proportion of any possible creature and so is absolutely supernatural. (25f; Fs) (notabene)
()
12/3 Our inquiry is with the absolutely supernatural. It regards man's vertical finality to God. It regards such vertical finality in the strictest sense, so that man is not merely subordinate to God but also somehow enters into the divine life and participates in it. When Rahner writes on Christology within an evolutionary perspective, he very explicitly means that there is a threefold personal self-communication of divinity to humanity, first, when in Christ the Word becomes flesh, secondly, when through Christ men become temples of the Spirit and adoptive sons of the Father, thirdly, when in a final consummation the blessed know the Father as they are known by him. (26; Fs) (notabene)
()
15/3 Vertical finality is obscure. When it has been realized in full, it can be known. When it is in process, what has been attained can be known, but what has not, remains obscure. When the process has not yet begun, obscurity prevails and questions abound. Is it somehow intimated? Is the intimation fleeting? Does it touch our deepest aspirations? Might it awaken such striving and groaning as would announce a new and higher birth? (26; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Aristoteles: vertikale Finalität; Psychologie (Potenz), Kirchenväter, Thomas; Theorie vor Wille; praeparatio evangelica

Kurzinhalt: that Aristotle's thought offered rather stony ground for the objectification of the life of the spirit; psychology: causality not intentionality (Intentionalität); priority of intellect over will

Textausschnitt: 18/3 In a celebrated passage Aristotle granted that his ideal of the theoretic life was too high for man and that, if one lived it, one would do so not as a man but as having something divine present within one. Nonetheless he went on to urge us to dismiss those that would have us resign ourselves to our mortal lot. He pressed us to strive to the utmost to make ourselves immortal and to live out what was finest in us. For that finest, though slight in bulk, still surpassed by far all else in power and in value. (27; Fs) (notabene; FN: Aristoteles, Ethik)
()
19/3 It is not hard to discern in this passage an acknowledgment of vertical finality in its multivalence and in its obscurity. In its multivalence, for there is in man a finest; it surpasses all else in power and in value; it is to be let go all the way. In its obscurity, for what is the divine in man, and what would be going all the way? (27; Fs)
()
20/3 One has only to shift, however, from the corpus of Aristotelian writings to that of the Christian tradition, to recognize in Aristotle's position a sign of things to come. So Christian humanists have spoken of a praeparatio evangelica in the Gentile world and, more bluntly, St. Paul said to the Athenians: "What you worship but do not know-this is what I now proclaim". (Acts 17:23). (27; Fs)
()
21/3 If in the Greek patristic tradition theoria became the name of contemplative prayer, if medieval theologians derived from Aristotle's principles an argument that man naturally desired to know God by his essence, it still remains that Aristotle's thought offered rather stony ground for the objectification of the life of the spirit. For the priority accorded the object gave metaphysics a dominant role. Psychology had to think in terms of potencies, or faculties, that were not among the data of consciousness. Worse, since psychology envisaged plant as well as animal and human life, the relation of operation to object was conceived, not precisely as intentionality, but vaguely as causality. Further, the priority of objects entailed a priority of intellect over will, since will was conceived as rational appetite; and on the priority of intellect over will, there somehow followed a priority of speculative over practical intellect. (27f; Fs) (notabene)
()

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Metaphysik und Intentionalität; Fragen als Operatoren der Intentionalität

Kurzinhalt: It follows that the single cognitional operation is neither a merely immanent psychological event nor yet a properly objective cognitional attainment. It has the intermediate status of an intentional act:

Textausschnitt: 22/3 Intentionality analysis yields a contrasting picture of the subject. Along with the rest of modern science, it eschews dependence on metaphysics. For metaphysicians do not agree. A critically constructed metaphysics presupposes a theory of objectivity, an episte-mology. An epistemology has to distinguish between knowing, as illustrated by any cognitional operation, and adult human knowing, which is constituted by a set of cognitional operations that satisfy a normative pattern. It follows that the single cognitional operation is neither a merely immanent psychological event nor yet a properly objective cognitional attainment. It has the intermediate status of an intentional act: as given, it refers to some other; but the precise nature and validity of that reference remain to be determined; and such determination is reached through the further intentional operations needed to complete the pattern constitutive of full objectivity. In a word, phenomenology brackets reality to study acts in their intentionality. In the very measure that it prescinds from questions of objectivity, it all the more efficaciously prepares the way for a convincing epistemology. (28; Fs) (notabene)
()
23/3 Intentionality analysis, like the rest of modern science, begins from the given. Unlike the rest of modern science, which dilates upon electrons and viruses, it can remain with the given, with human intentional operations dynamically related in their self-assembling pattern. (28; Fs)
()
24/3 In its broad lines this dynamism rests on operators that promote activity from one level to the next. The operators are a priori, and they alone are a priori. Their content is ever an anticipation of the next level of operations and thereby is not to be found in the contents of the previous level. (28; Fs) (notabene)
()
26/3 Three types of operator yield four levels of operation. Each lower level is an instance of vertical finality, and that finality is already realized as the higher levels function. The lower level, accordingly, prepares for the higher and is sublated by it. (29; Fs) (notabene)
()
27/3 We experience to have the materials for understanding; and understanding, so far from cramping experience, organizes it, enlarges its range, refines its content, and directs it to a higher goal. We understand and formulate to be able to judge, but judgment calls for ever fuller experience and better understanding; and that demand has us clarifying and expanding and applying our distinctions between astronomy and astrology, chemistry and alchemy, history and legend, philosophy and myth, fact and fiction. We experience and understand and judge to become moral: to become moral practically, for our decisions affect things; to become moral interpersonally, for our decisions affect other persons; to become moral existentially, for

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Vertikale Finalität - Selbsttranszendenz (self-transcendence)

Kurzinhalt: Such vertical finality is another name for self-transcendence

Textausschnitt: 28/3 Such vertical finality is another name for self-transcendence. By experience we attend to the other; by understanding we gradually construct our world; by judgment we discern its independence of ourselves; by deliberate and responsible freedom we move beyond merely self-regarding norms and make ourselves moral beings. (29; Fs)
()
33/3 But here we meet the ambiguity of man's vertical finality. It is natural to man to love with the domestic love that unites parents with each other and with their children, with the civil love that can face death for the sake of one's fellowmen, with the all-embracing love that loves God above all. But in fact man lives under the reign of sin, and his redemption lies not in what is possible to nature but in what is effected by the grace of Christ. (31; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Übergang von Logik -> Methode (Aristoteles); Faculty psychology; Psychologie und Metaphysik; Intentionalitätsanalyse

Kurzinhalt: For logic what is first is premises. Among premises come first the most universal:; Because metaphysics is first, psychology has to be a faculty psychology:; Method reverses such priorities

Textausschnitt: 34/4 The transition we envisage is from logic to method. Aristotle himself would not admit the strict application of his own Posterior Analytics outside the field of mathematics. Modern science places its reliance, not on any principles or laws it has discovered and may revise, but upon empirical method. Modern scholarship operates on similar lines in its very different field: it is a matter of growing familiarity with the data, advancing comprehension of their meaning and significance, and complete submission to the demand for revision when contrary data or a fuller comprehension come to light. My own study, Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas," would show the continuity of such ideas of method with the Aristotelian and Thomist tradition, while my larger work, Insight, sets forth a generalized empirical method that operates principally on the data of consciousness to work out a cognitional theory, an epistemology, and a metaphysics. First it asks what one is doing when one is knowing. Next, why is doing that knowing? Thirdly, what does one know when one does it? (45; Fs) (notabene)

35/4 A shift from logic to method is a change rather in structure than in content. Both logic and method start from principles, from what is first in an ordered set (primum in aliquo or dine). But the order of logic differs from the order of method. For logic what is first is premises. Among premises come first the most universal: they regard being, and so metaphysics is the first of the sciences. Because metaphysics is first, psychology has to be a faculty psychology: its basic terms are modifications of metaphysical terms, and so it has much to say of potencies and habits, which are not among the immediate data of consciousness, and it relates acts to objects not by intentionality but by efficient and final causality. Again, because metaphysics is first, a primacy goes to speculative intellect which concerns itself with metaphysics. (45f; Fs) (notabene)

38/4 Further, the shift from logic to method includes an acknowledgment of the autonomy of science and of scholarship. But the autonomy recognized is under the control of method. Such controlled autonomy ensures both openness to current views and alertness to spot needed revisions. It grounds sharp distinctions between the results of scientific work and the extrascientific opinions of scientists, between scholarly conclusions and nonscholarly pronouncements. If it permits modern science and scholarship to correct what in the Aristotelian corpus might be mistaken for philosophy, it thereby puts on a rational basis what otherwise tended to be, initially the haphazard result of a long-sustained war of attrition, but later the wholesale desertion of a venerable and still valuable tradition. (46f; Fs)

36/4 Method reverses such priorities. Its principles are not logical propositions but concrete realities, namely, sensitively, intellectually, rationally, morally conscious subjects. Among investigations the key place goes to the self-appropriation of the subject, to his discovery and acknowledgment of human authenticity and unauthenticity, to his option for authenticity and, thereby, for a philosophic foundation less showy but far more effective than an appeal to demonstrations. There follows the replacement of a faculty psychology by an intentionality analysis. Finally, as intentionality analysis distinguishes successive levels of conscious operations by the type of questions they answer, as it has questions for intelligence (what? why? how? what for?) precede questions for reflection (is that so? are you certain?) and both precede questions for deliberation (is it good? is it truly good?), so also it acknowledges the sublation of the earlier by the later. By sublation the later goes beyond the earlier, sets up a higher objective, introduces new operations, but so far from setting aside or interfering with the earlier preserves them in their integrity, refines their performance, extends their relevance, enriches their significance. On this showing speculative intellect loses its primacy. The key position now pertains to the deliberating subject, and his deliberations are existential, for they determine what he is to be; they are interpersonal, for they determine his relations with others; they are practical, for they make this earth a better or a worse place in which we are to live. (46; Fs) (notabene)

39/4 Finally, there is an important difference between method in the sciences and method in philosophy. Empirical method leaves the sciences open to radical revision, because its appeal is to the data of sense but its basic terms and relations denote not the data of sense but constructs derived from empirically established laws. In contrast, the basic terms and relations of an empirically established cognitional theory are not just constructs but also data of immediate consciousness. Its basic terms denote conscious events. Its basic relations denote stages in conscious process. Hence, to introduce new basic terms and new basic relations and thereby establish a radical revision would be, not merely the revision of a theory, but the creation of a new type of consciousness. (47; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: 5 Punkte bezüglich des Verhältnisses zwischen Aristoteles (Logik, Analytica Posteriora) und Methode

Kurzinhalt: Posterior Analytics (Aristotle, Thomas); that method, so far from excluding logic, includes it; Thomas als Lehrer (teacher);

Textausschnitt: 41/4 I now must add five observations. Three of them are theoretical. Two of them are factual. But the five together will help us make the turn from "Aristotle Today" to "Aristotle in Aquinas." (47; Fs)

42/4 The first of the theoretical observations is that method, so far from excluding logic, includes it. It adds to logic such nonlogical operations as observing, describing, comparing, stumbling on problems, discovering solutions, devising tests, checking results. But integral to such nonlogical operations there are within method itself the properly logical operations of defining terms, formulating hypotheses, working out presuppositions, and inferring conclusions. (47f; Fs) (notabene)(notabene)

43/4 The second of the theoretical observations is that inferences can be explanatory without their premises being necessarily true. Fourteenth-century theologians were very accurate logicians and they rightly contended that what necessarily is true would be true in every possible world. But modern scientists are content with explanations that hold in this world. Indeed, they are content to claim that the explanations they offer are the best available at the present time. (48; Fs)
()
46/4 On three theoretical there follow two factual observations. The first is that Aristotle in his own writings left necessary premises and conclusions to the mathematicians. His own rule was to seek in each subject no greater exactitude than the matter permitted. In his eyes it was just as silly to ask a politician for demonstrations as to accept plausible reasons from a mathematician. (48; Fs)

47/4 Our second factual observation is very brief. It is that the theology of Aquinas was not more influenced by the Posterior Analytics than was the philosophy of Aristotle. It is true that Aquinas quoted the Analytics much more than Aristotle did. But it also is true that he was not thereby caught in the implications of that work. For the implications depend upon essential predication, and Aquinas consistently denied that we knew either the essence of God or the substance of material objects. (48f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan, Thomas: 3 Gründe einer Kontinuität; mehr ein Wandel der Form als dem Inhalt nach; Gnade, Habitus

Kurzinhalt: the medieval specialization was implicitly methodical;

Textausschnitt: 55/4 First there is the continuity from the implicit to the explicit. I have argued explicitly for a method in theology. But the medieval specialization was implicitly methodical. Its commentaries and books of sentences sought to do what today is achieved in research, interpretation, and history. Its questions and summa's did the work now carried on in dogmatics and systematics. Then as now theology operated methodically, but method now is talked about and then it was not. (51f; Fs)

56/4 Secondly, (..) Where he discoursed at length on virtues as operative habits, we can think with the Greeks of arete as excellence and develop the moral feelings that promote it. Where he conceived the grace of justification as a supernatural habit, we can note his doctrine that that grace makes us choose what is right where before we chose what was wrong, and so can give it the more familiar name of conversion. For him theology was not only science but-something better-wisdom; and this we can retain in terms of the successive sublations observed in intentionality analysis, where the curiosity of sense is taken over by the inquiry of intelligence, where inquiry is taken over by rational reflection, where reflection prepares the way for responsible deliberation, where all are sublimated by being-in-love-in love with one's family, in love with the human community, in love with God and his universe. (51f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Unterschied: sensation - perception; consciousness - self-knowledge; Infrastruktur und Suprastruktur -> Gefühle

Kurzinhalt: As outer experience it is sensation as distinct from perception. As inner experience it is consciousness as distinct from self-knowledge

Textausschnitt: For example, any scientist will distinguish sharply between his hypothesis and the data to which he appeals. To the data the hypothesis adds a suprastructure of context, problem, discovery, formulation. But the data, as appealed to, are not yet the infrastructure. For, as appealed to, the data are named; and the naming involves its own suprastructure of a technical language and of the scientific knowledge that had to be acquired to use that language accurately. Moreover, this suprastructure supposes an ordinary language, through which one advances to a grasp of scientific terminology, and a commonsense style of knowledge, through which one advances to scientific knowledge. So finally one comes to the infrastructure. It is pure experience, the experience underpinning and distinct from every suprastructure. As outer experience it is sensation as distinct from perception. As inner experience it is consciousness as distinct from self-knowledge, consciousness as distinct from any introspective process in which one inquires about inquiring, and seeks to understand what happens when one understands, and endeavors to formulate what goes on when one is formulating, and so on for all the inner activities of which all of us are conscious and so few of us have any exact knowledge. (57; Fs) (notabene)
()
I say that so few have any exact knowledge of these operations, for while they are conscious, still that consciousness is not knowledge but only the infrastructure in a potential knowledge that few get around to actuating by adding its appropriate suprastructure. (57f; Fs) (notabene)

To conclude this subsection, let us note a possibility. It may be that inner religious and outer sociocultural factors come together to constitute a new religious consciousness inasmuch as (1) the inner religious factor resembles an infrastructure while (2) the outer sociocultural factor makes possible, or begins to countenance, or expresses, or interprets the religious experience. (58; Fs)

12/5 Further Illustrations of Consciousness as Infrastructure. My book, Insight, is an account of human understanding. As a book, it is an outer sociocultural factor providing expression and interpretation of events named insights. But at the same time it is inviting the reader to self-discovery, to performing in and for himself the illustrative insights set forth in successive chapters, to adverting to what happens in himself when the insights occur and, no less, to what is missing when they do not occur, until eventually as is hoped he will be as familiar with his own intelligence in act as he is with his ocular vision. (58; Fs)

13/5 What can be done for insights, can also be done for feelings. Feelings simply as felt pertain to an infrastructure. But as merely felt, so far from being integrated into an equable flow of consciousness, they may become a source of disturbance, upset, inner turmoil. Then a cure or part of a cure would seem to be had from the client-centered therapist who provides the patient with an ambiance in which he is at ease, can permit feelings to emerge without being engulfed by them, come to distinguish them from other inner events, differentiate among them, add recognition, bestow names, gradually manage to encapsulate within a suprastructure of knowledge and language, of assurance and confidence, what had been an occasion for disorientation, dismay, disorganization. (58; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Infrastruktur, Suprastruktur: Tiefenpsychologie

Kurzinhalt: I shall use the term "register" when I mean that we know what is going on within us without our being aware of it.

Textausschnitt: 14/5 I have been distinguishing between an infrastructure of insights as discoveries or of feelings as felt and, on the other hand, a suprastructure of insights as formulated in hypotheses or of feelings as integrated in conscious living. Perhaps I may add a few random indications that depth psychologists are not unaware of the existence and relevance of some such distinction. (58; Fs) (notabene)

[...] the fact that there is no strict alternative between conscious and unconscious, but that there are, as H. S. Sullivan has pointed out in a lecture, several levels of consciousness. Not only is the repressed impulse still effective - one of the basic discoveries of Freud - but also in a deeper level of consciousness the individual knows about its presence. [...] For the sake of saving repetitive explanations I shall use the term "register" when I mean that we know what is going on within us without our being aware of it. (58f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Entfremdung: Institutionen, Bürokratie; bias

Kurzinhalt: that the large establishment and its bureaucratic organization is a fourfold source of that conjunction of dissatisfaction and hopelessness that is named alienation and foments revolutions.

Textausschnitt: 20/5 Ours is a time of very large establishments. They are conspicuous in finance, industry, commerce. They have kept growing on all levels of government with its numerous,
()
21/5 The numerous tasks to be performed in a large establishment generate the type of organization named bureaucracy.
()
22/5 The more precise the policies, the more efficient the procedures, the more exigent the standards and their controls, then the closer will be the approximation to the ideal bureaucracy.
()
23/5 It remains that the large establishment and its bureaucratic organization is a fourfold source of that conjunction of dissatisfaction and hopelessness that is named alienation and foments revolutions. (61; Fs)

30/5 The large establishment and its bureaucratic administration, then, suffer from four defects. Its products and its services are specified by universals, but the good is always more concrete than a set of universals. Its mode of operation is rigid with little tolerance for discretionary adaptation. Its capacity for the more alert observation and the more critical reflection that generate revised ideas and remodeled operations seems no greater than that attributed to the scientific community by Thomas Kuhn. Its size, finally, its complexity, and its solidarity with other large establishments and bureaucracies provide a broad field for the ingenuity of egoists, the biases of groups, the disastrous oversights of 'practical' common sense. (63; Fs) (notabene)

24/5 For policies, procedures, standards are all expressed in general terms. Generalities never reach the full determinateness of concrete reality. But what is good has to be good in every respect, for the presence of any defect makes it bad. My point is very ancient, for over two millennia ago Aristotle pronounced equity to be virtue and defined it as a correction of the law where the law is defective owing to its universality. Like laws, the policies, procedures, standards of a bureaucracy are universal. But unlike laws, they are not tolerant of equitable correction. (61; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: 1. Aufklärung, ENLIGHTENMENT

Kurzinhalt: 1. Auklärung in Unterschied zur 2. Aufklärung

Textausschnitt: 34/5 Culturally its first underpinnings came with the relativization of Euclidean geometry: from being regarded as the unique deduction of necessary truth from self-evident principles it became just one of many possible geometric systems deduced from freely chosen postulates. Newton's mechanics suffered a similar fate when Einstein's special relativity was accepted;

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: 2. Aufklärung, ENLIGHTENMENT

Kurzinhalt: It is a profound transformation in mathematics and natural science. It is paralleled by a transformation in philosophy

Textausschnitt: 38/5 Such in summary fashion is the second enlightenment. It is a profound transformation in mathematics and natural science. It is paralleled by a transformation in philosophy. It is complemented by the vast development in human studies stemming from the initiatives of the German Historical School. It has found allies in sociological and psychological tendencies away from the reductionist postulate of positivist philosophy. (65; Fs) (notabene)

39/5 Of itself this second enlightenment is culturally significant. But it may have as well a social mission. Just as the first enlightenment had its carrier in the transition from feudal to bourgeois society, so the second may find a role and task in offering hope and providing leadership to the masses alienated by large establishments under bureaucratic management. (65; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christentum:infrastructure, suprastructure

Kurzinhalt: As infrastructure it is the dynamic state of being in love in an unrestricted fashion,; the distinctiveness of Christianity lies in this suprastructure

Textausschnitt: 56/5 When the choice falls on Christianity, the following points may be noted: (71; Fs)

A classical formulation of Christian religious experience may be found in St. Paul's statement that God's love has flooded our inmost heart through the Holy Spirit he has given us (Rom. 5:5).

As infrastructure it is the dynamic state of being in love in an unrestricted fashion, a conscious content without an apprehended object.

Its suprastructure, however, is already extant in the account of Christian origins: God sending his only Son for our salvation through death and resurrection and the sending of the Spirit.

The distinctiveness of Christianity lies in this suprastructure. To it the adherents of non-Christian religions may wish to ascribe the characterization of religious experience as being in love.
There is to Christianity an aspiration to universalism, e.g., I Tim. 2:4. Perhaps the simplest explanation of this universalism would be that (1) the salvation of the Christian is in and through charity, and (2) this gift as infrastructure can be the Christian account of religious experience in any and all men.
From this basis one may proceed to a general account of emerging religious consciousness, whether universalist, or ecumenist, or 'bottled effervescence,' or alienated by secular or ecclesiastical bureaucracy, or seeking the integration of religious awakening with a fuller development of the second enlightenment, or distorted by human obtuseness, frailty, wickedness. (71; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Metaphysische Psychologie - Christologie; transformation of falling in love

Kurzinhalt: metaphysical psychology: has underpinned theological accounts of the person of Christ

Textausschnitt: 7/6 Scholastic psychology was a metaphysical psychology. It was a doctrine of the essence of the soul, of its potencies, of their informing habits and acts, and of the objects of the acts. So little did consciousness enter into this psychology that Aristotle treated in the same work the psychology of men, of animals, and of plants. (75; Fs)

8/6 Traditionally it has been this psychology that has underpinned theological accounts of the person of Christ, of his human perfections, and of the grace given all men but superabundantly to him. (75; Fs) (notabene)
()
12/6 Now when psychology is conceived not as subalternate to metaphysics but as a science in its own right, then it proceeds from the data of consciousness. Its basic terms name conscious operations. Its basic relations name conscious processes. Its account of truly human development is of conscious subjects moving cumulatively through their operations to the self-transcendence of truth and love. (76; Fs) (notabene)

13/6 On this view of human development advance ordinarily is from below upwards. It is from experiencing through inquiry to understanding; from intelligent formulations through reflection to judgment; from apprehended reality through deliberation to evaluation, decision, action. (76; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christologie - Philosophie; Unmittelbarkeit, Welt der Bedeutung; Offenbarung: signate not exercite

Kurzinhalt: divine revelation comes to us through the mediation of meaning; human development more commonly is from below upwards but more importantly, as we have urged, it is from above downwards

Textausschnitt: 17/6 Contemporary Catholic theology deprecates any intrusion from philosophy. The result inevitably is, not no philosophy, but unconscious philosophy, and only too easily bad philosophy. (77; Fs) (notabene)
()
19/6 For all of us have lived from infancy in a world of immediacy, a world of sights and sounds, of tastes and smells, of touching and feeling, of joys and sorrows. It was from within that world (as described by Jean Piaget) that we first developed operationally by assimilating new objects to objects already dealt with, by adjusting old operations to new occasions, by combining differentiated operations into groups, and by grouping groups in an ascending hierarchy. (77f; Fs)
()
22/6 In contrast the world mediated by meaning goes beyond experiencing through inquiry to ever fuller understanding, beyond mere understanding through reflection to truth and reality, beyond mere knowing through deliberation to evaluated and freely chosen courses of action. Now mere experiencing has to be enhanced by deliberate attention. Chance insights have to submit to the discipline of the schoolroom and to the prescriptions of method. Sound judgment has to release us from the seduction of myth and magic, alchemy and astrology, legend and folktale; and it has to move us to the comprehensive reasonableness named wisdom. Most of all we have to enter the existential sphere, where consciousness becomes conscience, where the cognitional yields to the moral and the moral to the religious, where we discern between right and wrong and head for holiness or sin. (78; Fs) (notabene)
()
23/6 No one is simply ignorant of these two worlds, of their different procedures, of the differences between their respective criteria. But commonly this advertence is not thematic; it is only lived. As the Scholastics put it, men possess it not signate but only exercite. And because the possession is only latent and implicit, confusions easily arise. Besides the presence of parents to their infant child, there also is the presence of the parents to one another. No one would fail to notice the difference between these two instances of presence. But when a theologian gets along with a minimal philosophy, he can tell us without further ado that he argues for a Christology of presence. When the absence of philosophy is taken as proof of sincere pastoral concern, many will be entranced by his proposal. (78f; Fs) (notabene)

24/6 But the fact is that the presence of Christ to us is not presence in the world of immediacy: "Happy are they who never saw me and yet have found faith" {John 20:29). The fact is that divine revelation comes to us through the mediation of meaning. It comes through meaning transmitted by tradition, meaning translated from ancient to modern tongues, meaning here clarified and there distorted by human understanding, meaning reaffirmed and crystalized in dogmas, meaning ever coming to life in God's grace and God's love. (79; Fs) (notabene)

26/6 But this claim, I feel, would be more attractive if it were not involved in vast oversimplifications. However much the one-way traffic law may suit a Christology of presence, it runs counter to the structure and procedures of the world mediated by meaning. Human development more commonly is from below upwards but more importantly, as we have urged, it is from above downwards. Logic would have us argue from the causa essendi no less than from the causa cognoscendi, from the sphericity of the moon to its phases as well as from the phases to the moon's sphericity. In a contemporary transcendental method one clarifies the subject from objects and one clarifies the objects from the operations by which they are known. In each of the empirical sciences one proceeds not only from the data of observation and experiment to the formulation of laws, but also from the ranges of theoretical possibility explored by mathematicians to physical systems that include empirical laws as particular cases. In theology, finally, one proceeds not only from the data of revelation to more comprehensive statements but also from an imperfect, analogous yet most fruitful understanding of mystery to the syntheses that complement a via inventionis with a via doctrinae. (79f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christologie und Geschichte; Bultmann

Kurzinhalt: history: creation of the nineteenth century; contrast: precritical belief in testimony - critical understanding of evidence;

Textausschnitt: () History in this contemporary sense largely was the creation of the nineteenth century, and its acceptance in the Catholic church has occurred only slowly and gradually in the present century. It found its way first into church history, then into patristic and medieval studies, and finally in recent decades into biblical studies. (80; Fs)
()
29/6 This contrast between precritical belief in testimony and critical understanding of evidence is of the greatest theological significance. When the New Testament is viewed as testimony to be believed because it is credible, then the greatest emphasis will be placed on the words of Jesus Christ himself, for they are supremely credible, while a fundamentalist adherence will spread indiscriminately over every aspect of every word and sentence because all are divinely inspired. Then the theologian has only to open his Bible to find convincing proof for whatever preconceived ideas he may happen to entertain. But when the New Testament is viewed as evidence, then one need hardly believe what the Synoptic Gospels affirm if one is concerned to differentiate stylistic features, discern successive strata, and compose a history of the synoptic tradition. Then what Jesus really said and did belongs to a stratum still earlier than any to be verified in the successive contributions to the synoptic tradition, and the Jesus of history becomes either Bultmann's itinerant rabbi who eventually was crucified or, more recently, the hopefully fuller figure that is the objective of the new quest of the historical Jesus.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Chrstologie, kerygma addressed to Existenz; Heilsgeschichte; Botschaft in Wechselwirkung zu unserer Entscheidung

Kurzinhalt: 5 Arten der Forschung; aber keine bezieht sich auf die Botschaft im eigentlichen Sinn; in correlation with the response it elicits, that in that response there emerges the message as message-for-us

Textausschnitt: 37/6 I have distinguished five different genera of inquiry. All five can be applied to the New Testament. The textual critic can specialize in the manuscript tradition. The exegete can master all related literatures and bring them to bear on an understanding of this or that section of the text. The factual historian can assemble the factual statements in the New Testament, submit them to his critical scrutiny, and seek to fit them in the context of other known contemporary events. The ethically oriented historian can compare the moral attitudes of New Testament personages with those of other human communities or he can subsume them under some moral code to praise them or blame them. But while all of these approaches have their significance and value, none of them deals with what manifestly is the principal concern of the New Testament. For first and last, the New Testament is a book with a message; the message is presented in a great variety of manners, in narratives and parables, in precepts and counsels, in exhortations and warnings. The message is depicted as emanating from the man, Jesus, who suffered, died, was quickened from the dead, and now sits at the right hand of the Father in heaven. The message announces the imminent coming of the kingdom of God, and, as it challenged Jew and Greek two millennia ago, so too today it challenges us with a last word about last things. As Saul on the way to Damascus heard a voice saying: "Saul, Saul, why do you persecute me?" so each of us is to hear from the same voice either of two verdicts. That verdict may be: "[...] anything you did for one of my brothers here, however humble, you did for me." But again it may be: "[...] anything you did not do for one of these, however humble, you did not do for me." (83; Fs)

38/6 Our third step continues the second. We began from the exigence of a post-Kantian transcendental method that attends not just to the object, not just to the subject, but to each in itself and in its dependence on the other. We proceeded from that generality to the currently common view that the New Testament pertains to the genus, Heilsgeschichte, that it centers on a kerygma addressed to Existenz. We have now to note that the message is at once simple, radical, and intensely personal, that it stands in correlation with the response it elicits, that in that response there emerges the message as message-for-us. (83f; Fs) (notabene)

39/6 The message then is simple, as simple as the "Follow me" addressed to Simon and Andrew, to James and John, to Levi the publican. It is as radical as the counsel to leave father and mother and all one possesses, to renounce wealth and honors, to put up with every indignity, day after day to take up one's cross. Simple and radical, the message is intensely personal. It is "Follow me," "for my sake and for the Gospel," "for the sake of my name," "for the sake of the kingdom of God," that is, for the kingdom for which Jesus himself lived and died. (84; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christologie - eine theologische Frage; : historischer Jesus - Christus der Glaubens

Kurzinhalt: Bezug zwischen den drei Arten einer Beschäftigung mit Geschichte und dem Christus des Glaubens; Gegenüberstellung: Fundamentalist - Wissenschaftler

Textausschnitt: () There is the contrast between the Jesus of history and the Christ of faith. There is the suggested option between a functional and an ontological Christology. There is the problem of uniting the concern of the inquiring subject with the objective wealth of scriptural scholarship. On each of these topics something must be said. (85; Fs)

44/6 The contrast between the Jesus of history and the Christ of faith may be approached from the distinction already drawn of three kinds of historical writing, namely, writing that deals mainly
(1) with questions of fact, or
(2) with moral issues, or
(3) with matters pertaining to salvation.
Now different writing supposes difference in competence. A historian trained to deal with questions of fact also is competent to deal with factual issues that serve to introduce matters pertaining to the second and third style of historical writing. But this does not necessarily imply that he will possess the moral sensibility or the religious concern that will fit him for an open and adequate treatment of matters proper to these further fields. In brief, he can treat certain aspects of the Jesus of history, but he may be unequal to discerning the Christ of faith or to determining the factual presuppositions of the Christ of faith. (85; Fs) (notabene)

45/6 Similarly, a religious person will readily discern the Christ of faith but, unless he has been trained in the techniques of scientific history, he will be prone to a fundamentalist interpretation of the New Testament. For him any question of the Jesus of history, as understood by scientific history, will be a matter not of science but of unbelief and infidelity. Nonetheless, there are not only possible but also actually existing religious persons, committed to the Christ of faith, yet also fully cognizant of the nature and procedures of scientific history. They are aware that the New Testament was written by men of faith and addressed to men of faith; they are aware that the authors of the books in the New Testament expressed themselves far more in the vocabulary of their own later day than in the less evolved vocabulary possible in the time of the Jesus of history. And so they not only present the Christ of faith but also join in the new quest for the historical Jesus. (85f; Fs) (notabene)
()
47/6 It is in this coincidence that there is to be found the clue to Christological method. This we have characterized as selecting what is valid in current views without becoming involved in positions open to radical change. Now what is open to radical change, is the incipient and still tentative reconstruction of the thought and language of the Jesus of history. What can be valid in current views is based on the contemporary and so firsthand evidence we possess on the beliefs of the early church. By discerning Christian tradition in that evidence, by coming to grasp its immanent structure and intelligibility, by leaving open the questions still to be settled by the reconstruction of the Jesus of history, the theologian, I submit, will find a first and basic component in a methodically developing Christology. (86; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christologie: ontologische oder funktional

Kurzinhalt: A merely functional Christology acknowledges no more than a series of religious events; ... is not strictly ontological

Textausschnitt: 48/6 A second determination of Christological method comes from asking whether New Testament Christology is ontological or functional. Our answer will be that it is neither merely functional nor yet strictly ontological. (86; Fs)
49/6 A merely functional Christology acknowledges no more than a series of religious events. There is factual evidence that people in New Testament and later times believed Jesus to have risen from the dead. Such acts of believing are historically established. They constitute the set of events referred to as Christology. (86f; Fs) (notabene)
50/6 Now this is all true enough but it ignores the notion of salvation history. It is not a factual history of acts of believing. It is history of what happened on the evidence believers discern in the light of faith. But there was no question for the New Testament writers that the Jesus who was condemned and crucified, who died and was buried, also rose from the dead. One may agree with them or one may disagree; but if one disagrees, one will not attempt Christian salvation history; one will limit oneself to factual history. (87; Fs)
51/6 At the same time New Testament Christology is not strictly ontological. It purports to deal with persons that really existed and with events that really occurred. But it does not go into the hermeneutics of its message and, least of all, does it go into that recondite department of hermeneutics that involves one in cognitional theory, epistemology, and metaphysics. (87; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christologie: heuristische Struktur (Beispiel: Feuer); conjunction: object - subject; Erfahrung - Sohnschaft

Kurzinhalt: On the side of the data one discerns three points: ...; criterion. Our own experience of our own sonship provides a first criterion,

Textausschnitt: 54/6 A heuristic structure, then, is a conjunction both of data on the side of the object and of an operative criterion on the side of the subject. Accordingly, a Christological heuristic structure will be a similar conjunction giving rise to the succession of Christologies set forth in New Testament writings and further developed in the formulations of individuals and of communities down the ages. On the side of the data one discerns three points:
(1) that Jesus is named time and again from different viewpoints and in different contexts the Son of God;
(2) that we through faith are sons of God and by baptism are one in Christ {Gal. 3:26-28), that God sent his only Son that we might acquire the status of sons as is proved to us by the sending of the Spirit of Christ crying in our hearts "Abba! Father!" (Gal. 4:3-7; Rom. 8:14-17); and
(3) that the Spirit we have received from God knows all and has been given us that we may know all that God of his own grace gives us (1 Cor. 2:10-16; John 14:16,17, 26). (87f; Fs)

55/6 In correspondence with such data there arises in the Christian subject his or her heuristic structure. In many contexts and from many viewpoints Jesus was named the Son of God, and that gives rise to the multiple question: How are we in our own minds to understand Jesus as Son of God? Are we to suppose it is a mythic or merely honorific title such as was given to kings? Or does it simply denote the mission of the Messiah? Or does it point to an inner reality such as is our own divine sonship through Christ and in the Spirit, so that as God in us is the Spirit, so God in Jesus is the Word? Or does the sonship of Jesus mean, as the church for centuries has understood it, that Jesus was truly a man leading a truly human life but his identity was the identity of the eternal Son of God consubstantial with the Father? (88; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Christologie - Person; Person Christi, Definition: Identität, Bewusstsein, Subjektivität

Kurzinhalt: By identity I understand the third of the three meanings of one; indivisum in se et divisum a quolibet alio; consciousness: intentional and conscious; subject - subjectivity

Textausschnitt: 65/6 ... I shall attempt to offer some explanation of the statement: the person of Christ is an identity that eternally is subject of divine consciousness and in time became subject of a human consciousness. I shall speak (1) of identity, (2) of human consciousness, (3) of human subjectivity, (4) of divine subjectivity, and (5) of the compatibility of one identity with the two subjectivities. (91; Fs)

66/6 By identity I understand the third of the three meanings of one. There is one in the sense of instance: a first instance is one; a second makes two; still another and there are three; and so on to infinity. (91; Fs)
64/6 There next is one in the sense of intelligible unity. There are many phases of the moon, for its appearance changes night by night. But there is only one moon, for the many appearances have a single explanation: the moon is spherical. (91; Fs)
65/6 Thirdly, there is one in the sense of one and the same. It is the one that presupposes the intelligible unity already mentioned but adds to it an application of the principles of identity and contradiction. So it is one in the sense of the old definition: indivisum in se et divisum a quolibet alio. Such is the "one and the same" of the Chalcedonian decree. (91; Fs)

66/6 Next, consciousness. Man's sensitive, intellectual, rational, and moral operations have two distinct but related characteristics. They are both intentional and conscious.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Hypostatische Union; 3 Subjekte des göttlichen Bewusstseins (Trinität); state of being in love

Kurzinhalt: higher synthesis of intellectual, rational, and moral consciousness that is the dynamic state of being in love; The two processions ground four real relations of which three are really distinct from one another

Textausschnitt: 69/6 But we must now turn to the main component in the hypostatic union. Can one speak intelligibly of three distinct and conscious subjects of divine consciousness? I believe that one can, but to do so one must take the psychological analogy of the Trinitarian processions seriously, one must be able to follow the reasoning from processions to relations and from relations to persons, and one has to think analogously of consciousness. (93; Fs) (notabene)
()
70/6 The psychological analogy, then, has its starting point in that higher synthesis of intellectual, rational, and moral consciousness that is the dynamic state of being in love. Such love manifests itself in its judgments of value. And the judgments are carried out in decisions that are acts of loving. Such is the analogy found in the creature. (93; Fs) (notabene)

71/6 Now in God the origin is the Father, in the New Testament named ho Theos, who is identified with agape (1 John 4:8,16). Such love expresses itself in its Word, its Logos, its verbum spirans amorem, which is a judgment of value. The judgment of value is sincere, and so it grounds the Proceeding Love that is identified with the Holy Spirit. (93; Fs)
72/6 There are then two processions that may be conceived in God; they are not unconscious processes but intellectually, rationally, morally conscious, as are judgments of value based on the evidence perceived by a lover, and the acts of loving grounded on judgments of value. The two processions ground four real relations of which three are really distinct from one another; and these three are not just relations as relations, and so modes of being, but also subsistent, (eg: FN!) and so not just paternity and filiation but also Father and Son. Finally, Father and Son and Spirit are eternal; their consciousness is not in time but timeless; their subjectivity is not becoming but ever itself; and each in his own distinct manner is subject of the infinite act that God is, the Father as originating love, the Son as judgment of value expressing that love, and the Spirit as originated loving. (93f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Erfahrung der Gnade

Kurzinhalt: Experience of grace, then, is ...: experience of man's capacity for self-transcendence, of his unrestricted openness to the intelligible, the true, the good

Textausschnitt: 42/3 Experience of grace, then, is as large as the Christian experience of life. It is experience of man's capacity for self-transcendence, of his unrestricted openness to the intelligible, the true, the good. It is experience of a twofold frustration of that capacity: the objective frustration of life in a world distorted by sin; the subjective frustration of one's incapacity to break with one's own evil ways. It is experience of a transformation one did not bring about but rather underwent, as divine providence let evil take its course and vertical finality be heightened, as it let one's circumstances shift, one's dispositions change, new encounters occur, and-so gently and quietly-one's heart be touched. It is the experience of a new community, in which faith and hope and charity dissolve rationalizations, break determinisms, and reconcile the estranged and the alienated, and there is reaped the harvest of the Spirit that is " [...] love, joy, peace, patience, kindness, goodness, fidelity, gentleness, and self-control" {Gal. 5:22). (32f; Fs) (notabene)
Kommentar (10.12.2003): Also, die Erfahrung der Gnade als
1) Erfahrung des Vermögens und Vollzuges der Selbsttranszendenz als Offenheit gegenüber dem Intelligiblen, Wahren und Guten
2) als Erfahrung der Behinderung dieses Vermögens und Vollzuges in einer zweifachen Weise: 2.1 durch die objektive Sünde der Welt, 2.2 durch die eigene Impotenz, dem Streben in der rechten Weise nachzukommen
3) Erfahrung der Heilung eines hartnäckigen krummen Habitus
4) als Erfahrung einer in der rechten Weise strebenden Gemeinschaft

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Religious studies - theology; animal: rationale - symbolisches; Natur - Geschichte

Kurzinhalt: animal rationale, the rational animal - the symbolic animal; man understood as nature - understood as historic; religious studies confined to what is in the world

Textausschnitt: 1/8 Traditionally man was defined with abstract generality as the zoon logikon, the animal rationale, the rational animal. More concretely today he is regarded as the symbolic animal, whose knowledge is mediated by symbols, whose actions are informed by symbols, whose existence in its most characteristic features is constituted by a self-understanding and by commitments specified by symbols. On the abstract view man was understood as nature. On the relatively recent view man is understood as historic: for the symbols that inform his being vary with the cultures into which he is born, and the cultures themselves change with the passage of time. They emerge, they develop, they flourish, they influence one another, they can go astray, vanish with their former carriers, only to reappear with fresh vitality and vigor grafted upon new hosts. (115; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Mehrdeutigkeit der Erfahrung; Carl Rogers, Jung, Karen Horney, Abraham Maslow

Kurzinhalt: THE AMBIGUITY OF EXPERIENCE; infrastructure - suprastructure; in contrast to Jung, Karen Horney writes: "[...] there is no strict alternative between conscious and unconscious; peak experiences

Textausschnitt: 8/8 What I have illustrated from cognitional theory, also may be illustrated from psychiatry. There is Carl Rogers' client-centered therapy. It aims to provide the patient with an ambiance in which he feels at ease, permits his feelings to emerge, comes to distinguish them from other inner events, to compare different feelings with one another, to add recognition to their recurrence, to bestow names upon them, to manage gradually to encapsulate within a suprastructure of language and knowledge, of confidence and assurance, an infrastructure of feelings that by themselves had been an occasion for turmoil, disorientation, dismay, disorganization. (117; Fs)
()
10/8 In contrast to Jung, Karen Horney writes: "[...] there is no strict alternative between conscious and unconscious, but [...] there are [...] several levels of consciousness. Not only is the repressed impulse still effective-one of the basic discoveries of Freud-but also in a deeper level of consciousness the individual knows about its presence." After making this point, Karen Horney proceeded to pin it down with a technical term: she would use the word, register, when she meant that we know what is going on within us without our being aware of it. (117f; Fs) (notabene)
()
... To quote Klages, the thing in question (the matter repressed) is not so much a thing that is not thought as one that is not recognized." (118; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Tradition - Authentizität; The issue is the struggle of authenticity against unauthenticity

Kurzinhalt: THE CULTIVATION OF RELIGIOUS EXPERIENCE; What is fundamental is human authenticity; minor - major authenticity, to pay a double price for their personal attainment of authenticity

Textausschnitt: 14/8 Because man is a symbolic animal, his development is only partly a matter of his genes. All its higher reaches depend upon his historical milieu with its techniques of socialization, ..
()
The sower, we read, went out to sow his seed, and some fell by the wayside, some among thorns, some on stony ground, but some on good soil where it brought forth fruit now thirty-, now sixty-, now a hundred-fold. The seed, we are told, is the word, for the word is the tool of the symbolic animal. The ground is human consciousness in the polyphony of its many levels. But consciousness does not heed when absorbed in outer cares, or distracted by pleasures, or hardened in waywardness. And even when it is fruitful, its fruitfulness will vary with the cultivation it has received. (119; Fs)

16/8 In time there emerge professional cultivators: ascetics and mystics, seers and prophets, priests and ministers. There is sought the transformation of consciousness that makes possible a human life that is a life of prayer. There is found the inspiration that speaks to the heart of a tribe or clan,
()
19/8 But it would be a mistake, I think, to concentrate on such differences to the neglect of what is more fundamental. For in the main such differences represent no more than the ongoing process in which man's symbols become ever more differentiated and specialized. What is fundamental is human authenticity, and it is twofold. There is the minor authenticity of the human subject with respect to the tradition that nourishes him. There is the major authenticity that justifies or condemns the tradition itself. The former leads to a human judgment on subjects. The latter invites the judgment of history upon traditions. Let us dwell briefly on both these forms. (120; Fs)
()
22/8 So it is that commonly men have to pay a double price for their personal attainment of authenticity. Not only have they to undo their own lapses from righteousness but more grievously they have to discover what is wrong in the tradition they have inherited and they have to struggle against the massive undertow it sets up.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: commitment - drifters;

Kurzinhalt: What, then, is commitment? Negatively, one might perhaps say that it is absent in the man or woman that just drifts through life,

Textausschnitt: 26/8 What, then, is commitment? Negatively, one might perhaps say that it is absent in the man or woman that just drifts through life, content to do what everyone else is doing, to say what everyone else is saying, to think what everyone else is thinking, where the "everyone else" in question is just drifting too. Out of that company of drifters one steps when one faces the problem of personal existence, that is, when one finds out for oneself that one has to decide for oneself what one is to do with oneself, with one's life, with one's five talents or two or lonely one. (123; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Erfahrung der Gnade; Verschränkung zw. Kognitivem und religiösem Fortschritt

Kurzinhalt: three stages in the inner life: purgative, illuminative, unitive way; relationships between religious development and cognitive development

Textausschnitt: () ... to ask in what manner God's love flooding our hearts is a human experience and just how it fits into human consciousness. (125; Fs)

33/8 First, then, it is an experience, not in the broad sense that refers to the coming together and compounding of many conscious elements, but rather in the technical sense that refers to a single element and so constitutes not a structure but an infrastructure. (125; Fs)

34/8 Secondly, consciousness is like a polyphony, or like a concerto that blends many themes in endless ways. So too religious experience within consciousness may be a leading voice or a middle one or a low one; it may be dominant and ever recurrent; it may be intermittently audible; it may be weak and low and barely noticeable. Again, religious experience may fit in perfect harmony with the rest of consciousness; it may be a recurrent dissonance that in time increases or fades away; it may vanish altogether, or, at the opposite extreme, it may clash violently with the rest of experience to threaten disruption and breakdown. As the metaphor from music offers an enormous variety of suggestions, so too the lives of men and women present every degree and shade in the intensity of religious experience, in the frequency of its recurrence, in the harmony or dissonance of its conjunction with the rest of consciousness. (125; Fs)

35/8 Thirdly, as religious experience is found to vary when one compares one individual with another, so too it may be found to develop in the lifetime of this or that individual. Hence there was long repeated the traditional distinction of three stages in the inner life. Beginners were said to be in the purgative way, for theirs was the initial task of reducing and, as far as possible, eliminating the conflict between their religious commitment and the other themes recurrent in their consciousness. Next came the illuminative way in which the significance and implications of religious commitment were ever more fully apprehended and understood. Finally, there was listed a unitive way in which potential conflicts were under control, the full significance of religious commitment was understood and accepted, and in mortal beings there could be verified the harvest of the Spirit catalogued by St. Paul: "love, joy, peace, patience, kindness, goodness, fidelity, gentleness, and self-control" (Gal. 5:22). (125f; Fs)

36/8 Lastly, there are the somewhat intricate relationships between religious development and cognitive development in man. In its spontaneous unfolding cognitive development may be characterized as from below upwards: it proceeds from the data of experience through the unifications and relational networks spun by understanding towards a process of verification that ends with a verdict of acceptance or rejection. Moreover, there is a certain necessity to this order of development:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Selbst-Transzendenz auf verschiedenen Stufen: Gefühl, Intellekt, Entscheidung; (Binswanger, Hopkins)

Kurzinhalt: transition from consciousness to conscience, from moral feelings to the exercise of responsibility; all bear convincing testimony that self-transcendence is the eagerly sought goal

Textausschnitt: 8/9 In various ways clinical psychologists have revealed in man's preconscious activity a preformation, as it were, and an orientation towards the self-transcendence that becomes increasingly more explicit as we envisage successive levels of consciousness. (131; Fs)

9/9 Perhaps most revealing in this respect is a distinction drawn by the existential analyst, Ludwig Binswanger, between dreams of the night and dreams of the morning. ...
()
13/9 Beyond the data of experience, beyond questions for intelligence and the answers to them, beyond questions for reflection concerned with evidence, truth, certitude, reality, there are the questions for deliberation. By them we ask what is to be done and whether it is up to us to do it. By them is effected the transition from consciousness to conscience, from moral feelings to the exercise of responsibility, from the push of fear and the pull of desire to the decisions of human freedom. So it is that on the level of deliberating there emerges a still further dimension to self-transcendence. On previous levels there stood in the foreground the self-transcendence of coming to know. But deliberation confronts us with the challenge of self-direction, self-actualization, self-mastery, even self-sacrifice. (132; Fs) (notabene) (notabene)

14/9 Already I have spoken of consciousness as a polyphony with different themes at different intensities sung simultaneously. Now I would draw attention to the different qualities, to what Gerard Manley Hopkins might call the different self-taste, on the successive levels: the spontaneous vitality of our sensitivity, the shrewd intelligence of our inquiring, the detached rationality of our demand for evidence, the peace of a good conscience and the disquiet released by memory of words wrongly said or deeds wrongly done. Yet together they form a single stream, and we live its unity long before we have the leisure, the training, the patience to discern in our own lives the several strands. (132; Fs)

15/9 The basic unity of consciousness reaches down into the unconscious. It is true that conflicts do arise, as the psychiatrists have insisted. But this truth must not be allowed to distract us from a far profounder and far more marvelous harmony. In man, the symbolic animal, there is an all but endless plasticity that permits the whole of our bodily reality to be fine-tuned to the beck and call of symbolic constellations. The agility of the acrobat, the endurance of the athlete, the fingers of the concert pianist, the tongue of those that speak and the ears of those that listen and the eyes of those that read, the formation of images that call forth insights, the recall of evidence that qualifies judgments, the empathy that sets our own feelings in resonance with the feelings of others-all bear convincing testimony that self-transcendence is the eagerly sought goal not only of our sensitivity, not only of our intelligent and rational knowing, not only of our freedom and responsibility, but first of all of our flesh and blood that through nerves and brain have come spontaneously to live out symbolic meanings and to carry out symbolic demands. (132f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Überzeugung und objektive Wahrheit; Unmittelbarkeit - Bedeutung (Empiristen - Rationalisten)

Kurzinhalt: INNER CONVICTION AND OBJECTIVE TRUTH; Man the symbolic animal lives in both of these worlds; philosophers opt for one of the two worlds;

Textausschnitt: 19/9 At first blush inner conviction and objective truth stand at opposite poles. Inner conviction is subjective. Objective truth is the truth about what is already-out-there-now for everyone to see and grasp and handle. It is public truth, and the publicity is spatial. Precisely because it is spatial, because in principle it can be tested by anyone, it is beyond doubt or question. (134; Fs) (notabene)
20/9 Still questions do arise. One can distinguish between the world of immediacy and the world mediated by meaning. The world of immediacy includes all the data of sense and all the data of consciousness. It consists of two parts: the totality of the data of sense is the sphere of objectivity that is spatial, public, in principle open to anyone's inspection; the totality of the data of consciousness is an aggregate of distinct and segregated subjectivities none of which can inspect what is going on in any of the others. (134; Fs) (notabene)
21/9 To be contrasted with this world of immediacy there is the world mediated by meaning. It consists of all that is to be known by asking questions and arriving at correct answers. It is a world unknown to infants but gradually introduced to children as they learn to speak, to boys and girls as they study in school, to students and scholars in centers of learning. (134; Fs)
22/9 Man the symbolic animal lives in both of these worlds. As animal he lives in the world of immediacy and, like Macbeth, is liberated from his fantasies when he adverts to the sure and firm-set earth on which he treads. As symbolic, he both suffers from the fantasies and brings about his liberation, for that consists not merely in the pressure on the soles of his treading feet but also in his certainty that the earth is firm-set and will not give way under his tread. (134; Fs) (notabene)

23/9 Still man the symbolic animal has long been a puzzle to man the philosopher. Insofar as philosophers search for simplicity and coherence, they opt for one of the two worlds and attempt to get along without the other. Empiricists opt for the world of immediacy, and proceed to empty out from the world mediated by meaning everything that is not immediately given. Rationalists take their stand on demonstrative argument and, if they go along with the ancient Eleatics, will argue that there cannot be more than one being and that that one being cannot undergo any change. (134f; Fs) (notabene)
24/9 But both of these are extreme positions. Empiricists usually find it convenient to take an occasional excursion into the world mediated by meaning, at the very least to expound and prove their own position. Rationalists can advert to the fact that questions are raised with respect to the data of experience and that answers are confirmed by pointing to data that show what they say. So they are led to supplement the apodictic power of demonstration with the intuitions of sense and/or consciousness. But both empiricist excursions into meaning and rationalist appeals to intuition are compromises. They renege on their initial premise of simplicity and coherence. They point the way to a new starting point that acknowledges the complexity of man the symbolic animal. (135; Fs)
25/9 The so-called "new" starting point is, of course, very old. It goes back to Plato and Aristotle. It reached crises in the medieval controversy between Augustinians and Aristotelians and in the later victory of modern science over Aristotelian constructions. It heads into a quite different starting point in the twentieth century in which the notion of method aspires to a foundational role. (135; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Brancis Bacon: Novum Organum -> neues Ideal

Kurzinhalt: FROM ARISTOTLE'S Posterior Analytics TO NEWTON'S Principia; cautious rule of the Royal Society that excluded questions that neither observation nor experiment could solve

Textausschnitt: 30/9 With the first stage of that transformation we are now concerned. If its triumph was Newton, still its goal was not Aristotelian theoretical knowledge but the practical utility praised by Francis Bacon in his Novum Organum. Its conceptual framework took its inspiration not from Aristotle's metaphysics but from Galileo's program of mathematicizing nature. Its field of inquiry was defined not by Aristotle's intellect, capable of fashioning and becoming all, but by the cautious rule of the Royal Society that excluded questions that neither observation nor experiment could solve. (136; Fs) (notabene)

32/9 In the second chapter of the first book of that work one is aware that Aristotle's basic concern is with causal necessity. We think we understand, he notes, when we know the cause, know that it is the cause, and know that the effect cannot be other than it is. But straightway this concern with things and their causes is transposed into syllogistic theory. We are told how knowledge of causal necessity is expressed in appropriate subjects and predicates, premises and conclusions, and thereby manifests its nature as science. We are told how one science can find its principles in the conclusions of another more general science. But when at the end of the second book it is asked how the initial premises are obtained on which the whole deductive structure has to rest, we are told about a rout followed by a rally. The line breaks. Sauve quipeut! But as the fleeing line scatters in every direction, somewhere someone will turn and make a stand. Another will join him, and then another. The rally begins. The pursuing enemy now is scattered. Victory may be snatched from the jaws of defeat. I think this military analogy is sound enough. For it represents the chance accumulation of clues that can combine into a discovery. But it is not at all clear that a necessary truth will be discovered and not a mere hypothesis, a mere possibility that has to be verified if it is to merit the name not of truth but of probability. If the only premises the Posterior Analytics can provide are just hypotheses, verifiable possibilities, then we have many words about causal necessity but no knowledge of the reality. (136f; Fs)

33/9 Further, the syllogistic approach distinguished philosophy and science simply as the more and the less general. It followed that together they formed a seamless robe with the basic terms and basic relations of philosophy ramifying through the less general fields and robbing them of their autonomy. But experimental science has to be autonomous. For ...

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Von der Logik zur Methode; Verifikation ist kein Beweise -> Fehlschluss;

Kurzinhalt: FROM LOGIC TO METHOD; Verification is not proof; to affirm the consequent of an hypothesis, settles nothing about the truth of the antecedent

Textausschnitt: 34/9 The Aristotelian hegemony had been broken, but Aristotelian notions not directly challenged by the new science lived on in quiet possession of the field of common assumptions. Among them was the view that science consisted in true and certain knowledge of causal necessity. Indeed, Newton's deduction of the orbits of the moon and of the planets was regarded as a stunning confirmation ()

35/9 But the logic of the matter is simple. Verification is not proof. For verification is an affirmation of what follows from scientific hypothesis, theory, system. But to affirm the consequent of an hypothesis, settles nothing about the truth of the antecedent from which the consequent follows. A logical conclusion is to be had only when the attempt to verify turns up contrary instances; for then one denies the consequent and from that denial there follows the denial of the antecedent. Accordingly, the principles and laws of an empirical science, no matter how frequently they are verified, may be esteemed ever more probable but may not be considered to be definitively established. (138; Fs) (notabene)

36/9 Moreover, the progress of modern science points in the same direction. Newton was acclaimed because he was considered to have done for mechanics what Euclid had done for geometry. But in the nineteenth century it became clear that Euclidean geometry could no longer be considered the one and only possible geometry. In the twentieth the repeated verification of Einstein's special relativity made it probable that a non-Euclidean geometry was the appropriate conceptualization in physics. (138; Fs) (notabene)

37/9 Similarly, Laplace's determinism was found to have shaky foundations. For Heisenberg's relations of indeterminacy (or uncertainty) reveal a knowledge that is not less but greater than the knowledge offered by classical laws. Formerly, indeed, probability was thought to be no more than a cloak for our ignorance. But now the tables are turned. For classical laws hold only under the blanket proviso, other things being equal. So it is that classical predictions can be notably mistaken because they fail to foresee the interference of some alien factor. But, further, the verification of classical laws is never exact: no more is demanded than that actual measurements fall within the limits set by a theory of probable errors of observation. In brief, classical theory consists of two parts: there is the classical law, and it sets an ideal norm from which actual measurements do not diverge systematically; there is the theory of measurement and it sets the limits within which errors of observation may be considered probable. But, as Patrick Heelan has pointed out, the same two aspects are contained within the single formalism proposed by quantum mechanics. For the single formalism admits two interpretations: one interpretation yields an ideal norm from which actual measurements do not diverge systematically; the other interpretation of the same formalism informs us of the distribution of the divergence from the norm. (138f; Fs)

39/9 There has occurred, then, a transition from logic to method. It has occurred in the field of natural science. It does not, by any means, involve an elimination of logic: for it still is logic that cares for the clarity of terms, the coherence of propositions, the rigor of inferences. But it does involve a shift in the significance of logic. For Aristotle in his Posterior Analytics made his demonstrative syllogism the central piece in his construction both of the nature of science and of the relations between sciences. That construction has turned out to be a procrustean bed on which science cannot lie. So far from providing the key to the whole nature of science, logic has to be content with the task of promoting clarity, coherence, and rigor in the formulation and application of hypotheses and theories. Further, while it is essential that this task be properly performed, still the significance of that performance is measured not by logic itself but by method. For an empirical science is not confined to logical operations with respect to terms, propositions, inferences. It includes observation, description, the formulation of problems, discovery, processes of experimentation, verification, revision. Within the larger whole logic ensures the clarity of terms, the coherence of propositions, the rigor of inferences. And the more successfully it performs that task, the more readily will there come to light not the definitive immutability but the defects of current views and the need to seek more probable opinions. (139f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Ursache für das Versiegen der Einsicht; bias (general), Verschlossenheit

Kurzinhalt: why does the flow of fresh insights dry up? Why, if challenges continue, do responses fail?; insights only if people have open minds; the wheel of progress becomes a wheel of decline when the process is distorted by bias

Textausschnitt: 15/7 But, one may ask, why does the flow of fresh insights dry up? Why, if challenges continue, do responses fail? Why does a minority that was creative cease to be creative and become merely dominant? (104; Fs) (notabene)

There are many intermediate answers that correspond to the many and varied circumstances under which civilizations break down. But there is one ultimate answer that rests on the intrinsic limitations of insight itself. For insights can be implemented only if people have open minds. Problems can be manifest. Insights that solve them may be available. But the insights will not be grasped and implemented by biased minds. There is the bias of the neurotic fertile in evasions of the insight his analyst sees he needs. There is the bias of the individual egoist whose interest is confined to the insights that would enable him to exploit each new situation to his own personal advantage. There is the bias of group egoism blind to the fact that the group no longer fulfills its once useful function and that it is merely clinging to power by all the maneuvers that in one way or another block development and impede progress. There is finally the general bias of all 'good' men of common sense, cherishing the illusion that their single talent, common sense, is omnicompetent, insisting on procedures that no longer work, convinced that the only way to do things is to muddle through, and spurning as idle theorizing and empty verbiage any rational account of what has to be done.1 (104f; Fs) (notabene)

16/7 Not only is there this fourfold exclusion of fresh insights by the neurotic, by the bias of individual and, worse, of group egoism, and by the illusory omnicompetence of common sense. There also is the distorting effect of all such bias on the whole process of growth. Growth, progress, is a matter of situations yielding insights, insights yielding policies and projects, policies and projects transforming the initial situation, and the transformed situation giving rise to further insights that correct and complement the deficiencies of previous insights. So the wheel of progress moves forward through the successive transformations of an initial situation in which are gathered coherently and cumulatively all the insights that occurred along the way. But this wheel of progress becomes a wheel of decline when the process is distorted by bias. Increasingly the situation becomes, not the cumulative product of coherent and complementary insights, but the dump in which are heaped up the amorphous and incompatible products of all the biases of self-centered and shortsighted individuals and groups. Finally, the more the objective situation becomes a mere dump, the less is there any possibility of human intelligence gathering from the situation anything more than a lengthy catalogue of the aberrations and the follies of the past. As a diagnosis of terminal cancer denies any prospect of health restored, so a social dump is the end of fruitful insight and of the cumulative development it can generate. (105f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Heilung (nur durch: creative process); zwei Bewegungen; Verschränkung: Moral - Ökonomie

Kurzinhalt: love: commands commitment and joyfully carries it out, no matter what the sacrifice involved; romand empire; when physicists can think on the basis of indeterminacy, economists can think on the basis of freedom

Textausschnitt: 17/7 I have spoken of creating in history and of its nemesis. But my topic also calls for a few words on healing. In fact, the genesis and breakdown of civilization occupy only the first six of the ten volumes Toynbee devoted to his A Study of History. In the last four there emerges a new factor, for out of the frustration and disgust of the internal proletariat there come the world religions and a new style of human development. (106; Fs)

18/7 For human development is of two quite different kinds. There is development from below upwards, from experience to growing understanding, from growing understanding to balanced judgment, from balanced judgment to fruitful courses of action, and from fruitful courses of action to the new situations that call forth further understanding, profounder judgment, richer courses of action. (106; Fs)

19/7 But there also is development from above downwards. There is the transformation of falling in love: the domestic love of the family; the human love of one's tribe, one's city, one's country, mankind; the divine love that orientates man in his cosmos and expresses itself in his worship. Where hatred only sees evil, love reveals values. At once it commands commitment and joyfully carries it out, no matter what the sacrifice involved. Where hatred reinforces bias, love dissolves it, whether it be the bias of unconscious motivation, the bias of individual or group egoism, or the bias of omnicompetent, shortsighted common sense. Where hatred plods around in ever narrower vicious circles, love breaks the bonds of psychological and social determinisms with the conviction of faith and the power of hope. (106; Fs)

20/7 What I have attributed to love and denied to hatred, must also be denied to any ambiguous and so deceptive mixture of love and hatred. If in no other way at least from experience we have learnt that professions of zeal for the eternal salvation of souls do not make the persecution of heretics a means for the reconciliation of heretics. On the contrary, persecution leads to ongoing enmity and in the limit to wars of religion. In like manner wars of religion have not vindicated religion; they have given color to a secularism that in the English-speaking world regards revealed religion as a merely private affair and in continental Europe thinks it an evil. (106; Fs)

21/7 Again, while secularism has succeeded in making religion a marginal factor in human affairs, it has not succeeded in inventing a vaccine or providing some other antidote for hatred. For secularism is a philosophy and, no less than religion, it may lay claim to absolutes of its own. In their name hatred can shift from the religious group to the social class. So the professions of tolerance of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment did not save from the guillotine the feudal nobility of France, and the Marxist march of history in Russia has attended to the liquidation not merely of the bourgeoisie but also of the Romanovs, the landowners, and the kulaks.1 (106f; Fs)

22/7 As healing can have no truck with hatred, so too it can have no truck with materialism. For the healer is essentially a reformer: first and foremost he counts on what is best in man. But the materialist is condemned by his own principles to be no more than a manipulator. He will apply to human beings the stick-and-carrot treatment that the Harvard behaviorist, B. F. Skinner, advocates under the name of reinforcement. He will maintain with Marx that cultural attitudes are the by-product of material conditions and so he will bestow upon those subjected to communist power the salutary conditions of a closed frontier, clear and firm indoctrination, controlled media of information, a vigilant secret police, and the terrifying threat of the labor camps. Again, while Christians accord to God's grace the principal role in touching men's hearts and enlightening their minds, it would seem that the true believer in the gospel according to Marx must be immersed in proletarian living conditions, on the ground that only such material conditions can confer upon him the right thinking and righteous feeling proper to proletarian class consciousness.2 (107; Fs)

23/7 Healing then is not to be confused with the dominating and manipulating to which the reforming materialist is confined by his own principles. It has to be kept apart from religious hatred of heretical sects and from philosophic hatred of social classes.3 But besides these requirements, intrinsic to the nature of healing, there is the extrinsic requirement of a concomitant creative process. For just as the creative process, when unaccompanied by healing, is distorted and corrupted by bias, so too the healing process, when unaccompanied by creating, is a soul without a body. Christianity developed and spread within the ancient empire of Rome. It possessed the spiritual power to heal what was unsound in that imperial domain. But it was unaccompanied by its natural complement of creating, for a single development has two vectors, one from below upwards, creating, the other from above downwards, healing. So when the Roman empire decayed and disintegrated, the church indeed lived on. But it lived on, not in a civilized world, but in a dark and barbarous age in which, as a contemporary reported, men devoured one another as fishes in the sea. (107f; Fs) (notabene)

24/7 If we are to escape a similar fate, we must demand that two requirements are met. The first regards economic theorists; the second regards moral theorists. From economic theorists we have to demand, along with as many other types of analysis as they please, a new and specific type that reveals how moral precepts have both a basis in economic process and so an effective application to it. From moral theorists we have to demand, along with their other various forms of wisdom and prudence, specifically economic precepts that arise out of economic process itself and promote its proper functioning. (108; Fs) (notabene)

25/7 To put the same points in negative terms, when physicists can think on the basis of indeterminacy, economists can think on the basis of freedom and acknowledge the relevance of morality. Again, when the system that is needed for our collective survival does not exist, then it is futile to excoriate what does exist while blissfully ignoring the task of constructing a technically viable economic system that can be put in its place.4 (108; Fs) (notabene)
Is my proposal Utopian? It asks merely for creativity, for an interdisciplinary theory that at first will be denounced as absurd, then will be admitted to be true but obvious and insignificant, and perhaps finally be regarded as so important that its adversaries will claim that they themselves discovered it. (108; Fs)

A lecture m the series, Anniversary Lectures, The Thomas More Institute, Montreal, May 13, 1975. Previously published in Bernard Lonergan: 3 Lectures (Montreal: Thomas More Institute Papers/75, 1975), pp. 55-68.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Voegelin (Euripides, Johannes): Symbol. Leben - Tod; Plato (Höhlengleichnis); Zug - Gegenzug; helkein, sophrosyne

Kurzinhalt: Euripides: "Who knows if to live is to be dead and..."; there is a pull or attraction that, if followed, puts an end to questioning; and there are counterpulls that...;

Textausschnitt: 15/12 A basic symbol for that search was phrased by Euripides when he exclaimed, "Who knows if to live is to be dead and to be dead to live?" The symbol was resumed by Plato in the Gorgias (492 E) and elaborated at the end of that dialogue in the Myth of the Judgment of the Dead. But its most effective setting occurs at the end of the Apology when Socrates concludes, "But now the time has come to go. I go to die, and you to live. But who goes to the better lot is unknown to anyone but the God." (189; Fs)
16/12 Obviously what Voegelin is raising is a question not just for philosophers but for everyman. So there is no occasion for surprise when the same symbol comes from the lips of Jesus in Matthew's Gospel, "For whoever would save his life (psychen) will lose it; and whoever loses his life for my sake will find it. What then will it profit a man, if he gains the whole world but has to suffer the destruction of his life" (Matt. 16:25-26). Or again one may read in Paul, "If you live according to the flesh, you are bound to die; but if by the spirit you put to death the deeds of the body, you will live" (Rom. 8:15). (189; Fs)
()
18/12 I have been speaking of the double meaning of life and death as a symbol, and Voegelin would stress the point. For from the symbol one can either go backward to the engendering experience or forward to the doctrines Plato and Aristotle were later to formulate. The latter course obviously is contrary to Voegelin's intent, and so he directs our attention to the Parable of the Cave. (189; Fs)
()
19/12 In brief there are opposite principles at work, and to them Plato adverts. On the one hand, opinion may lead through reason (logos) to the best (ariston), and its power is called self-restraint (sophrosyne); on the other hand, desire may drag us (helkein) towards pleasures and its rule is called excess (hybris) ...
()
20/12 In brief there is a pull or attraction that, if followed, puts an end to questioning; and there are counterpulls that, when followed, leave questions unanswered and conscience ill at ease. The former alternative is what Voegelin means by a movement luminous with truth, or again by existing in the truth, or again by the truth of existence. The latter alternative is existence in untruth. As he contends, this luminosity of existence with the truth of reason precedes all opinions and decisions about the pull to be followed. Moreover, it remains alive as the judgment of truth in existence whatever opinions about it we may actually form. In other words, there is an inner light that runs before the formulation of doctrines and that survives even despite opposing doctrines. To follow that inner light is life, even though to worldly eyes it is to die. To reject that inner light is to die, even though the world envies one's attainments and achievements. (190; Fs) (notabene)
21/12 For Voegelin, then, the classic experience of reason in fourthcentury Athens was something poles apart from the reason cultivated in late medieval metaphysics and theology, from the reason of Descartes and the rationalists, from the reason of the French Enlightenment and the German absolute idealists. It took its stand not on logic but on inner experience. Its conflicts were not public disputations but inner trials.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Voegelin: inneres Licht; Aristoteles (Ethik), Zug - Gegenzug; Offenbarung - Information; periagoge - metanoia

Kurzinhalt: inner light; classic experience of reason: It took its stand not on logic but on inner experience; revelation - information; gospel (Justin): philosophy brought to the state of perfection

Textausschnitt: 21/12 For Voegelin, then, the classic experience of reason in fourthcentury Athens was something poles apart from the reason cultivated in late medieval metaphysics and theology, from the reason of Descartes and the rationalists, from the reason of the French Enlightenment and the German absolute idealists. It took its stand not on logic but on inner experience. Its conflicts were not public disputations but inner trials. Its victory was the saving of one's life, keeping one's soul undefiled, holding ever to the upward way, pursuing righteousness with wisdom, so that we may be dear to ourselves and to the gods (Rep. 621 BC). This, of course, is Plato. But the sobriety of the Nicomachean Ethics does not imply that Aristotle holds a different view. (190f; Fs) (notabene)
()
22/12 It is not only classic philosophy but also the gospel that symbolizes existence as a field of pulls and counterpulls.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Welte (Dogma) -> Lonergan dreht W.s Position um; Perzeptualismus als Seinsvergessenheit

Kurzinhalt: Nicene decree -> forgetful of being because it speaks of ousia; dogmas interpreted by one who habitually dwells in the world of the perceptualist there would be forgetfulness ...

Textausschnitt: 27/12 Welte suspects the Nicene decree to have been forgetful of being because it speaks of ousia and so must mean das beständig Anwesende, das beständig Vorliegende. In these expressions I would distinguish two elements. There is a perceptual element, the presence (Anwesenheit) of what lies before one (Vorliegende). There is a static logical element (Beständigkeit). Though both tie in with the massive problem Plato expressed symbolically in his Parable of the Cave, they do so in different manners and I shall speak of them separately. (193; Fs)
()
28/12 Is then perceptualism the same as Heidegger's forgetfulness of being? The question supposes Heidegger's meaning to be well known. Let me say very simply that perceptualism is forgetfulness of the inner light, the light that raises questions and, when answers are insufficient, keeps raising further questions. It is the inner light of intelligence that asks what and why and how and what for and, until insight hits the bull's-eye, keeps further questions popping up. It is the inner light of reasonableness that demands sufficient reason before assenting and, until sufficient reason is forthcoming, keeps in your mind the further questions of the doubter. It is the inner light of deliberation that brings you beyond the egoist's question - What's in it for me? - to the moralist's question - Is it really and truly worthwhile? - and if your living does not meet that standard, bathes you in the unrest of an uneasy conscience. (193; Fs) (notabene)
Kommentar eg (02/03/2004): Perceptualismus als Seinsvergessenheit des inneren Lichtes - damit dreht Lonergan Weltes Position, die ja eine Art "geistiger" Perzeptualismus ist, um.
29/12 The ascent from the darkness of the cave to the light of day is a movement from a world of immediacy that is already out there now to a world mediated by the meaningfulness of intelligent, reasonable, responsible answers to questions. (193; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Kritik an: Welte, Voegelin; Wurzel d. statischen Denkens; Logik - verifizierbare Möglichkeit; Metaphysik, Dogma

Kurzinhalt: static thinking has its source, not in Greek or other metaphysics, but in any doctrine that gives one-sided attention to logic;

Textausschnitt: 31/12 Besides presence, the Greek word, ousia, is thought to connote permanence, to forget the dynamic, and point to the static. I have expressed the opinion that static thinking has its source, not in Greek or other metaphysics, but in any thought or doctrine that gives one-sided attention to logic. The logical ideal of clarity, coherence, and rigor can be pursued with excellent results, provided the pursuit is only part of a larger ongoing investigation that has other resources and fuller goals than logic alone can attain. Admittedly there is to the Posterior Analytics a one-sidedness that concentrates on necessity and slights verifiable possibility; and it was by concentrating on verifiable possibility that modern science proved its superiority to Aristotelian logic. But that logic is so much less than the whole of Aristotle. (193f; Fs) (194; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan über Voegelin; Zug - Gegenzug; Offenbarung - Information, zweifache Offenbarung u. Gnade; "In-Between"

Kurzinhalt: only through one's own experience of that dynamism one can advert to its working in others; a twofold grace: an inner operative grace - an outer grace; "In-Between" and "Beyond"

Textausschnitt: 35/12 I believe, then, that Welte has a real point insofar as he associates doctrine with a grave risk of congealed minds. But Voegelin makes a similar point though in a quite different manner. He is aware of the self-transcending dynamism of truly human living, of its mythical and symbolic expression, of its philosophic expression, and of its expression in the prophets of the Old Testament and in the writers of the New. 35/12 I believe, then, that Welte has a real point insofar as he associates doctrine with a grave risk of congealed minds. But Voegelin makes a similar point though in a quite different manner. He is aware of the self-transcending dynamism of truly human living, of its mythical and symbolic expression, of its philosophic expression, and of its expression in the prophets of the Old Testament and in the writers of the New. He is aware that only through one's own experience of that dynamism can one advert to its working in others. By a brilliant extension he moves on to his distinction between revelation and information. Items of information are all about us: they are the stock in trade of the media. But revelation is not just one more item of information. In its essential moment it is a twofold pull: being drawn by the Father, listening to him, learning from him; and being drawn by the Son, crucified, dead, and risen. Again, it is a twofold grace: an inner operative grace that plucks out hearts of stone and replaces them with hearts of flesh; and the outer grace of the Christian tradition that brings the gospel to our ears. (195; Fs) (notabene). By a brilliant extension he moves on to his distinction between revelation and information. Items of information are all about us: they are the stock in trade of the media. But revelation is not just one more item of information. In its essential moment it is a twofold pull: being drawn by the Father, listening to him, learning from him; and being drawn by the Son, crucified, dead, and risen. Again, it is a twofold grace: an inner operative grace that plucks out hearts of stone and replaces them with hearts of flesh; and the outer grace of the Christian tradition that brings the gospel to our ears. (195; Fs) (notabene)

36/12 Now I think Voegelin's criticism of doctrines and doctrinization to be exaggerated. But everyone will expect this of me, so there is no point in my repeating here what I have already said rather abundantly. What I do believe to be important on the present occasion is to insist how right I consider Voegelin to be in what he does say. For what he does say is foundational. It is the kind of knowledge by which people live their lives. It is the kind of knowledge that scientists and scholars, philosophers and theologians, presuppose when they perform their specialized tasks. It is the knowledge of which Newman wrote in his Grammar of Assent, Polanyi wrote in his Personal Knowledge, Gadamer in his Truth and Method. It is the kind of knowledge thematized by ascetical and mystical writers when they speak of the discernment of spirits and set forth rules for distinguishing between pull and counterpull, between being drawn by the Father to be drawn to the Son and, on the other hand, the myriad other attractions that distract the human spirit. (195; Fs)

37/12 Indeed it is in this long history of spiritual writing that one finds the confirmation of Voegelin's "In-Between" and his "Beyond." For being drawn by the Father is neither merely human nor strictly divine but "In-Between." As movement is from the mover but in what is moved, so the drawing is from the Father but in the suppliant. Again, because the drawing is from the Father, it bears the stamp of unworldliness; it is not just me but from the "Beyond." Finally, because there are not only pulls but also counterpulls, because the first can dignify the second, and the second can distort the first, there is need for discernment and, no less, difficulty in attaining it. (196; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Verallgemeinerte empirische Methode; gemeinsamer Kern aller Wissenschaften: 3-fache Scheme: attentive, intelligent, reasonable, responsible

Kurzinhalt: GENERALIZED EMPIRICAL METHOD; normative pattern of recurrent and related operations that yield ongoing and cumulative results in natural science, in hermeneutics, in history,

Textausschnitt: 43/9 Generalized empirical method envisages all data. The natural sciences confine themselves to the data of sense. Hermeneutic and historical studies turn mainly to data that are expressions of meaning. Clinical psychology finds in meanings the symptoms of conflicts between conscious and preconscious or unconscious activities. Generalized empirical method operates on a combination of both the data of sense and the data of consciousness: it does not treat of objects without taking into account the corresponding operations of the subject; it does not treat of the subject's operations without taking into account the corresponding objects. (140f; Fs)

44/9 As generalized empirical method generalizes the notion of data to include the data of consciousness, so too it generalizes the notion of method. It wants to go behind the diversity that separates the experimental method of the natural sciences and the quite diverse procedures of hermeneutics and of history. It would discover their common core and thereby prepare the way for their harmonious combination in human studies. From various viewpoints man has been named the logical animal, the symbolic animal, the self-completing animal. But in each of these definitions man is regarded as an animal, and so he is an object for the natural sciences. At the same time, he is regarded as logical or symbolic or self-completing; he lives his life in a world mediated by meaning; and so he is a proper object for hermeneutic and historical studies. What then is the common core of related and recurrent operations that may be discerned both in natural science and in human studies? (141; Fs)

45/9 In the natural sciences the key event is discovery. ... Again, in hermeneutics the key event is understanding: ... In history, again, the key operation is understanding, and so it was that Johann Gustav Droysen extended the procedures of hermeneutics to the whole of history by observing that not only individuals but also families, peoples, states, religions express themselves. Nor is understanding alien to common sense.

46/9 However, understanding is only one of the many components that have to be combined to constitute an instance of human knowledge. It presupposes data, whether given to sense or given in consciousness: for our understanding always is an insight, a grasp of intelligible unity or intelligible relationship; and a grasp of unity presupposes the presentation of what needs unification, as a grasp of intelligible relationship presupposes the presentation of what can be related. Again, such insight or grasp presupposes inquiry: that search, hunt, chase for the way to piece together the merely given into an intelligible unity or innerly related whole. Nor is it enough to discover the solution. One also must express it adequately. Otherwise one will have had the mere experience of the occurrence of a bright idea, but one will not have the power to recall it, use it, apply it. There is a further point to such expression whether in word or deed. Insights are a dime a dozen. For the most part they occur, not with respect to data in all their complexity, but with respect to merely schematic images. Dozens of such images are needed to approximate to what actually is given, and so it is that the expression of insight has to be followed by a very cool and detached process of reflection that marshals the relevant evidence and submits it to appropriate tests before laying claim to any discovery or intention. (142; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: authentische Subjektivität -> Objektivität;

Kurzinhalt: that objectivity is the fruit of authentic subjectivity, of being attentive, intelligent, reasonable, responsible; satisfying those norms is the highroad to the objectivity ...

Textausschnitt: 49/9 It is time to conclude. We have been asking whether there is any connection between inner conviction and objective truth. By inner conviction we have meant not passion, not stubbornness, not wilful blindness, but the very opposite; we have meant the fruit of self-transcendence, of being attentive, intelligent, reasonable, responsible; in brief, of being ruled by the inner norms that constitute the exigences for authenticity in the human person. But for objectivity we have distinguished two interpretations. There is the objectivity of the world of immediacy, of the already-out-there-now, of the earth that is firm-set only in the sense that at each moment it has happened to resist my treading feet and bear my weight. But there also is the objectivity of the world mediated by meaning; and that objectivity is the fruit of authentic subjectivity, of being attentive, intelligent, reasonable, responsible. (144; Fs)
50/9 In my opinion, then, inner conviction is the conviction that the norms of attentiveness, intelligence, reasonableness, responsibility have been satisfied. And satisfying those norms is the highroad to the objectivity to be attained in the world mediated by meaning and motivated by values. (144; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Moderne Methode - Aristoteles (Analytica Posteriora)

Kurzinhalt: On all three counts (Praxis, Autonomie, Relation) it ran counter to the ideal set forth in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics; first principles - method

Textausschnitt: 7/10 Now I have already had occasion to point out certain elements in that revolution. It aimed at utility, and so it was concerned with everyday materials, their manipulation, their mastery, through a process of trial and error. It demanded autonomy: its basic terms and relations were to be mathematical in their origins and experimental in their justification. It was concerned not with words but with reality and so it excluded questions that could not be resolved by an appeal to observation or experiment. On all three counts it ran counter to the ideal set forth in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. Despite an initial concern with understanding things, that work devoted its efforts to the construction of a theory of science out of the terms, relations, inferences constitutive of the demonstrative syllogism. Instead of developing science by combining mathematical notions with their experimental verification, the Posterior Analytics conceived philosophy and science as a single, logically interlocking unity, in which philosophy was to provide the sciences with their basic terms and principles. Instead of directing men's minds to practical results, Aristotle held that science was concerned with necessary truth, that what can be changed is not the necessary but the contingent, and so the fruit of science can be no more than the contemplation of the eternal truths it brought to light. (147f; Fs) (notabene)
()
11/10 Aristotle, then, was quite right in holding that a science that consisted in the grasp of necessary truth had to be purely theoretical and could not be practical. But from the start modern science intended to be practical. Today there are many steps along the way from basic research to pure science, from pure science to applied, from applied to technology, from technology to engineering. But the multiplicity does not obscure the underlying unity. For us good theory is practical, and good practise is grounded in sound theory. Where the Aristotelian placed his reliance on first principles he considered necessary, the modern scientist places his reliance ultimately not on his basic laws and principles but on his method. It was the method that brought forth the laws and principles in the first place, and it will be the method that revises them if and when the time for revision comes. (149; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Dilthey, Unterschied zw Geisteswissenschaften und Naturwissenschaften; Boeckh: Philologie

Kurzinhalt: ...it is the human spirit that constructs the meanings and responds to the motivating values. But what man has constructed man can reconstruct

Textausschnitt: 31/10 At once it follows that there is a profound difference between natural science and historical study. Both the scientist and the historian would understand: the scientist would understand nature; the historian would understand man. But when the scientist understands nature, he is not grasping nature's understanding of itself; for though nature is intelligible, it is not intelligent. But when the historian understands man, his understanding is a recapturing of man's understanding of himself. This recapturing is interpretation. It differs from the understanding that it recaptures, for it makes thematic, puts in words, an understanding that was not thematized but lived. Yet in another fashion it corresponds to what it recaptures; for it envisages an earlier situation and recounts how an individual or group understood that situation and revealed themselves by their understanding of it. (154; Fs) (notabene)
32/10 In Dilthey we have an echo of Vico's claim that it is human affairs that men best understand, for human affairs are the product of human understanding. Again, in Dilthey we have an anticipation of R. G. Collingwood's view that historical knowledge is a reenactment of the past. Finally, we have only to shift our gaze from the interpreter to the persons under scrutiny, to arrive at a phenomenological ontology. The endless variety exhibited in human living has its root in the endless variety of the ways in which people understand themselves, their situation, and the human condition. Such understanding commonly is of the type that spontaneously is generated and spontaneously communicated, the type that may be named com-monsense. It is constitutive of the basic department of human knowledge, the department expressed in ordinary language. Like ordinary language it varies from place to place and from time to time. It enters into the intelligible form man communicates to the products of his ingenuity and his skill. It is part and parcel of human conduct. It is constitutive of the cognitional and the moral reality that makes man the 'symbolic animal' of the historians and the 'self-completing animal' of the sociologists. (154; Fs)
()
33/10 Let us now revert to August Boeckh's definition of philology as the interpretative reconstruction of the constructions of the human spirit. The constructions of the human spirit are man and his world: for his world is a world mediated by meaning and motivated by value; and it is the human spirit that constructs the meanings and responds to the motivating values. But what man has constructed man can reconstruct. What man has responded to in thought and word and deed, he can respond to once more if only in thought and word and feeling. Such reconstructing and such responding-to-once-more are the interpretations of the scholar and the narratives of the historian. (154f; Fs)
()
34/10 We may conclude this section by noting that historical studies, so conceived, have all the marks of a distinct specialization. Like natural science history is empirical, but where the sciences seek universal principles, laws, structures, seriations, history would understand particular words, deeds, situations, movements. Where the several sciences each construct their own technical languages, historians as an ongoing group are confronted with the task of deciphering and learning all the languages of mankind whether still living or though long since dead. Where the sciences come to know parts or aspects of the universe that common sense never would discover, historians enlarge their own common sense to the point where it encapsulates something of the common sense of other places and times. Lastly, as other specializations, so the study of history leads to the formation of a professional group that develops its own proper procedures and traditions, enforces an initiation ritual of doctoral studies, meets in its own annual congresses, and stocks special libraries with its reference works, surveys, journals, and monographs. (155; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Dialektik, Ricoeur, Fortschritt, Rückschritt (progess - decline) Rationalisierung; Religion: recover from decline

Kurzinhalt: Ricoeur. a hermeneutic of recovery and suspicion; Rationalizations multiply, accumulate, are linked together ...

Textausschnitt: 40/10 The end of the age of innocence means that authenticity is never to be taken for granted. Mathematicians had to generalize their notion of number to include irrational and imaginary numbers. Physicists had to develop quantum theory because instruments of observation modified the data they were to observe. In similar fashion human studies have to cope with the complexity that recognizes both (1) that the data may be a mixed product of authenticity and of unauthenticity and (2) that the very investigation of the data may be affected by the personal or inherited unauthenticity of the investigators. (157; Fs) (notabene)
41/10 The objective aspect of the problem has come to light in Paul Ricoeur's distinction between a hermeneutic of recovery, that brings to light what is true and good, and a hermeneutic of suspicion, that joins Marx in impugning the rich, or Nietzsche in reviling the humble, or Freud in finding consciousness itself an unreliable witness to our motives. Again, it may be illustrated in my own account of "The Origins of Christian Realism," that distinguished the Christological and Trinitarian doctrines of Tertullian, Origen, and Athanasius on the basis of a philosophic dialectic. Tertullian under Stoic influence was oriented towards a world of immediacy. Origen under Middle Platonist influence was in a world mediated by meaning, where however meaning was the meaning of ideas. Athanasius finally was in the world mediated by meaning, where the meaning was the truth of the Christian kerygma. (157; Fs)
()
44/10 Similarly, decline is cyclic and cumulative, but now unauthenticity distorts what authenticity would have improved. The policies, projects, plans, courses of action that come from creative insight into the existing situation have the misfortune of running counter not merely to vested interests but to any and every form of human unauthenticity. Doubts are raised, objections formulated, suspicions insinuated, compromises imposed. Policies, projects, plans, courses of action are modified to make the new situation not a progressive product of human authenticity but a mixed product partly of human authenticity and partly of human obtuseness, unreasonableness, irresponsibility. As this process continues, the objective situation will become to an ever greater extent an intractable problem. The only way to understand it correctly will be to acknowledge its source in human waywardness. The only way to deal with it will be to admonish the wayward. But such sophistication may be lacking, and then one can expect not repentance but rationalization. So decline continues unabashed. The intractable problem keeps growing. Rationalizations multiply, accumulate, are linked together into a stately system of thought that is praised by all who forget the adage: Whom the gods would destroy, they first make blind. (157f; Fs) (notabene)
45/10 Can a people, a civilization, recover from such decline? To my mind the only solution is religious. What will sweep away the rationalizations?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Praxis (von oben nach unten), spekulative, kontemplative Vernunft: Notwendigkeit: Grund für die Vorherrschaft

Kurzinhalt: praxis (from above downwards); contemplative intellect: the older view grounded its hegemony on necessity; praxis acknowledges the end of the age of innocence

Textausschnitt: 50/10 If I have referred to so many and so different thinkers, it has not been to agree with all of them but rather to discern despite their differences a common concern with what I have named praxis. On an older view contemplative intellect, or speculative reason, or rigorous science was supreme, and practical issues were secondary. But the older view grounded its hegemony on necessity. That claim no longer is made. If we are not simply to flounder, we have to take our stand on authenticity: on the authenticity with which intelligence takes us beyond the experimental infrastructure to enrich it, extend it, organize it, but never to slight it and much less to violate its primordial role; on the authenticity with which rational reflection goes beyond the constructions of intelligence and draws sharply the lines between astrology and astronomy, alchemy and chemistry, legend and history, magic and science, myth and philosophy; on the authenticity with which moral deliberation takes us beyond cognitional process into the realm of freedom and responsibility, evaluation and decision, not in any way to annul or slight experience or understanding or factual judgment, but to add the further and distinct truth of value judgments and the consequent decisions demanded by a situation in which authenticity cannot be taken for granted. (160; Fs) (notabene)
()
51/10 It follows that, while empirical method moves, so to speak, from below upwards, praxis moves from above downwards. Empirical method moves from below upwards, from experience to understanding, and from understanding to factual judgment. It can do so because it can presuppose that the data of experience are intelligible and so are objects that straightforward understanding can master. But praxis acknowledges the end of the age of innocence. It starts from the assumption that authenticity cannot be taken for granted. Its understanding, accordingly, will follow a hermeneutic of suspicion as well as a hermeneutic of recovery. Its judgment will discern between products of human authenticity and products of human unauthenticity. But the basic assumption, the twofold hermeneutic, the discernment between the authentic and the unauthentic set up a distinct method. This method is a compound of theoretical and practical judgments of value. The use of this method follows from a decision, a decision that is comparable to the claim of Blaise Pascal that the heart has reasons which reason does not know. (160; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Verhältnis (Schlussfolgerung): Religionswissenschaft (Religious Studies) und Theologie

Kurzinhalt: the more religious studies and theology put to good use the whole battery of methods, the more they will move asymptotically towards an ideal situation

Textausschnitt: 61/10 I have distinguished different methods: experimental, foundational, historical, dialectical, critically practical. (164; Fs)

My first conclusion is that the more religious studies and theology put to good use the whole battery of methods, the more they will move asymptotically towards an ideal situation in which they overlap and become easily interchangeable. (164; Fs)

62/10 As a second conclusion I would say that such overlapping and interchangeability are ideal in the sense that they are desirable. Theology and religious studies need each other. Without theology religious studies may indeed discern when and where different religious symbols are equivalent; but they are borrowing the techniques of theologians if they attempt to say what the equivalent symbols literally mean and what they literally imply. Conversely, without religious studies theologians are unacquainted with the religions of mankind; they may as theologians have a good grasp of the history of their own religion; but they are borrowing the techniques of the historian of religions, when they attempt to compare and relate other religions with their own. (164; Fs)

63/10 Thirdly, if any agree that such an ultimate overlapping and interchangeability are desirable, their praxis will include a recognition of the obstacles that stand in its way and an effort to remove them. Now a discovery of the obstacles is not difficult. For we concluded to this end from the assumption that both theologians and students of religions would put to good use the whole battery of methods that have been devised. It follows that there are as many possible obstacles as there are plausible grounds for rejecting or hesitating about any of these methods. It follows, finally, if the methods really are sound, that the obstacles may be removed, at least for authentic subjects, by applying both the hermeneutic of suspicion and the hermeneutic of recovery: the hermeneutic of suspicion that pierces through mere plausibility to its real ground; the hermeneutic of recovery that discovers what is intelligent, true, and good in the obstruction and goes on to employ this discovery to qualify, complement, correct earlier formulations of the method. (164; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Naturrecht und Geschichte; Geschichte, Philologie

Kurzinhalt: Nature is given man at birth. Historicity is what man makes of man;

Textausschnitt: 4/11 A contemporary ontology would distinguish two components in concrete human reality: on the one hand, a constant, human nature; on the other hand, a variable, human historicity. Nature is given man at birth. Historicity is what man makes of man. (170; Fs)
5/11 This making of man by man is perhaps most conspicuous in the educational process, in the difference between the child beginning kindergarten and the doctoral candidate writing his dissertation. Still this difference produced by the education of individuals is only a recapitulation of the longer process of the education of mankind,

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Naturrecht in der Geschichte; Einsicht der Griechen (Tier, Mensch); Aristoteles' Definition v. Natur

Kurzinhalt: From that premise there followed a conclusion. What had been made by human convention ...; ...in the notion of natural right was found its rebuttal; Aristotel: nature as an immanent principle of movement and of rest

Textausschnitt: 9/11 It was the sheer multiplicity and diversity of the practises and beliefs of the peoples of the earth that led the ancient Greeks to contrast animals and men. The habits of each species of animal were uniform and so they could be attributed to nature. But the practises and beliefs of men differed from tribe to tribe, from city to city, from region to region: they had to be simply a matter of convention. (171; Fs)
10/11 From that premise there followed a conclusion. What had been made by human convention, could be unmade by further convention. Underpinning human manners and customs there was no permanent and binding force. (171f; Fs)

11/11 The conclusion was scandalous, and in the notion of natural right was found its rebuttal. Underneath the manifold of human lifestyles, there existed a component or factor that possessed the claims to universality and permanence of nature itself. (172; Fs)
()
12/11 However, this component or factor admits two interpretations. It may be placed in universal propositions, self-evident truths, naturally known certitudes. On the other hand, it may be placed in nature itself, in nature not as abstractly conceived, but as concretely operating. It is, I believe, the second alternative that has to be envisaged if we are to determine norms in historicity. (172; Fs) (notabene)
13/11 Now Aristotle defined a nature as an immanent principle of movement and of rest. In man such a principle is the human spirit as raising and answering questions. As raising questions, it is an immanent principle of movement. As answering questions and doing so satisfactorily, it is an immanent principle of rest. (172; Fs) (notabene)
15/11 Still, intellectual satisfaction, however welcome, is not all that the human spirit seeks. Beyond satisfaction it is concerned with content and so the attainment of insight leads to the formulation of its content. We express a surmise, suggest a possibility, propose a project. But our surmise may awaken surprise, our suggested possibility give rise to doubts, our project meet with criticism. In this fashion intelligence gives way to reflection. The second type of question has emerged. As intelligence thrust us beyond the flow of sensitive spontaneity, so now reflection thrusts us beyond the more elementary concerns of both sense and intelligence. The formulated insight is greeted with such further and different questions as, Is that so? Are you sure? There is a demand for sufficient reason or sufficient evidence; and what is sufficient is nothing less than an unconditioned, though a virtually unconditioned (such as a syllogistic conclusion) will do. (172f; Fs) (notabene)
16/11 It remains that the successful negotiation of questions for intelligence and questions for reflection is not enough. They do justice to sensitive presentations and representations. But they are strangely dissociated from the feelings that constitute the mass and momentum of our lives. Knowing a world mediated by meaning is only a prelude to man's dealing with nature, to his interpersonal living and working with others, to his existential becoming what he is to make of himself by his own choices and deeds. So there emerge questions for deliberation. Gradually they reveal their scope in their practical, interpersonal, and existential dimensions. Slowly they mount the ladder of burgeoning morality. Asking what's in it for me gives way to asking what's in it for us. And both of these queries become tempered with the more searching, the wrenching question, Is it really worthwhile? (173; Fs)
17/11 It is a searching question. The mere fact that we ask it points to a distinction between feelings that are self-regarding and feelings that are disinterested. Self-regarding feelings are pleasures and pains, desires and fears. But disinterested feelings recognize excellence: the vital value of health and strength; the communal value of a successfully functioning social order; the cultural value proclaimed as a life to be sustained not by bread alone but also by the word; the personal appropriation of these values by individuals; their historical extension in progress; deviation from them in decline; and their recovery by self-sacrificing love. (173; Fs)


12/11 However, this component or factor admits two interpretations. It may be placed in universal propositions, self-evident truths, naturally known certitudes. On the other hand, it may be placed in nature itself, in nature not as abstractly conceived, but as concretely operating. It is, I believe, the second alternative that has to be envisaged if we are to determine norms in historicity. (172; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Naturrecht; Fragen ( der Intelligenz, Reflexion, Entscheidung) und der Grund des Wissens einer Antwort; Gewissen

Kurzinhalt: The nagging conscience is the recurrence of the original question that has not been met. The good conscience is the peace of mind that confirms the choice of something truly worthwhile

Textausschnitt: 19/11 Yet all questioning heads into the unknown and all answering contributes to what we are to do. When I ask why or how or what for, I intend intelligibility, but the question would be otiose if already I knew what the intelligibility in question was. When I ask whether this or that is really so, I intend the true and the real, but as yet I do not know what is true or what will be truly meant. When I ask whether this or that project or undertaking really is worthwhile, I intend the good, but as yet I do not know what would be good and in that sense worthwhile. (173f; Fs)

20/11 Questioning heads into the unknown, yet answering has to satisfy the criterion set by the question itself. Otherwise the question returns in the same or in another form. Unless insight hits the bull's-eye, the question for intelligence returns. How about this? How does that fit in? A self-correcting process of learning has begun, and it continues until a complementary and qualifying set of insights have stilled the flow of further relevant questions for intelligence. In like manner questions for reflection require not just evidence but sufficient evidence; until it is forthcoming, we remain in doubt; and once it is had, doubting becomes unreasonable. Finally questions for deliberation have their criterion in what we no longer name consciousness but conscience. The nagging conscience is the recurrence of the original question that has not been met. The good conscience is the peace of mind that confirms the choice of something truly worthwhile. (174; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Naturrecht - Prinzip der Bewegung: Liebe - Selbsttranszendenz

Kurzinhalt: principle of movement and of rest: being-in-love - ongoing process of self-transcendence

Textausschnitt: 21/11 I have been speaking of nature as a principle of movement and of rest, but I have come up with many such principles and so, it would seem, with many natures. There are different questions: for intelligence, for reflection, for deliberation. Each is a principle of movement. Each also is an immanent norm, a criterion, and thereby a principle of rest once the movement is complete. (174; Fs) (notabene)
22/11 It remains that the many form a series, each in turn taking over where its predecessor left off. What is complete under the aspect of intelligibility, is not yet complete under the aspect of factual truth; and what is complete under the aspect of factual truth, has not yet broached the question of the good. Further, if what the several principles attain are only aspects of something richer and fuller, must not the several principles themselves be but aspects of a deeper and more comprehensive principle? And is not that deeper and more comprehensive principle itself a nature, at once a principle of movement and of rest, a tidal movement that begins before consciousness, unfolds through sensitivity, intelligence, rational reflection, responsible deliberation, only to find its rest beyond all of these? I think so. (174f; Fs) (notabene)
23/11 The point beyond is being-in-love, a dynamic state that sublates all that goes before, a principle of movement at once purgative and illuminative, and a principle of rest in which union is fulfilled. (175; Fs)
24/11 The whole movement is an ongoing process of self-transcendence. There is the not yet conscious self of deep sleep. There is the fragmentarily conscious self of the dream state. There is the awakened self aware of its environment, exerting its capacities, meeting its needs. There is the intelligent self, serializing and extrapolating and generalizing until by thought it has moved out of the environment of an animal and towards a universe of being. There is the reasonable self, discerning fact from fiction, history from legend, astronomy from astrology, chemistry from alchemy, science from magic, philosophy from myth. There is the moral self, advancing from individual satisfactions to group interests and, beyond these, to the overarching, unrelenting question, What would be really worthwhile? (175; Fs)
25/11 Yet this great question commonly is more promise than fulfillment, more the fertile ground of an uneasy conscience than the vitality and vigor of achievement. For self-transcendence reaches its term not in righteousness but in love and, when we fall in love, then life begins anew. A new principle takes over and, as long as it lasts, we are lifted above ourselves and carried along as parts within an ever more intimate yet ever more liberating dynamic whole. (175; Fs)
26/11 Such is the love of husband and wife, parents and children. Such again, less conspicuously but no less seriously, is the loyalty

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Naturrecht - Dialektik der Geschichte; Quelle und Rechtfertigung des Naturrechts

Kurzinhalt: DIALECTIC OF HISTORY; The source of natural right lies in the norms immanent in human intelligence ... The vindication of natural right lies in the dialectic of history

Textausschnitt: 27/11 I have said that people are responsible individually for the lives they lead and collectively for the world in which they live them. Now the normative source of meaning, of itself, reveals no more than individual responsibility. Only inasmuch as the immanent source becomes revealed in its effects, in the functioning order of society, in cultural vitality and achievement, in the unfolding of human history, does the manifold of isolated responsibilities coalesce into a single object that can gain collective attention. (176; Fs)
28/11 Further, the normative source of meaning is not the only source, for the norms can be violated. Besides intelligence, there is obtuseness; besides truth there is falsity; besides what is worthwhile, there is what is worthless; besides love there is hatred. So from the total source of meaning we may have to anticipate not only social order but also disorder, not only cultural vitality and achievement but also lassitude and deterioration, not an ongoing and uninterrupted sequence of developments but rather a dialectic of radically opposed tendencies. (176; Fs)
29/11 It remains that in such a dialectic one finds 'writ large' the very issues that individuals have to deal with in their own minds and hearts. But what before could be dismissed as, in each case, merely an infinitesimal in the total fabric of social and cultural history, now has taken on the dimensions of collective triumph or disaster. Indeed, in the dialectic there is to be discerned the experimental verification or refutation of the validity of a people's way of life, even though it is an experiment devised and conducted not by human choice but by history itself. (176; Fs)
30/11 Finally, it is in the dialectic of history that one finds the link between natural right and historical mindedness. The source of natural right lies in the norms immanent in human intelligence, human judgment, human evaluation, human affectivity. The vindication of natural right lies in the dialectic of history and awesomely indeed in the experiment of history. Let us set forth briefly its elements under six headings. (176; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Dialektik der Geschichte; Naturrecht; Entwicklung auf verschiedenen Ebenen; Vorherbestimmung

Kurzinhalt: Again, as always, emancipation has its root in self-transcendence. But in the contemporary context it is such self-transcendence as includes an intellectual, a moral, and an affective conversion. As intellectual, this conversion draws a sharp ...

Textausschnitt: 31/11 First, human meaning develops in human collaboration. There is the expansion of technical meanings as human ingenuity advances from the spears of hunters and the nets of fishers to the industrial complexes of the twentieth century. There is the expansion of social meanings in the evolution of domestic, economic, and political arrangements. There is the expansion of cultural meanings as people reflect on their work, their interpersonal relationships, and the meaning of human life. (176f; Fs)

32/11 Secondly, such expansions occur on a succession of plateaus. The basic forward thrust has to do with doing, and it runs from primitive fruit gatherers to the wealth and power of the ancient high civilizations of Egypt, Mesopotamia, and other lands. Development then is mainly of practical intelligence, and its style is the spontaneous accumulation of insights into the ways of nature and the affairs of men. There also is awareness of the cosmos, of reality being more than nature and man, but this awareness has little more than symbolic expression in the compact style of undifferentiated consciousness. (177; Fs)

33/11 An intermediate forward thrust has to do mainly with speech. Poets and orators, prophets and wise men, bring about a development of language and a specialization of attention that prepare the way for sophists and philosophers, mathematicians and scientists. There occurs a differentiation of consciousness, as writing makes language an object for the eye as well as the ear; grammarians organize the inflections of words and analyze the construction of sentences; orators learn and teach the art of persuasion; logicians go behind sentences to propositions and behind persuasion to proofs; and philosophers exploit this second-level use of language to the point where they develop technical terms for speaking compendiously about anything that can be spoken about; while the more modest mathematicians confine their technical utterances to relations of identity or equivalence between individuals and sets; and similarly the scientists have their several specialized languages for each of their various fields. (177; Fs)

34/11 On a third plateau attention shifts beyond developments in doing and in speaking to developments generally. Its central concern is with human understanding where developments originate, with the methods in natural science and in critical history which chart the course of discovery, and more fundamentally with the generalized empirical method that underpins both scientific and historical method to supply philosophy with a basic cognitional theory, an epistemology, and by way of a corollary with a metaphysics of proportionate being. (177; Fs)

35/11 On this plateau logic loses its key position to become but a modest part within method; and logical concern-with truth, with necessity, with demonstration, with universality-enjoys no more than marginal significance. Science and history become ongoing processes, asserting not necessity but verifiable possibility, claiming not certitude but probability. Where science, as conceived on the second plateau, ambitioned permanent validity but remained content with abstract universality, science and history on the third plateau offer no more than the best available opinion of the time, yet by sundry stratagems and devices endeavor to approximate ever more accurately to the manifold details and nuances of the concrete. (178; Fs)

36/11 These differences in plateau are not without significance for the very notion of a dialectic of history. The notion of fate or destiny or again of divine providence pertains to the first plateau. It receives a more detailed formulation on the second plateau when an Augustine contrasts the city of God with the earthly city, or when a Hegel or a Marx set forth their idealistic or materialistic systems on what history has been or is to be. A reversal towards the style of the first plateau may be suspected in Spengler's biological analogy, while a preparation for the style of the third plateau may be discerned in Toynbee's A Study of History. For that study can be viewed, not as an exercise in empirical method, but as the prolegomena to such an exercise, as a formulation of ideal types that would stand to broad historical investigations as mathematics stands to physics.1 (178; Fs)

37/11 In any case the dialectic of history, as we are conceiving it, has its origin in the tensions of adult human consciousness, its unfolding in the actual course of events, its significance in the radical analysis it provides, its practical utility in the invitation it will present to collective consciousness to understand and repudiate the waywardness of its past and to enlighten its future with the intelligence, the reasonableness, the responsibility, the love demanded by natural right. (178; Fs) (notabene)

38/11 Our third topic is the ideal proper to the third plateau. Already in the eighteenth century it was anticipated in terms of enlightenment and emancipation. But then inevitably enough enlightenment was conceived in the well-worn concepts and techniques of the second plateau; and the notion of emancipation was, not a critique of tradition, but rather the project of replacing traditional backwardness by the rule of pure reason. (178; Fs)

38/11 Subsequent centuries have brought forth the antitheses to the eighteenth-century thesis. The unique geometry of Euclid has yielded to the Riemannian manifold. Newtonian science has been pushed around by Maxwell, Einstein, Heisenberg to modify not merely physics but the very notion of modern science. Concomitant with this transformation has been the even more radical transformation in human studies. Man is to be known not only in his nature but also in his historicity, not only philosophically but also historically, not only abstractly but also concretely. (178f; Fs)

39/11 Such is the context within which we have to conceive enlightenment and emancipation, not indeed as if they were novelties for they have been known all along, but in the specific manner appropriate to what I have named the third plateau. As always enlightenment is a matter of the ancient precept, Know thyself. But in the contemporary context it aims to be such self-awareness, such self-understanding, such self-knowledge, as to grasp the similarities and the differences of common sense, science, and history, to grasp the foundations of these three in interiority which also founds natural right and, beyond all knowledge of knowledge, to give also knowledge of affectivity in its threefold manifestation of love in the family, loyalty in the community, and faith in God. (179; Fs)

40/11 Again, as always, emancipation has its root in self-transcendence. But in the contemporary context it is such self-transcendence as includes an intellectual, a moral, and an affective conversion. As intellectual, this conversion draws a sharp distinction between the world of immediacy and the world mediated by meaning, between the criteria appropriate to operations in the former and, on the other hand, the criteria appropriate to operations in the latter.2 Next, as moral, it acknowledges a distinction between satisfactions and values, and it is committed to values even where they conflict with satisfactions. Finally, as affective, it is commitment to love in the home, loyalty in the community, faith in the destiny of man. (179; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: B. Welte: Konzil von Nizäa (Seinsvergessenheit); statisch (als Ideal, Möglichkeit, Tatsächlichkeit), Aristoteles (Analytica Posteriora); homoousios (Athanasius )

Kurzinhalt: ... how static was the approach to reality and the apprehension of it set forth in the Nicene decree; homoousios, the Nicene decree was just as static and just as dynamic as what Athanasius found in the Bible

Textausschnitt: The biblical approach to reality, by and large, is centered on events. Its concern is dynamic. In contrast, at Nicea and in subsequent councils there emerges the static approach of Greek metaphysics, an approach concerned with the present and permanent, and so an approach that Heidegger has criticized as a forgetfulness of being. There arises accordingly the question whether theologians today have on their hands the task of finding a different way of handling the issues that for centuries were thought to have been handled satisfactorily at Nicea. (185f; Fs)
()
11/12 Let us now ask how static was the approach to reality and the apprehension of it set forth in the Nicene decree. It will suffice to take the key term, homoousios. According to Athanasius this key term means that statements true of the Father also are true of the Son except that the Son is not the Father. Now is this meaning static or dynamic? Obviously we have to consider the statements that Athanasius had in mind. Nor is any difficulty involved, for Athanasius proceeds to quote a number of statements true both of the Father and of the Son. He finds them not in some text of Greek metaphysics but in the scriptures. As understood by Athanasius, then, the Nicene decree was just as static and just as dynamic as what Athanasius found in the Bible. (188; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Collingwood über Geschichte

Kurzinhalt: philosophy of history (Philosophiegeschichte): the methodological component present in the consciousness that a scientific historian has of his own performance

Textausschnitt: 5/13 So much for familiarity. Besides that, there is authority, and I quote Collingwood's The Idea of History:
Philosophy cannot interfere with history according to the Hegelian formula of superimposing a philosophical history on the top of ordinary history. [...] Ordinary history is already philosophical history [...] within the concrete whole which is historical knowledge, philosophical knowledge is a component part. [...]
[...] (history is necessary) relatively to philosophy as the concrete thought of which philosophy is only the methodological moment. [...]
[...] (history is) the consciousness of one's own activity as one actually performs it. ... For even when the events which the historian studies are events that happened in the distant past, the condition of their being historically known is that [...] the evidence for them should be here and now before him and intelligible to him. For history [...] lives only, as a present interest and pursuit, in the mind of the historian when he criticizes and interprets [...] documents, and by so doing relives for himself the states of mind into which he inquires.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Methode (allgemein); kein Regelwerk; 3 Grundfragen; Notwendigkeit (14. Jhdt. - Thomas, Aristoteles)

Kurzinhalt: method; question for understanding, reflection, responsibility; From the beginning of the 14 century: that necessary knowledge results from the necessary implication of one concept in another (not Aquinas a. Aristotle)

Textausschnitt: 10/13 Method is not to be confused with anything as pedestrian as a recipe, a prescription, a set of directions. For recipes, and the like, lead only to single results. They may be repeated as often as you please, but the repetition yields no more than another instance of the original product. What may be advertised as the New Method Laundry may clean anyone's clothing, but it will never do anything else. (204; Fs)

11/13 The key instance to method, I feel, lies in the relation between questioning and answering. The questioner, while he does not know the answer, at least intends it. Moreover, the question itself sets a standard that leads to the rejection of insufficient answers; and insufficient answers need not be useless: they may help the questioner to pin down more accurately the precise issue he wished to raise. Further, such clarification may bring to light the existence of intermediate questions that have to be resolved before the initially intended question can be met. There is then an ongoing dynamism in questioning and answering. It heads through insufficient answers to the clarification and, as well, to the distinction of questions; and while this prepares the way to the eventual discovery of relevant answers, those very answers in turn can provide the source and stimulus to a fresh wave of questions. (204f; Fs)

12/13 I have been speaking of this ongoing process as though it occurred between a pair of individuals. But, far more importantly, it can be the common concern of associations of scientists. The members of such associations will have passed successfully through the initiatory ritual of attaining a Ph.D. They will be at home in the technical language which they alone understand and speak. That language will provide the repository of the novel conceptual systems introduced by the pioneers and the renovators in their field. It provides the instrument through which are handed on the ideals that should govern their thinking and the procedures to be followed in their investigations. It is kept alive and up-to-date through congresses, through journals and books, through school libraries, and interdisciplinary undertakings. In this fashion questions raised anywhere can be known elsewhere; they can give rise to an array of insufficient answers that successively beg for a clarification of the issue or issues; and the clarifications will hasten, as far as is possible at the time, the new answers which initial questions may have done more to intimate than to formulate. (205; Fs)

13/13 I have been stressing what I have noted elsewhere, that a method is not a set of rules to be followed meticulously by a dolt but a framework for collaborative creativity.1 But now I have to add that (1) questions are of different kinds, (2) each kind has its own immanent objective and criterion, and (3) the objectives stand in an ascending order with each completing what its predecessor had attained. (205; Fs)

14/13 The first of the kinds is the question for understanding. It arises when one is intelligent enough to experience a lack: one lacks an understanding of some aspect or aspects of the data. As long as that lack continues to be experienced, answers that are proposed and considered will have to be rejected simply because the lack remains. So the objective of the first kind of question is the attainment of an understanding of specified data. The criterion of the attainment of a proper understanding is that answers are proving sufficient, that questions no longer need further clarification, that the initial lack of understanding has been replaced by an insight that grasps why things are so. (205f; Fs)

15/13 The second kind of question is for reflection. Aristotle remarked that we think we understand when we know the cause, know that it is the cause, and know that the effect cannot be other than it is.2 Now the open point in this affirmation is the meaning of "necessity." From the beginning of the fourteenth century, by and large, it seems to have been tacitly assumed that necessary knowledge results from the necessary implication of one concept in another. But such a view cannot, I believe, be foisted on Aristotle or Aquinas. For them the primary object of understanding was the representative image, the example, the instance, in which intelligence grasped the intelligibility of what the image represents. Such a grasp is a conscious intellectual event that, at times, is resoundingly satisfactory. Its formulation in concepts is a further process, equally conscious, and intelligently resting on the content of the insight.3 (206; Fs) (notabene)

16/13 It follows that over and above the abstract necessity that may be elicited from the implication of one abstract concept in another, there is the more concrete necessity that may be intelligently grasped in representative images and, under due provisos, in sensible data. For example, one can ask abstractly what an eclipse is. But one may also refer to a concrete situation in which a man, pointing to the darkening of the moon, asks why the moon is darkened in this manner.4 The abstract question demands an abstract answer, and to proceed from the abstract definition to an actual necessity no number of further abstract necessities are enough. There also is needed an understanding of an existing situation into which the abstractions fit. But if the question is put with regard to a concrete situation in which an eclipse actually is taking place, then an understanding of that situation will grasp not only the cause of the darkening of the moon but also the necessity of that effect. (206; Fs)

17/13 The third type of question regards responsibility. There are responsibilities intrinsic to natural science, others intrinsic to human science, others to religious studies. Our observations, for the moment, must be confined to natural science. In such science there is a responsibility to the data: it is violated when the data are fraudulently produced. There is a responsibility to intelligence or reasonableness, and it is neglected when one overlooks the inadequacy of answers and, no less, when one withholds a qualified assent when further relevant questions are not made available. Finally, there is responsibility regarding the possible products of scientific advance. Because knowing is good, advance in knowing is good. Because the products of science can be turned to evil use by evil will, one's own will becomes evil in approving the evil use. (206f; Fs)

18/13 Such are the three questions, and I have said that their objectives stand in an ascending order. For the second question has its origin in an incompleteness of the first question and answer, and the third question has its origin in an incompleteness of the second question and answer. So our hypotheses and theories remedy our previous lack of understanding; but are they just bright ideas, or do they represent the best available opinion of the day? Still, even a consensus in favor of high probability would not preclude a still further question. New knowledge opens up new possibilities, and possibilities may be put to good or evil use; and so the question of responsibility arises out of the question for reflection and the answer to it. (207; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Methode (allgemein); Fragen (3 Typen) als Ausdruck der Selbsttranszenden (Dynamik); Wurzel: das Unbewusste

Kurzinhalt: method; degrees of self-transcendence (6 Stufen); drifters: have not yet found themselves

Textausschnitt: 20/13 But before closing this first part of my first section, I feel I should indicate roughly, not yet the stages, but perhaps the successive degrees of self-transcendence. The first is the emergence of consciousness in the fragmentary form of the dream, where human substance yields place to the human subject. The second is waking when our senses and feelings come to life, where our memories recall pleasures and our imaginations anticipate fears, but our vitality envisages courses of action. The third is inquiry which enables us to move out of the mere habitat of an animal and into our human world of relatives, friends, acquaintances, associates, projects, accomplishments, ambitions, fears. The fourth is the discovery of a truth, which is not the idle repetition of a "good look" but the grasp in a manifold of data of the sufficiency of the evidence for our affirmation or negation. The fifth is the successive negotiation of the stages of morality and/or identity till we reach the point where we discover that it is up to ourselves to decide for ourselves what we are to make of ourselves, where we decisively meet the challenge of that discovery, where we set ourselves apart from the drifters. For drifters have not yet found themselves. They have not yet found their own deed and so are content to do what everyone else is doing. They have not yet found a will of their own, and so they are content to choose what everyone else is choosing. They have not yet developed minds of their own, and so they are content to think and say what everyone else is thinking and saying. And everyone else, it happens, can be doing and choosing and thinking and saying what others are doing and choosing and thinking and saying. (208; Fs) (notabene)
21/13 But this fifth stage in self-transcendence becomes a successful way of life only when we really are pulled out of ourselves as, for example, when we fall in love, whether our love be the domestic love that unites husband and wife and children, or the love of our fellows whose well-being we promote and defend, or the love of God above all in whom we love our neighbor as ourselves. (208; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Elemente des menschlichen Wissens; parallel: Sinnesdaten und Bewusstsein

Kurzinhalt: George Santayana (Skepticism and Animal Faith); that the data of sense and the data of consciousness are parallel; Similarly the data of consciousness are not an instance of self-knowledge but ...

Textausschnitt: 25/13 But a parallel liberation can be bestowed on human studies. One way to this goal is the quantification of statements about human beings. An alternative way is to have philosophy do for human studies what mathematics does for natural science. I may presume that you are familiar with the former procedure, and so I may be content to indicate what the latter entails. In 1923 George Santayana published a book entitled Skepticism and Animal Faith. The pair were considered opposites with skepticism the lot of an elite and animal faith the lot of the masses. But neither animal faith nor skepticism is compatible with the general dynamics of method: animal faith asks no questions, and skepticism answers none. For me the real alternatives are animal faith and critical philosophy. On the one hand, animal faith is the fate of everyone who learns in childhood to speak his mother tongue, may entertain no doubt about all he believes he knows, but never has found out for himself and in himself just what are the events that come together to constitute human knowledge. On the other hand, in the measure that one finds out for oneself and in oneself just what these events are, one not merely is a critical philosopher but also one successful enough to be liberated, especially from animal faith in some unknowable thing-in-itself. (209f; Fs)
26/13 I may be asked just what events do come together to constitute human knowing. Very schematically, there are three: first, the givenness of the data, which is the objective of research; secondly, a cumulative series of insights into the data, which respond to the question for intelligence and yield a hypothesis; thirdly, a probable judgment on the adequacy of the insights. (210; Fs) (notabene)
27/13 At this point there may return the notion that human knowing is not a threefold compound but a single simple act at least in the field of our own consciousness. Certainly many have thought of consciousness as an inward look, an instance of what they may name introspection, and it is by such a look (they might claim) that we are aware of the givenness of the data, the occurrence of insights, the sufficiency of the evidence. But to my mind this is just a fresh avatar of the intuitions attributed to animal faith. For I believe that the data of sense and the data of consciousness are parallel. The data of sense do not constitute human knowledge but only a first step to such knowledge. Similarly the data of consciousness are not an instance of self-knowledge but only a first step towards attaining such knowledge. All our intentional acts also are conscious acts. But to advert to them as conscious, we have to deemphasize the intentional and heighten the conscious side of the act. Only when that is achieved can we proceed to gain insight into the relations that unify our conscious acts and then to pass judgment on the validity of the relations. (210f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Vier Bedeutungen von Sinn (meaning): kognitiv, effektiv, konstitutiv, kommunikativ

Kurzinhalt: Besides being cognitive, meaning is efficient.

Textausschnitt: 29/13 To this end we propose to speak of the four basic functions of meaning: it is cognitive, efficient, constitutive, communicative. It is cognitive. Human knowledge is discursive, a matter of questions and answers, and so one's knowledge is no better (and no worse) than the questions one can raise and the answers one can give. The world of the infant is no bigger than the nursery, but the world of the adult extends from the present back to its past and forward to its future. It includes not only the factual but also the possible, the ideal, the normative. It expresses not only what one has found out for oneself but also what we have managed to learn from the memories of other men, from the common sense of the community, from the pages of literature, from the labors of scholars, from the investigations of scientists, from the experience of saints, from the meditations of philosophers and theologians. It is within this larger world that we live out our lives. To it we refer when we speak of the real world. But because it is mediated by meaning and motivated by value, because meaning can go astray and evaluation become corrupt, because there is myth as well as science, fiction as well as fact, deceit as well as honesty, error as well as truth, that larger world is insecure. (211; Fs)

30/13 Besides being cognitive, meaning is efficient.
()
31/13 A third function of meaning is constitutive.
()
32/13 A fourth function of meaning is communicative.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: 4 Grade d gemeinsamen Bedeutung (common meaning); Sinn; Natur - Geschichte, Tradition (kleine, große Authentizität)

Kurzinhalt: Such common meaning has four degrees: existential, authentic or unauthentic; major, minor authenticity or unauthenticity; for a subject to take the tradition uncritically is for him to realize what: progress - decline

Textausschnitt: 34/13 Community is not just a by-product of a geographical frontier but the achievement of common meaning. Such common meaning has four degrees. It is potential when there is a common field of experience, and to withdraw from that common field is to get out of touch. Common meaning is formal when there is common understanding, and one withdraws from that common understanding as misunderstanding and incomprehension supervene. Common meaning is actual inasmuch as there are common judgments, areas in which all affirm and deny in the same manner; but common meaning is diluted as consensus fails. Common meaning is realized by decisions and especially by permanent dedication, in the love that makes families, in the loyalty that makes states, in the faith that makes religions. (212f; Fs)

36/13 It is momentous, for it can be authentic or unauthentic, and this can happen in two distinct ways. There is the minor authenticity or unauthenticity of the subject with respect to the tradition in which he was raised. There is the major authenticity or unauthenticity that justifies or condemns the tradition itself. As Kierkegaard asked whether he was a Christian, so divers men can ask themselves whether they are authentically religious, authentically philosophers, authentically scientists. They may answer that they are, and they may be right. But they may answer affirmatively and still be mistaken. On a series of points they will realize what the ideals of the tradition demand; but on another series their lives diverge from those ideals. Such divergence may be overlooked from a selective inattention, a failure to understand, an undetected rationalization. What I am is one thing; what an authentic Christian or Buddhist is, is another, and I am unaware of the difference. My unawareness is unexpressed. I have no language to express what I am, so I use the language of the tradition that I unauthentically appropriate, and thereby I devaluate, distort, water down, corrupt that language. (213; Fs)
37/13 Such devaluation, distortion, dilution, corruption may occur only in scattered individuals. But it may occur on a more massive scale, and then the words are repeated but the meaning is gone. The chair remains the chair of Moses, but occupied by scribes and Pharisees. The theology is still Scholastic, but the Scholasticism is decadent. The name of science may be invoked but, as Edmund Husserl has argued, all significant scientific ideals can vanish to be replaced by the conventions of a clique. So the unauthenticity of individuals becomes the unauthenticity infecting a tradition. For a subject to take the tradition uncritically is for him to realize what objectively is unauthentic but for him subjectively is thought authentic. (213; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Bedeutung: Streben nach Selbsttranszendenz; Friedrich Heiler -> Lonergan: Zusammenfassung des Gemeinsame in d. Religionen in 7 Punkten

Kurzinhalt: What is that meaningfulness?, the meaningfulness of striving to become self-transcendent and of making progress on the way -> into intelligent, reasonable consciousness; this reality, transcendent and immanent

Textausschnitt: 48/13 In brief, the methods of natural science have contributed much to religious studies, but their contribution is incomplete. What is wanting is an account of the meaningfulness of religious tradition, belief, imperatives, rituals: not indeed of the meaningfulness that would meet the requirements of a logical positivist or linguistic analyst, but of the meaningfulness that can demand the totality of a person's response. Again, it is the meaningfulness that is expressed by a historian of religion, read by those for whom the religion has come to life, and by them recognized as an account of their own commitment. (216; Fs)

49/13 But what is that meaningfulness? How is it reached? How is it
investigated? (217; Fs)
It is, I should say, the meaningfulness of striving to become self-transcendent and of making progress on the way. It is the emergence of the self not only from the consciousness of the dream into waking consciousness but into intelligent consciousness that gradually promotes us from being animals in a habitat to becoming human beings in a universe, into the reasonable consciousness that judges in accord with the evidence, into the responsible consciousness that makes its way from individual and group egoism beyond the bias of omnicompetent common sense to the consciousness of one in love-in love with the family, in love with fellow citizens in this world, in love with God above all. (217; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Gottesfrage: Feuerbach, Projektion; 2 Gegenargumente

Kurzinhalt: materialism, immanentism, critical realism; seeking: not mere quality but potentiality and finality; a projection does not differ from G. Santayana's animal faith

Textausschnitt: 59/13 In other words, there is an inner light that runs before the formulation of doctrines and that survives even despite opposing doctrines. To follow that inner light is life, even though to worldly eyes it is to die. To reject that inner light is to die, even though the world envies one's attainments and achievements. (219; Fs)


55/13 My starting point was our questions and answers, and it probably has not escaped you that such a basis fits in very neatly with Feuerbach's contention that man's notion of God is a projection on the sky of idealized human qualities. We seek understanding, and God is all-intelligent; we seek sufficient evidence for our judgments and God is all-knowing; we seek moral excellence and God is goodness and love. (218; Fs) (notabene)

56/13 I must be content with two observations. First, such seeking is not mere quality but potentiality and finality; and it is potentiality and finality not confined to some category but, on the contrary, scorning any arbitrary burking of questions. (218; Fs)

56/13 I must be content with two observations. First, such seeking is not mere quality but potentiality and finality; and it is potentiality and finality not confined to some category but, on the contrary, scorning any arbitrary burking of questions. (218; Fs)
57/13 Secondly, I note that the word, projection, recalls the cinematic projector and before it the magic lantern. But the slide or film does not experience, does not inquire intelligently, does not judge on the basis of sufficient reason, does not decide freely and responsibly. In brief, a projection does not differ from George Santayana's animal faith. (218; Fs)
58/13 So much for a materialist option. Next, I propose to consider both the immanentist and the critical realist options simultaneously, not because the two do not differ, but because one can say much about religious experience without opting for either side of a philosophic difference. (218; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan über Voegelin (Vernunft; inneres Licht, metaxy, In-Between); Newman (notional assent)

Kurzinhalt: here is an inner light that runs before the formulation of doctrines and that survives even despite opposing doctrines. To follow ...;

Textausschnitt: 59/13 Dr. Eric Voegelin has explained that he got into problems of religious understanding one winter when, at an adult education institute in Vienna where he grew up, he followed weekly lectures by Deussen, the philosopher who translated the Upanishads. Dr. Voegelin is author of a work in many volumes on Order and History; but his parerga include incisive essays on Greek philosophy and the New Testament. He has set aside the common but strange assumption that reason, for Plato and Aristotle, was much the same as the deductivism of late medieval Scholasticism, seventeenth-century rationalism, nineteenth-century idealism. His contention has been that reason in the Greek classic experience was moral and religious; in Athens the appeal to reason was the appeal of men in an age of social and cultural decay seeking a way to recall their fellows from darkness and lead them towards the light. His account of religious experience centers on the struggle in the soul and it draws freely on both Plato and the New Testament. He acknowledges pulls and counterpulls. To follow the former puts an end to questioning. To opt for the latter leaves questions unanswered and conscience ill at ease. The former alternative is what Voegelin means by a movement luminous with truth, or again by existing in the truth, or again by the truth of existence. The latter alternative is existence in untruth. As he contends, this luminosity of existence with the truth of reason precedes all opinions and decisions about the pull to be followed. Moreover, it remains alive as the judgment of truth in existence whatever opinions about it we may actually form. In other words, there is an inner light that runs before the formulation of doctrines and that survives even despite opposing doctrines. To follow that inner light is life, even though to worldly eyes it is to die. To reject that inner light is to die, even though the world envies one's attainments and achievements. (219; Fs) (notabene)

60/13 Voegelin holds that such experiences, while valid symbols and legitimately made the basis of a "Saving Tale" to guide our lives, are not to be handed over to hypostatizing and dogmatizing. (219; Fs)
There is no In-Between other than the metaxy experienced in a man's existential tension toward the divine ground of being; there is no question of life and death other than the question aroused by pull and counter-pull; there is no Saving Tale other than the tale of the divine pull to be followed by man; and there is no cognitive articulation of existence other than the noetic consciousness in which the movement becomes luminous to itself.
A little later we read: (220; Fs)
Kommentar eg (3/10/2004): cf. Voegelin, Evangelium
Myth is not a primitive symbolic form, peculiar to early societies and progressively to be overcome by positive science, but the language in which the experiences of divine-human participation in the In-Between become articulate. The symbolization of participating existence, it is true, evolves historically from the more compact form of the cosmological myth to the more differentiated forms of Philosophy, Prophecy, and the Gospel, but the differentiating insight, far from abolishing the metaxy of existence, brings it to fully articulate knowledge. When existence becomes noetically luminous as the field of pull and counter-pull, of the question of life and death, and of the tension between human and divine reality, it also becomes luminous for divine reality as the Beyond of the metaxy which reaches into the metaxy in the participatory event of the movement. There is no In-Between of existence as a self-contained object but only existence experienced as part of a reality which extends beyond the In-Between.
61/13 Let me now attempt to say what I make of this. First, I shall quote and comment. I quote: "[...] there is no Saving Tale other than the tale of the divine pull to be followed by man." What is this divine pull? We have explicit references to John 6:44: "No man can come to me unless he is drawn by the Father who sent me," and to John 12:32: "And I shall draw all men to myself, when I am lifted up from the earth." The context then is not only biblical but Joanine. (220; Fs)
62/13 Next, I quote: "[...] there is no cognitive articulation of existence other than the noetic consciousness in which the movement becomes luminous to itself." I ask: What is the movement of noetic consciousness and when does it become luminous to itself? For Voegelin "nous," whence the adjective, noetic, is in the classic experience moral and religious. But in the present context the religious component becomes far more emphatic. For in this movement of consciousness there is "[...] a mutual participation (methexis, metalepsis) of human and divine; and the language symbols expressing the movement are not invented by an observer who does not participate in the movement but are engendered in the event of participation itself. The ontological status of the symbols is both human and divine." So Voegelin appeals both to Plato who claimed that his myth of the puppet player was "an alethes logos, a true story," whether "received from a God, or from a man who knows" (Laws 645B) and, as well, to the prophets promulgating their sayings as the "word" of Yahweh. In brief, we are offered an account of revelation or, perhaps, inspiration. (220f; Fs) (notabene)
63/13 It is, however, an account of revelation or inspiration that can meet the needs of a philosophy of religion. For as Voegelin further remarked, "The symbolization of participating existence [...] evolves historically from the more compact form of the cosmological myth (the reference is to ancient Egypt and Mesopotamia) to the more differentiated forms of Philosophy, Prophecy, and the Gospel, but the differentiating insight, far from abolishing the metaxy of existence, brings it to fully articulate knowledge." (221; Fs)
64/13 One may ask whether one is not to confuse this differentiating insight with its fully articulate knowledge and, on the other hand, the repudiated dogmatizing and doctrinization. There are grounds for such an interpretation for later Voegelin speaks of "[...] the loss of experimental reality through doctrinization." Now the luminous experience of existing in the truth is indeed an instance of experimental reality, and a doctrinization that abolishes the one also is the loss of the other. In that case doctrinization seems associated with what Newman would have named merely notional apprehension and merely notional assent, which do imply an exclusion of real apprehension and assent. (221; Fs)
There remains the repudiation of "hypostatization." It seems to me fully justified if applied to Gnostic constitutions of the ple-roma through the designation of abstract names, or even, if anyone wishes, applied to the Hegelian dialectical deduction of the universe through an interplay of opposed Begriffe. But behind such applications there is a far deeper issue, and on it I can now do no more than invite you to an examination of Giovanni Sala's comparison of my cognitional theory with Kant's, and of William Ryan's comparison of my intentionality analysis with that of Edmund Husserl. The seminal work seems to me to be Le Blond's Logique et methode chez Aristote. (221f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Bedeutung: pastoral? Augustinus: (innerer u. äußerer Lehrer); Paulus; drifter

Kurzinhalt: Augustine : the teacher outside us whose words we hear; and the teacher within us: God the Father, his Son, and their Spirit: Paul; drifter - commitment (incarnation of a meaning)

Textausschnitt: 12/14 What then does "pastoral" mean? For Fr. Chenu one gets into difficulty when one puts the cart before the horse. The words of the Good Shepherd preceded conciliar decrees. But if first one clarifies the meaning of "doctrine" and then sets about explaining the meaning of "pastoral," one tends to reduce "pastoral" to the application of "doctrine" and to reduce the application of "doctrine" to the devices and dodges, the simplifications and elaborations of classical oratory. But what comes first is the word of God. The task of the church is the kerygma, announcing the good news, preaching the gospel. That preaching is pastoral. It is the concrete reality. From it one may abstract doctrines, and theologians may work the doctrines into conceptual systems. But the doctrines and systems, however valuable and true, are but the skeleton of the original message. A word is the word of a person, but doctrine objectifies and depersonalizes. The word of God comes to us through the God-man. The church has to mediate to the world not just a doctrine but the living Christ. (227f; Fs) (notabene)
()
17/14 On this point St. Augustine composed a dialogue with the title, The Teacher, in which his main point was the existence of two teachers: the teacher outside us whose words we hear; and the teacher within us: God the Father, his Son, and their Spirit. The teacher outside utters sounds. If we are familiar with the language, the sounds will be recognized as words; memory will recall their meanings; intelligence combines them into sentences; and sentences coalesce into discourse which we can understand. But if we go further and ask whether the discourse is true or false, wise or foolish, we may have recourse to the common sense or the wisdom we have acquired over the years. Still we must bear in mind that, while common sense and human wisdom may suffice in human affairs, they are unequal to the affairs of God. As St. Paul wrote to the Corinthians, "'Things beyond our seeing, things beyond our hearing, things beyond our imagining, all prepared by God for those who love him,' these it is that God has revealed to us through the Spirit" (1 Cor. 2:9-10). And in contrast with that revelation he shortly added, "A man who is unspiritual refuses what belongs to the Spirit of God; it is folly to him; he cannot grasp it, because it needs to be judged in the light of the Spirit" (! Cor. 2:14). (229; Fs)

19/14 Still their condition is not hopeless. To each may come the existential moment when they discover in themselves and for themselves that it is up to themselves to settle what they are to be. Whether their tradition be Jewish or Christian, Muslim or Hindu, Buddhist or Taoist, there are things to be done and things to be left undone, things to be said and things to be passed over, thoughts to be entertained and thoughts to be dismissed. As a life spent in mere drifting lacks meaning, so a lifetime of commitment to a selected style or pattern of thinking, saying, doing is an incarnation of a meaning and makes one's living meaningful. Again, the greater the commitment, the more meaningful the life; and the less the commitment, the obscurer and the more dubious is the meaning. (230; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Wieder: 2-fache Bedeutung von Leben und Tod: Euripides, Sokrates, Johannes, Paulus

Kurzinhalt: the twofold meaning of death: in the Greek + in a far sharper form in the words of our Lord;

Textausschnitt: 20/14 There is a further aspect to the matter. For attention to the meaning of one's life leads to the further question of the meaning of death. Is death the end of living or is it the entry into another world? The question comes easily to man. The Greek tragedian, Euripides, could exclaim, "Who knows if to live is to be dead, and to be dead to live?" Plato at the end of the Apology has Socrates say to his judges, "But now the time has come to go. I go to die, and you to live. But who goes to the better lot is unknown to anyone but the God." Four centuries later in the fourth gospel, in the chapter that precedes the Last Supper, Jesus says to the apostles, Philip and Andrew,
In truth, in very truth I tell you, a grain of wheat remains a solitary grain unless it falls into the ground and dies; but if it dies, it bears a rich harvest. The man who loves himself is lost, but he who hates himself in this world will be kept safe for eternal life. If anyone serves me, he must follow me; where I am, my servant will be. Whoever serves me will be honoured by my Father (John 12: 24-26).
21/14 For Christians, then, the meaning of life is momentous. The twofold meaning of life and the twofold meaning of death that occurs in the Greek classics also occurs in a far sharper form in the words of our Lord. He who loves himself is lost. He who hates himself in this world will be kept safe for life eternal. (230f; Fs)
22/14 This is strong doctrine and it is put into practise only through the grace of God. It is the grace of being drawn by the Father. In the sixth chapter (vv. 41-45) of St. John's Gospel we read: (231; Fs)
At this the Jews began to murmur disapprovingly because he said, 'I am the bread which came down from heaven.' They said, 'Surely this is Jesus son of Joseph; we know his father and mother. How can he now say, "I have come down from heaven"?' Jesus answered, 'Stop murmuring among yourselves. No man can come to me unless he is drawn by the Father who sent me [...] Everyone who has listened to the Father and learned from him comes to me.'
23/14 Not only does the Father draw us to Christ, but Christ himself also draws us by his passion and death. For he himself said, "And I shall draw all men to myself, when I am lifted up from the earth." And the evangelist comments immediately, "This he said to indicate the kind of death he was to die" (John 12:32-33). Drawn by the Father and drawn by the Son, the Holy Spirit brings God's own love to us. So St. Paul could write, "[...] God's love has flooded our inmost heart through the Holy Spirit he has given us" (Rom. 5:5). (231; Fs)
24/14 St. Paul's estimate of the magnitude of this gift of the Holy Spirit is known to all with his chapter on love. (231; Fs)
I may speak in tongues of men or of angels, but if I am without love, I am a sounding gong or a clanging cymbal. I may have the gift of prophecy, and know every hidden truth; I may have faith strong enough to move mountains; but if I have no love, I am nothing. I may dole out all I possess, or even give my body to be burnt, but if I have no love, I am none the better.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Authentizität (kleine u. große); sekulare Welt; Sünde (Todsünde, lässliche Sünde, habituelle Sünde); operative Gnade

Kurzinhalt: authenticity is twofold; this-worldly secularists - other-worldly believers; barriers to enlightenment, barriers to loving God above all; sin: mortal, occasional; grace: operative (Aquinas), sanctifying, actual

Textausschnitt: 4. AUTHENTICITY

27/14 The question of authenticity is twofold: there is the minor authenticity of the subject with respect to the tradition that has nourished him; there is the major authenticity that justifies or condemns the tradition itself. The first passes a human judgment on persons; the second is the judgment of history and ultimately the judgment of divine providence upon traditions. (233; Fs)

28/14 As Kierkegaard asked himself whether he was a Christian, so divers men can ask themselves whether or not they are genuine Catholics or Protestants, Muslims or Buddhists, Platonists or Aristotelians, and so on. They may answer that they are, and be correct in their answers. But they also may answer affirmatively and still be mistaken. In this case there will exist a series of points in which what they are coincides with what the ideals of the tradition demand, but there will be another series in which there is a greater or less divergence. These points of difference are overlooked, whether from a selective inattention, or a failure to understand, or an undetected rationalization. What I am is one thing, what a genuine Christian or Buddhist is, is another, and I am unaware of the difference. My unawareness is unexpressed; I have no language to express what I really am, so I use the language of the tradition I unauthentically appropriate, and thereby I devaluate, distort, water down, corrupt that language. (233; Fs)

29/14 Such devaluation, distortion, corruption may occur only in scattered individuals. But it may occur on a more massive scale, and then the words are repeated but the meaning is gone. The chair is still the chair of Moses, but it is occupied by scribes and Pharisees. Traditional doctrine is still taught, but it is no longer convincing. The religious order still reads out the rules, but one may doubt that the home fires are still burning. The sacred name of science is still invoked, but when each field is divided into more and more specialties and these specialties cultivated by ever smaller groups, one may be led to ask with Edmund Husserl to what extent any significant ideal of science actually functions, indeed to what extent the ideals of science are being replaced by the conventions of a clique. If, in such eventualities, anyone were to accept a tradition as it stands, he could hardly do more than authentically realize unauthenticity. (233; Fs)

30/14 Truly enough, the modern world is in advance of its predecessors in its mathematics, its natural science, its human science, and the wealth and variety of its literary potentialities. But it was on the basis of his trust in God that modern man had erected his states and cultures, yet more and more he has opted to sustain them by an appeal to man's complete autonomy. He would acknowledge man's intelligence, his rationality, his responsibility, but he would not acknowledge more. For the consistent secularist to speak of God is, at best, irrelevant; to turn to God-except by way of a political gesture or an emotional outlet-is to sacrifice the good that man both knows and, by his own resources, can attain. (234; Fs) (notabene)

31/14 Such has been the mounting challenge to religion and, since it provides a paradigm for its many parallels, it seems worthwhile to analyze its elements. I shall first indicate ambiguities that arise when a people, sharing a common language, divides into this-worldly secularists and other-worldly believers. For the two groups will differ both in the realities and in the values they acknowledge. The otherworldly believers hold that God exists and is operative in religious living; the this-worldly secularists do not. Again, the other-worldly believers acknowledge other-worldly values, and this acknowledgment influences in varying degrees their this-worldly valuations; but the this-worldly secularists avoid such a complication for they acknowledge no other-worldly values and so are free to concentrate on the values of this world. (234; Fs) (notabene)

32/14 Next, a person's horizon is the boundary of what he knows and values. There follows a notable difference in the horizons of this-worldly secularists and other-worldly believers. For what we know and how we arrange our scale of values determines our horizons, and our horizons determine the range of our attention, our consideration, our valuations, our conduct. (234; Fs)

33/14 Further, there are two main components in a person's horizon. There is the main stem: what we know and what we value. There are extensions through the persons we know and care for, since knowing them and caring for them involve us in what they know and care for. (234; Fs)

34/14 Moreover, such extensions may be mutual, and then the horizon of each is an extension of the horizon of the other. They may interrelate all the members of a group, and as such a cohesive group increases in size, there is a need for organizing-for distinguishing, within the whole, smaller groups comparable to the organs of a living body. (234f; Fs)

35/14 Horizons develop both in their main stem of knowing and caring and in their extensions through involvement in the knowing and caring of others. Development in the main stem increases the depth and range of the consequent horizon; and this increase leads to a development in the extensions, since our knowing others and our concern for them involve some sharing in the objects they know and care for. Moreover, inasmuch as among such objects there will be persons that know and care for their own circle, there will result a mediation of involvement at a second remove. Finally, developing horizons open the way to reciprocity on the part of those with whom one has become involved. (235; Fs)

36/14 There are many ways, familiar and perhaps unfamiliar, in which people come to know and care for others. But I think it best to omit the familiar and to avoid the obscurity of the unfamiliar. What seems more pressing is to turn to three things: barriers, breakthroughs, and breakdowns. Barriers block development. Breakthroughs overcome barriers. Breakdowns undo past achievement.1

37/14 We have already illustrated the notion of a barrier in contrasting this-worldly secularists and other-worldly believers. The realities they acknowledge and the values they esteem diverge, and for St. Paul that divergence is extremely grave: (235; Fs)
[...] only the Spirit of God knows what God is. This is the Spirit that we have received from God, and not the spirit of the world, so that we may know all that God of his own grace gives us. [...] A man who is unspiritual refuses what belongs to the Spirit of God; it is folly to him; he cannot grasp it, because it needs to be judged in the light of the Spirit (1 Cor. 2:11-14).

38/14 Such was the message of St. Paul to the Corinthians almost two millennia ago. While I think it relevant to an account of the barrier between secularists and believers, I must recall what I have already said tonight, that people may accept in good faith mistaken views that have become traditional, and that even the original mistake would hardly have occurred without the scandal given by otherworldly believers. (235; Fs)

39/14 In this campaign one does well to turn to John Henry Cardinal Newman's Grammar of Assent and, specifically, to the passages in which he distinguishes notional apprehension from real apprehension, and notional assent from real assent. For the barriers to enlightenment are merely notional apprehension and merely notional assent, when we are content with understanding the general idea and give no more than an esthetic response that it is indeed a fine idea. On the other hand, the attainment of enlightenment is the attainment of real apprehension, real assent, and the motivation to live out what we have learnt. It is brought about through regular and sustained meditation on what it really means to be a Christian, a real meaning to be grasped not through definitions and systems but through the living words and deeds of our Lord, our Lady, and the saints, a meaning to be brought home to me in the measure that I come to realize how much of such meaning I have overlooked, how much I have greeted with selective inattention, how much I have been unwilling to recognize as a genuine element in Christian living. So gradually we replace shallowness and superficiality, weakness and self-indulgence, with the imagination and the feelings, with the solid knowledge and heartfelt willingness of a true follower of Christ. (236; Fs)

40/14 Both in the process of purification and in the process of enlightenment there are times when we resemble the two disciples on the Pope John's road to Emmaus before the stranger joined them on their journey, when they recalled with dismay how high had been their hopes before Jesus was scourged, condemned, and crucified; and there are other times when we resemble the disciples as they listened to the stranger's account of all that the scriptures had foretold and, as they later remarked, "Did we not feel our hearts on fire as he talked with us on the road [...]?" (Luke 24:32). Such times of spiritual dismay and spiritual elation have been interpreted as the language used by the inner teacher in his converse with our hearts. And if the elation is accompanied by a willingness to do good that hitherto we were unwilling to do, then it is the sign of a grace that Aquinas named operative, a grace foretold by Ezekiel with the words: "I will.[...] put a new spirit into them; I will take the heart of stone out of their bodies and give them a heart of flesh. Then they will conform to my statutes and keep my laws. They will become my people, and I will become their God" (Ezek. 11:19-20). (236f; Fs)

41/14 Both in the Old Testament and in the New there are given the two commandments. (237; Fs)

Then one of the lawyers [...] asked him, 'Which commandment is first of all?' Jesus answered, 'The first is, "Hear, O Israel: The Lord your God is the only Lord; love the Lord your God with all your heart, with all your soul, with all your mind, and with all your strength." The second is this: "Love your neighbour as yourself.'' There is no other commandment greater than these' (Mark 12:28-31; cf. Deut.6:4-5, Lev. 19:18).

42/14 A real apprehension of these commandments and a real assent to their binding force for each of us are given us by sanctifying grace, for then "God's love has flooded our inmost heart through the Holy Spirit he has given us" (Rom.5:5). But even then we must watch and pray that we enter not into temptation, for beyond sanctifying grace we also need actual graces, even operative actual graces, that take us through the processes of purification and enlightenment towards the state of union with God. (237; Fs)

43/14 I began by recalling how Pope John XXIII desired the church to leap forward in its apostolic mission by preaching to mankind the living Christ. I spoke in turn of the meaning, the function, and the relevance of a pastoral council. I ended by speaking of authenticity, of the genuine fruit of religious education and of pastoral ministry. Since that fruit fundamentally comes through God's grace, since that grace is given in answer to prayer, I would conclude by begging you one and all to pray that this Institute of Religious Education and Pastoral Ministry, and all similar undertakings, prove to be instruments that bountifully promote the realization of Pope John's intentions. It is a prayer that the members of Christ's body on earth bring forth fruit thirtyfold, sixtyfold, a hundredfold. (237f; Fs)

A lecture given twice at Boston College, 1981, first in June, during the eighth annual Lonergan Workshop, then in July, during the tenth-anniversary celebration of The Institute of Religious Education and Pastoral Ministry. To be published in the proceedings of that celebration and in a future volume of Lonergan Workshop.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Bewusstsein: Differentierung: Unmittelbarkeit (naiver Realismus, Empirismus), Commonsense, religiöse

Kurzinhalt: scientific, religious, scholarly, modern philosophic differentiation of consciousness; not from objects mediated by 'ordinary' meaning, but from the immediate data of consciousness

Textausschnitt: I. DIFFERENTIATIONS OF CONSCIOUSNESS

2/15 For centuries theologians were divided into diverse schools. The schools differed from one another on most points in systematic theology. But all shared a common origin in medieval Scholasticism and so they were able to understand one another and could attempt, if not dialogue, at least refutation. But with the breakdown of Scholasticism, that common ancestry is no longer a bond. Wide divergences in doctrine are being expressed by Catholic theologians. If each abounds in his wisdom, he also tends to be mystified by the existence of views other than his own. (239; Fs)

3/15 If one is to understand such diversity, one must, I believe, advert to the sundry differentiations of human consciousness. A first differentiation arises in the process of growing up. The infant lives in a world of immediacy. The child moves towards a world mediated by meaning. For the adult the real world is the world mediated by meaning, and his philosophic doubts about the reality of that world arise from the fact that he has failed to advert to the difference between the criteria for a world of immediacy and, on the other hand, the criteria for a world mediated by meaning. (239; Fs)

4/15 Such inadvertence seems to be the root of the confusion concerning objects and objectivity that has obtained in Western thought since Kant published his Critique of Pure Reason.1 In the world of immediacy the only objects are objects of immediate experience, where "experience" is understood in the narrow sense and denotes either the outer experience of our senses or the inner experience of our consciousness. But in the world mediated by meaning - i.e., mediated by experiencing, understanding, and judging - objects are what are intended by questions and known by intelligent, correct, conscientious answers. It is by his questions for intelligence (quid sit, cur ita sit), for reflection (an sit), for moral deliberation (an honestum sit), that man intends without yet knowing the intelligible, the true, the real, and the good. By that intending man is immediately related to the objects that he will come to know when he elicits correct acts of meaning. Accordingly, naive realism arises from the assumption that the world mediated by meaning is known by taking a look. Empiricism arises when the world mediated by meaning is emptied of everything except what can be sensed. Idealism retains the empiricist notion of reality, insists that human knowledge is constituted by raising and answering questions, and concludes that human knowledge is not of the real but of the ideal. A critical realism finally claims that human knowledge consists not in experiencing alone but in the threefold compound that embraces experiencing and understanding and judging. (240; Fs)

5/15 Besides the differentiation of consciousness involved in growing up, further differentiations occur with respect to the world mediated by meaning. Here the best known is the eventual separation of scientific from commonsense meaning. (240; Fs)

6/15 Its origins are celebrated in Plato's early dialogues in which Socrates explains what he means by a definition that applies omni et soli, seeks such definitions of courage, sobriety, justice, and the like, shows the inadequacy of every proposed solution, and admits that he himself is unable to answer his own questions. But a generation or so later in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics we find not only general definitions of virtue and vice but also definitions of an array of specific virtues each one flanked by a pair of vices that sin by excess or by defect. But Aristotle was not content merely to answer Socrates' question. By his example he showed how it can be done; he scrutinized linguistic usage; selected the precise meanings that suited his purpose; constructed sets of interrelated terms; and employed such sets to systematize whole regions of inquiry. (240f; Fs)

7/15 In this fashion was effected the differentiation of commonsense meaning and scientific meaning. Socrates and his friends knew perfectly well what they meant by courage, sobriety, justice. But such knowledge does not consist in universal definitions. It consists simply in understanding when a term may be used appropriately; and such understanding is developed by adverting to the response others give to our statements. As common sense does not define, so it does not enounce universal principles; it offers proverbs, i.e., bits of advice it may be well to bear in mind when the occasion arises; hence "Strike the iron while it is hot" and "He who hesitates is lost" are not so much contradicted as complemented by "Look before you leap." Finally, common sense does not syllogize; it argues from analogy; but its analogies resemble, not those constructed by logicians in which the analogue is partly similar and partly dissimilar, but rather Piaget's adaptations which consist of two parts: an assimilation that calls on the insights relevant to somewhat similar situations; and an adjustment that adds insights relevant to the peculiarities of the present situation. (241; Fs)

8/15 But besides the world mediated by commonsense meanings, there is another world mediated by scientific meanings, where terms are defined, systematic relationships are sought, and procedures are governed by logic and methods. This second world was approximated by Plato's distinction between the flux of phenomena and the immutable forms. It was affirmed more soberly in Aristotle's distinction between what is first for us and what is first in itself. It has reappeared in Eddington's two tables: one brown, solid, heavy; the other colorless, mostly empty space, with here and there an unimaginable wavicle. So it is that scientists live in two worlds: at one moment they are with the rest of us in the world of common sense; at another they are apart from us and by themselves with a technical and controlled language of their own with reflectively constructed and controlled procedures. (241; Fs)

9/15 Besides the scientific there is a religious differentiation of consciousness. It begins with asceticism and culminates in mysticism. Both asceticism and mysticism, when genuine, have a common ground that was described by St. Paul when he exclaimed: "[...] God's love has flooded our inmost heart through the Holy Spirit he has given us" (Rom. 5:5). That ground can bear fruit in a consciousness that lives in a world mediated by meaning. But it can also set up a different type of consciousness by withdrawing one from the world mediated by meaning into a cloud of unknowing.2 Then one is for God, belongs to him, gives oneself to him, not by using words, images, concepts, but in a silent, joyous, peaceful surrender to his initiative. (241f; Fs)

10/15 Ordinarily the scientific and the religious differentiations of consciousness occur in different individuals. But they can be found in the same individual as was the case with Thomas of Aquin. At the end of his life his prayer became so intense that it interfered with his theological activity. But earlier there could have been an alternation between religious and theological differentiation, while later still further differentiation might have enabled him to combine prayer and theology as Teresa of Avila combined prayer and business. (242; Fs)

11/15 Besides the scientific and the religious there is the scholarly differentiation of consciousness. It combines the common sense of one's own place and time with a detailed understanding of the common sense of another place and time. It is a specifically modern achievement and it results from nothing less than a lifetime of study. (242; Fs)

12/15 Besides the scientific, the religious, and the scholarly, there is the modern philosophic differentiation. Ancient and medieval philosophers were concerned principally with objects. What differentiation they attained, did not differ from the scientific. But in modern philosophy there has been a sustained tendency to begin, not from objects mediated by 'ordinary' meaning, but from the immediate data of consciousness. In a first phase from Descartes to Kant, the primary focus of attention was cognitional activity. But after the transition, operated by absolute idealism, there was a notable shift in emphasis. Schopenhauer wrote on Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung; Kierkegaard took his stand on faith; Newman took his on conscience; Nietzsche extolled the will to power; Dilthey aimed at a Lebensphilosophie; Blondel at a philosophy of action; Scheler was abundant on feeling; and similar tendencies, reminiscent of Kant's emphasis on practical reason, have been maintained by pragmatists, existentialists, personalists. (242; Fs) (notabene)

13/15 We have distinguished four differentiations of consciousness: the scientific, the religious, the scholarly, and the modern philosophic. We have noted the possibility of one compound differentiation in which the scientific and the religious were combined in a single individual. But there are five other possibilities of a twofold differentiation,3 and there are four possibilities of a threefold differentiation.4 In addition there is one case in which a fourfold differentiation may occur by combining scientific, religious, scholarly, and the modern philosophic differentiation. Similarly, there is a single case of simply undifferentiated consciousness which is at home only in the realm of common sense. (242f; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Scholastik: Versäumnis (Geschichtlichkeit); 1. Prinzipien: Invarianten der menschl. Intentionalität

Kurzinhalt: Scholastic aim > one grave defect: it was content with a logically and metaphysically satisfying reconciliation (Posterior Analytics); de facto invariants of human conscious intentionality

Textausschnitt: 21/15 As already indicated, there was a slight tincture of theoretically differentiated consciousness in the Greek councils. But principally it was in the medieval period that there was undertaken the systematic and collaborative task of reconciling all that had been handed down by the church from the past. A first step was Abelard's Sic et Non, in which one hundred and fifty-eight propositions were both proved and disproved by arguments drawn from scripture, the fathers, the councils, and reason. In a second step Gilbert of Porreta used Abelard to define the existence of a question; in this fashion Abelard's Non became Videtur quod non and his Sic became Sed contra est. To these were added a general response, in which principles of solution were set forth, and then particular responses to the arguments advanced on either side. A third step was the composition of books of sentences that collected and classified relevant passages from scripture and tradition. A fourth step was the commentaries on books of sentences, in which the technique of the question was employed to reconcile or eliminate contrary views. A fifth step was to obtain a conceptual system that would enable theologians to give coherent solutions to all the questions they raised; and this coherence was sought partly by adopting and partly by adapting the Aristotelian corpus. (245; Fs)
22/15 Scholastic theology was a monumental achievement. Its influence on the church has been profound and enduring. Up to Vatican II, which preferred a more biblical turn of speech, it has provided much of the background whence proceeded pontifical documents and conciliar decrees. Yet today by and large it is abandoned, and that abandonment leaves the documents and decrees that relied on it almost mute and ineffectual. Such is the contemporary crisis in Catholicism. It is important to indicate why it exists and how it can be overcome. (245; Fs)

23/15 The Scholastic aim of reconciling differences in statements of Catholic tradition had one grave defect: it was content with a logically and metaphysically satisfying reconciliation; it did not realize how much of the multiplicity in its inheritance constituted not a logical or a metaphysical but basically a historical problem. (245f; Fs)

25/15 In contrast, modern mathematics is fully aware that its axioms are not necessary truths but freely chosen and no more than probably consistent postulates. The modern sciences ascertain, not what must be so, but only what is in itself hypothetical and so in need of verification. First principles in philosophy are not just verbal propositions but the de facto invariants of human conscious intentionality. What was named speculative intellect now turns out to be merely the operations of experiencing, understanding, and judging, performed under the guidance of the moral deliberation, evaluation, decision, that selects an appropriate method and sees to it that the method is observed. The primacy now belongs to praxis and the task of philosophy is to foster the emergence of authentic human beings. Finally, it is only on the basis of intentionality analysis that it is possible to understand human historicity or to set forth the foundations and criticize the practise of contemporary hermeneutics and critical history. (246; Fs)
26/15 The defects of Scholasticism, then, were the defects of its time. It could not inspect the methods of modern history and thereby learn the importance of history in theology. It could not inspect modern science and thereby correct the mistakes in Aristotle's conceptual system. But if we cannot blame the Scholastics for their shortcomings, we must undertake the task of remedying them. A theology is the product not only of faith but also of a culture. It is cultural change that has made Scholasticism no longer relevant and demands the development of a new theological method and style, continuous indeed with the old, yet meeting all the genuine exigences both of Christian religion and of up-to-date philosophy, science, and scholarship. (246f; Fs)


24/15 Secondly, the Aristotelian corpus, on which Scholasticism drew for the framework of its solutions, suffers from a number of defects. The Posterior Analytics set forth an ideal of science in which the key element is the notion of necessity. On this basis science is said to be of the necessary, while opinion regards the contingent; similarly, wisdom is said to be of the necessary, while prudence regards contingent human affairs. There follows the supremacy of speculative intellect, and this can be buttressed with a verbalism that attributes to common terms the properties of scientific terms. Finally, while man is acknowledged to be a political animal, the historicity of the meanings that inform human living is not grasped, and much less is there understood the possibility of history being scientific. (246; Fs)

27/15 Until that need is met, pluralism will not be exorcized. Undifferentiated consciousness will always want a commonsense theology. Scientifically differentiated consciousness will drift towards secularism. Religiously differentiated consciousness will continue to wobble between empiricism and idealism. But the worthy successor to thirteenth-century achievement will be the fruit of a fivefold differentiated consciousness, in which the workings of common sense, science, scholarship, intentionality analysis, and the life of prayer have been integrated. (247; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Konversion - Pluralismus; der authentische Christ -> 3-fache Konversion

Kurzinhalt: The authentic Christian strives for the fulness of intellectual, moral, and religious conversion

Textausschnitt: 28/15 Conversion involves a new understanding of oneself because, more fundamentally, it brings about a new self to be understood. It is putting off the old man and putting on the new. It is not just a development but the beginning of a new mode of developing. Hence besides the beginning there is to be considered the consequent development. This may be great or average or small. It may be marred by few or by many relapses. The relapses may have been fully corrected, or they may still leave their traces in a bias that may be venial or grave. (247; Fs) (notabene)

29/15 Conversion is three-dimensional. It is intellectual inasmuch as it regards our orientation to the intelligible and the true. It is moral inasmuch as it regards our orientation to the good. It is religious inasmuch as it regards our orientation to God. The three dimensions are distinct, so that conversion can occur in one dimension without occurring in the other two, or in two dimensions without occurring in the other one. At the same time the three dimensions are solidary. Conversion in one leads to conversion in the others, and relapse from one prepares for relapse in the others. (247; Fs)
30/15 By intellectual conversion a person frees himself from confusing the criteria for knowledge of the world of immediacy with the criteria for knowledge of the world mediated by meaning. By moral conversion he becomes motivated primarily not by satisfactions but by values. By religious conversion he comes to love God with his whole heart and his whole soul and all his mind and all his strength; and in consequence he will love his neighbor as himself. (247f; Fs)
31/15 The authentic Christian strives for the fulness of intellectual, moral, and religious conversion. Without intellectual conversion he tends to misapprehend not only the world mediated by meaning but also the word God has spoken within that world. Without moral conversion he tends to pursue not what truly is good but what only apparently is good. Without religious conversion he is radically desolate: in the world without hope and without God (Eph. 2:12). (248; Fs)
32/15 While the importance of moral and religious conversion may readily be granted, hesitation will be felt by many when it comes to intellectual conversion. They will feel it is a philosophic issue and that it is not up to theologians to solve it. But while these contentions are true, they are not decisive. The issue is also existential and methodical. Theologians have minds. They have always used them. They may use them properly and they may use them improperly. Unless they find out the difference for themselves or learn about it from someone else, they will be countenancing a greater pluralism than can be tolerated. (248; Fs)
33/15 Indeed in my opinion intellectual conversion is essentially simple. It occurs spontaneously when one reaches the age of reason, implicitly drops earlier criteria of reality (Are you awake? Do you see it? Is it heavy? etc.), and proceeds to operate on the criteria of sufficient evidence or sufficient reason. But this spontaneous conversion is insecure. The use of the earlier criteria can recur. It is particularly likely to recur when one gets involved in philosophic issues. For then the objectification of what is meant by sufficient evidence or sufficient reason may become exceedingly complex, while the objectification of taking a good look is simplicity itself. So one becomes a naive realist; if one takes that seriously, one becomes an empiricist; if that proves uncomfortable, one can move on to idealism; then to pragmatism; then to phenomenology. But far less laborious than traveling round that circuit is the task of finding out just what sufficient evidence is. I grant that facing that issue calls for some concentration. But enormously more concentration is needed to explore the philosophies that either neglect sufficient evidence or, on the other hand, propose excessive criteria. (248; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Sprache, Schlussfolgerung; wenn A, dann B als Grundfrom des Schließens; Kausalsatz, Konzessivsatz, Bedingungssatz

Kurzinhalt: Thus a study of language has given us a working hypothesis: the form of inference is the simple hypothetical argument.

Textausschnitt: 4a Any language has a number of syntactical forms that are peculiarly inferential. Most obvious is the causal sentence, because A, therefore B, where A and B each stand for one or more propositions. Next comes the concessive sentence, although A, still not B, which is the natural instrument of anyone ready to admit the propositions, A, but wishing to deny that A implies B. To meet such denial, to give separate expression to the implication of B in A, there is the host of conditional sentences, if A, then B, which may be past or present, proximate or remote future, particular or general, actually verified or the pure interconnection grammarians call contrary-to-fact. It is not hard to see that these three syntactical forms are peculiarly inferential. Just as 'so that' and 'in order that' express the relations of efficient and final causality, so also 'because,' 'although,' and 'if are the special tools of reasoning man. (Fs) (notabene)

4b Closely related to these linguistic tools is the transition from informal to formal inference. It appears a fact that spontaneous thinking sees at once the conclusion, B, in apprehending the antecedents, A. Most frequently the expression of this inference will be simply the assertion of B. Only when questioned do men add that the 'reason for B' is A; and only when a debate ensues does there emerge a distinction between the two elements in the 'reason for B,' namely, the antecedent fact or facts, A, and the implication of B in A (if A, then B). Thus the transition from informal to formal inference is a process of analysis: it makes explicit, at once in consciousness and in language, the different elements of thought that were present from the first moment. For when B simply is asserted, it is asserted not as an experience but as a conclusion; else a question would not elicit the answer, B because of A. Again, when this answer is given, there would be no meaning to the 'because' if all that was meant was a further assertion, A. On the contrary, the causal sentence (because A, therefore B) compresses into one the three sentences of the formal analysis (if A, then B; A; ? B). (Fs) (notabene)

5a No doubt these considerations throw some light both on the prevalence of enthymeme and on the awkwardness of a logical theory that overlooks the normal syntax of inference to design a Procrustean bed with predication. But at any rate it is from the syntactical forms that the logician derives his simple hypothetical argument. This is of the type (Fs)
If A, then B
But A
() B. (Fs)

5b Its indefinite flexibility is apparent: A and B each stand for one or two or any number of propositions; the propositions may be categorical, disjunctive, or hypothetical; and there is no reason why any of them should be forced into the mold of subject, copula, and predicate. No less apparent is the radical simplicity of this type. Every inference is the implication of a conclusion in a premise or in premises: the conclusion is B; the premise or premises are A; the implication is, if A, then B. Thus a study of language has given us a working hypothesis: the form of inference is the simple hypothetical argument. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Wirkursache als "Influx"; Durandus, Molina, and Banez (3 verschiedene Interpretationen von Wirkursache als "Influx"

Kurzinhalt: First, one may say that in such a causal series there are two and only two instances of influx and so two and only two real instances of efficient causality: from A to B, and from B to C; but there is no third influx from A to C; accordingly ...

Textausschnitt: 1 Efficient Causality and the Causal Series

52b To grasp the author's position, it is necessary, even at the cost of considerable space, to find a more general viewpoint than he presents. The fundamental issue is the nature of the reality of efficient causality; that is, What is the reality which, if existent, makes the proposition, A is the efficient cause of B, true, but which, if nonexistent, makes it false? There are two answers. One may affirm that the desired necessary and sufficient condition is a causally efficient influence proceeding from A to subject of) B. On the other hand, one may consider the foregoing either a mere modus significandi or else sheer imagination, to affirm that the required necessary and sufficient condition is a real relation of dependence in B with respect to its ground and source, its id a quo, A. In this view, the reality of efficient causality is the relativity of the effect qua effect; one also may say that it is the relative element in the Aristotelian actio, actus huius ut ab hoc; that is, B is an act pertaining to A inasmuch as it is from A. (Fs) (notabene)


1.1 Efficient Causality as Influx

54a When one thinks of efficient causality as influx and attempts to analyse the causal series (A is efficient cause of B, and B is efficient cause of C), one may arrive at any of three opinions. First, one may say that in such a causal series there are two and only two instances of influx and so two and only two real instances of efficient causality: from A to B, and from B to C; but there is no third influx from A to C; accordingly, mediate causality is not a true species of causality but merely a name for the combination of two other instances. However, one may dislike this conclusion and desire to make the mediate causec really and truly a cause. Hence, secondly, one may say that in the causal series there are, at least at times, three instances of influx and so three instances of efficient causality: not only from A to B, and from B to C, but also a third from A to C; simultaneously both A and B exert an influx to produce C. Now while this makes A the efficient cause of C not only in name but also in reality, it does so by making A the immediate cause of C; mediate causality is not saved. Hence, thirdly, one may say that there is a real difference between B as effect of A and B as cause of C, and this real difference is what explains the reality of mediate efficient causality; first, an influx from A gives B'; secondly, an influx from A gives B"; thirdly, an influx from B" gives C. Thus efficient causality thought of as influx yields three views of the causal series, and one may note that there is some resemblance between these three views and the views respectively of Durandus, Molina, and Banez. I shall not say that Durandus, Molina, Banez, or any of their followers arrived at their positions in the foregoing manner' I am not engaged in history but in listing theoretical possibilities, and merely draw attention to a resemblance among three possibilities ano three historical opinions. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Wirkursache: Influx - Bedingung (göttlicher Plan); Begriff der Unmittelbarkeit

Kurzinhalt: Efficient Causality; the created cause, not as cause, but as conditioned; the only solution is to postulate a master plan that ...;

Textausschnitt: 1.2 Efficient Causality and Relation of Dependence

55a As there is an alternative view of efficient causality, so also there is an alternative analysis of the causal series. Distinguish between the series properly so called and the merely accidental series: the latter is illustrated by Abraham begetting Isaac, and Isaac, Jacob, where evidently Abraham does not beget Jacob; the former is illustrated by my moving the keys of my typewriter, and my typewriter typing out these paragraphs, where evidently I am more a cause of the typed paragraphs than the typewriter is. Now in the accidental series there are only two real relations of dependence on an id a quo: B depends on A, C depends on B; but the relation of C to A is not of causal dependence but of conditioned to condition. On the other hand, in the proper causal series, there are three real relations of dependence with respect to an id a quo: B depends on A, C depends on B, and C depends on A even more than on B. Since there are three real relations of dependence, there are three real instances of efficient causality, and, as it appears, the instance of merely mediate causality (which causes such trouble when thinking is in terms of influx) turns out to involve more dependence, and so more causality, than the apparently immediate instance. This leads to an examination of the notion of immediacy. What is it? A first answer is in terms of space and time; but this necessarily is irrelevant, for there are causes and effects outside space and time. A second answer is in terms of proximity in the enumeration of terms in the causal series; but terms have their place in the series inasmuch as they are causes of what follows and instruments or means with respect to what precedes; and so we are brought to the etymology; the 'immediate' involves a negation of a medium, a middle, a means; and such a negation may be either 'not being a means' or 'not using a means'; what is not a means may be termed immediate immediatione virtutis; what does not use a means may be termed immediate immediatione suppositi; the former is what has first place in the proper causal senes; the latter pertains in turn to each preceding term in the proper causal series. (Fs) (notabene)

55b Now with this analysis of the causal series, different views may arise when one asks the grounds of affirming that God, any created cause, and the created cause's effect form a proper causal series. Three sets of grounds have been offered; the first regards only immanent acts and so from its lack of universality has fallen into desuetude; the second regards all created causes and, indeed, as causes; the third is equally universal, for it regards all created causes, but it regards them, not as causes, but as conditioned. An argument for the first view may be put as follows: When I see, I act and so am an efficient cause; but when I see, I add to my own ontological perfection; to enable me to make such an addition I must receive a physical premotion; and only God can be the cause of such premotions in the general case. The second view proceeds more generally: Only absolute being is the sufficient ground for the production of being; hence, insofar as it produces being, every created cause must be an instrument; further, this instrumentality affects the created cause as cause, for there is a real difference between potentia agendi and ipsum agere, and that real difference is in the created cause as such; but it cannot be produced by the created cause, for nothing can add to its own perfection; and it must be attributed to God, for it involves the production of being, and only God is proportionate to that. (Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (10/02/2005): potentia agendi -> gemäß der Natur der kontingenten Ursache; ipsum agere -> mit dem "göttlichen" Zusatz als Vermögen, etwas ins Sein zu setzen.

56a The third view regards the created cause, not as cause, but as conditioned.e As in the second view, only infinite being is the proportionate cause of being, of the event as event, of the actual emergence of the effect, of the exercise of efficiency; hence, all finite causes are instruments, naturally proportionate to producing effects as of a given kind, but not naturally proportionate to producing effects as actual occurrences. However, this limitation is operative, not through some entitative and remediable defect in the created cause (for the only remedy would be to make it infinite), but through the manifest fact that finite causes are all conditioned. Since no finite cause can create, it must presuppose the patient on which it acts, suitable relations between itself and its patient, and the noninterference of other causes. Over these conditions the finite cause has no control, for the conditions must be fulfilled before the finite cause can do anything. Next, though the conditions are finite entities and negations of interference, though the conditions of the efficiency of one finite cause may be fulfilled by suitable operations and abstentions on the part of other finite causes, still it remains that all the other finite causes equally are conditioned. Hence, appeal to other finite causes can do no more than move the problem one stage further back; it can do that as often as one pleases; but never can it solve the problem. The only solution is to postulate a master plan that envisages all finite causes at all instants throughout all time, that so orders all that each in due course has the conditions of its operation fulfilled and so fulfils conditions of the operation of others. But since the only subject of such a master plan is the divine mind, the principal agent of its execution has to be God. Demonstrably, then, God not only gives being to, and conserves in being, every created cause, but also he uses the universe of causes as his instruments in applying each cause to its operation, and so is the principal cause of each and every event as event. Man proposes, but God disposes. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Wirkursache: Widerlegung -> Frage nach der Realität des Influx; potentia agendi and ipsum agere; motus est in mobili, actio est in passo

Kurzinhalt: Either the influx is or it is not really distinct from what it produces. If it is, there is an infinite series. If it is not, ...

Textausschnitt: 1.3 Critique of Views on Efficient Causality

57a Such are six views on the issue. I believe that the first three are easily refuted, that the fourth and fifth involve fallacies, that the sixth is demonstrated validly. The troublesome question for anyone who would defend any of the first three views is whether the influx is a reality. If it is not a reality, then efficient causality is not a reality but only a thought or, perhaps more accurately, a bit of imagination. But if the influx is a reality, it would seem that there must be an infinity of influences for each case of efficient causality. For if the influx is a reality, it must be produced itself; that production would involve a further influx, and that influx a further production. One might wish to say, Sistitur in primo.f But why? Either the influx is or it is not really distinct from what it produces. If it is, there is an infinite series. If it is not, then influx is just another name for the effect. At this point, the defender will urge that the influx is indeed a reality, that there are not an infinity of influences for each effect, and the reason is that the influx is a different type of reality from the effect - the type that eliminates the infinite series. But what type is that? I know only one, the real relation. There is no real efficient causality of efficient causality, and so on to infinity, because the reality of efficient causality is the reality of a real relation, and 'relatio relationis est ens rationis.'g It should seem that the first three views, while they differ profoundly on the reality of mediate efficient causality, have in common the source of their differences, namely, a failure to think out what is the reality of efficient causality as such. (Fs) (notabene)

57b The fourth view (the first on the second concept of efficient causality) involves a fallacy. When I see, it is true that I act in the sense that grammatically 'I' is subject of a verb in the active voice. But that does not prove that ontologically I am the efficient cause of my own seeing. Nor is it likely that anyone will find a proof that I am. For both Aristotle and Aquinas, external sensation has its efficient cause in the sensible object. Again, for both, 'intelligere est pati.' Again, for both, 'appetibile apprehensum movet appetitum,' and in later Thomist doctrine of the will, the act of willing an end is effected quoad exercitium actus by God. (Fs)

58a The fallacy of the fifth position lies in affirming that the real difference between potentia agendi and ipsum agere is a reality added to the agent as agent; in fact, that reality is the effect, added to the patient as patient (motus est in mobili, actio est in passo), and predicated of the agent as agent only by extrinsic denomination; it has to be so, for otherwise either metaphysical laws have exceptions or else a motor immobilis would be a contradiction in terms; nor is it possible to demonstrate that, while action as action is predicated of the agent by extrinsic denomination, still created action as created is predicated of the agent by intrinsic denomination; what alone is demonstrable about created action as such is that it is conditioned, and that happens to be the premise of the sixth view. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Finalität (qui, quo), cuius gratia; vertikale, horizontale Finalität: instrumental, dispositive, material, obödiential

Kurzinhalt: the ... distinction between finis qui and finis quo has given two distinct types of finality: the absolute finality of all things to God in his intrinsic goodness; the horizontal finality: instrumental, dispositive, material, obediential

Textausschnitt: 1 Vertical Finality

19a The common instances of finality fall into two classes: the response of appetites to motives, and the orientation of processes to terms. But if we are to formulate the notion of vertical finality, b it is extremely important to break away from instances and to conceive things generally. First, then, the mere fact of response or of orientation does not constitute finality. Any positivist will admit that appetites do respond to motives, that processes are orientated to terms. Quite coherently, any positivist will deny final causality since, beyond such concomitance and correlation, causality requires that appetite respond because of motive, that process be orientated because of term. Moreover, causality is not yet final causality. If appetite responds because motive moves, if process is orientated because an intelligent agent envisages and intends a term, there is causality indeed; but it is efficient and not final. No doubt, in the concrete, such efficiency is connected intimately with finality. But rigorously one must maintain that there is final causality if, and only if, appetite responds because the motive is good; if, and only if, process is orientated because the term is good. (Fs) (notabene)

19b For the final cause is the cuius gratia, and its specific or formal constituent is the good as cause. Under this formal constituent may be had either of two material differences: the good may be cause as motive for the response of appetite or as term for the orientation of process. But with regard to the formal constituent itself, it is necessary to distinguish between qui and quo, between the good thing which is motive or term and the mode of motivation or termination. Now in our hierarchic universe God is at once absolute motive and absolute term: 'omnia appetunt Deum'; 'omnia intendunt assimilari Deo.' On the other hand, the mode in which the different grades of being respond to God as motive or attain him as term is always limited; this remains true even in the beatific vision, in which the infinite as motive is apprehended finitely and as term is attained finitely. Further, the ground of such limitation is essence: remotely it is substantial essence; proximately it is the essence of an ontological accident, the essence, say, of sensitive appetite, of rational appetite, of infused charity; for it is essence that limits, that ties things down to a given grade of being, that makes them respond to motives of a given type, that assigns them their proper and proportionate ends. Finally, there are many grades of being, each with its defining essence and its consequent and commensurate mode of appetition and process; accordingly, one has to think of the universe as a series of horizontal strata; on each level reality responds to God as absolute motive and tends to him as absolute term; but on each level it does so differently, for the limitation of essence reappears in the limitation of the mode of appetition and response, of process and orientation. (Fs) (notabene)

20a Thus the application to the hierarchic universe of the notional distinction between finis qui and finis quo d has given two distinct types of finality: the absolute finality of all things to God in his intrinsic goodness; the horizontal finality of limiting essence to limited mode of appetition and of process. But now attention must be drawn to a third type of finality, that of any lower level of appetition and process to any higher level. This we term vertical finality. It has four manifestations: instrumental, dispositive, material, obediential. First, a concrete plurality of lower activities may be instrumental to a higher end in another subject: the many movements of the chisel give the beauty of the statue. Second, a concrete plurality of lower activities may be dispositive to a higher end in the same subject: the many sensitive experiences of research lead to the act of understanding that is scientific discovery. Third, a concrete plurality of lower entities may be the material cause from which a higher form is educed or into which a subsistent form is infused: examples are familiar. Fourth, a concrete plurality of rational beings have the obediential potency to receive the communication of God himself: such is the mystical body of Christ with its head in the hypostatic union, its principal unfolding in the inhabitation of the Holy Spirit by sanctifying grace, and its ultimate consummation in the beatific vision which Aquinas explained on the analogy of the union of soul and body. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Vertikale Finalität; Unterschied zw. den Finalitäten; Definition - finis operis: hoc ad quod opus ordinatum est ab agente

Kurzinhalt: The difference of vertical from absolute and from horizontal finality is quite clear

Textausschnitt: 21a If the existence of such vertical finality has always been recognized its ground and nature have hardly been studied. Partly this neglect may be explained by an unduly apologetic conception of finis operis; for if one defines finis operis as resulting from the abstract nature of the thing, then necessarily one restricts finality to horizontal finality, absolute finality becomes a difficulty, and vertical finality subjectively inconceivable. But not only is such a restriction arbitrary; it cannot claim even the sanction of tradition, which defines finis operis not in terms of abstract nature but as hoc ad quod opus ordinatum est ab agente. However, a perhaps stronger reason for the neglect of vertical finality lies in the fact that modern science throws a great deal of light on its nature. Straightforward metaphysics suffices for a knowledge of absolute and of horizontal finality: the former results from the idea of an absolute good; the latter results from the theorem of essence as principle of limitation. But vertical finality seems to operate through the fertility of concrete plurality. Just as the real object tends to God as real motive and real term, just as the essence of the real object limits the mode of appetition and of process, so a concrete plurality of essences has an upthrust from lower to higher levels. But just as this fact is shrouded in the mists of Aristotelian science
- and here we generalize Dr Doms' complaint against Aristotelian biology
- so it is most conspicuous to one who looks at the universe with the eyes of modern science, who sees subatoms uniting into atoms, atoms into compounds, compounds into organisms, who finds the pattern of genes in reproductive cells shifting, ut in minori parte to give organic evolution within limited ranges f who attributes the rise of cultures and civilizations to the interplay of human plurality, who observes that only when and where the higher rational culture emerged did God acknowledge the fulness of time permitting the Word to become flesh and the mystical body to begin its intussusception of human personalities and its leavening of human history. (Fs)

22a The difference of vertical from absolute and from horizontal finality is quite clear. Absolute finality is to God in his intrinsic goodness: it is universal; it is unique; it is hypothetically necessary, for if there is anything to respond to motive or to proceed to term, then its response or tendency can be accounted for ultimately only by the one self-sufficient good. Horizontal finality results from abstract essence; it holds even when the object is in isolation; it is to a motive or term that is proportionate to essence. But vertical finality is in the concrete; in point of fact it is not from the isolated instance but from the conjoined plurality; and it is in the field not of natural but of statistical law, not of the abstract per se but of the concrete per accidens. Still, though accidental to the isolated object or the abstract essence, vertical finality is of the very idea of our hierarchic universe, of the ordination of things devised and exploited by the divine Artisan. For the cosmos is not an aggregate of isolated objects hierarchically arranged on isolated levels, but a dynamic whole in which instrumentally, dispositively, materially, obedientially,g one level of being or activity subserves another. The interconnections are endless and manifest. Vertical finality would seem beyond dispute. (Fs)

22b But if one acknowledges that the same thing, besides its absolute reference to God, may have one finality horizontally and another vertically, there arises the question of systematic comparison between the latter two types of end. First, then, a horizontal end is more essential than a vertical end: for the horizontal end is the end determined by the essence of the thing, while the vertical end is had only by escaping the limitation of isolated essence through the fertility of concrete plurality. On the other hand, a vertical end is more excellent than a horizontal end: for the horizontal end is on the lower level of being but the vertical on some higher level; and from the very concept of hierarchy the higher is the more excellent. Inversely, one cannot say that the vertical end is non-essential or that the horizontal end is not excellent. For the vertical end, though it escapes the limitation of isolated essence and its abstract per se, nonetheless results from the same essence when in concrete combination with other essence. Again, though the vertical end is more excellent, still it is so only relatively; all finality is ultimately to the absolute good, and all is limited in mode of appetition or of process, so that the difference in excellence between higher and lower is never more than a difference in mode with respect to the absolute good. (Fs)

23a With perfect generality this establishes hierarchic criteria of more essential and more excellent ends. Universally, the horizontal end is more essential, the vertical end is more excellent. Thus the essential end of oxygen is to perform the offices of oxygen as oxygen; but its more excellent end is its contribution to the maintenance of human life, and this end oxygen attains not in isolation nor per se but in combination with other elements and within the human biological process. Similarly, we have to establish the contention of Aquinas that the most essential good of marriage is the child but its most excellent end lies on the supernatural level. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Liebe: 4 Aspekte, je 2 als Akt eines Vermögens (principium quo) und Akt eines Subjekts (principium quod)

Kurzinhalt: As act of a faculty (principium quo) love is, in the first instance, the basic form of appetition: ...; Further, love is the act of a subject (principium quod), and as such it is ...

Textausschnitt: The Concept of Love

2.1 Four Aspects

23b The difficulty of conceiving love h adequately arises from its essential concreteness and from the complexity of the concrete.i Even on a preliminary analysis there are at least four simultaneous aspects. For any activity is at once the act of a faculty j and the act of a subject. As act of a faculty (principium quo) love is, in the first instance, the basic form of appetition: it is the pure response of appetite to the good, nihil aliud [...] quam complacentia boni, while desire, hope, joy, hatred, aversion, fear, sadness are consequents of the basic response and reflect objective modifications in the circumstances of the motive good. But again, as act of a faculty, love, besides being the basic form of appetition, is also the first principle of process to the end loved, and the whole of the process is thus but the self-expression of the love that is its first principle. Further, love is the act of a subject (principium quod), and as such it is the principle of union between different subjects. Such union is of two kinds, according as it emerges in love as process to an end or in love in the consummation of the end attained. The former may be illustrated by the love of friends pursuing in common a common goal. The latter has its simplest illustration in the ultimate end of the beatific vision, which at once is the term of process, of amor concupiscentiae, and the fulfilment of union with God, of amor amicitiae. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Sexualität, Bipolarität: Mittel der Fruchtbarkeit; Einigung als sekundäres Ziel; Ehe: rationale Form der Finalität der Sexualität zu Nachkommen

Kurzinhalt: marriage is the rational form .. of sex and of the finality of sex to the child; so marriage will be an incorporation of the horizontal finality of sex much more than of sex itself

Textausschnitt: 45b Here three points are to be observed. First, marriage is the rational form, the incorporation on the level of reason, not of the child nor of the fecundity of parents, but of sex and of the finality of sex to the child. Not the child, for it advances to the level of reason by divine action, by the infusion of the soul. Not the fecundity of parents, for the marriage is valid even though the parents are sterile. It incorporates sex, for the sexual deficiency of impotence is a diriment impediment; and it incorporates the finality of sex to the child, for the object of marital right is actus per se apti ad prolis generationem. In the second place, marriage is more an incorporation of the finality of sex than of sex itself. Of course, it is just the opposite that seems true to phenomenologist scrutiny, for that ignores the metaphysical principle that what is prior quoad se is posterior quoad nos, r and that the more ultimate final cause enters more intimately into the nature of a thing than the more proximate.

Einfügung Fußnote 73: See Thomas Aquinas, Super Librum De causis, lect. 1. This, I think, touches upon a fundamental methodological error in the analysis presented by Dr Doms. I agree that sex is to be distinguished from fecundity, as impotence from sterility. I agree with the validity of the question, What is the ontological significance of bisexuality? It is only a terminological difference when he asserts that the meaning of marriage is union and I say that the act and end of bisexuality is union, or when in different ways we both place two ends beyond this union. But when he speaks of this meaning of union as immanent, intrinsic, immediate, I distinguish: in the chronological order of human knowledge or of the development of human appreciation, the union is first; but in the ontological order the ordinations to the ends are more immanent, more intrinsic, more immediate to the union than the union itself. For what is first in the ontological constitution of a thing is not the experiential datum but, on the contrary, what is known in the last and most general act of understanding with regard to it; what is next, is the next most general understanding; etc. Thus the proximate end of bisexuality is union; but of its nature, bisexuality is an instrument of fecundity, so that the end of fecundity is more an end of bisexuality than is union; similarly, bisexual union has a vertical finality to higher unions of friendship and charity; and these enter more intimately into the significance of bisexuality than does the union on the level of nature. See my note on immediatio virtutis, in 'St. Thomas' Theory of Operations,' Theological Studies 3 (1942) 376, for references to this line of Thomist thought [Grace and Freedom 64-65]. As to the difficulty that frequently procreation is objectively impossible and may be known to be so, distinguish motives and ends; as to motives, the difficulty is solved only by multiple motives and ends; as to ends, there is no difficulty, for the ordination of intercourse to conception is not a natural law, like 'fire burns,' but a statistical law,s which suffices for an objective ordination.

But, as we argued above, on the essential or horizontal level of natural spontaneity, sex is but a differentiation of fecundity and a means to the adult offspring that is the end of fecundity. If, then, reason incorporates sex as sex is in itself, it will incorporate it as subordinate to its horizontal end, and so marriage will be an incorporation of the horizontal finality of sex much more than of sex itself; nor is this to forget vertical finality, for vertical and horizontal finalities are not alternatives, but the vertical emerges all the more strongly as the horizontal is realized the more fully. Third and last, the incorporation of natural finality to adult offspring involves a redirection of that finality to higher ends. The life of reason and rational appetite has its end, here below, in the historical unfolding of the human good life ((Q"); the life of grace has its end in the triumphant mystical body in heaven (P"). Hence, when the finality to adult offspring (Z") is incorporated on the level of reason, it becomes a finality to educated adult offspring (Y"); and when it is incorporated on the level of grace, it becomes a finality to Christianly educated offspring (X"). The latter subsumption and redirection of lower under higher finality is clearer than the former. Christian parents are the representatives and the instruments of Christ and his bride, the church, and so they generate children to have them regenerated in Christ, and they educate them for their eternal role in the triumphant mystical body in heaven. But just as the life of grace wills offspring for the full expansion of the mystical body, so also the life of reason wills offspring for the continuity of reason's own historical unfolding of the human good life. It is this elevation of lower finality that makes the end of marriage not only the procreation but also the education of children, with the former the material and the latter the formal condition of historical continuity; further, the relativity of history accounts for the relativity in the obligation of parents to educate. But as theologians, let alone parents, rarely think of the historical process, it must be noted that we speak not of a finis operantis but of a finis operis and that we do so in its most general terms. No one will find a motive in the historical process as such. What moves men and women is some concrete aspect of history, a national destiny, the maintenance of a cultural tradition, the continuity of a family; and even this will be apprehended by parents, not in its abstract generality, but concretely as the good of bringing into the world and leaving in it behind them others like themselves. (Fs) (notabene)
47a This brings us to our main analytic conclusion. The process of bisexual fecundity (Z, Z', Z") is in man integrated with the processes of reason and of grace. Such integration takes place by projection, by the incorporation of the lower level of activity within the higher. The incorporation on the level of reason is generically a friendship (Y) and specifically a contractual bond (Y')l the latter has a horizontal finality to the procreation and education of children (Y"), but the former has a vertical dynamism tending to advance in human perfection (Q'). Similarly, the incorporation on the level of grace is generically a special order of charity (X) but specifically a sacramental bond (X'); the latter has a horizontal finality to the procreation and Christian education of children (X"), but the former a vertical dynamism tending to advance in Christian perfection (P'). (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Sexualität, Ehe, Polygamie: Antrieb der Sexualität -> Augustinus; unendliches Verlangen -> Objekt d. Sexualität

Kurzinhalt: The sexual extravagance of man ... has its ultimate ground in St Augustine's Fecisti nos ad te, Domine, et inquietum est cor nostrum donec requiescat in te; ... tend to center an infinite craving on a finite object or release

Textausschnitt: 4.3 Conformity with Traditional Doctrine

48a Now if this analysis satisfies the exigencies of modern data and insights, it is no less true that it leads immediately to the traditional position on the ends of marriage. For the criteria of more essential and more excellent ends may be applied in three ways, to the organistic union (Z'), to the marriage contract (Y'), and to the sacrament (X'). The first application gives the traditional position on polygamy: the horizontal finality of organistic union to offspring is more essential than the vertical finality to monogamous marriage; hence, under special circumstances, divine providence might permit polygamy for the sake of the more essential end and find other means to secure the more excellent personalist end. The second and third applications to monogamous marriage itself, whether contract or sacrament, are parallel: in both cases the horizontal finality to procreation and education of children is more essential than the vertical finality to personal advance in perfection; and if we take the terms 'primary' and 'secondary' in the sense of more and less essential, we have at once the traditional position that the primary end of marriage is the procreation and education of children. Further, our less essential vertical finality corresponds at least roughly with the traditional secondary ends of mutuum auxilium and honestum remedium concupiscentiae. For mutual aid is the spontaneous division of labor in the organistic union; it is the companionship and the good deeds of friendship; it is mutual support in spiritual advance to Christian perfection; it is all three, not isolated on the levels of nature, reason, and grace, but integrated and inseparable in the expansion of love into a common consciousness and conscience in the pursuit of life, the good life, and eternal life. The virtuous remedy for concupiscence would seem but the reverse aspect of the same thing. For if the virtuous remedy is sometimes understood narrowly as a legitimate outlet for sexual impulse, still such a view hardly squares with the fact that there is much more than sex in sexual impulse. The sexual extravagance of man, unparalleled in the animals, has its ultimate ground in St Augustine's Fecisti nos ad te, Domine, et inquietum est cor nostrum donec requiescat in te. t The ignorance and frailty of fallen man tend to center an infinite craving on a finite object or release: that may be wealth, or fame, or power, but most commonly it is sex. Thus marriage, not merely by the outlet of intercourse but in all its aspects, is a virtuous remedy: the manifold activities of the home drain off energies that otherwise would ferment; the educative process of the life in common and the responsibility of children develop character and mature wisdom; the pursuit of Christian perfection establishes a peace of soul that attacks concupiscence at its deepest root. In this fashion it would seem that the traditional secondary ends may be identified with the vertical upthrust to friendship and charity, to human and Christian perfection. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Augustinus; Ehe, Jungfräulichkeit, Witwenschaft, temporäre Abstinenz

Kurzinhalt: Fundamental would be the position that in the state of integral nature virginity would have been neither praiseworthy nor virtuous. Hence, ...

Textausschnitt: 4.4 A Qualification

49a It remains that the strength of this upthrust is not to be exaggerated. An integral part of Catholic thought on marriage is the doctrine that virginity is preferable to marriage, widowhood to second marriage, temporary abstinence to use within marriage (1 Corinthians 7.25-40). The precise implications of this doctrine are not too clear. Because of his position on original sin, the Pelagians charged St Augustine with a rejection of Christian defense and praise of marriage. St Augustine answered that marriage was good but concupiscence evil, indeed a disease to be tolerated only for the sake of children. Now it is quite certain that by concupiscence St Augustine does not mean simply the spontaneous tendencies by which two beings are invited to function as parts of the larger unit of the family; along with that natural phenomenon he also means an effect of original sin, a constituent in original sin, an instrument in its transmission, and in fallen nature a fecund cause of actual sin. Such global and concrete thinking was alone possible in the fifth century. It does not admit direct transference to the more elaborate conceptual field of later theology - though, as was lamentably conspicuous in the case of Baius and Jansenius, a realization of the illegitimacy of such direct transference has not always been had. Account, then, must be taken of later development, and in this the main factor would seem to have been the theorem of the supernatural u and its concomitant position that Adam's immunity from concupiscence was not natural but preternatural. Now, since in the lifetime of Aquinas this theoretical advance was still in process of development, it would be easy to attach too much significance to his maintenance in the Sentences of the essentially Augustinian position of an excusatio matrimonii et copulae. In any case that rigorous view seems to have been dropped by moral theologians, while the dynamic Thomist position would take its basis not in the explicit argument of the Sentences for the excusatio, namely, the eclipse of rational control in orgasm, but rather in broader considerations of different states of human nature. Fundamental would be the position that in the state of integral nature virginity would have been neither praiseworthy nor virtuous. Hence, absolutely, what is best for man is the full actuation of all his capacities. But in the disequilibrium of fallen nature, with lower spontaneity taking care of itself, with reason apt to be misled by the historical aberrations of the civitas terrena, with the wisdom of God appearing folly to man, man's best is not full actuation of all potentiality but rather concentration on the higher levels of activity. Such concentration is commended to all, though in the triple form of virginity, w widowhood, and temporary abstinence in marriage. So understood, the counsel does not imply any negation of an objective upward tendency from organistic union to a common pursuit of Christian perfection, though indeed it does emphasize the limitations of such an upthrust under actual circumstances and the need of supplementing it by an opposite procedure. Excellent is the instrumentality of husband and wife to Christ and his bride, the church - an instrumentality that participates the love of the principal causes and brings forth to them the children that extend to full stature the mystical body. Excellent is the Christian home, a focal point that turns aside the influences of the world to rear children in an atmosphere of wholesome fear and love. But the bulwark of that excellence, the palpable proof of its ever doubted possibility, is the greater excellence that rises, not through organistic tendency but immediately, to concern with the one thing necessary, our eternal embrace with God in the beatific vision.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Intellekt als Potenz; Intellekt als Erfassen von Washeiten; ens per essentiam

Kurzinhalt: What differentiates intellect from sense is precisely its grasp of essence; recognition of the essentially dynamic character of our intellects and, in particular, of our notion of being

Textausschnitt: 2 The Finalistic Notion of Being

145b My second topic has to do with the notion of being, and I shall begin with a problem. You will agree, I believe, that there is one and only one ens per essentiam, that it is not an immediate object of our knowledge in this life, that the only immediate objects of our present knowledge are entia per participationem. It follows that our intellectual knowledge of being cannot result from abstraction of essence. For if from a horse I abstract essence, what I abstract is the essence, not of being, but of horse; if from a man I abstract essence, what I abstract is the essence, not of being, but of man; and the same holds for every other immediate object of our present knowledge. No being by participation can yield us knowledge of the essence of being, because no being by participation has the essence of being; and what is true of essence, equally is true of quiddity, nature, species, and form. A being by participation no more has the quiddity of being, the nature of being, the species of being, the form of being, than it has the essence of being. (Fs) (notabene)

146a Now this fact gives rise to a problem. What differentiates intellect from sense is precisely its grasp of essence or, if you prefer, its grasp of quiddity or nature or species or form. But in this life we do not grasp the essence or quiddity or nature or species or form of being. How then can we have any intellectual notion, any intellectual concept, any intellectual knowledge of being? Indeed, to put the problem with the sharpness that is essential, how is it that we have precisely such an intellectual notion of being that (1) we can conceive the ens per essentiam and (2) we can pronounce the only beings that we do know directly to be merely entia per participationem? (Fs) (notabene)

146b Further, this problem of the notion of being is not unique, isolated, unparalleled. If in this life we cannot know God by his essence, it also is true that we know the essences of material things only rarely, imperfectly, doubtfully. If our knowledge of essence is so rare and imperfect, should we not conclude either that Aristotle and Aquinas were mistaken in characterizing human intellect by knowledge of essence or, perhaps, that we have not intellects in the full sense of that term? (Fs) (notabene)

146c Many of you, I feel, will incline to the latter alternative. Human intellect is in genere rerum intelligibilium ut ens in potentia tantum, it belongs to the realm of spirit merely as potency. Its knowing is process. It is not some simple matter of grasping essence and affirming existence. It is the prolonged business of raising questions, working out tentative answers, and then finding that these answers raise further questions. Dynamism, process, finality are fundamental features of our intellects in this life. Hence, knowledge of things by their essences is for us, not an accomplished fact, but only the goal, the end, the objective of a natural desire. (Fs) (notabene)

147a Moreover, according to Aquinas, the object of the natural desire of our intellects includes the ens per essentiam. When we learn of God's existence, spontaneously we ask what God is; but to ask what something is, releases a process that does not come to rest until knowledge of essence is attained; therefore we have a natural desire to know God by his essence. (Fs)

147b By such reasoning I was led in Insight to affirm that our natural intellectual desire to know was a natural intellectual desire to know being. The desire, precisely because it is intelligent, is a notion.d But the notion is not any innate idea or concept or knowledge. It is a desire for ideas, for concepts, for knowledge but, of itself, it is merely discontented ignorance without ideas, without concepts, without knowledge. Again, it is not a postulate. Postulates are parts of hypothetical answers, but the desire to know grounds questions. Nor is there any need to postulate questions. They are facts. (Fs) (notabene)

147c What is the issue here? I think it both very simple and very fundamental. If intellect is not characterized by its capacity to grasp essence, then I believe that one parts company from Aristotle and Aquinas and, as well, from any adequate account of the nature of human intelligence. If, on the other hand, intellect is characterized by its capacity to grasp essence, then the fact that our knowledge of essences is so slight can be met only by a full recognition of the essentially dynamic character of our intellects and, in particular, of our notion of being. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Urteil als Maßstab der Objektivität

Kurzinhalt: First, then, is this universe of being the real world? There is one standard, one criterion, one absolute, and that is true judgment

Textausschnitt: Knowledge of Concrete, Actual Existence

147d My third topic had to do with the objective universe of being. According to Insight this universe is to be known by the totality of true judgments and it is not to be known humanly without true judgments. Four main questions arise. First, is this universe of being the real world? Secondly, is it concrete? Thirdly, is it the actually existing universe, or merely an essentialist universe? Fourthly, how can concrete, actual existence be known on the account of knowledge offered by Insight? First, then, is this universe of being the real world? e Clearly, if by the real world one means what is to be known by the totality of true judgments and not without true judgments, then by definition the universe of being and the real world are identical in all respects. However, it frequently happens that the expression, the real world, is employed in quite a different sense. In this sense each of us lives in a real world of his own.f Its contents are determined by his Sorge, by his interests and concerns, by the orientation of his living, by the unconscious horizong g that blocks from his view the rest of reality. To each of us his own private real world is very real indeed. Spontaneously it lays claim to being the one real world, the standard, the criterion, the absolute, by which everything is judged, measured, evaluated. That claim, I should insist, is not to be admitted. There is one standard, one criterion, one absolute, and that is true judgment. Insofar as one's private real world does not meet that standard, it is some dubious product of animal faith h and human error. On the other hand, insofar as one's private real world is submitted constantly and sedulously to the corrections made by true judgment, necessarily it is brought into conformity with the universe of being. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Coreth; Horizont (verschiedene Horizonte: reine Vernunft, Idealismus)

Kurzinhalt: ... in the horizon of the wise man ... the objective pole is an unrestricted domain, and the subjective pole is the philosopher practicing transcendental method ...

Textausschnitt: 198b Now it is technically simpler to express the foregoing in terms of 'horizon.'i Literally, a horizon is a maximum field of vision from a determinate standpoint. In a generalized sense, a horizon is specified by two poles, one objective and the other subjective, with each pole conditioning the other. Hence, the objective pole is taken, not materially, but like the formal object sub ratione sub qua attingitur; similarly, the subjective pole is considered, not materially, but in its relation to the objective pole. Thus the horizon of pure reason is specified when one states that its objective pole is possible being as determined by relations of possibility and necessity obtaining between concepts, and that its subjective pole is logical thinking as determining what can be and what must be. Similarly, in the horizon of critical idealism, the objective pole is the world of experience as appearance, and the subjective pole is the set of a priori conditions of the possibility of such a world. Again, in the horizon of the expert, the objective pole is his restricted domain as attained by accepted scientific methods, and the subjective pole is the expert practicing those methods; but in the horizon of the wise man, the philosopher of the Aristotelian tradition, the objective pole is an unrestricted domain, and the subjective pole is the philosopher practicing transcendental method, namely, the method that determines the ultimate and so basic whole. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Vergleich: Coreth - Gilson

Kurzinhalt: ... while Prof. Gilson's immediate realism cannot be mediated and so is dogmatic, Fr Coreth's immediate realism ... is mediated;

Textausschnitt: 2.3 Gilson and Coreth

197a Thirdly, to complete our circle of comparisons, we must now turn to Prof. Gilson and Fr Coreth. Here we are met with massive similarities, and it is the difference that requires clarification. For both are realists: they acknowledge the real existence of minerals, plants, animals, men, and God. Both are immediate realists: though Fr Coreth mediates this immediacy, still for him no less than for Prof. Gilson realism is immediate truth. In both immediate realisms an a posteriori component is recognized: neither attempts to restore the pure reason that Kant undertook to refute. Not only are both Thomists, but also both are quite convinced of the priority of metaphysics over everything in general and over cognitional theory most particularly. Finally, as realism for Prof. Gilson is a whole, as his thinking deals with philosophies as wholes, so too for Fr Coreth the priority of the whole over the parts is cardinal. (Fs)

197b The basic difference is that, while Prof. Gilson's immediate realism cannot be mediated and so is dogmatic, Fr Coreth's immediate realism not only can be but also is mediated. For Prof. Gilson realism is a whole that one must accept or reject, and with this Fr Coreth agrees. For Prof. Gilson realism is a whole that cannot be assembled step by step with every step guaranteed as alone rational, and with this Fr Coreth flatly disagrees. His transcendental method is essentially the method for explicitating the whole: for transcendental method ascertains conditions of possibility, and the first and foremost of all conditions of possibility is the whole itself. (Fs)
198a Let us attempt to get clear this point about a philosophy as essentially a whole. Aristotle and Aquinas distinguish the expert and the wise man: the expert orders everything within a restricted domain; the wise man orders everything. Further, to call a congress of all experts representing all restricted domains does not secure the presence of a wise man, for none of the experts knows the relations between the restricted domains. Knowledge of the whole, then, is distinct from knowledge of the parts, and it is not attained by a mere summation of the parts. The very fact that the expert restricts his domain implies that he also restricts the number of aspects under which he considers the objects within his domain; as the restrictions are removed, further aspects come to light; only when all restrictions are removed do all aspects come to light; and once all restrictions are removed, there can be no ulterior and higher viewpoint from which new aspects come to light with a consequent revision and reordering of previous acquisition. So the unrestricted viewpoint is ultimate and basic: it is wisdom and its domain is being. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Lonergan über Coreth (Gilson): Vollzug (performance); Magen - Schachtel (stomache - box)

Kurzinhalt: ... he begins, not from statement, but from a performance, a Vollzug, asking questions; Nihil in intellectu nisi prius fuerit in sensu

Textausschnitt: 199b However, if Fr Coreth grants that statements have a meaning only within a horizon, how can he escape the dogmatism that Prof. Gilson believes inevitable? The answer is that he begins, not from statement, but from a performance, a Vollzug, asking questions. It is a performance that begins early in childhood and is continued even by an Aquinas until a higher form of knowledge supervenes. No doubt, that performance will be interpreted or overlooked in different manners when assumed within different horizons; but it is given to be interpreted or overlooked whether or not it is assumed. Nor can any doubt be entertained about the fact of the performance. To doubt questioning is to ask whether questions occur. The condition of the possibility of doubting is the occurrence of questioning. Fr Coreth, then, begins from a clearly known, universally accessible, indubitable occurrence. (Fs) (notabene)

200b Now the determination of the two poles is the determination of a horizon, and it is easy to see that Fr Coreth's horizon is total and basic. It is total, for beyond being there is nothing. It is basic, for a total horizon is basic; it cannot be transcended, gone beyond, and so it cannot be revised. (Fs)

200c But further, for Fr Coreth being is precisely what St Thomas meant by being. For as intended in questioning, being is unrestricted. In that premise there is already included the conclusion that esse de se est illimitatum, whence it will follow that finite being is a compound of essence and existence and that every ens is an ens by its relations to esse. (Fs)

200d From this it would seem to follow that being for Fr Coreth and being for Prof. Gilson must be exactly the same. For Prof. Gilson also means by being what St Thomas meant. It remains that this identification is not without its difficulties, for if the objective pole in Fr Coreth's horizon is the same as the objective pole in Prof. Gilson's, the subjective poles are manifestly different. (Fs)

200e Thus Fr Coreth would accept the principle, Nihil in intellectu nisi prius fuerit in sensu. But he would have to distinguish, say, between the way there is nothing in a box and the way there is nothing in a stomach. When there is nothing in a box, a box does not feel empty; when there is nothing in a stomach, the stomach does feel empty. Human intelligence is more like a stomach than like a box. Though it has no answers, and so is empty, still it can ask questions. (Fs)

200g Again, for Prof. Gilson, our knowledge of being is a posteriori: abstract concepts of being and existence are had by abstracting from sense; and to reach the concrete there is added to the abstractions his intellectual vision. But for Fr Coreth, being is an a priori, i.e., the intention of being in questioning bears no resemblance to sensitive or empirical knowledge. What is perceived is not unknown, not to be known, but already known. But being as intended in questioning is the exact opposite of the object of perception: it is not already known; it is unknown; it is to be known. In other words, the analysis of questioning forces one to conceive human intelligence, not on the analogy of sense, but properly in terms of intelligence itself. (Fs)
201a Moreover, we have seen that Fr Coreth rejects the idealist's acceptance of idealism as contradictory, that Prof. Gilson regards idealism as non-contradictory, that consequently he is left with a problem of a bridge from a concept of l'etre en general to an existence concrete, actuelle, extra-mentale, and that, inevitably enough, this bridge has to be an intellectual perception of existence. This narrative, it would seem, enables us to pick the exact point at which Prof. Gilson and Fr Coreth part company. Both agree that idealism is noncontradictory. But where Fr Coreth maintains that the idealist's acceptance of idealism is contradictory, and so eliminates the problem of the bridge, Prof. Gilson acknowledges a problem of a bridge and so arrives at his need for an intellectual perception of being. Hence, being can be a priori for Fr Coreth, because for him the idealist is involved in self-contradiction; but being must be a posteriori for Prof. Gilson, because for him idealism is not self-contradictory. (Fs)

201b Finally, there remains the question how Fr Coreth and Prof. Gilson both arrive at the same objective pole, being in the Thomist sense, when their subjective poles are mutually exclusive. The explanation would seem to be that, if Prof. Gilson does not thematize questioning, nonetheless he asks questions and so intends what is intended in questioning; further, while Prof. Gilson asserts an intellectual perception of existence, still he is careful to integrate this perception within the structure of Thomist cognitional theory, and so is able to shift from a theory of being as something seen in data to a theory of being as something affirmed in perceptual judgments of existence. Hence, inasmuch as Prof. Gilson asks questions and gives rational answers, his position coincides with that of Fr Coreth, and as the subjective poles are the same so the objective poles are the same. On the other hand, if Prof. Gilson were to operate simply and solely with a concept of being that can be 'seen' in any sensible datum, not only would his subjective pole differ from Fr Coreth's but also it would be impossible for him to reach being in the Thomist sense as his objective pole; for being as object of perception is being in which essence and existence are only notionally distinct. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Offenheit als Tatsache, Haltung und Geschenk (Lonergan, Aristoteles, Thomas), Staunen; unbegrenztes Streben; gratia sanans, elevans

Kurzinhalt: unrestricted desire to know; Openness as a fact is the pure desire to know; Openness as achievement is the self in its self-appropriation and self-realization;

Textausschnitt: 186a The basic orientation,d finally, is the pure, detached, disinterested, and unrestricted desire to know. I should note that this desire, when it is functioning, is no less immediate than the levels of consciousness when they are functioning. (Fs) (notabene)

3 Opennesse as (1) fact, (2) achievement, (3) gift.

186b Openness as a fact is the pure desire to know. It is, when functioning, immediately given. It is referred to by Aristotle when he speaks of the wonder that is the beginning of all science and philosophy. f It is referred to by Aquinas when he speaks of the natural desire to know God by his essence. (Fs) (notabene)

186c Openness as an achievement has two aspects. In its more fundamental aspect it regards the subject, the noEsis, the pense pensante. Here stages towards its acquisition are communicated or objectified in precepts, methods, criticism. Achievement itself arises when the actual orientation of consciousness coincides with the exigences of the pure, detached, disinterested, unrestricted desire to know. (Fs) (notabene)
186d But openness as achievement also has a consequent aspect that regards the object, the noEma, the pense pense. For the pure desire to function fully, to dominate consciousness, there are needed not only precepts, methods, criticism, but also a formulated view of our knowledge and of the reality our knowledge can attain. Thus I should maintain that the crop of philosophies produced since the Enlightenment are not open to revealed truths because they possess no adequate account of truth. (Fs) (notabene)
I have spoken of openness as (1) fact and (2) achievement. (Fs)

186e As fact, it is an intrinsic component in man's makeup. But as fact it does not consistently and completely dominate human consciousness. (Fs)

186f It is a fact to which man has to advert, which he has to acknowledge and accept, whose implications for all his thinking and acting have to be worked out and successfully applied to actual thinking and actual acting. (Fs) (notabene)

186g Hence, besides openness as primordial fact, there also is openness as achievement. The history of religion, of science, of philosophy in all their vicissitudes is the history of such achievement. (Fs) (notabene)

But there is also openness as a gift, as an effect of divine grace. (Fs)

186h Man's natural openness is complete. The pure desire is unrestricted. It inquires into everything, and asks everything about everything. (Fs)

The correlative to the pure desire is 'being,' omnia, at once completely universal and completely concrete. (Fs) (notabene)

186k Nonetheless, there is a contrast, almost an antinomy, between the primordial fact and achievement, for the primordial fact is no more than a principle of possible achievement, a definition of the ultimate horizon that is to be reached only through successive enlargements of the actual horizon. (Fs) (notabene)

187a But such successive enlargements only too clearly lie under some law of decreasing returns. No one ever believed that the world would be converted by philosophy. In the language at once of scripture and of a current philosophy, man is fallen. There is then a need of openness as a gift, as an effect of grace, where grace is taken as gratia sanans. (Fs) (notabene)

187b Further, the successive enlargements of the actual horizon fall into two classes. There are the enlargements implicit in the very structure of human consciousness, the enlargements that are naturally possible to man. But there is also an ultimate enlargement, beyond the resources of every finite consciousness, where there enters into clear view God as unknown, when the subject knows God face to face, knows as he is known. This ultimate enlargement alone approximates to the possibility of openness defined by the pure desire; as well, it is an openness as a gift, as an effect of grace and, indeed, of grace not as merely sanans but as elevans, as lumen gloriae. (Fs) (notabene)

4 Openness and religious experience.g

187c The three aspects of openness are to be related. Openness as fact is for openness as gift; and openness as achievement rises from the fact, and conditions and, at the same time, is conditioned by the gift. (Fs)

187d But openness as fact is the inner self, the self as ground of all higher aspiration. (Fs)
Openness as achievement is the self in its self-appropriation and self-realization. (Fs)
Openness as gift is the self entering into personal relationship with God. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Definition: dynamische Struktur; materiell, formal, dynamisch

Kurzinhalt: Each part is what it is in virtue of its functional relations to other parts; The whole itself may be self-assembling, d self-constituting; then it is formally dynamic. It is a dynamic structure

Textausschnitt: 205d A whole, then, has parts. The whole is related to each of the parts, and each of the parts is related to the other parts and to the whole. (Fs)

206a Not every whole is a structure. When one thinks of a whole, there may come to mind some conventional quantity or arbitrary collection whose parts are determined by an equally conventional or arbitrary division. In such a case, e.g., a gallon of milk, the closed set of relations between whole and parts will be a no less arbitrary jumble of arithmetic ratios. But it may also happen that the whole one thinks of is some highly organized product of nature or art. Then the set of internal relations c is of the greatest significance. Each part is what it is in virtue of its functional relations to other parts; there is no part that is not determined by the exigences of other parts; and the whole possesses a certain inevitability in its unity, so that the removal of any part would destroy the whole, and the addition of any further part would be ludicrous. Such a whole is a structure. (Fs)

207a The parts of a whole may be things, bricks, timbers, glass, rubber, chrome. But the parts may also be activities, as in a song, a dance, a chorus, a symphony, a drama. Such a whole is dynamic materially. But dynamism may not be restricted to the parts. The whole itself may be self-assembling, d self-constituting; then it is formally dynamic. It is a dynamic structure. (Fs)-

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Unterschied: Bewusstsein und Selbst-Erkenntnis (Consciousness and Self-knowledge)

Kurzinhalt: ... distinction between consciousness and self-knowledge. Self-knowledge is the reduplicated structure

Textausschnitt: 208a Where knowing is a structure, knowing knowing must be a reduplication of the structure. Thus if knowing is just looking, then knowing knowing will be looking at looking. But if knowing is a conjunction of experience, understanding, and judging, then knowing knowing has to be a conjunction of (1) experiencing experience, understanding and judging, (2) understanding one's experience of experience, understanding, and judging, and (3) judging one's understanding of experience, understanding, and judging to be correct. (Fs) (notabene)

208b On the latter view there follows at once a distinction between consciousness and self-knowledge.f Self-knowledge is the reduplicated structure: it is experience, understanding, and judging with respect to experience, understanding, and judging. Consciousness, on the other hand, is not knowing knowing but merely experience of knowing, experience, that is, of experiencing, of understanding, and of judging. (Fs) (notabene)

208c Secondly, it follows that all cognitional activities may be conscious yet none or only some may be known. So it is, in fact, that both acts of seeing and acts of understanding occur consciously, yet most people know what seeing is and most are mystified when asked what understanding is. (Fs) (notabene)

208d Thirdly, it follows that different cognitional activities are not equally accessible.g Experience is of the given. Experience of seeing is to be had only when one actually is seeing. Experience of insight is to be had only when one actually is having an insight. But one has only to open one's eyes and one will see; one has only to open and close one's eyes a number of times to alternate the experience of seeing and of not seeing. Insights, on the other hand, cannot be turned on and off in that fashion. To have an insight, one has to be in the process of learning or, at least, one has to reenact in oneself previous processes of learning. While that is not peculiarly difficult, it does require (1) the authenticity that is ready to get down to the elements of a subject, (2) close attention to instances of one's own understanding and, equally, one's failing to understand, and (3) the repeated use of personal experiments in which, at first, one is genuinely puzzled and then catches on. (Fs)
Kommentar (05/31/05): Interessant unten: Unterschied in der Erfahrung von Intelligenz und Rationalitt.

209a Fourthly, because human knowing is a structure of different activities, experience of human knowing is qualitatively differentiated. When one is reflecting, weighing the evidence, judging, one is experiencing one's own rationality. When one is inquiring, understanding, conceiving, thinking, one is experiencing one's own intelligence. When one is seeing or hearing, touching or tasting, one is experiencing one's own sensitivity. Just as rationality is quite different from intelligence, so the experience of one's rationality is quite different from the experience of one's intelligence; and just as intelligence is quite different from sensitivity, so the experience of one's intelligence is quite different from the experience of one's sensitivity. Indeed, since consciousness is of the acting subject qua acting, the experience of one's rationality is identical with one's rationality bringing itself to act; the experience of one's intelligence is identical with one's bringing one's intelligence to act; and the experiencing of one's sensitivity is identical with one's sensitivity coming to act. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Erfahrung: innere, äußere

Kurzinhalt: external experience may be of spatial objects, it itself is not a spatial object and, still less, is internal experience

Textausschnitt: 209b Fifthly, then, experience commonly is divided into external and internal. External experience is of sights and sounds, of odors and tastes, of the hot and cold, hard and soft, rough and smooth, wet and dry. Internal experience is of oneself and one's apprehensive and appetitive activities. Still, if the meaning of the distinction is clear, the usage of the adjectives, internal and external, calls for explanation. Strictly, only spatial objects are internal or external and, while external experience may be of spatial objects, it itself is not a spatial object and, still less, is internal experience. Accordingly, we must ask what is the original datum that has been expressed by a spatial metaphor;h and to that end we draw attention to different modes of presence. (Fs)

209c There is material presence, in which no knowing is involved, and such is the presence of the statue in the courtyard. There is intentional presence, in which knowing is involved, and it is of two quite distinct kinds. There is the presence of the object to the subject, of the spectacle to the spectator; there is also the presence of the subject to himself, and this is not the presence of another object dividing his attention, of another spectacle distracting the spectator; it is presence in, as it were, another dimension, presence concomitant and correlative and opposite to the presence of the object. Objects are present by being attended to; but subjects are present as subjects, not by being attended to, but by attending. As the parade of objects marches by, spectators do not have to slip into the parade to become present to themselves; they have to be present to themselves for anything to be present to them; and they are present to themselves by the same watching that, as it were, at its other pole makes the parade present to them. (Fs)

210a I have been attempting to describe the subject's presence to himself. But the reader, if he tries to find himself as subject, to reach back and, as it were, uncover his subjectivity, cannot succeed. Any such effort is introspecting, attending to the subject; and what is found is, not the subject as subject, but only the subject as object; it is the subject as subject that does the finding. To heighten one's presence to oneself, one does not introspect; one raises the level of one's activity.1 If one sleeps and dreams, one is present to oneself as the frightened dreamer. If one wakes, one becomes present to oneself, not as moved but as moving, not as felt but as feeling, not as seen but as seeing. If one is puzzled and wonders and inquires, the empirical subject becomes an intellectual subject as well. If one reflects and considers the evidence, the empirical and intellectual subject becomes a rational subject, an incarnate reasonableness. If one deliberates and chooses, one has moved to the level of the rationally conscious, free, responsible subject that by his choices makes himself what he is to be and his world what it is to be. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Objektivität als innere Relation von Wissen zu Sein; Identität von Sein und Realität; intentio intendens, intenta; noesis, noema

Kurzinhalt: that knowledge is intrinsically objective, that objectivity is the intrinsic relation of knowing to being, and that being and reality are identical.

Textausschnitt: The Epistemological Theorem

211a At this point one may ask why knowing should result from the performance of such immanent activities as experiencing, understanding, and judging. This brings us to the epistemological theorem,j namely, that knowledge in the proper sense is knowledge of reality or, more fully, that knowledge is intrinsically objective, that objectivity is the intrinsic relation of knowing to being, and that being and reality are identical. (Fs)

211b The intrinsic objectivity of human cognitional activity is its intentionality. Nor need this intentionality be inferred, for it is the dominant content of the dynamic structure that assembles and unites several activities into a single knowing of a single object. Human intelligence actively greets every content of experience with the perplexity, the wonder, the drive, the intention, that may be thematized by (but does not consist in) such questions as, What is it? Why is it so? Inquiry through insight issues forth in thought that, when scrutinized, becomes formulated in definitions, postulates, suppositions, hypotheses, theories. Thought in turn is actively greeted by human rationality with a reflective exigence that, when thematized, is expressed in such questions as, Is that so? Are you certain? All marshaling and weighing of evidence, all judging and doubting, are efforts to say of what is that it is and of what is not that it is not. Accordingly, the dynamic structure of human knowing intends being. That intention is unrestricted, for there is nothing that we cannot at least question. The same intention is comprehensive, for questioning probes every aspect of everything; its ultimate goal is the universe in its full concreteness. Being in that sense is identical with reality: as apart from being there is nothing, so apart from reality there is nothing; as being embraces the concrete totality of everything, so too does reality. (Fs) (notabene)

211c This intrinsic relation of the dynamic structure of human knowing to being and so to reality primarily is not pense pense but pense pensante, not intentio intenta but intentio intendens, not noEma but noEsis. It is the originating drive of human knowing. Consciously, intelligently, rationally it goes beyond: beyond data to intelligibility; beyond intelligibility to truth and through truth to being; and beyond known truth and being to the truth and being still to be known. But though it goes beyond, it does not leave behind. It goes beyond to add, and when it has added, it unites. It is the active principle that calls forth in turn our several cognitional activities and, as it assembles them into single instances of knowing, so it assembles their many partial objects into single total objects. By inquiry it moves us from sensing to understanding only to combine the sensed and understood into an object of thought. By reflection it moves us from objects of thought through rationally compelling evidence to judgments about reality. From the partial knowledge we have reached it sends us back to fuller experiencing, fuller understanding, broader and deeper judgments, for what it intends includes far more than we succeed in knowing. It is all-inclusive, but the knowing we achieve is always limited. (Fs) (notabene)

212a As answers stand to questions, so cognitional activities stand to the intention of being. But an answer is to a question, because it and the question have the same object. So it is that the intrinsic relation of the dynamic structure of human knowing passes from the side of the subject to the side of the object, that the intentio intendens of being becomes the intentio intenta of this or that being. So the question, What's this? promotes the datum of sense to a 'this' that has a 'what-ness' and 'is.' The promotion settles no issues, but it does raise issues. It is neither knowledge nor ignorance of essence and existence, but it is the intention of both. What the essence is and whether that essence exists are, not answers, but questions. Still, the questions have been raised, and the very fact of raising them settles what the answers will have to be about. The intentio intendens of the subject summons forth and unites cognitional activities to objectify itself in an intentio intenta that unites and is determined by the partial objects of the partial activities. As the intentio intendens of the dynamic structure, so the corresponding intentio intenta of the structured cognitional activities is intrinsically related to being and reality. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: intentio intendens: Objektivität in Potenz; intentio intenta: Objektivität in actu; Frage u. Antwort transzendieren das Subjekt

Kurzinhalt: Empiricists, Rationalists; objectivity of human knowing is a triple cord; the conditions of the conditioned may be fulfilled, and then the conditioned is virtually an unconditioned

Textausschnitt: 212b It remains that the two relations are not identical. The intentio intendens is not knowing but merely intending: it is objectivity in potency. But the intentio intenta resides not in mere intending but in structured activities of knowing: it is objectivity in act. Moreover, objectivity in act, because it resides not in a single operation but in a structured manifold of operations, is not some single property of human knowing but a compound of quite different properties. Empiricists have tried to find the ground of objectivity in experience, rationalists have tried to place it in necessity, idealists have had recourse to coherence. All are partly right and partly wrong, right in their affirmation, but mistaken in their exclusion. For the objectivity of human knowing is a triple cord; there is an experiential component that resides in the givenness of relevant data; there is a normative component that resides in the exigences of intelligence and rationality guiding the process of knowing from data to judging; there finally is an absolute component that is reached when reflective understanding combines the normative and the experiential elements into a virtually unconditioned, i.e., a conditioned whose conditions are fulfilled. (Fs) (notabene)

213a The objectivity of human knowing, then, rests upon an unrestricted intention and an unconditioned result. Because the intention is unrestricted, it is not restricted to the immanent content of knowing, to Bewusstseinsinhalte; at least, we can ask whether there is anything beyond that, and the mere fact that the question can be asked reveals that the intention which the question manifests is not limited by any principle of immanence. But answers are to questions, so that if questions are transcendent, so also must be the meaning of corresponding answers. If I am asked whether mice and men really exist, I am not answering the question when I talk about images of mice and men, concepts of mice and men, or the words, mice and men; I answer the question only if I affirm or deny the real existence of mice and men. Further, true answers express an unconditioned. Mice and men are contingent, and so their existence has its conditions. My knowing mice and men is contingent, and so my knowing of their existence has its conditions. But the conditions of the conditioned may be fulfilled, and then the conditioned is virtually an unconditioned; it has the properties of an unconditioned, not absolutely, but de facto. Because human knowing reaches such an unconditioned, it transcends itself. For the unconditioned qua unconditioned cannot be restricted, qualified, limited; and so we all distinguish sharply between what is and, on the other hand, what appears, what seems to be, what is imagined or thought or might possibly or probably be affirmed; in the latter cases the object is still tied down by relativity to the subject; in the former the self-transcendence of human knowing has come to its term; when we say that something is, we mean that its reality does not depend upon our cognitional activity. (Fs)

213b The possibility of human knowing, then, is an unrestricted intention that intends the transcendent, and a process of self-transcendence that reaches it. The unrestricted intention directs the process to being; the attainment of the unconditioned reveals that at some point being has been reached. So, quite manifestly, a grasp of dynamic structure is essential to a grasp of the objectivity of our knowing. Without the dynamism one may speak of concepts of being, affirmations of being, even the idea of being; but unfailingly one overlooks the overarching intention of being which is neither concept nor affirmation nor idea.1 Again, without the structure there is no place for three quite different elements of objectivity and no thought of a third resulting from a reflective understanding of the other two; yet the empiricists are right in their insistence on data, for in the givenness of data resides the experiential component of objectivity; there is something to the idealist insistence on coherence, for in the directive exigences of intelligence and rationality there resides the normative component of objectivity; and there is something to the rationalist insistence on necessity, for a conditioned whose conditions are fulfilled is virtually an unconditioned, and reflective understanding grasps such a virtually unconditioned whenever it finds the fulfilment of conditions in the data of sense or consciousness and, at the same time, derives from normative objectivity the link that binds conditions with conditioned. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Gegenpositionen (counterpositions); treffende Charakteristik: der naive Realist; Idealist

Kurzinhalt: The generalization contains two elements, one positive, and the other negative; The idealist is not impressed ...; Denken to Anschauen

Textausschnitt: Counterpositions Criticized

214a The alternative to distinguishing is confusion.k We have been engaged in distinguishing between human knowing and its component elements and between the objectivity of human knowing and the objectivity proper to different components in human knowing. When, however, the distinctions are not drawn, confusion easily if not inevitably occurs. (Fs)

214b From the viewpoint of the validity of human knowing, such confusions may be divided into two classes that are dialectically related. The naive realist correctly asserts the validity of human knowing, but mistakenly attributes the objectivity of human knowing, not to human knowing, but to some component in human knowing. The idealist, on the other hand, correctly refutes the naive-realist claim that the whole objectivity of human knowing is found in some component of human knowing, but mistakenly concludes that human knowing does not yield valid knowledge of reality. The strength of the naive-realist position is its confidence in the validity of human knowing; its weakness is its inability to learn. On the other hand, the strength of the idealist position is the sharpness with which it refutes the mistaken claims of naive realists; its weakness is its inability to break completely with the confusions introduced by naive realism. (Fs) (notabene)

215a If theoretically this dialectical process could begin from any confusion, commonly its starting point is the myth that knowing is looking. Jack or Jill is invited to raise a hand and to look at it. The hand is really out there; it is the object. The eye, strangely, is not in the hand; it is some distance away in the head; it is the subject. The eye really sees the hand; it sees what is there to be seen; it does not see what is not there to be seen. That is objectivity. (Fs) (notabene)

215b Once the essence of objectivity has been grasped in this dramatic instance, there follow generalization and deduction. The generalization contains two elements, one positive, and the other negative. The positive element in the generalization is that any cognitional activity that sufficiently resembles ocular vision must be objective; for if it sufficiently resembles ocular vision, one can grasp the essence of objectivity in it no less than in ocular vision; and an activity that possesses the essence of objectivity must be objective. The negative element is that any cognitional activity that does not sufficiently resemble ocular vision cannot be objective; for it lacks what is essential to objectivity; of itself, therefore, any such activity is merely immanent; it may have some subordinate or derivative role to play in human knowing, particularly when knowing is not immediate but mediate; but from the nature of the case it can make no proper contribution to the objectivity of human knowing, for of itself it has nothing to contribute. (Fs) (notabene)

215c The positive and negative elements of the generalization provide a basis whence one can deduce what human knowing must be and what it cannot be. With such premises to hand, one does not have to bother too much about cognitional fact. The analogy of ocular vision reveals what intellectual activity must be like if it is objective; it must be like seeing. Even if introspection discovers no intellectual activity that resembles seeing, still some such activity really must exist; for if it did not, then our intellectual activity would be merely immanent, and idealism would be correct; but the conclusion is false, and therefore the premise must be false. Again, no serious difficulty arises from the fact that introspection brings to light intellectual activities that do not resemble seeing; it is true that such activities make no contribution of their own to the objectivity of human knowing; they are not constitutive of our immediate knowledge or our knowledge by acquaintance; but they can perform some useful function in the subordinate and derivative parts of our knowing, in our mediate knowledge or our knowledge by description. Just what these functions are, of course, is somewhat obscure; but we may with confidence look forward to the time when sound and sane study and research will have cleared up these extraordinarily difficult and complicated problems. In the meantime, however, we have complete certitude with regard to the essentials of the matter. Knowing, if objective, is like seeing. We know that we know, and so, in some analogous sense of the word, see, we see our knowing. We know the truth of our knowing; but truth is the correspondence of the knowing to the known; therefore, in some analogous sense of the word, see, we see the correspondence of our knowing to the known. Finally, science is of the universal; but scientific knowledge is at least possible; therefore, in some analogous sense of the word, see, we see universals. (Fs) (notabene)

216a The idealist is not impressed. He feels that the distinction between appearance and reality has been overlooked. By appearance he does not mean any illusion or hallucination. He means precisely what Jack or Jill really does see: the shape of an outstretched hand, its color, the lines that mark it, its position out there in front of the head. He is willing to add what Jack and Jill do not see: the feelings inside the hand and the conjunction in ordinary experience of the feelings with the visible object. All of that is not reality but appearance. And by reality he means what is meant by Jack, Jill, and the naive realist. Such is his thesis, and he argues as follows. (Fs) (notabene)
216b When I lift a lump of lead, I may report either that the lead is heavy or that the lead feels heavy. When I gaze out my window at a green field, I may report either that the field is green or that the field looks green. Such alternative reports are not equivalent. When I say 'is heavy' or 'is green,' I am using language that purports to report the real properties of real things. When I say 'feels heavy' or 'looks green,' I am not committing myself to any statement about the objective properties of things but, on the contrary, am limiting my statement to impressions made on me. Hence it is quite possible for one to say that, while he does not know whether or not the field really is green, at least it appears green to him. Knowledge of appearance, then, is one thing; and knowledge of reality is another. (Fs) (notabene)

216c Now what does Jack know when he looks at his hand? What does Jill know when she looks at hers? Two answers are possible, so Jack may say that his hand is out there in front of his face, and Jill may say that her hand at least seems to be out there in front of her face. Nor is the difference between the two answers difficult to detect. When Jack says 'is,' he is not reporting what he knows by sight alone; he also has made a judgment; he has added Denken to Anschauen. When Jill says 'seems,' she is limiting her report to what is known by sight alone; the act of reporting involves thought and judgment; but what is reported is simply and solely what is known by her seeing, the appearance of a hand in front of her face. (Fs) (notabene)

217a No less than the naive realist, the idealist is capable of generalization and deduction. As sight, so also hearing, smelling, tasting, touching are constitutive, not of knowledge of reality, but only of knowledge of appearances. What is true of outer sense also is true of inner sense: by our consciousness we know, not our reality, but only its appearance. Hence, when we inquire, understand, think, we have only appearances to investigate, to understand, to think about. When we judge, our judgments must be based, not on things themselves, but only on their appearance. There is no way in which knowledge of reality could creep into our cognitional operations. Hence all our statements must be modified with the qualification, 'as far as appearances go.' To say that men commonly do not add that qualification or that they are not ready to admit it even when its necessity is demonstrated, is just another way of saying that they suffer from a transcendental illusion. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Der kritische Realist; Denken in Bildern; Bilderwelt - Ausstreckung auf das Sein (intention of being)

Kurzinhalt: ... objective knowledge of reality in looking, perceiving, Anschauung? It is because their world is a picture world. If their world were the universe of being ...; ex umbris et imaginibus in veritatem

Textausschnitt: 218a Against the idealist of the type in question the critical realist maintains that sense does not know appearances. It is just as much a matter of judgment to know that an object is not real but apparent, as it is to know that an object is not apparent but real. Sense does not know appearances, because sense alone is not human knowing, and because sense alone does not possess the full objectivity of human knowing. By our senses we are given, not appearance, not reality, but data. By our consciousness, which is not an inner sense, we are given, not appearance, not reality, but data. Further, while it is true enough that data of sense result in us from the action of external objects, it is not true that we know this by sense alone; we know it as we know anything else, by experiencing, understanding, and judging. Again, it is not true that it is from sense that our cognitional activities derive their immediate relationship to real objects; that relationship is immediate in the intention of being; it is mediate in the data of sense and in the data of consciousness inasmuch as the intention of being makes use of data in promoting cognitional process to knowledge of being; similarly, that relationship is mediate in understanding and thought and judgment, because these activities stand to the originating intention of being as answers stand to questions. (Fs)

218b Finally, against both the naive realist and the idealist of the types in question, the critical realist urges the charge of picture thinking. Why does the naive realist ground objective knowledge of reality in looking, perceiving, Anschauung? Why does the idealist assert that it is by Anschauung that our cognitional activities have their immediate relationship to objects?1 It is because their world is a picture world. If their world were the universe of being, they would agree that the original relationship of cognitional activity to the universe of being must lie in the intention of being. But their world is a picture world; the original relationship of cognitional activity to the picture is the look; and so it is in looking that the naive realist finds revealed the essence of objectivity, and it is in Anschauung that the critical idealist places the immediate relation of cognitional activity to objects. There exists, then, something like a forgetfulness of being. There exists in man a need for an intellectual conversion ex umbris et imaginibus in veritatem. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Seinsvergessenheit -> Umdeutung der Subjektivität u. Objektivität (abwertend); Gemeinschaft

Kurzinhalt: The forgetfulness of being ... has brought about a semantic reversal. Subjectivity once was a pejorative term; praise of subjectivity seems to imply a condemnation of objectivity

Textausschnitt: Knowing and Living

219a The forgetfulness of being, manifested by naive realists and idealists,l has brought about a semantic reversal. Subjectivity once was a pejorative term;111 it denoted a violation of the normative exigences of intelligence and rationality. But it has come to denote a rejection of misconceived objectivity and a reaffirmation of man's right to be himself even though he cannot untie the hard and intricate knots of philosophy. (Fs)

219b This new usage is not without its own myth, in which Jack and Jill are concerned, not with their hands, but with one another. They look, of course, but much more they talk. They are not merely objects, but also subjects: an 'I' and 'thou' that add up to the single personal total of 'us' talking about 'ourselves' and what 'we' have done and shall do. (Fs) (notabene)

219c Objectivity, as misconceived, is transcended. The problem of the bridge from 'in here' to 'out there' tends to vanish when the whole stress falls on the interpersonal situation,n the psychic interchange of mutual presence, the beginnings of what may prove to be a lifelong union. (Fs) (notabene)

219d Objectivity, as correctly conceived, is by no means rejected. For Jack and Jill are not characters out of a social worker's casebook. They are neither unperceptive, nor stupid, nor silly. If they were, acquaintance would not blossom into friendship, nor friendship into intimacy. (Fs)

219e Still, this recognition of objectivity is only implicit, and, above all, it is not objective knowing but human living o that is the main point. To understand the myth, one has to move beyond strictly cognitional levels of empirical, intellectual, and rational consciousness to the more inclusive level of rational self-consciousness.p Though being and the good are coextensive, the subject moves to a further dimension of consciousness as his concern shifts from knowing being to realizing the good. Now there emerge freedom and responsibility, encounter and trust, communication and belief, choice and promise and fidelity. On this level subjects both constitute themselves and make their world. On this level men are responsible, individually, for the lives they lead and, collectively, for the world in which they lead them. It is in this collective responsibility for common or complementary action that resides the principal constituent of the collective subject referred to by 'we,' 'us,' 'ourselves,' 'ours.' (Fs) (notabene)
Kommentar (06/11/05): Wichtige Stelle oben -> Gemeinschaft
219f The condition of possibility of the collective subject is communication, and the principal communication is not saying what we know but showing what we are. To say what one knows presupposes the labor of coming to know. But to show what one is, it is enough to be it; showing will follow; every movement, every word, every deed, reveal what the subject is. They reveal it to others, and the others, in the self-revelation that is their response, obliquely reveal to the intelligent subject what he is. In the main it is not by introspection but by reflecting on our living in common with others that we come to know ourselves. (Fs)

220a What is revealed? It is an original creation. Freely the subject makes himself what he is; never in this life is the making finished; always it is still in process, always it is a precarious achievement that can slip and fall and shatter. Concern with subjectivity, then, is concern with the intimate reality of man. It is concern, not with the universal truths that hold whether a man is asleep or awake, not with the interplay of natural factors and determinants, but with the perpetual novelty of self-constitution, of free choices making the chooser what he is. (Fs)

220b Further aspects of the significance of subjectivity are endless, for the intimate reality of man grounds and penetrates all that is human. But the point to be made here is, not to go on insisting on this significance which, commonly enough, is recognized, but to draw attention to a real danger inherent in the semantic reversal that we have noted. For the danger is that the values of subjectivity in its more recent sense will be squandered by subjectivity in its prior and pejorative sense. Unless the two meanings are sharply distinguished, praise of subjectivity seems to imply a condemnation of objectivity. But condemnation of objectivity induces, not a merely incidental blind spot in one's vision, but a radical undermining of authentic human existence. (Fs) (notabene)

220c It is quite true that objective knowing is not yet authentic human living; but without objective knowing there is no authentic living; for one knows objectively just insofar as one is neither unperceptive, nor stupid, nor silly; and one does not live authentically inasmuch as one is either unperceptive or stupid or silly. (Fs)

220d It is quite true that the subject communicates not by saying what he knows but by showing what he is, and it is no less true that subjects are confronted with themselves more effectively by being confronted with others than by solitary introspection. But such facts by themselves only ground a technique for managing people; and managing people is not treating them as persons. To treat them as persons one must know and one must invite them to know. A real exclusion of objective knowing, so far from promoting, only destroys personalist values. (Fs)

221a It is quite true that concern for subjectivity promotes as much objective knowing as men commonly feel ready to absorb. Authentic living includes objective knowing, and far more eagerly do human beings strive for the whole than for the part. Nonetheless it remains that the authentic living of anyone reading this paper, though it must start at home, cannot remain confined within the horizons of the home, the workshop, the village. We are citizens of our countries, men of the twentieth century, members of a universal church. If any authenticity we achieve is to radiate out into our troubled world, we need much more objective knowing than men commonly feel ready to absorb. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Unterschied: Subjekt - Substanz; Drifter

Kurzinhalt: The first distinction is between substance and subject; drifter

Textausschnitt: The Subject

222c
1 The first distinction is between substance and subject.g When one is sound asleep, one is actually a substance and only potentially a subject. To be a subject, one at least must dream. But the dreamer is only the minimal subject: one is more a subject when one is awake, still more when one is actively intelligent, still more when one actively is reasonable, still more in one's deliberations and decisions when one actively is responsible and free. (Fs)

223a Of the human substance it is true that human nature is always the same; a man is a man whether he is awake or asleep, young or old, sane or crazy, sober or drunk, a genius or a moron, a saint or a sinner. From the viewpoint of substance, those differences are merely accidental. But they are not accidental to the subject, for the subject is not an abstraction; he is a concrete reality, all of him, a being in the luminousness of being. (Fs)

223b Substance prescinds from the difference between the opaque being that is merely substance and the luminous beingh that is conscious. Subject denotes the luminous being. (Fs)

223c
2 The being of the subject is becoming. One becomes oneself. When I was a child, I was a subject; but I had not yet reached the use of reason; I was not expected to be able to draw reasonably the elementary distinctions between right and wrong, true and false. When I was a boy, I was a subject; but I was a minor; I had not reached the degree of freedom and responsibility that would make me accountable before the law. The self I am today is not numerically different from the self I was as a child or boy; yet it is qualitatively different. Were it not, you would not be listening to me. Were you yourselves not, I would not be talking to you in this way. (Fs)

223d
3 The subject has more and more to do with his own becoming. When an adult underestimates a child's development and tries to do for the child what the child can do for itself, the child will resent the interference and exclaim, 'Let me do it.' Development is a matter of increasing the number of things that one does for oneself, that one decides for oneself, that one finds out for oneself. Parents and teachers and professors and superiors let people do more and more for themselves, decide more and more for themselves, find out more and more for themselves. (Fs)

223e
4 There is a critical point in the increasing autonomy of the subject. It is reached when the subject finds out for himself that it is up to himself to decide what he is to make of himself.i At first sight doing for oneself, deciding for oneself, finding out for oneself, are busy with objects. But on reflection it appears that deeds, decisions, discoveries affect the subject more deeply than they affect the objects with which they are concerned. They accumulate as dispositions and habits of the subject; they determine him; they make him what he is and what he is to be. (Fs)

223f The self in the first period makes itself; but in a second period this making oneself is open-eyed, deliberate. Autonomy decides what autonomy is to be. (Fs)

224a The opposite to this open-eyed, deliberate self-control is drifting. The drifter has not yet found himself; he has not yet discovered his own deed, and so is content to do what everyone else is doing; he has not yet discovered his own will, and so he is content to choose what everyone else is choosing; he has not yet discovered a mind of his own, and so he is content to think and say what everyone else is thinking and saying; and the others too are apt to be drifters, each of them doing and choosing and thinking and saying what others happen to be doing, choosing, thinking, saying. (Fs)
224b I have spoken of an opposite to drifting, of autonomy disposing of itself, of open-eyed, deliberate self-control. But I must not misrepresent. We do not know ourselves very well; we cannot chart the future; we cannot control our environment completely or the influences that work on us; we cannot explore our unconscious and preconscious mechanisms. Our course is in the night; our control is only rough and approximate; we have to believe and trust, to risk and dare. (Fs)

224c
5 In this life the critical point is never transcended. It is one thing to decide what one is to make of oneself: a Catholic, a religious, a Jesuit, a priest. It is another to execute the decision. Today's resolutions do not predetermine the free choice of tomorrow, of next week or next year, of ten years from now. What has been achieved is always precarious: it can slip, fall, shatter. What is to be achieved can be ever expanding, deepening. To meet one challenge is to effect a development that reveals a further and graver challenge. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Sünde der Moderne: Selbstbestimmung als Fundament; Jaspers

Kurzinhalt: The sin of modernity ... It is the fully deliberate and permanently intended determination to be oneself

Textausschnitt: 228a ... From that enormous development the church has held off: it could praise the ends; it could not accept the means; and so it could not authentically participate in the process that eliminated the standardized man of classicist thought and ushered in the historical consciousness t of today. (Fs)

228b Modern man has created his states and his sciences, his philosophies and his histories, his cultures and his literatures, on the basis of absolute autonomy. There is human intelligence, human reasonableness, human responsibility, and that is all there is. To speak of God is at best irrelevant; to turn to God - except by way of political gesture or emotional outlet - is to sacrifice the good we know and by our own resources can attain. (Fs) (notabene)

228c Karl Jaspers repeats from Kierkegaard, or perhaps from Nietzsche, that unless I sinned, I could not be myself. The sin of modernity u is not any sin of frailty, any transient lapse, any lack of advertence or consent. It is the fully deliberate and permanently intended determination to be oneself, to attain the perfection proper to man, and to liberate humanity from the heavy hand of ecclesiastical tradition, ecclesiastical interference, ecclesiastical refusal to allow human beings to grow and be themselves. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Erlösung - Sünde; komplexe Intelligibilität (imaginäre Zahlen)

Kurzinhalt: Sin is not something that is understood.... It is the irrationality of a rational creature. ... transcendent intelligibility of God meeting the unintelligibility of sin

Textausschnitt: 3.4 A Complex Intelligibility

12a Again, the redemption is not a simple but a complex intelligibility; and I use the word 'complex' in the sense that the mathematician speaks of 'complex numbers.' The mathematician uses not only rational but also irrational numbers, not only real numbers but also imaginary numbers. And everything goes well, provided he does not mix them up, provided he does not consider that they are all numbers in exactly the same sense and manner. Similarly with regard to the redemption, we must not think of it as something that will fall into a single intelligible pattern. There is in this world the unintelligibility of sin. Sin is not something that is understood. It is not something for which you can give a reason. Why did the angels sin? Why did our first parents sin? Strictly, if there were a reason why, not simply a pretense or an excuse, it would not have been a sin. Sin represents a surd. It is the irrationality of a rational creature. It is not something that arises because God wants it to arise. To think of it that way is to think of it as though it were something intelligible, something that admitted an explanation. Everything that is, everything that is intelligible, has an explanation. But sin is not something that is; it is a failure. It is not something that is intelligible; it is an irrational. And so St Thomas can say that God in no manner whatever wills the evil of guilt, that is, the pure element that is simply sin and nothing more. God in no manner whatever wills sin, and only indirectly does God will the evil of natural defects or of penalties, punishments. The divine will regards the good. The divine will permits sin. The divine will, as a consequence of willing an orderly universe, indirectly wills the accidents of natural defect and the natural consequences of sin. Consequently, in thinking about the redemption one must make an effort - and it requires an effort - to avoid the tendency to think that an explanation casts everything one can think of into a single intelligible pattern. It does that insofar as what one is considering is intelligible, has a reason. But the redemption regards sin, it presupposes sin, and it is the transformation of the situation created by sin. Consequently, in a consideration of the redemption one has to have in mind the existence not of a simple intelligibility but of the transcendent intelligibility of God meeting the
unintelligibility of sin. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Erlösung; vielfältige Intelligibilität

Kurzinhalt: William of Auvergne; It is like an empirical law, not like a mathematical theory. In the second place, it is not a static but a dynamic intelligibility.And finally, it is not an intelligibility that can be put in a single formula ...

Textausschnitt: 13b Such, then, are the general characteristics, the precautions that one must take, I think, in seeking a total view of the redemption. There is an intelligibility to be grasped, but that intelligibility is not a necessity. It is an expression of what God thought wise, what God thought good, and that is intelligible, but it is not an expression of what simply had to be. It is like an empirical law, not like a mathematical theory. In the second place, it is not a static but a dynamic intelligibility. It has to do with the reversal of roles: the death that is the consequence of sin becomes the means of salvation. In the third place, it is not an abstract but an incarnate intelligibility. It resides in the love Christ manifested to us and the effects of that love on us. In the fourth place, it is not a simple but a complex intelligibility; it includes the surd. There are elements to it, namely sin, that are simply nonintelligible, and there are consequences to sin that have, as it were, a devaluated intelligibility. And finally, it is not an intelligibility that can be put in a single formula but one that exhibits many aspects. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Erlösung; Opfer - Wortgebrauch: Septuaginta, klassisches Griechisch

Kurzinhalt: One meaning was used uniformly in the Septuagint, and the other in classical Greek. In classical Greek the word hilaskesthai means to placate the gods,

Textausschnitt: 15a First of all, the death of Christ is conceived as a sacrifice. That conception is recurrent in St Paul. 'Christ our Pasch has been sacrificed' (1 Corinthians 5.7). Again, 'Christ offered himself up as a sacrifice of sweet odor' (Ephesians 5.2). It occurs, implicitly at least, in the statements in the synoptic Gospels and in 1 Corinthians, chapter 11, on the institution of the Eucharist: 'This is my body which is given for you; this is my blood which is to be shed for you for the remission of sin.' But above all it is in the Epistle to the Hebrews that the death of Christ is presented as a sacrifice. Chapters 1 to 3 are devoted to presenting the new mediator between God and man. And a contrast is set up with Moses, who gave the old law. Chapters 5 and 7 are concerned with the new priesthood, chapter 8 with the new covenant, the new testament, chapters 9 and 10 with the sacrifice of the new law, which is the sacrifice of the death of Christ and the perpetual intercession of Christ for us before God. To go into details of the conception of the death of Christ as a sacrifice would be an enormous task. I could not even begin to enumerate the texts of the scripture relevant to it. But it is a conception of which no doubt whatever can be entertained by a Catholic. (Fs)

15b However, the precise sense in which there is a sacrifice raises a question that has to do with the meaning of the Greek word hilaskesthai. On the meaning of that word, C.H. Dodd, a professor at Cambridge University, in The Journal of Theological Studies, about 1931, drew attention to the fact that the usage of the word in classical Greek was quite different from that in the Greek translation of the Old Testament, the Septuagint. The root of the word permitted two different meanings. One meaning was used uniformly in the Septuagint, and the other in classical Greek. In classical Greek the word hilaskesthai means to placate the gods, to avert their anger or vengeance. In the Septuagint, hilaskesthai conveys the meaning of something that removes sin, that puts aside a barrier that prevents man's access to God. As you can see, the nuance in the different meanings of hilaskesthai has considerable difference of implications for religious thought and religious feeling. The implications for the interpretation of the New Testament in some aspects are quite certain, in others less so. A clear example of hilaskesthai used in the sense of the removal of sins occurs in Hebrews 2.17, where it is stated that Christ became priest in order to hilaskesthai the sins of the people - in the Vulgate propitiaret delicta populi. Hilaskesthai is an action exercised upon sin, and that is the Septuagint meaning of the word. It is not an action exercised upon the feelings of a god, as in the rites of pagan Greece. (Fs) (notabene)
16a Another point to be noted about the interpretation or understanding of the redemption, the death and resurrection of Christ, in terms of sacrifice is that, on the one hand, the connection of sacrifice with liturgy, with prayer, with the piety of the people of God makes it an extremely helpful mode of thought, an aspect of the intelligibility of the death and resurrection of Christ, while on the other hand, because sacrifice is not traditionally, not in any but the most barbarous religions, human sacrifice - but the sacrifice of Christ is in his own blood - clearly the notion of sacrifice is not an intelligibility that exhausts the meaning of the redemption. A ritual meaning such as is connoted, a liturgical meaning such as is suggested, by the name 'sacrifice,' while it conveys enormously the aspect of personal relations between the sinner and God, still does not exhaust the meaning of the reality, insofar as Christ's sacrifice was not simply a ritual act, but his own suffering and death and glorious resurrection.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Das Problem der Befreiung

Kurzinhalt: The Problem of Liberation; Essentially the problem lies in an incapacity for sustained development. The tension divides and disorientates cognitional activity by ...

Textausschnitt: 653a The elements in the problem are basically simple. Man's intelligence, reasonableness, and willingness
(1) proceed from a detached, disinterested, unrestricted desire to know,
(2) are potentialities in process of development towards a full effective freedom,
(3) supply the higher integration for otherwise coincidental manifolds on successively underlying psychic, organic, chemical, and physical levels,
(4) stand in opposition and tension with sensitive and intersubjective attachment, interest, and exclusiveness, and
(5) suffer from that tension a cumulative bias that increasingly distorts immanent development, its outward products, and the outer conditions under which the immanent development occurs. (Fs) (notabene)

653b Essentially the problem lies in an incapacity for sustained development. The tension divides and disorientates cognitional activity by the conflict of positions and counterpositions. This conflict issues into contrary views of the good, which in turn make good will appear misdirected, and misdirected will appear good. There follows the confounding of the social situation with the social surd to provide misleading inspiration for further insights, deceptive evidence for further judgments, and illusory causes to fascinate unwary wills. (Fs) (notabene)

653c The problem is radical, for it is a problem in the very dynamic structure of cognitional, volitional, and social activity. It is not a question of error on this or that general or particular issue. It is a question of orientation, approach, procedure, method. It affects concretely every issue, both general and particular, for it recurs with every use of the dynamic structure. (Fs)

654a The problem is permanent. It vanishes if one supposes man's intelligence, reasonableness, and willingness not to be potentialities in process of development but already in possession of the insights that make learning superfluous, of the reasonableness that makes judgments correct, of the willingness that makes persuasion unnecessary. Again, it vanishes if one supposes the elimination of the tension and opposition between the detached, disinterested, unrestricted desire to know and, on the other hand, attached, interested, and narrow sensitivity and intersubjectivity. But in fact both development and tension pertain to the very nature of man, and as long as they exist the problem remains in full force. (Fs) (notabene)
654b The problem is independent of the underlying manifolds. No doubt, if the underlying manifolds were different, the higher cognitional and volitional integration would differ in its content. But such a change of content would leave the dynamic structure of the higher integration unmodified; and it is in the structure that the problem resides. It follows that neither physics nor chemistry nor biology nor sensitive psychology can bring forth devices that go to the root of the trouble. (Fs) (notabene)

654c The problem is not primarily social. It results in the social surd. It receives from the social surd its continuity, its aggravation, its cumulative character. But its root is elsewhere. Hence it is that a revolution can sweep away old evils and initiate a fresh effort; but the fresh effort will occur through the same dynamic structure as the old effort and lead to essentially the same results. (Fs) (notabene)
654d The problem is not to discover a correct philosophy, ethics, or human science. For such discoveries are quite compatible with the continued existence of the problem. The correct philosophy can be but one of many philosophies, the correct ethics one of many ethical systems, the correct human science an old or new view among many views. But precisely because they are correct, they will not appear correct to minds disorientated by the conflict between positions and counterpositions. Precisely because they are correct, they will not appear workable to wills with restricted ranges of effective freedom. Precisely because they are correct, they will be weak competitors for serious attention in the realm of practical affairs. (Fs) (notabene)

654e The problem is not met by setting up a benevolent despotism to enforce a correct philosophy, ethics, or human science. No doubt, if there is to be the appeal to force, then it is better that the force be directed by wisdom than by folly, by benevolence than by malevolence. But the appeal to force is a counsel of despair. So far from solving the problem, it regards the problem as insoluble. For if men are intelligent, reasonable, and willing, they do not have to be forced. Only in the measure that men are unintelligent, unreasonable, unwilling, does force enter into human affairs. Finally, if force can be used by the group against the wayward individual and by the larger group against the smaller, it does not follow that it can be used to correct the general bias of common sense. For the general bias of common sense is the bias of all men, and to a notable extent it consists in the notion that ideas are negligible unless they are reinforced by sensitive desires and fears. Is everyone to use force against everyone to convince everyone that force is beside the point? (Fs) (notabene)

655a The problem is real. In the present work it has been reached in the compendious fashion that operates through the integral heuristic structure of proportionate being and the consequent ethics. But the expeditiousness of the procedure must not be allowed to engender the mistake that the problem resides in some theoretical realm. On the contrary, its dimensions are the dimensions of human history, and the fourth, fifth, and sixth volumes of Arnold Toynbee's Study of History illustrate abundantly and rather relevantly the failure of self-determination, the schism in the body social, and the schism in the soul that follow from an incapacity for sustained development. (Fs)

655b The solution has to be a still higher integration of human living. For the problem is radical and permanent; it is independent of the underlying physical, chemical, organic, and psychic manifolds; it is not met by revolutionary change, nor by human discovery, nor by the enforced implementation of discovery; it is as large as human living and human history. Further, the solution has to take people just as they are. If it is to be a solution and not a mere suppression of the problem, it has to acknowledge and respect and work through man's intelligence and reasonableness and freedom. It may eliminate neither development nor tension yet it must be able to replace incapacity by capacity for sustained development. Only a still higher integration can meet such requirements. For only a higher integration leaves underlying manifolds with their autonomy yet succeeds in introducing a higher systematization into their nonsystematic coincidences. And only a still higher integration than any that so far has been considered can deal with the dialectical

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Ethik: dynamische Struktur des Wissens als Grundlage von Metaphysik und Ethik

Kurzinhalt: For just as the dynamic structure of our knowing grounds a metaphysics, so the prolongation of that structure into human doing grounds an ethics

Textausschnitt: 626a There follows a conclusion of fundamental importance, namely, the parallel and interpenetration of metaphysics and ethics. For just as the dynamic structure of our knowing grounds a metaphysics, so the prolongation of that structure into human doing grounds an ethics. Just as the universe of proportionate being is a compound of potency, form, and act, because it is to be known through experience, understanding, and judgment, so the universe of man's proportionate good is a compound of objects of desire, intelligible orders, and values, because the good that man does intelligently and rationally is a manifold in the field of experience, ordered by intelligence, and rationally chosen. Just as metaphysics is a set of positions opposed by sets of counterpositions that arise from the incomplete domination in knowing of the detached and disinterested desire to know, so also values are true and false, orders are troubled by disorders, and desires are unnecessarily frustrated, because the detachment and disinterestedness of the pure desire easily fails to develop into fully rational self-consciousness. Just as the counterpositions of metaphysics invite their own reversal by their inconsistency with intelligent and reasonable affirmation, so the basically similar counterpositions of the ethical order, through the shorter and longer cycles of the dialectic of progress and decline, either enforce their own reversal or destroy their carriers. Just as the heuristic structure of our knowing couples with the generalized emergent probability of the proportionate universe, to reveal an upwardly directed dynamism of finality towards ever fuller being, so the obligatory structure of our rational self-consciousness
(1) finds its materials and its basis in the products of universal finality,
(2) is itself finality on the level of intelligent and rational consciousness, and
(3) is finality confronted with the alternative of choosing either development and progress or decline and extinction. (Fs)

626b The theme of the parallel and interpenetration of metaphysics and ethics cannot be expanded further in the present context, but at least something must be said on its methodological ground. We refused to conceive metaphysical method either as an abstract or as a concrete or as a transcendental deduction, not because we denied the exposition of a metaphysics to make use of the deductive form, but because we placed the principles of metaphysics neither in sentences nor in propositions nor in judgments but in the very structure of our knowing. Because that structure is latent and operative in everyone's knowing, it is universal on the side of the subject; and because that structure can be distorted by the interference of alien desires, it grounds a dialectical criticism of subjects. Again, because that structure is employed in every instance of knowing, it is universal on the side of the proportionate object; and because the structure remains dynamic until all questions are answered, it regards every proportionate object concretely. Accordingly, metaphysical method can take subjects as they are, invoke dialectical criticism to bring their fundamental orientations into agreement, and apply this agreement to the whole domain of proportionate being in its concreteness. But essentially the same method is available for ethics. Deductivism is brushed aside, not because there are no universally valid precepts, nor because conclusions do not follow from them,b but because the most basic precepts with all their conclusions fail to go to the root of the matter. For the root of ethics, as the root of metaphysics, lies neither in sentences nor in propositions nor in judgments but in the dynamic structure of rational self-consciousness. Because that structure is latent and operative in everyone's choosing, it is universal on the side of the subject; because that structure can be dodged, it grounds a dialectical criticism of subjects. Again, because that structure is recurrent in every act of choice, it is universal on the side of the object;c and because its universality consists not in abstraction but in inevitable recurrence, it also is concrete. Accordingly, ethical method, as metaphysical, can take subjects as they are; it can correct any aberration in their views by a dialectical criticism; and it can apply these corrected views to the totality of concrete objects of choice. Such a method not only sets forth precepts but also bases them on their real principles, which are not propositions or judgments but existing persons; it not only sets forth correct precepts but also provides a radical criticism for mistaken precepts; it is not content to appeal to logic for the application of precepts, for it can criticize situations as well as subjects, and it can invoke dialectical analysis to reveal how situations are to be corrected; finally, because such a method clearly grasps an unchanging dynamic structure immanent in developing subjects that deal with changing situations in correspondingly changing manners, it can steer a sane course between the relativism of mere con-creteness and the legalism of remote and static generalities; and it can do so, not by good luck nor by vaguely postulating prudence, but methodically, because it takes its stand on the ever recurrent dynamic generality that is the structure of rational self-consciousness. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Ethik; Hedonist: Position - Gegenposition

Kurzinhalt: ... a quite coherent position, as long as no claim is made that it is either intelligent or reasonable.

Textausschnitt: 629c Feelings and sentiments are bypassed for, though one begins from objects of desire, one finds the potential good not in them alone but in the total manifold of the universe. This step does not suppose the discovery of some calculus to measure pleasure and pain, nor does it introduce any claim that the pleasure outweighs the pain. Quite simply it notes that objects of desire are manifold, that this manifold, so far from being isolated, is part and parcel of the total manifold, and that it is in the total manifold that concretely and effectively the potential good resides. Now it is to this first step that the hedonist or sentimentalist must object. He must claim that the meaning of the term 'good' is settled on the unquestioning and unquestionable level of experience, that the good has to be the good as experienced, and that opposite to the good there is the no less real category of evil as experienced. Moreover, the foregoing is a quite coherent position, as long as no claim is made that it is either intelligent or reasonable. The trouble is that the claim cannot be avoided, and once it is made the contradiction becomes obvious; for it is only by excluding the relevance of questions for intelligence and reflection that the good can be identified with objects of desire; and if such questions are excluded, then intelligence and reasonableness are excluded. On the other hand, if the determination of the notion of the good is a matter of intelligent inquiry and critical reflection, then critical reflection's affirmation will be knowledge of the actual component of the good, intelligent inquiry's explanation will be knowledge d of the formal component of the good, the manifold of objects of desire can be no more than a potential good, and the way is open to the discovery that the manifold of indifferent objects and even the manifold of objects of aversion also are a potential good. Finally, to throw in the obvious methodological note, the positions and counterpositions of metaphysics not only have their prolongations into ethics but also these prolongations respectively invite development or invite reversal by the same dialectical procedures as the metaphysical originals. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Freiheit; Unterschied: Gesetz d. Materie - d. Geistes

Kurzinhalt: ... they differ radically from the laws of matter, not only in their higher point of application, but also in their nature and content

Textausschnitt: 641a At this point, however, there crops up the ambiguity of the notion of law. There are, then, the laws of matter and the laws of spirit.e The laws of matter are investigated by empirical scientists, and when spirit is said to be legislative, one means that spirit originates intelligible orders that are parallel to the intelligibilities investigated by empirical scientists. On the other hand, the laws of spirit are the principles and norms that govern spirit in the exercise of its legislative function; and they differ radically from the laws of matter, not only in their higher point of application, but also in their nature and content. As has been seen, the laws of matter are abstract, and they can be applied concretely only by the addition of further determinations from a nonsystematic manifold. But the laws of spirit reside in the dynamic structure of its cognitional and volitional operations, and their concrete application is effected through spirit's own operations within that dynamic structure. Thus, in working out the notion of the good, we discovered in the rationally self-conscious subject an exigence for consistency between his knowing and his doing, and we saw how a body of ethical precepts could be derived simply by asking what concretely was implicit in that exigence. As metaphysics is a corollary to the structure of knowing, so ethics is a corollary to the structure of knowing and doing; and as ethics resides in the structure, so the concrete applications of ethics are worked out by spirit inasmuch as it operates within the structure to reflect and decide upon the possible courses of action that it grasps. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Freiheit als besondere Form der Kontingenz; Verantwortung

Kurzinhalt: Freedom, then, is a special kind of contingence. It is contingence that arises, not from the empirical residue that grounds materiality and the nonsystematic, but in the order of spirit, ...

Textausschnitt: 641b It follows that there is a radical difference between the contingence of the act of willing and the general contingence of existence and occurrence in the rest of the domain of proportionate being. The latter contingence falls short of strict intelligible necessity, not because it is free, but because it is involved in the nonsystematic character of material multiplicity, continuity, and frequency. But the contingence of the act of will,f so far from resulting from the nonsystematic, arises in the imposition of further intelligible order upon otherwise merely coincidental manifolds. Moreover, that imposition of further intelligible order is the work of intelligence, of rational reflection, and of ethically guided will. Nonetheless, that imposition of intelligible order is contingent. For, on the one hand, even when possibility is unique, so that rational consciousness has no alternative, still the unique possibility is not realized necessarily. To claim that the sole reasonable course of action is realized necessarily is to claim that willing is necessarily consistent with knowing. But that claim is preposterous, for it contradicts the common experience of a divergence between what one does and what one knows one ought to do. Nor is it preposterous merely in fact but also in principle, for actual consistency between knowing and deciding is the result of deciding reasonably, and what results from deciding reasonably cannot be erected into a universal principle that proves all decisions to be necessarily reasonable. (Fs) (notabene)

642a Freedom, then, is a special kind of contingence. It is contingence that arises, not from the empirical residue that grounds materiality and the nonsystematic, but in the order of spirit, of intelligent grasp, rational reflection, and morally guided will. It has the twofold basis that its object is merely a possibility and that its agent is contingent not only in his existence but also in the extension of his rational consciousness into rational self-consciousness. For it is one and the same act of willing that both decides in favor of the object or against it and that constitutes the subject as deciding reasonably or unreasonably, as succeeding or failing in the extension of rational consciousness into an effectively rational self-consciousness. (Fs) (notabene)

642b Accordingly, freedom possesses not only the negative aspect of excluding necessity but also the positive aspect of responsibility. Intelligent grasp of a possible course of action need not result automatically in its execution, for critical reflection can intervene to scrutinize the object and evaluate the motives. Critical reflection cannot execute the proposed action, for it is simply a knowing. Knowing cannot necessitate the decision, for consistency between knowing and willing becomes an actuality only through the willing. The decision, then, is not a consequent but a new emergence that both realizes the course of action or rejects it, and realizes an effectively rational self-consciousness or fails to do so. Nonetheless, though the act of will is a contingent emergence, it also is an act of the subject; the measure of the freedom with which the act occurs also is the measure of his responsibility for it. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Moralische Impotenz; positiver, negativer Aspekt

Kurzinhalt: To assert moral impotence is to assert that man's effective freedom is restricted ... in the profound fashion that follows from incomplete intellectual and volitional development.

Textausschnitt: 650a To assert moral impotence is to assert that man's effective freedom is restricted, not in the superficial fashion that results from external circumstance or psychic abnormality, but in the profound fashion that follows from incomplete intellectual and volitional development. For when that development is incomplete, there are practical insights that could be had if a man took time out to acquire the necessary preparatory insights, and there are courses of action that would be chosen if a man took time out to persuade himself to willingness. There follows a gap between the proximate effective freedom he actually possesses and, on the other hand, the remote and hypothetical effective freedom that he would possess if certain conditions happened to be fulfilled. Now this gap measures one's moral impotence. For complete self-development is a long and difficult process. During that process one has to live and make decisions in the light of one's undeveloped intelligence and under the guidance of one's incomplete willingness. And the less developed one is, the less one appreciates the need of development and the less one is willing to take time out for one's intellectual and moral education. (Fs)

650b Moreover, as the scotosis of the dramatic subject, so the moral impotence of the essentially free subject is neither grasped with perfect clarity nor totally unconscious.i For if one were to represent a man's field of freedom as a circular area, then one would distinguish a luminous central region in which he was effectively free, a surrounding penumbra in which his uneasy conscience keeps suggesting that he could do better if only he would make up his mind, and finally an outer shadow to which he barely if ever adverts. Further, these areas are not fixed; as he develops, the penumbra penetrates into the shadow and the luminous area into the penumbra while, inversely, moral decline is a contraction of the luminous area and of the penumbra. Finally, this consciousness of moral impotence not only heightens the tension between limitation and transcendence but also can provide ambivalent materials for reflection; correctly interpreted, it brings home to man the fact that his living is a developing, that he is not to be discouraged by his failures, that rather he is to profit by them both as lessons on his personal weaknesses and as a stimulus to greater efforts; but the same data can also be regarded as evidence that there is no use trying, that moral codes ask the impossible, that one has to be content with oneself as one is. (Fs) (notabene)

650c This inner tension and its ambivalence are reflected and heightened in the social sphere. For rational self-consciousness demands consistency between knowing and doing not only in the individual but also in the common concerns of the group. To the ethics of the individual conscience there is added an ethical transformation of the home, of the technological expansion, of the economy, and of the polity. But just as individual intelligence and individual reasonableness lead to the individual decisions that may be right or wrong, so too common intelligence and common reasonableness lead to common decisions that may be right or wrong. Moreover, in both cases, decisions are right not because they are the pronouncements of the individual conscience, nor because they proceed from this or that type of social mechanism for reaching common decisions, but because they are in the concrete situation intelligent and reasonable. Again, in both cases, decisions are wrong, not because of their private or public origin, but because they diverge from the dictates of intelligence and reasonableness. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Moralische Impotenz; dreifache Befangenheit

Kurzinhalt: Now, as has been seen, common sense is subject to a threefold bias. Accordingly, we can expect that individual decisions will be likely to suffer from individual bias, ...

Textausschnitt: 651a Now, as has been seen, common sense is subject to a threefold bias. Accordingly, we can expect that individual decisions will be likely to suffer from individual bias, that common decisions will be likely to suffer from the various types of group bias, and that all decisions will be likely to suffer from general bias. There will result conflicts between the individual and the group, between economic and national groups within the state, and between states. But far more significant than these relatively superficial and overt conflicts will be the underlying opposition that general bias sets up between the decisions that intelligence and reasonableness would demand and the actual decisions, individual and common, that are made. For this opposition is both profound and unnoticed. As individuals, so societies fail to distinguish sharply and accurately between positions and counterpositions. As individuals, so societies fail to reach the universal willingness that reflects and sustains the detachment and disinterestedness of the unrestricted desire to know. More or less automatically and unconsciously, each successive batch of possible and practical courses of action is screened to eliminate as unpractical whatever does not seem practical to an intelligence and a willingness that not only are developed imperfectly but also suffer from bias. But the social situation is the cumulative product of individual and group decisions, and as these decisions depart from the demands of intelligence and reasonableness, so the social situation becomes, like the complex number, a compound of the rational and irrational. Then if it is to be understood, it must be met by a parallel compound of direct and inverse insights, of direct insights that grasp its intelligibility and of inverse insights that grasp its lack of intelligibility. Nor is it enough to understand the situation; it must also be managed. Its intelligible components have to be encouraged towards fuller development; and its unintelligible components have to be hurried to their reversal. (Fs)

652a Still, this is only the outer aspect of the problem. Just as the social situation with its objective surd proceeds from minds and wills that oscillate between the positions and the counterpositions, so too it constitutes the materials for their practical insights, the conditions to be taken into account in their reflection, the reality to be maintained and developed by their decisions. Just as there are philosophies that take their stand upon the positions and urge the development of the intelligible components in the situation and the reversal of the unintelligible components, so too there are counterphilosophies that take their stand upon the counterpositions, that welcome the unintelligible components in the situation as objective facts that provide the empirical proof of their views, that demand the further expansion of the objective surd, and that clamor for the complete elimination of the intelligible components that they regard as wicked survivals of antiquated attitudes. But philosophies and counterphilosophies are for the few. Like Mercutio, the average man imprecates a plague on both their houses. What he wants is peace and prosperity. By his own light he selects what he believes is the intelligent and reasonable but practical course of action; and as that practicality is the root of the trouble, the civilization drifts through successive less comprehensive syntheses to the sterility of the objectively unintelligible situation and to the coercion of economic pressures, political forces, and psychological conditioning. (Fs)

652b Clearly, both the outward conditions and the inner mentality prevalent in social decline intensify to the point of desperation the tension, inherent in all development but conscious in man, between limitation and transcendence. One can agree with Christian praise of charity, with Kant's affirmation that the unqualified good is the good will, with existentialist exhortations to genuineness. But good will is never better than the intelligence and reasonableness that it implements. Indeed, when proposals and programs only putatively are intelligent and reasonable, then the good will that executes them so faithfully and energetically is engaged really in the systematic imposition of ever further evils on the already weary shoulders of mankind. And who will tell which proposals and programs truly are intelligent and reasonable, and which are not? For the only transition from the analytic proposition to the analytic principle is through concrete judgments of fact, and alas, the facts are ambivalent. The objective situation is all fact, but partly it is the product of intelligence and reasonableness, and partly it is the product of aberration from them. The whole of man is all fact, but it also is malleable, polymorphic fact. No doubt, a subtle and protracted analysis can bring to light the components in that polymorphic fact and proceed to a dialectical criticism of any proposal or program. But to whom does it bring the light? To how many? How clearly and how effectively? Are philosophers to be kings or kings to learn philosophy? Are they to rule in the name of wisdom subjects judged incapable of wisdom? Are all the members of our democracies to be philosophers? Is there to be a provisional dictatorship while they are learning philosophy? (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Fünf Regeln: Verstehe, verstehe systematisch -> Urteil; rationales Bewusstsein (Augustin, Thomas: geschaffene Teilname am ungeschaffenen Licht)

Kurzinhalt: My first two rules - Understand, Understand systematically ... My third and fourth rules - Reverse counterpositions, Develop positions

Textausschnitt: 40a I have been indicating the dimensions of the issue, and now I must attempt to clarify my position. My first two rules - Understand, Understand systematically - yield no more than bright ideas, hypotheses, theories; and none of these is knowledge. Of themselves, they are merely sounding brass and tinkling cymbal. Only when one can go beyond them to affirm their truth, to assert that things are so, does one reach knowledge; and taking that step is a matter of good judgment. My third and fourth rules - Reverse counterpositions, Develop positions - introduce the problem of judgment, inasmuch as they are concerned not merely with the inner coherence of systematic understanding but also with a conversion of the subject that judges. It remains that the four rules together fall short of the present issue. (Fs) (notabene)

40b However, if we ask what good judgment is, I think it will appear that the four rules have a preparatory value. Whenever we understand, we feel called upon to judge; but it is only when we understand not merely the matter in hand but also its relevant context that we can judge well. Children understand many things, but we say that they reach the age of reason when they are about seven years old. A youth understands ever so much more than a child, yet he is accounted a minor in the eyes of the law until he reaches the age of twenty-one. Every cobbler is thought a fair judge, provided he sticks to his last. Finally, the universal principle of good judgment has been named wisdom; because it orders all things, it can judge all; but we must note that philosophy holds itself to be, not wisdom attained, but a love of wisdom and a movement towards it. (Fs)

40c In each of these instances the same feature recurs. Good judgment in a given area is not attained until, within the limits of that area, a certain fulness of understanding is reached. It seems to follow that my rules urging understanding, systematic understanding, and the coherence of systematic understanding head one to the limit where good judgment becomes possible. (Fs)

40d Still, possibility is one thing and actuality another. For judgment demands more than adequately developed understanding. It supposes a transformation of consciousness, an ascent from the eros of intellectual curiosity to the reflective and critical rationality that is the distinguishing mark of man. On that higher level, there becomes operative what Augustine named a contemplation of the eternal reasons, what Aquinas attributed to our created participation of uncreated light, what a modern thinker might designate as rational consciousness. On that level there emerges the proper content of what we mean by truth, reality, knowledge, objectivity; and by the same movement we ourselves in our own reasonableness are involved, for every judgment is at once a personal commitment, an endeavor to determine what is true, and a component in one's apprehension of reality.1 (Fs)
41a However, if I believe that there is no substitute for good judgment, if I believe that method, instead of seeking a substitute, has to make use of good judgment, it is not my intention to entrust the advance of science to the vagaries of individual opinion. No less than those that evade or deny the significance of good judgment, I too believe that a method has to include some technique for overcoming individual, group, and general aberration. Where I would differ is in the technique. I acknowledge the full significance of judgment and its personal element, but my third and fourth rules imply a further judgment on individual judgments. Developing positions and reversing counterpositions are equivalent to judging judgments; and the definitions of positions and counterpositions are based on ultimate philosophic alternatives, that is, on the diverse manners in which individual judgment can go wrong not merely incidentally but in the grand manner of a superficial or a mistaken philosophy. (Fs)
41b It is true, of course, that others may and will disagree with my account of the matter. But from the nature of the case, I think that disagreement in the main will be limited to naming positions what I name counterpositions, and to naming counterpositions what I name positions. There would result a number of distinct schools, but their number could not be very large, their epistemological assumptions and implications would be in the open, and the individuals that chose between them could do so with an adequate awareness of the issues and of their own personal responsibility in judging. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Peter Abaelard: Sic et Non -> Methode d. Questio; Petrus Lombardus

Kurzinhalt: That definition became the basis of a technique that endured for centuries. A proposition was prefaced with the question mark Utrum ...

Textausschnitt: 43a In his Sic et non Peter Abelard listed 158 propositions, and to each of them he appended patristic passages that seemed to show that the proposition was to be both affirmed and denied. This work automatically established two points: negatively, it showed that to settle an issue it was not enough to quote the Fathers of the church; positively, it implied the existence of a department of inquiry in which medieval man was on his own. A slightly later writer, Gilbert de la Porre, gave a particularly clearheaded definition of the existence of a quaestio: a quaestio exists if, and only if, there are good reasons both for affirming and for denying one and the same proposition. That definition became the basis of a technique that endured for centuries. A proposition was prefaced with the question mark Utrum; passages from scripture and from the Fathers were cited in favor of the affirmative and then in favor of the negative answer; to these were added any of the arguments that might be current; then the author gave his solution and closed by applying its principles to each of the quotations or arguments he had begun by citing. (Fs)

43b What was the material basis of these questions? About the year 1150 there appeared Peter Lombard's Quattuor libri sententiarum. It was an ordered compilation of scriptural and patristic passages bearing on Christian doctrine; if it did not emphasize oppositions as did Abelard's less thorough and less learned work, neither did it conceal them. Peter Lombard was something of a positivist, setting forth the data, and repeatedly leaving to the prudens lector the task of reconciliation. For over three centuries commentaries were written by almost every ranking theologian on Peter's Sentences, and the commentaries consisted in an ever growing and changing series of quaestiones. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: "Philosophie von []" (philosophy of []); Philosophie als Liebe zur Weisheit; kein statisches System (geistiges Auge, Universalien); Thomas von Aquin; kein Ausgang von Axiomen, sondern von Grundoperationen

Kurzinhalt: If anyone reads St Thomas, one notices no similarity to Euclidean procedure. He does not start from a set of definitions and axioms,

Textausschnitt: 66b I began with history as a subject, and spoke of occasional history, technical history, explanatory history; now we will move to the topic 'philosophy of [...]' (Fs)

67a One is asked traditionally to think of philosophy absolutely; philosophy is something, it is not of something else; philosophy is logic or epistemology or ontology or psychology or cosmology or ethics or natural theology or preferably all put together; but it is that and nothing more nor less. What is this 'philosophy of ...'? Philosophy of history is one member of a species or genus. There is philosophy of nature, philosophy of science, philosophy of spirit, philosophy of man, philosophy of law, philosophy of religion, philosophy of education, philosophy of art, philosophy of history. What is this 'philosophy of [...]'? (Fs)

67b It is a question that can be given a general answer very easily in traditional terms. Philosophy, as one case of a very explicit and deliberate etymology, means love of wisdom. It is a modest reply to the assertiveness of the Sophists, who proposed to hand out wisdom, while the philosophers had a lot more but did not think that they had got there yet. Wisdom is the ordering of all. And because it is an apprehension of universal order, it is also a potentiality of ultimate judgment. A judgment on anything has to take into account everything that is relevant to that point; and consequently ultimate judgments have to take into account everything. Hence wisdom is a principle not only of universal order but also of ultimate judgment. But while wisdom as such is concerned with universal order and ultimate judgment, still it will, of its very nature, have application to particular fields. Precisely because it is universal and ultimate, it will have its participation in such fields as science, nature, spirit, art, law, education, religion, history; and so you have this 'philosophy of [...]' (Fs)

67c The general answer is one thing, and the technique of setting up a 'philosophy of [...],' a philosophy that is so conceived that it automatically becomes a 'philosophy of [...],' is quite another. Philosophy can be misconceived, I would say, as a dam across the river of life and thought, rather than the bed in which the river flows. What seems to me to have provoked that view of philosophy arises from taking the easy way of conceiving one's own intellect, one's own intelligence,1 pretty much in the same way as one comes to know God. You know the methodological procedure in natural theology of coming to the concept of God. It begins from the effects and proceeds by a method of analogy, of affirmation, negation, and eminence, to a concept of God. Man can proceed in exactly the same way to knowledge of his intelligence. There are the effects of intelligence in the sciences (sciences in the sense of written books of science), in the use of common names, in intelligent products. And from that one goes on, proceeding on the analogy that just as with our eyes we see, so there is a spiritual eye. If we use common names, this spiritual eye looks at universals. And since we have general principles, well, the spiritual eye sees the connections between these universals. When it sees those connections, you have a universal and necessary truth of which you are absolutely certain. While particular people might not be certain about it, still per se it is certain. And while these truths, since they are universal and necessary, hold for all possible worlds, still there may be very many qualifications to be added on. Yet per se they are true, and their being true is not the being true which is formaliter in iudicio, something that is in the mind; rather the truths are out there too. Finally, there is the notion of system as a deduction from a set of principles. What system? Well, something like Euclid's Elements. You lay down axioms as definitions, and then you proceed to deduce. If philosophy is conceived in that manner, it is going to be extremely difficult to get the type of wisdom that finds its applications in particular fields. (Fs)

68a Let me handle very briefly the notion of a system.2 If anyone reads St Thomas, one notices no similarity to Euclidean procedure. He does not start from a set of definitions and axioms, and he never treats any question by giving one proof and writing the matter off with Quod erat demonstrandum. Rather, he sets up an ordered series of questions, and in the Summa theologiae he subdivides the questions into articles. In a work like the Summa contra Gentiles, in his ordered set of topics, he brings to bear on each, not just one argument but several, and sometimes approximately twenty, and the arguments are all different; but when you move to the next question, well, it is pretty much the same arguments coming up again in a somewhat different application, and so on. Now St Thomas is systematic. Of what does his system consist? It consists of a basic set of operations that can be combined and recombined in various ways, and the various combinations are able to handle all the questions that arise. We have here, then, a concept, a notion, of system that is something far less static and abstract than Euclidean deduction. Moreover, it is a notion of system that can be applied to very concrete, very human developments. It is the fundamental notion of Piaget's some twenty volumes on child psychology.3 Now, if you conceive system this way - a man has a system, he is thinking systematically, he is reaching systematic knowledge, insofar as he possesses a basic set of related operations - then, because the operations are related, the terms, the products, of the operations will be related. Because the operations are related to one another, the operations can be combined in various ways. You can have all sorts of terms, all sorts of problems, and you will know exactly what the meaning is in each term because you know exactly what the operations are and what are the relations between them. Moreover, one has, as it were, the mastery of a field in which this group of operations is more or less the principle and the intelligibility. (Fs)

69a Now philosophy can be conceived as a basic group of operations; and as an insight into what that basic group of operations might be, you can take experiencing, understanding, and judging. The understanding can be differentiated, and you can get different kinds of combining of experiencing, understanding, and judging. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Geschichte: Substanz -> Subjekt; Hegel, Londergan; Subjekt - Geschichtlichkeit (historicity)

Kurzinhalt: The subject is this substance inasmuch as he is known by consciousness;

Textausschnitt: 71b The first of these is the notion of historicity, of Geschichtlichkeit. It is said of Hegel, or he said it himself, that he transferred philosophy from the substance to the subject, Spinoza wrote about the substance, Hegel wrote about the subject.1 The notion of the subject is a difficult notion to get hold of. One is not a subject, though one is a substance, when one is asleep and not dreaming. If one starts to dream, one becomes a subject, though a subject of an inferior type. But when one wakes up, one is much more of a subject, one is an empirical subject, a subject of acts of sense, seeing, hearing, and so on. If one inquires, understands, a new dimension emerges in consciousness; one is not only an empirical but also an intelligent subject. If one questions one's understanding, proceeds to judge, one becomes, one takes on the further dimension of, the rational subject. When one comes to making a decision or choice, the choice involves not only die chosen but also the chooser, and one is in die final level of the human subject, the self-conscious subject. (Fs) (notabene)

72a What is the subject? Well, the subject is what is known in consciousness. It is a term that, as it were, involves a leap from such metaphysical terms as substance and subsistence, which are defined and are verified independently of whether the subject is conscious or not. The subject is this substance inasmuch as he is known by consciousness; and not only is the subject known by consciousness, but he is also constituted qua subject by consciousness. It is when one moves from the metaphysical level of thinking to another level that there is a discontinuity, and I was talking about the notion of the subject to illustrate that discontinuity. We are always substances, but we are subjects only when we are awake, and we are subjects in different degrees according to what type of activity is going on in us. (Fs) (notabene)

72b Now just as man is a subject known and constituted by consciousness, so also man is known and constituted in his humanity by historicity, by this historical dimension of his reality. That notion of historicity is one that happens to be receiving all sorts of attention this century. From the thought of Martin Heidegger, there has radiated - often with decreasing degrees of dependence - a whole series of illuminations and transformations in previous ways of dunking of tilings. The notion goes back much further than Heidegger, but an illustration of it is the application of Heidegger's existentialism to depth psychology, and I will try to use a paper by Ludwig Binswanger on the dream and existence to elaborate.2 (Fs)

73a He distinguishes two types of dreams: the dream of the night, which is more largely determined by somatic influences, and the dream of the morning, in which the existent is shaping himself and his world. Consciousness is such that there is always a subject conscious of something, and the range of things the subject is conscious of is the horizon. Now the dream of the morning is a symbolic, incipient positing of the subject and his world. That world is not just a world of objects; it is a world in which the subject is acting, and because this human acting is determined, conditioned, by the historical developments of the past and a contribution to what the history of the immediate future is to be, you also have its historicity in the very constitution of the subject. (Fs)

73b To try to get hold of this notion from a slightly different angle, or perhaps to carry the point a step further, note that a person suffering from amnesia does not know who he is. If I were to forget that I was a Jesuit, a priest, a professor of theology, and so on, my possible activities would be entirely out of conformity with what I am. My memory of myself is constitutive, a fundamental determinant, of what I do. And to generalize, if a people were to forget themselves as a people, if all Canadians were to have amnesia insofar as they are Canadians, then Canada would no longer exist, and the same is true of any other people. There is an existential memory that is constitutive of the people qua people just as there is an
existential memory constitutive of a personality qua personality. (Fs)

73c Again, the history of a people is an account, an interpretation, of what the people were; but what the people were was their own self-interpretation. A man is not just a thing; he is what he does. What he says, what he works for, is all a function of his experience, his accumulated experience, understanding, judgment, his mentality, his way of thinking, what he approves of and disapproves of, what he wants and does not want. His mental activities are the main determinants of all his actions, and his mental activities include an interpretation, an idea, of what he himself is and what he is for - his nature and destiny. As this is true of the individual, so also it is true of the group. The historian, in writing the history of the people, in interpreting what the people were, is not the first to step into the field of interpretation. There is an understanding that was constitutive of the history that is written about, not only the understanding of the historian. (Fs) (notabene)

73d So history becomes an objectification of the existential memory of the people, of their self-interpretation. Just as drama is an objectification, a symbolization, of human life in some aspect or some situations, so, on a more fundamental level, you could say that all living is in a sense drama - people dealing with people and things. That more fundamental drama is the more fundamental objectification in civilization of what, more originally, the person is. In that way, one has a comparison between drama and history - as though drama is, as it were, a prehistorical, more simple type of history, of objectification and criticism of the way that people live, while history is a fuller, more ample, more reflective drama. (Fs)

Kommentar (04/28/06): "Just as drama is an objectification, a symbolization, of human life in some aspect or some situations, ..." Von daher verständlich der Begriff "dramatisches Subjekt". (Fs)

74a Now what I have been trying to do is to suggest this notion of historicity, but it is a very difficult notion to get hold of. On the other hand, it is a field of very fruitful reflections on the nature and significance of history. I cannot carry this notion any further here.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Dialektik - Subjekt, Geschichte; Plato - Eristik; Dialektik - Bewegung - Gegenposition - Umkehr

Kurzinhalt: The contradiction is not between statements that he makes; the contradiction is between the statements that he makes and the subject that he is

Textausschnitt: 74b I will now go on to another notion that emerges on the level of philosophic reflection on history. The notion is dialectic. About the beginning of the last decade, Joseph Moreau wrote a very small book on idealism and realism in Plato,1 and its final paragraph ended up with a statement from Blondel, L 'Action (1893), in which Blondel said that a fully coherent idealism ends by eliminating all the differences that separate it from realism.2 It is the statement that one type of philosophy, if fully coherent, if worked out to the end, becomes another; and there you have a fundamental opposition between what I call positions and counterpositions. Positions express the dynamic structure of the subject qua intelligent and qua reasonable. Counterpositions contradict that structure. Whenever a person is explicitly affirming - presenting or affirming - a counterposition, he is involved in a queer type of contradiction. The contradiction is not between statements that he makes; the contradiction is between the statements that he makes and the subject that he is. He is intelligent and reasonable, and purports to be intelligent and reasonable, and he would not admit any fall from intelligence or reasonableness. Yet the implications of the one, the real consequences, so to speak, of the one, and the implications of the other, which are in a field of conceptions or a field of judgments, are in conflict. (Fs) (notabene)

75a Such a conflict tends to work itself out in one way or another. It sets up a tension, and it is a principle of movement; and that, to my mind, is a fundamental instance of what is meant by dialectic. It is in the concrete, it involves tension and opposition, and it is a principle of change; and the change is not so much, not merely, in the statements; it will also be in the subject who comes to a fuller realization, a fuller appropriation, of what he himself really is. The effect of the dialectic is not simply a matter of straightening out the sentences, and affirming the ones that are true and denying the ones that are false. A person can be affirming propositions that are true, but misinterpreting them; and you cannot correct what is wrong with him by telling him the right ones, because he is always going to bring in the misinterpretation. There is a more fundamental step: the development in the subject himself through dialectic. (Fs) (notabene)

75b Now that dialectic goes on not merely within the individual. Platonic dialectic was dialogue. There was ruled out eristic dialectic, that is, argument for argument's sake: the man in Goldsmith's deserted village, though vanquished, could argue still.3 But let the argument have its run, let it have its free course, and things will come to light that we had not thought of before. The Platonic dialogue is a concrete, group use of dialectic in that individual sense. The individual will make his statements, and another individual will state what this subject really is, in an implicit manner no doubt, but there is another example of dialectic. A third example, what Aristotle called dialectic, was reviewing the opinions of all the people that discussed the question before him; and there you have the dialogue put out into time. But what goes on in the subject, what goes on in the dialogue, what goes on in the development of opinions on a single question, that also has relevance to the total field of human development; and that is history. (Fs)

75c Now that notion of development has come to notice today. It is a little hard to describe it; there has been both Hegelian and Marxist dialectic. Think of Hegel's account, in the Phenomenology of Spirit, of the master-slave relations.4 It is a beautiful piece of work. It describes the initial situation, where you have a master who is really master and the slave who is really slave. But time goes on, and the master becomes more and more dependent upon the slave, and the roles become reversed. That is an illustration of the notion of development of situations working themselves out to their consequences. But that notion of dialectic has been plunged into the problem of the interpretation, the grand-scale interpretation, of history on the philosophic level, and that is very much a problem of our time. The liberals - the Enlightenment and then the liberals - had a doctrine, an interpretation, of history in terms of progress. Things were getting better and better. The Marxists had an interpretation in terms of what they call the materialistic dialectic of history, which has become the interpretation of human reality in Russia and in China; and it seems to be accepted there in all seriousness as the correct view of this world and what its meaning is, what it is about. (We had a sample today with Mr Khrushchev's speech at the United Nations.5)

76a We have had others of these grand-scale interpretations of history. Another example is Rosenberg's myth of the twentieth century,6 which is the interpretation of history behind the Nazi movement. There is very definitely a problem here. Christopher Dawson, in a recent book, The Historic Reality of Christian Culture,7 speaks of these movements going on and of Christians having very little influence because of largely passive attitudes. Eric Voegelin, in his New Science of Politics8 suggests - perhaps does more than suggest - that the Christian view of this world, as waiting for the second coming of Christ, left a vacuum of meaning in that merely day-to-day aspect of human living which these modern philosophies of history are attempting to fill. When they fill it, they obtain stupendous results, stupendous influence over human life in all its aspects, as is illustrated by nineteenth-century progressivism - it goes on well into this century - and the influence of Marx at the present time. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Symbol: Definition

Kurzinhalt: A symbol is an image that either induces an affect, causes the affect to arise, or on the other hand expresses an affect - one has the affect first and the image emerges

Textausschnitt: 98d Now briefly consider symbolic meaning. It is the meaning of affect in the most elementary form. By affects and our affections - affections are something more elaborate than affects - we have our orientation in life, in the world. They reveal the direction of our living, our attitudes to the world, to other persons, to things. A symbol is an image that either induces an affect, causes the affect to arise, or on the other hand expresses an affect - one has the affect first and the image emerges. Further, images that are symbols, that is, expressions or causes of affects, also reveal the attitude and the orientation of a person in the world and towards other persons. (Fs) (notabene)
Kommentar (05/15/06): Definition Symbol ... (Fs)

99a Now such affects, such symbols, have been studied very thoroughly in this century. The Freudian study of symbols, particularly of dream symbols, is based largely on interpersonal relations, and interpersonal relations gone wrong. The Greek cycle of Seven against Thebes,1 in which the family centering around Oedipus was involved in all sorts of crimes and hatreds, provides the fundamental nucleus of the description. There is an entirely different analysis worked out by Jung. But I would like to mention a recent study by Gilbert Durand, Les Structures anthropologiques de I'imaginaire.2 There are some thirty-five pages of bibliography, so he has been over a fair amount of material. (Fs)

99b Durand sets aside all the Freudian analysis of symbols as pertaining to a certain type of civilization, a certain type of family problem, and he does not go on to the higher dynamics of Jungian psychology, but he connects symbols, images that express affects, with three fundamental dominant reflexes. There is the reflex by which we maintain our balance: if one is going to fall, one's reflex interrupts everything else until one recovers one's equilibrium. It is a dominant reflex: it operates spontaneously, masterfully; it cuts out everything else (as do the other dominant reflexes: swallowing and mating).3 (Fs)

100a Connected with maintaining one's equilibrium, there are what Durand calls the ascensional symbols: rising, standing, being upright, exercising control, manipulation, power, the sceptre, the sword, going up the ladder, the bird that flies, the tree that rises from the earth, all the symbols that express uprightness in the moral connotation of the word - something a child develops very strong feelings about in learning to walk, in learning to maintain its balance. (Fs)
100b Opposed to these ascensional symbols there are all the symbols of fear, and you get the whole combined in, for example, the image of St George and the dragon. The dragon combines in one monster all the symbols of fear or a vast number of them. On the other hand, St George destroying the dark dragon is mastering the object of fear; he is upright, he is riding, he holds the spear. A whole affective orientation is expressed in that symbol. (Fs)

100c The second dominant reflex is swallowing. You get an entirely different attitude from St George and the dragon when you take Jonah and the whale. The whale is just as much a monster as the dragon, but it is not terrifying. The object of terror is euphemized; it is not so bad after all. Jonah went down into the whale but he came out three days later and was just as well off as ever. Instead of mastering the object of fear, controlling it, dominating it, there is resignation, quietness, peace, and not the fall from the upright position but the descent, improving the descent when one is falling.4 (Fs)

100d You can see how Durand's analysis of symbols is connected with very fundamental physiological, psychic facts, and how it enables him to put together vast arrays of symbols. In the symbol there is a meaning, not on the conceptual level but still on a very real level; it has a meaning for people, all the meaning, for example, in the word 'upright'; it has connected with it all sorts of meanings, all sorts of feelings and suggestions, that are fundamentally affective and symbolic; the affective is directed toward something, and the meaning of the symbol is the meaning of the affect; or there can be a combination of affects, an interplay between affects as, for example, with courage overcoming fear, and so on. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Meinung, Intention, Realität; in Gott Identität von Intention und Realität; intentional - real - natürlich

Kurzinhalt: in God the natural and intentional reality are identical; 'intentional' is not opposed to 'real'; it is opposed to 'natural.'

Textausschnitt: 105a Further, perhaps we had best say a few words on the ontology, the reality, of meaning. One is apt to say that on the one hand there are things that are real and on the other there is 'mere meaning' - as though meaning were not a reality. The proper division is that esse reale, the real, divides into the 'natural' and the 'intentional'; the intentional order is the order of meaning. Now in God the natural and intentional reality are identical. For that reason, the procession of the Word is not simply the procession of the meaning of God, but also the procession of God himself, because in God the esse intentionale and the esse naturale are one and the same; and so when God utters himself, conceives himself, not only is there a concept of God but the reality of God too. There is the identity of the intentional and the natural. In us there is not that identity. We are ourselves even when we are asleep and having no dreams. Our unconscious is as much a part of us as our conscious living, and the two interpenetrate in a very complex fashion (into which we need not go). But it would be a mistake to think that a meaning is not a reality. Our conscious living and the meaning that it carries are just as real as the realities of the spirit, and they do not belong to some shadowy world that really does not count. One mistakes the whole significance of meaning if one does not get that point correct: 'intentional' is not opposed to 'real'; it is opposed to 'natural.'1 (Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (05/16/06): Die Identität von esse intentionale und reale in Gott ist die ontolgische Voraussetzung für das Realsymbol

105b Besides speaking of the ontology of meaning one might say a few words about the ethics of meaning. What exists by being willed is something that is meant. And of course what exists by being willed is something whose existence can be completely rational because the will is a rational appetite. And in us there is a spiraling upwards: we develop mentally and morally, we reach fuller and fuller meaning, and we realize those meanings in ourselves and in our environment by our willing. It is through this world, this intentional order, that human will has its creative opportunity, and it is within the intentional order that will is effective. Similarly, when I speak about what exists because it is willed, I mean what exists because it is loved, and love is just one instance of this creativity of the will. (Fs)
106a Opposed to what I was saying about meaning is what is called nihilism, the negation of any meaning to human life. Take the often repeated statement of Nietzsche that God is dead. What he meant was that the atheism, the agnosticism, the religious indifference, of the nineteenth century destroyed the meaning of all the cultural tradition on which the century was actually living. What he concluded was the necessity of recreating the whole of culture. The point there is that when you remove the fundamental element in the meaning of life, you have to find a new meaning or people are desperate. A recent book has been published with the title The Struggle for Meaning.11 Human living really is a struggle for meaning, an effort, because meaning is constituent of human living. The effort to live is fundamentally the struggle for meaning. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Trinität, Introspektion, Thomas; falsches Verständnis von Realität (Tertullian)

Kurzinhalt: crisis involved in overcoming the spontaneous estimate of the real, and the fear of idealism involved in this crisis

Textausschnitt: 4 Block to Integration: Notion of Reality

128c On the other hand, there did arise blocks which prevented attention to the results of psychological introspection and acknowledgment of their relevance. The root of those blocks is, in my opinion, twofold: a notion of reality and a notion of knowledge. We all spend approximately seven years before reaching the age of reason, but before reaching it we have some notion, some developed sense, of reality. We all possess a prerational feeling, sense, conviction, about what is real and what is not. That prerational conviction about what is real and what is not is not exactly the same as the distinction between id quod est and id quod non est. Indeed, it is so totally different that, when we first hear about ens, we wonder what on earth people are talking about. (Fs) (notabene)

129a There are two ways of conceiving reality, of judging what is real and what is not. One is an appeal to a sense of reality that is prerational. It is never eliminated; if it were, we would not function properly, we would become a psychological case. The other is in terms of ens cui suo modo competit esse. The two notions do not sound the same and are not the same. (Fs) (notabene)

129b The difference may be illustrated by contrasting Tertullian and the Council of Nicea on the divinity of the Son. Tertullian never denied the divinity of the Son, but he did not attribute the same properties to the Son that he attributed to the Father. The Father is eternal; the Son is temporal. The Father gives orders; the Son carries them out. Perhaps - for the exegetes are uncertain of the meaning of the passage1 - the Father is the whole and the Son is the derivative part. Now the fact that the same predicates are not attributed to the Son as to the Father caused Tertullian no difficulty for, in his opinion, the Son was divine because he was made of the same stuff as the Father. Divinity depends on what sort of stuff you are made of. This is a notion of divinity that fits in perfectly with the first sense of reality. According to the homoousios formula of Nicea, however, the Son is divine because the same predicates are to be attributed to him as to the Father, with one exception, the name 'Father.'2 This notion of divinity fits in with the notion of reality in terms of id quod est and id quod non est. Homoousios is conceived in terms of ens, of id quod est, of identity of predicates. By that standard, Tertullian did not properly acknowledge the divinity of the Son. And the difference between Tertullian and Nicea on this point is the difference between the two notions of reality we outlined. (Fs) (notabene)

130a Unfortunately, some people have the impression that, while Tertullian and others of his time may have made such a mistake, no one repeats it today. Nothing could be further from the truth. For until a person has made the personal discovery that he is making Tertullian's mistake all along the line, until he has gone through the crisis involved in overcoming the spontaneous estimate of the real, and the fear of idealism involved in this crisis, he is still thinking just as Tertullian did. It is not a sign that one is dumb or backward. St Augustine was one of the most intelligent men in the whole Western tradition, and one of the best proofs of his intelligence is the fact that he himself discovered that for years he was unable to distinguish between what is a body and what is real. (Fs) (notabene)

However, the notion of reality is only one part of the problem. The other is the notion of knowledge. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Trinität, Introspektion; falsches Verständnis: Wissen als Sehen

Kurzinhalt: A further consequence of conceiving knowing on the analogy of the popular notion of vision is the exclusion of the conscious subject. Objects are paraded before spectators ...

Textausschnitt: 5 Block to Integration: Notion of Knowledge

130b Now in this new block to integration ocular vision is a perfect symbol for knowing. When do you know? When you perform an act that is like an act of seeing. If you perform such an act, it is self-evident, unquestionable, beyond any possible rational doubt, that the object of that act is really and truly known, that it is valid, that it is objective. On the other hand, if a cog-nitional act is not like seeing, it is equally self-evident, unquestionable, and beyond possible doubt that its object is not really and truly known, that it really is not valid knowledge. That symbol, because it is symbolic, is absolutely convincing. Myths are not mere funny stories; a myth is something you are absolutely certain of. People who hold the earth is flat do not hold that view as a theory or hypothesis or possibility; they hold it as something which simply must be so. Similarly, one can be absolutely convinced that a cognitional act can be cognitional only if it resembles ocular vision. Of course, if it is like ocular vision, it does not need explanation but is self-evident. (Fs) (notabene)

130c Ocular vision here is ocular vision as popularly imagined. As scientifically studied, ocular vision demands distinction between 'real' color and visible color, between 'real' shapes and visible shapes. The 'real' color of the cassocks worn by the seminarians at the German College1 is always the same no matter what the age of the cassock, the lighting of the room, and so forth. The visible color varies with the age of the cassock, the number of times it has been washed, the light in which you see it. This is the visible color, unseen by most people. Again, artists see things in their perspective, but the rest of us see things the way in which they are built, the way in which they are not visible. We see everything in straight lines, in rectangles, and so forth; but that is not the way they are in fact visible.2 (Fs)
131a Now, if human knowing is to be conceived exclusively, by an epistemological necessity, as similar to ocular vision, it follows as a first consequence that human understanding must be excluded from human knowledge. For understanding is not like seeing. Understanding grows with time: you understand one point, then another, and a third, a fourth, a fifth, a sixth, and your understanding changes several times until you have things right. Seeing is not like that, so to say that knowing is like seeing is to disregard understanding as a constitutive element in human knowledge. (Fs) (notabene)

131b A further consequence of conceiving knowing on the analogy of the popular notion of vision is the exclusion of the conscious subject. Objects are paraded before spectators, and if the spectator wants to know himself, he must get out in the parade to be looked at. There are no subjects anywhere, for being a subject is not being something that is being looked at; it is being the one who is looking; it is not what is understood, but the one who is understanding; it is not what is being questioned, but the one asking the questions; and by the very fact that he is asking them, he is aware of himself asking the questions. And if the conscious subject has been excluded, it is not surprising that three conscious subjects are also excluded or at least omitted in the Trinity. (Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (05/21/06): "Objects are paraded before spectators, and if the spectator wants to know himself, he must get out ..." Diese einfache Feststellung erklrt von einer Tiefe her das Verhalten jener Zeitgenossen, die aus einem elementaren Antrieb her unter Menschen stets damit beschftigt sind, sich mglichst sichtbar in die Parade der Objekte einzureihen.

131c When understanding is excluded from knowledge, not on the grounds that we do not have intellects (for we are not materialists), but on the grounds that we do not have intelligence,3 then we may have spiritual eyes that look at universals, compare universals, see the possible nexus, and see the necessary nexus, and we may bow our heads in assent; but we are not understanding in the ordinary meaning of the word. And if understanding is excluded from conscious knowledge, there is no possibility of one's defining or clarifying because one understands. To speak of judging because one has understood, grasped, the unconditioned, will have no meaning. Without a notion of the conscious subject or of the intelligible emanation, the process from the judgment of value to the act of choice will also be overlooked. (Fs) (notabene)

132a For some twenty-three years now, I have been examining in theology. Jesuit students must take an examination which, besides the hundred theses on theology, includes all of philosophy. When a student is asked for a philosophical proof of human liberty, he is likely to appeal to consciousness. If it is objected that, in consciousness of a free act, we are conscious only of the fact that we chose one part or the other, but not of the possibility of choosing the opposite, most students are stumped. For the appeal to consciousness must be an appeal to the conscious subject who is principle of this act or that act and is aware of the fact that he is principle of either. The appeal must be to the conscious subject and to intelligible emanations. (Fs; ???)

132b The notions of knowledge and of reality which we have outlined, although distinct, still reinforce one another. Reality is what is known by an act much like an act of seeing, and not at all what is known by understanding and judging. A neat, closed-in world is built up in which there is no room for three conscious subjects in the Trinity. (Fs)

132c There is, then, a problem for Catholic thinkers in the field of trinitarian theory. We must use the word 'person' in speaking of God, and in its traditional sense; we are bound to the formula 'three persons in God.' But we can say 'three persons' and mean three conscious subjects, that is, use the word in the sense of three who are somebody although there is one consciousness for the three subjects. There is no major difficulty in integrating the notion of person as 'conscious subject' with the whole tradition of systematic theology on the Trinity; it simply is a matter of understanding what St Thomas said. One may understand what he said or merely repeat his formula, and that is the difference between having three conscious subjects and not having them in the Trinity. The real difficulty lies elsewhere. It lies in philosophic problems and their carry-over into theology. Theology is reason illuminated by faith. And should reason limp, well, limping reason illuminated by faith will not give perfect results. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Sein (esse) -> Unterschied zw. Seinsbegriff und Idee vom Sein usw.; Grundlage der Objektivität (Gilson)

Kurzinhalt: The notion of being is distinct from the concept of being; the notion and concept of being are different from knowledge of being; and the notion, concept, and knowledge of being are distinct from the idea of being

Textausschnitt: 134b [...]
What is the basis of the objectivity of our knowledge, what is its first contact with the objective? It occurs after you have a sense experience - when you ask, 'What is it?' and when you know what the answer to that is; and when you ask, 'Is it so?' An sit"? (Fs) (notabene)

134c What is this sit? It is the objective of the pure desire to know being. Questions are unlimited; you can't draw a line and say, 'So far and no further, no further questions.' The potency for asking questions is unlimited. And the object of that potency is unlimited. In that way our knowledge ties up with an unlimited objective that is being; such is our notion of being. (Fs)

134d The notion of being is distinct from the concept of being; the notion and concept of being are different from knowledge of being; and the notion, concept, and knowledge of being are distinct from the idea of being. The idea of being is God's essence. To understand God's essence is to understand God and everything else, which is what God's knowledge of himself and everything else is. The idea of being is the species intelligibilis that is the essence of God. Knowledge of being is had through judgment. The concept of being is had when you conceive anything; any concept is always a concept of being. For any concept is ordered to a judgment: Is it so? By the mere fact that it is ordered to a judgment, it is a concept of something ordered to esse. And what is being? Ens est id cui suo modo competit esse. So any concept is a concept of being. The notion of being is the desire to understand, which is prior to understanding anything. It is the wonder that is the beginning of all science and philosophy, but also the wonder that makes two-year-old children plague their parents with the number of questions they ask.1 (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Trinität - Bewusstsein; der Vater ist analog zur Erfassung ...

Kurzinhalt: the Father is God in a manner analogous to the grasp of sufficient evidence that necessitates one to judge; the Son is God in the same consciousness but

Textausschnitt: 135a Question: The next question concerned the fact that the judgment of identity in the person is made because of, and in, a multiplicity of acts. (Fs)

Response: We think of our identity in relation with a multiplicity of acts because it is the multiplicity of acts that causes the problem. So the problem of identity in the Trinity will not be the same. There is only one act, but there is a distinction because the three persons have the same consciousness differently: the Father is God in a manner analogous to the grasp of sufficient evidence that necessitates one to judge; the Son is God in the same consciousness but now a consciousness analogous to that of the dependence of the judgment on the grasp of sufficient evidence; the Holy Spirit is the same consciousness in a third manner, namely, as the dependence of the act of love on the grasp of sufficient evidence and the rational affirmation. The same consciousness is had differently by three persons. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Klärung: intelligibel (intelligibile); in genere intelligibilium ut actus

Kurzinhalt: St Thomas, where he says that sensible things are not in genere intelligibilium, that our intellects are in genere intelligibilium ut potentia tantum, that ...

Textausschnitt: 135b Question: What is the meaning of the term intelligibile as applied to acts of understanding, as distinct from the way it is applied to natural causes?

Response: The difference is clear enough in St Thomas, where he says that sensible things are not in genere intelligibilium, that our intellects are in genere intelligibilium ut potentia tantum, that to be in genere intelligibilium ut actus is to be infinite - that is a use of intelligibile that does not apply to natural objects: human intelligence is at the bottom of the ladder.1 The intelligibile is the sort of thing that for it to be in full act is to be infinite. It is in a category that moves off to infinity. It makes no sense to talk about the infinitely hot, but it does make sense to talk of the infinitely intelligible. That's with regard to usage. (Fs)

136a With regard to meaning, a learned book in Akkadian2 may inspire your admiration for its beautiful printing but you won't know what it means. It's intelligible but I don't understand anything. That is not the sense in which 'intelligible' is used when we speak of an intelligible emanation. When we speak of an intelligible emanation, we refer to the intelligible that can be only in an intelligent subject as intelligence in act. A city plan, a parish church or hall, may be very intelligently worked out but the plan itself is not intelligent at all; it is an effect of intelligence. But what goes on in a man's mind when he thinks of the plan? It is not merely an object that can be studied and admired as neatly contrived; it is not the contrived but the contriver - namely, the intelligent. People judge because of sufficient reason. And you may say that I am here tonight because of a sufficient reason; or that something happens and there is a sufficient reason for it. But the sufficient reason is not rational in itself; it is the grounded: what results from following reason. But what occurs in virtue of reason itself is the sort of thing that is moved because it is rational, by the reason itself. As in the expressions, 'It stands to reason,' 'If you had an ounce of gumption, you'd say yes,' and so on. We become impatient when addressed in that way. But what is being appealed to? The speaker is appealing to our rationality, to our ability to be moved by reason as distinct from any other type of pressure or threat. In that ability to be moved by reason, at its center - in the intellect itself, in the rational appetite that is the will - the place where theory counts and where, if we are rational, it should 'cut some ice' (even if it doesn't in practical affairs) there is to be located the field of intellectual emanations. (A book on logic is logical, but when the Greeks called man a zoon logikon - a logical animal - they were talking about him as rational. The Latins did not make a mistake in translating it animal rationale - a rational animal. The question is, What is rationale?) (Fs)

136b Question: Is it true to say then that intelligible and intelligent mean the same thing? (Fs)

Response: No. In general you can say that everything is intelligible: even prime matter, though not in itself but in its form; and the social surd but only within the dialectic. Everything is intelligible but only intelligent beings are intelligent. They are the only beings that understand. What is understanding? It is like seeing in this sense: that just as, if you are blind, you don't know what seeing is (you may figure out a theory about what it must mean but it is not something immediately evident to you, and can be evident only to someone who can open and close his eyes and see), so too unless you understand, you can't know what understanding means. The function of the earlier chapters of Insight is to stimulate the occurrence and experience of understanding. People object, 'The examples aren't familiar.' That is the point. If they were familiar, the act of understanding would occur so easily that it wouldn't be noticed. You have to work for it, and at long last it comes: 'I've got it!' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Intelligibile in actu est intellectus in actu - mobile, motivum, motum, movens
Intelligibile in actu est intellectus in actu

Kurzinhalt: Because of this analysis Aristotle can conclude to what you could never arrive at in a Platonic philosophy: a prime mover that is intelligent

Textausschnitt: 137b Question: The next questioner asked the meaning of the dictum, Intelligibile in actu est intellectus in actu. (Fs)

Response: That's St Thomas and Aristotle. The intelligent in act and the intelligible in act are identical. The intelligible in potency and the intelligent in potency are distinct. The intelligible in potency can be understood, the intelligent in potency can understand. It depends on Aristotle's analysis of action and passion. Aristotle, and St Thomas commenting on the Physics, distinguish the mobile, the motivum, the motum, and the movens; these are the elements distinguished in motus, motion.1 Now is the motion in the mover or in the moved? Are there two motions or only one? Aristotle shows that there is only one and that it is in the moved. Then, in the third book of the De anima (lectio secunda of St Thomas's Commentary), he applies this analysis to sensation. Hearing - your ear - and the bell are distinct; what sounds in potency and what hears in potency are distinct. But the hearing in act and the sounding in act are one and the same. The bell rings in the desert - does it sound? Not in Aristotle's view. There is no sounding act unless there is an ear hearing in act. He applied the same thing to the intellectual order. Intellectus in actu and intelligibile in actu are identical, but in potency they are distinct. Because of this analysis Aristotle can conclude to what you could never arrive at in a Platonic philosophy: a prime mover that is intelligent. Aristotle's prime mover is not an object but an identity of subject and object. In his quae sunt sine materia idem est intelligens et intellectum.2 Now that is a basic analysis of knowledge, but it doesn't deal with die problem of objectivity. Analysis of the judgment has to be added. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Symbol; Wechselbeziehung: Affekt - Bild, Imagination

Kurzinhalt: By a symbol is meant an affect-laden image. There is the image, and either it evokes the affect or the affect evokes it.

Textausschnitt: 189a A fourth type of meaning, one that again escapes the level of words, of clear concepts, of flat affirmations and negations, is the meaning of the symbol. By a symbol is meant an affect-laden image. There is the image, and either it evokes the affect or the affect evokes it. They correspond to one another. The affect finds expression in the image, resonates in the image, finds form and concreteness in the image; on the other hand, the image is dynamic, alive, moving, insofar as it is connected with the affect. Images or symbols have been studied in many different ways. In the Freudian account, symbols are expressions of family relationships, especially family relationships gone sour, and very sour, as illustrated by the Greek tragedies built about the story of the Seven against Thebes.1 Carl Jung is concerned with symbols of transformation, of conversion, of death and resurrection, with the preformation, on the level of the unconscious and of the sensitive soul, of man's higher spiritual activities.2 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Bibel; Bewusstsein: differenziert- undifferenziert

Kurzinhalt: ... what corresponds to the gospels is undifferentiated consciousness, whereas what corresponds to dogma is differentiated consciousness

Textausschnitt: 2a To this objective aspect of dogmatic development there corresponds of necessity a subjective aspect. For if there is a change in literary genre and a change in the manner of apprehending and considering the truth, then there is a change in man himself. But what exactly is this change in man himself?1 (Fs)

2b To begin with what is most obvious, there is no doubt that the interior state of a person who is asleep and dreaming is quite different from that of one who is wide awake: the kind of law that governs the succession and interrelation of dream-images, and the kind of pattern in which they emerge, are totally different from the patterns and laws that govern and order our daytime experiences. Not so obvious, perhaps, is the fact that waking consciousness is anything but a uniform, homogeneous state-that there are many different patterns in which our conscious acts emerge, some preceding and calling forth others, others following and complementing those that preceded them and called them forth. Quite different from each other are the interior states that accompany involvement with practical problems, the enjoyment of aesthetic experience, the arousal of mythic consciousness, the ardour of mystical illumination, the joyful sharing of friends in human intersubjectivity, and the specifically intellectual pursuits of the scientific mind. (Fs)

2c Conscious human acts emerge, therefore, within different patterns of experience, patterns that can be identified and described, distinguished from and related to each other. But the basic distinction to be made is between undifferentiated and differentiated consciousness. Consciousness is undifferentiated where the whole person is involved, operating simultaneously and equally with all of his powers. Differentiated consciousness, on the other hand, is capable of operating exclusively, or at least principally, on a single level, while the other levels are either entirely subordinated to the attainment of the goal of that level, or at least are held in check, so that they do not hinder its attainment. In the man of action, for example, imagination, affectivity, will, senses and practical intelligence all operate together: imagination represents the goal to be achieved, affectivity is drawn towards it, will embraces it, practical intelligence, with the aid of the senses, figures out how the goal is to be achieved and how the obstacles are to be removed that stand in the way of its attainment. Thus the whole person, with all his powers, tends towards a goal that is proportionate to man. In contrast, the scientist, or the speculative thinker, tends towards a goal that is not that of the whole man, but only of his intellect. The will is therefore restricted to willing the good of intellect, which is the truth; imagination throws up only those images that induce understanding or suggest a judgment; feelings and emotions, finally, are as if anaesthetised, so firmly are they kept in control. (Fs)

3a Bearing this basic distinction in mind, it is not hard to see that what corresponds to the gospels is undifferentiated consciousness, whereas what corresponds to dogma is differentiated consciousness. For the gospels are addressed to the whole person, on all levels of operation. The dogmas, on the contrary, demand a subject who can focus attention on the aspect of truth alone, so that other powers are under the sway of intellect, or else are somehow stilled. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Dogma, Dogmen: unklar, obskur; Mensch des Alltagslebens

Kurzinhalt: ... when intellect operates as just one among many diverse powers ... then less attention is focussed on the proper end of intellect

Textausschnitt: 4b It is argued that the dogmas are obscure, whereas the gospels are perfectly clear. In one sense this is true, but in another it is not. It can hardly be said that exegetes find the gospels perfectly clear: today, after almost twenty centuries, the learned articles, the monographs, the commentaries and the dictionaries, the various opinions and hypotheses, the methods and the schools of interpretation would seem to be increasing, not diminishing, in number. And if the gospels are not without obscurity, neither are the dogmas entirely lacking in clarity. Just as Euclid's Elements seem very obscure to those who have never learnt geometry, so dogmas, to the uneducated, seem very strange indeed. Yet to mathematicians the meaning of Euclid's Elements is so clear and precise that they present almost no problems of interpretation and therefore little ground for disputes among commentators or the never-ending labour of exegetes. And as the mathematician views Euclid, so the theologian views the dogmas of the Church. (Fs) (notabene)

5a The explanation is not hard to find. For when one's other powers are subordinated to one's intellect, one is apt to achieve that clarity and precision that is proper to intellect; those who have made some progress in the intellectual life, therefore, and can move with ease into the intellectual pattern of experience, find nothing more clear and precise than the meaning of a geometrical theorem or of a dogmatic definition. On the other hand, when intellect operates as just one among many diverse powers-and this applies to most people most of the time-then less attention is focussed on the proper end of intellect. In ordinary every-day living there is much that is taken for granted as being sufficiently clear; what is thus taken for granted may be described and stated in detail, from many different angles, but it is normally so tied to particular circumstances, so embedded in the intentions of individual people, that it can never be reduced to the clarity of a definition or a theorem. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Einwand: Dogma, Dogmen -> unklar - Bibel -> einfach und klar; Bewusstsein - Differenzierung

Kurzinhalt: It is plain, therefore, that dogmas pertain to religion most of all because they render differentiated consciousness religious

Textausschnitt: 5b So much for the clarity or obscurity of dogmas. We may move on to consider the second contention, that dogmas have little religious significance. This contention is normally coupled with such a glorification of the Hebrew mind, in its ancient simplicity, as to suggest that it was some special gift of God to the Hebrews, sealed with the approval of the scriptures and offered to all future ages as a model to be imitated. (Fs)

5c However, the fact is that the farther back we go towards ancient times, the less differentiated we find the consciousness of all men; the esteemed simplicity of the Hebrews, then, is characteristic not of them alone, but of all the more ancient races. Further, the less differentiated one's consciousness and the fewer the patterns of experience in which one lives out one's life, the less clearly, proportionately, does one grasp the diversity of human actions and the less capable, consequently, is one of drawing distinctions between one sphere of action and another. That is why among primitives the spheres of the sacred and the profane interpenetrate, without benefit of distinction or separation,1 and so those who in secular matters are most religious, in the sphere of religion are most prone to idolatry. The Hebrews themselves were no less inclined to idolatry than were other races; the difference was that their tendency to idolatry was held in check by the inspired teaching of the prophets, proclaimed with vehemence and constantly reiterated. There is little basis, then, for the romantic notion that undifferentiated consciousness is the religious consciousness par excellence. (Fs) (notabene)

6a There is no firmer footing for the correlative assertion that dogmas have little religious significance. For it is the function of religion to orientate and direct the whole of man's living towards God, and therefore, as consciousness develops, so too must religion. The simpler one's life-style, the simpler one's religion will be; but when human living becomes highly diversified and highly specialised, then to its many various aspects there correspond many and various functions of religion. (Fs)

6b It is plain, therefore, that dogmas pertain to religion most of all because they render differentiated consciousness religious- whether we think of such consciousness as already developed intellectually, or as standing in need of intellectual development. For differentiated consciousness reflects on, and passes judgment on religious matters, as it does on everything else, and such judgments affect the whole tenor and direction of life. And so if one argues that there is nothing religious about intellect, one is not serving the cause of true religion, but rather that of secularism. (Fs)

7a But one may say, surely primitives and children can be genuinely religious, and just as surely, religious living does not consist in intellectual exercises. Quite true, but the argument simply misses the point. For religion is not some eternal and immutable Platonic form, with but a single mode of participation for children and adults, for primitives and highly-developed peoples alike. As consciousness develops so too does religion, and so it is fallacious to infer that what is appropriate for children and for primitives constitutes the very essence of religion, always and everywhere the same. Secondly, as we have already said, with the development of consciousness religion takes on many aspects and fulfils many functions; if one particular aspect and function does not constitute the whole of religion, it does not follow that that particular aspect and function is therefore to be denied. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Regel: achte auf das Wort

Kurzinhalt: one simple rule for dealing with the arguments adduced by those who say that there is a radical discontinuity between the gospels and the dogmas: pay attention to the word as true

Textausschnitt: 10a There is, then, one simple rule for dealing with the arguments adduced by those who say that there is a radical discontinuity between the gospels and the dogmas: pay attention to the word as true. This is what the perceptionists overlook, who think that they know before they have made a judgment. It also escapes the idealists, who insist that what the perceptionists perceive is only the appearance of things, not things in themselves. The essentialists also miss the point, for they can no more distinguish between essence and being, in an adequate manner, than they can between thinking and knowing. There is the same basic flaw in those elaborate descriptions of forms or structures of thought that betray a lack of clear distinction between thinking and knowing. Finally, it is this same failure to attend to the word as true that mars the thinking of those who reduce the dogmas to hellenism; for hellenistic speculation was concerned with essences, whereas dogmas are affirmations of what is.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Vorwurf, Verwirrung: Subordinationismus (subordinationism) vor Nicaea; subtile Fehlschlüsse; Wille: Sohn, Vater

Kurzinhalt: If, however, one were to infer from this that the Father is invisible and the Son visible ... if one were to infer from such passages that the Son was born of the Father only when the Father willed to create ...

Textausschnitt: 40a
1. There are many conclusions, drawn from more recent theology, which, to those who are not very well versed in the matter, can seem rather subtle. (Fs)

40b For example, the scriptures represent the Father as the one who is hidden, whom no one has ever seen, and the Son as the one who reveals him. If, however, one were to infer from this that the Father is invisible and the Son visible, one would be going against the doctrine of the consubstantiality of the Father and the Son. For if there is only the one divine substance, then either it is invisible or it is visible. And therefore, if the Father is invisible, it follows of necessity that the Son is also invisible. (Fs) (notabene)

40c Again, in the scriptures the Father is the one from whom all things come, whereas the Son is the one through whom all things come (1 Cor 8,6; Col 1,17; Heb 1,3; Jn 1,3). Besides, the Son is the Word (Jn 1,1.18), the wisdom of God (1 Cor 1,24), the image of God (2 Cor 4, 4; Col 1,15); and one may add from the Old Testament whatever is said of wisdom (Prov 8, 22 ff) and of the creative word of God (Ps 32,6; Gen 1). But if one were to infer from such passages that the Son was born of the Father only when the Father willed to create, in order to assist the Father in creating and governing the universe, one would be involved in many errors. (Fs) (notabene)

40d For the substance of the Father and that of the Son is one and the same substance; therefore, if the Father is eternal, so also is the Son. Again, if the Father exists for his own sake, not for the sake of his creatures, no less does the Son exist for his own sake. (Fs)

41a And if the Father exists necessarily, then the Son exists necessarily. Further, just as the Father and the Son share the one substance, so in reality they also share a single will; and so the Son cannot be some object, really distinct from the Father's will, and arising out of a decision of the Father's will.1 (Fs)

41b Now these conclusions follow, beyond a shadow of doubt, from more recent theology, but the ante-Nicene authors, to judge from the language they used, had little grasp of them, and so they have been charged with subordinationism.2 (Fs)

41c If the term, subordinationism, is used to describe a certain fact, namely, that the ante-Nicene authors were not well up in the theology of a later age, then of course its use is both legitimate and useful. For before anything can be understood and explained, one must know precisely what it is that is to be understood and explained. (Fs)

41d On the other hand, if we consider the proper goal of scientific inquiry, which is understanding, then the term, subordinationism, becomes a source of the greatest obscurity and confusion. For it is anachronistic to conceive the doctrine of the ante-Nicene authors according to the criteria of a later theology, and anachronism precludes correct historical understanding. (Fs)

It is for this reason that, when we come later on to deal with the structure of the ante-Nicene movement,1 we shall speak, not of subordinationism, but rather of a kind of dialectic, whereby firm belief in the revealed word of God gradually eliminated less exact conceptions, and thus prepared the way for the later theology. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Tertullian: Denken in Bildern (Beispiel); Wurzel, Schössling, Frucht

Kurzinhalt: This passage shows how much Tertullian's mind is tied to images

Textausschnitt: 45a Therefore, although the Son is a substance emitted, or extruded, from the substance of the Father, their intimate union of knowledge and love, and the non-separation of the Son from the Father, constitute them as one. To explain this non-separation Tertullian draws on familiar images, used also by the Montanists:

"For God brought forth the Word, as the Paraclete also teaches, as the root brings forth the shoot, as the spring brings forth the stream, as the sun brings forth the beam. And these manifestations are emissions [probolas] of those substances from, which they proceed. And I would not hesitate to say that the shoot is the son of the root, the stream the son of the spring, the beam the son of the sun; because every source is a parent and everything that is brought forth from a source is its offspring. Much more is this true of the Word of God, who received the name of Son in the proper sense. But the shoot is not separated and removed from the root, nor the stream from the spring, nor the beam from the sun; neither is the Word removed and separated from God. Therefore, using these comparisons, I declare that it is my view that God and his Word, the Father and the Son, are two: for the root and the shoot are two things, but conjoined; the spring and the river are two manifestations, but undivided; the sun and the beam are two aspects, but they cohere. If one thing comes out of another, it is necessarily a second thing, different from that out of which it came, but it is not on that account separate from it. But where there is a second [person], there are two [persons], and where there is a third, there are three. For the Spirit is third, with God and the Son, as the fruit is third, coming from the root and the shoot, and the stream is third, coming from the spring and the river, and the point of light is third, coming from the sun and the beam. Nothing, however, is exiled from its source, from which it draws its properties. This conception of the trinity, as moving out from the Father in closely connected sequence, is in no way opposed to the monarchy, and it preserves the order of the divine economy".1 (Fs)

46a This passage shows how much Tertullian's mind is tied to images: the Son is other than the Father because a substance is emitted, or extruded, from a substance, and he proceeded, or came out; God is one, however, because two things are conjoined, two manifestations are undivided, two aspects cohere, because nothing is exiled from its source, and because the phases are tightly-woven. Elsewhere he says:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Tertullian, Monarchie

Kurzinhalt: But if he who is the monarch has a son, and if the son is given a share in the monarchy, this does not mean that the monarchy is automatically divided ...

Textausschnitt: 46b Thus Tertullian conceived the unity of God. Of the divine monarchy he has this to say:

"... But I say that there is no power and dominion that is so much that of a single person, so much his alone, so much a monarchy, that it is not also administered by other persons, close to him, whom he has appointed as his officials. But if he who is the monarch has a son, and if the son is given a share in the monarchy, this does not mean that the monarchy is automatically divided, ceasing to be a monarchy. For the monarchy belongs principally to him by whom it was communicated to the son and, being exercised by two who are so closely united with each other, it remains a monarchy ... But pay attention, I beg you, to the meaning rather than the sound of the words I use. A monarchy is overthrown only when another power, of equal condition and degree, and thus a rival, comes forward, as when Marcion introduces a second god, in opposition to the Creator, or when Valentinus and his followers, and Prodicus and his, bring in their many gods. Then indeed is the monarchy overthrown and the Creator destroyed".8 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Unterschied: Tertullian, "von einer Substanz", Geist als "Körper sui generis - Athanasius, homoousion; dem Sohn kommt alles zu ...

Kurzinhalt: ... difference between the meaning of the phrase, "of one substance", as used by Tertullian, and that of "homoousion", as used by Athanasius ... "All that is said of the Father is also to be said of the Son ...

Textausschnitt: 3. The next point is to grasp the difference between the meaning of the phrase, "of one substance", as used by Tertullian, and that of "homoousion", as used by Athanasius. For both Tertullian and Athanasius set out to establish the same thesis, namely that the Father is God, that the Son is also God, and that there is only one God. Equally, each of them makes use of images as a means of eliciting some understanding of this thesis. Athanasius, however, inquires so diligently, piously and soberly-to use the phrase of the first Vatican council-that his reason, illumined by faith, discovers the following rule: "All that is said of the Father is also to be said of the Son, except that the Son is Son, and not Father". On the other hand, Tertullian's mind is so immersed in the sensible that for him a spirit is a body sui generis; so confined is he to the sphere of the imagination that he explains the unity of the divine substance in terms of the concord of a monarchy, and a kind of organic undividedness and continuity. (Fs)

47b However, it is not our purpose to blame the ante-Nicene Christian authors for lacking the philosophical development that would have enabled them to shift from a naive to a critical realism, but rather to draw attention to the consequences of this lack. For it is not just that Tertullian had an inadequate conception of the unity of the divine substance; he even said some things that contradicted his own fundamental thesis. For he held that the Son was temporal: "There was a time when there was neither sin to make God a judge, nor a son to make God a Father".1 He may also have held that the Father and the Son were not, each in the same way, the divine substance: "... for the Father is the whole substance, whereas the Son is something derived from it, and a part of it, as he himself professes when he says, For the Father is greater than I".2 He also taught that the Son is subordinate to the Father: "... the one commanding what is to be done, the other doing what has been commanded".3 These positions stand in clear opposition to the principal thesis. For if the Son is God, and God is eternal, then the Son also is eternal; if the Son is God, and God is the whole divine substance, then the Son also is the whole divine substance; if the Son is God, and God commands, then the Son also commands. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Dialektik (dialectic), dialektischer Prozess; Unterscheidung: formales, materiales Prinzip, Ziel, der Prozess selbst; Tertullian

Kurzinhalt: The dialectic process is the actual elimination of the contradiction; in Tertullian we have found the material principle of a dialectic. For he held ...

Textausschnitt: 48a
4. We have been discussing the difference between the position of Tertullian and that of Athanasius. It is not enough, however, to grasp this difference; the significant thing is to understand the movement, or dialectic, that brought about the development from the one position to the other. This dialectic is, indeed, the heart of the whole matter. (Fs)

48b Within this dialectic we distinguish a material and a formal principal, the dialectic process itself, and the term, or goal, of the process. (Fs)

The material principle is an objective contradiction, which may be either explicit or implicit. (Fs)

The formal principle is the rational subject, under the aspect of his rationality, illumined either by the light of natural reason alone, or by the light of reason strengthened by the greater light of Faith. (Fs)

49a The dialectic process is the actual elimination of the contradiction. For it is a natural tendency of reason to get rid of contradictions. If the contradiction in question is only implicit, it is first made explicit; then one side of the contradiction can be clearly affirmed and the other denied. Where reason is somewhat tardy, or the matter itself rather difficult, the process is gradual: one by one, different elements of the contradiction are made explicit, until eventually the whole contradiction is eliminated. (Fs) (notabene)

49b The term of the dialectic is either heresy or an advance in theology. It is heresy, where only the light of natural reason is operative; it is an advance in theology, where reason is illumined and strengthened by faith. (Fs) (notabene)
49c Applying these general categories to our present topic, we can say that in Tertullian we have found the material principle of a dialectic. For he held that the Father is not the Son, nor the Son the Father, and that both are God: but he also held that the Son was temporal; he made a distinction between the whole divine substance, on the one hand, and a derived portion of it, on the other; and he had the Father commanding what was to be done, and the Son doing what was commanded. A few simple syllogisms suffice to show that the latter assertions contradict the basic thesis. Secondly, the formal principle, as far as rationality itself is concerned, is common to all thinking men; as far as reason illumined by faith is concerned, it is present in all believers, considered precisely as believers. Thirdly, the dialectic process itself is grasped, not in any single author, considered apart, but in a whole series of authors, coming one after the other, each in his own way trying to resolve the basic contradiction, until at last it is in fact totally eliminated. Finally, the term of this dialectic, inasmuch as it is an advance in theology, we shall find in Athanasius; inasmuch as it is heresy, we shall find it in the Arians. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Origenes, Dialektik; ho theos - theos; Logos: Gott durch Partizipation

Kurzinhalt: We are now in a position to locate Origen within the general dialectic that brought about a development in the manner of conceiving the Trinity; Origen understood the phrase, "The Father is greater than I" as having universal application: ...

Textausschnitt: 59c
4. We are now in a position to locate Origen within the general dialectic that brought about a development in the manner of conceiving the Trinity. (Fs)

60a In the first place, through his insistence on the strict immateriality of both the Father and the Son, he undermined every conception or theory which, unable to transcend the level of the senses, could think of the generation of the Son, and the unity of the Father and the Son, only in terms of "within" and "without", "separated" and "united", or other such spatial images. (Fs)

60b Further, not only did Origen exclude every appeal to a material analogy; he also introduced a spiritual analogy. For he focussed attention on a procession which belongs to rational consciousness itself, within which, in his own words, "an act of willing proceeds from the mind". In some such way, he thought, we should conceive the Son's proceeding from the Father. (Fs)

60c Origen's conception of this spiritual analogy is, however, different from that of later theologians, who had a precise grasp of the meaning of consubstantiality, and so admitted only one divine intellect, common to the Father, the Son and the Holy Spirit, and similarly, only one divine will. Origen, on the other hand, held that the Father knows himself much more perfectly than the Son knows him,1 and that the will of the Son is only the image of the Father's will.2 (Fs)

60d The Father and the Son, then, are two hypostases, one of which, coming from the other, is related to its source as image to exemplar; these two hypostases, each in its own manner, create and maintain their mutual relationship, by understanding and willing. "This image", says Origen, "also contains the unity in nature and substance of the Father and the Son".1 To come close to his meaning here, one may think of the highest form of Platonic participation, and think of it both as intellectual and as free. (Fs)

61a
5. It will be well to say something about this notion of participation, which somehow pertains to the very notion of image itself. For Origen ho theos and theos had different meanings, as had ho logos and logos. And so he thought that he had found a middle way between Sabellianism and Adoptionism, inasmuch as he held that the Father was the God, while the Son was God by participation, and was also the mediator through whom others were deified. (Fs)

[...]

"Herein1 lies the solution to the problem that disturbs many people who, professing their love for God, and fearful of saying that there are two gods, fall prey to false and impious doctrines, either denying that the Son is really distinct from the Father, because he whom they call the Son is only God with another name, or else denying the Son's divinity, saying that his nature and essence are quite different from the Father's.2 To them we say that autotheos is indeed the God [God himself], which is why our Saviour, praying to the Father, says, 'that they may know you, the one true God'. Whatever else, other than him who is called autotheos, is also God, is deified by participation, by sharing [metochE] in his divinity, and is more properly to be called not the God [ho theos] but simply God [theos]. This name, of course, is his in a special way, who is the first-born of all creation, being the first to be with God, drawing the divinity to himself; he is more to be honoured in this name than the other gods there are besides him (they whose God is the God [ho theos], according to the saying, 'The God of gods has spoken, and has summoned the earth') to them he gives being, drawing in abundance from God that whereby he might make them gods and give them help and support according to his own goodness".3


61b This style of thought, grounded in Plato's notion of participation, is applied by Origen not only to the divinity itself, as in the passage just cited, but also to other things. [...] Indeed, Origen understood the phrase, "The Father is greater than I" as having universal application: the Son and the Holy Spirit are incomparably more excellent than all other things, but between them and the Father, in turn, there is at least as great a gap, if not a greater one

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Origenes (Origon): Schwierigkeit der Beurteilung; Konsubstantialität oder Kreatur; Patron der Arianer

Kurzinhalt: Secondly, to move from words to meaning, it is clear (1) that Origen always held that the Son was eternal, in the strict sense of the word; (2) that ...

Textausschnitt: 64a
6. Mainly because of its relevance for the later Arian controversy, we must touch briefly on the question, whether or not Origen considered the Son a creature. (Fs)

64b First of all, if we accept the version of Rufinus, the following passage is from Origen:

"For we do not say, as the heretics think, that some part of the Father's substance became the Son; neither do we say that the Son came from outside of the Father's substance, being created by the Father, so that there was a time when he was not. But, excluding every corporeal interpretation, we do say that the Word and wisdom were born, without any bodily process, of the invisible and incorporeal God, in the manner in which an act of willing proceeds from the mind. And thus it will not seem absurd, since he is called 'the Son of his love' (cf. Col 1,13), if in the same way he is considered the Son of his will".1 (Fs)

64c To which one may add: "For he does not become Son, from having not been Son, through the adoption of the Spirit, but is by nature Son".2 (Fs)

65a On the other hand, if we take Jerome's word, we are led to a different conclusion. (Fs)

"Candidus says that the Son is of the Father's substance, erring in this, that he asserts a propolE, that is, an extrusion from the Father's substance. Origen, on the other hand, according to Arius and Eunomius, rejects the notion of his being extruded, or born, because this would suggest that the Father is divided into parts; what he says, rather, is that the Son is the highest and most excellent of creatures, and that he came into being through the Father's will, as did all other creatures".3

65b Now it is certain that verbally Origen called the Son ktisma and that he said that he was a creature; but so did many others, because they applied to the Son the passage in the book of Proverbs 8,22.4 (Fs) (notabene)

65c Secondly, to move from words to meaning, it is clear (1) that Origen always held that the Son was eternal, in the strict sense of the word; (2) that he affirmed that the Son was not made, and that he was the first-born of everything that was made (ton agenEton kai pasEs genEtEs physeOs prOtotokon);5 (3) that he said they were not to be listened to who inferred from John 1,4 that the Word was made (genEton einai ton logon);6 (4) that he denied that the Son had a beginning, before which he was not (archEn ... einai uiou proteron ouk ontos)7 (Fs)

66a Thirdly, there are no grounds for supposing that while the notion of consubstantiality developed only gradually, everybody always had a clear conception of creation. In fact, neither Plato, nor Aristotle, nor the Stoics, nor the Gnostics, had a doctrine of creation, in the strict sense of the word. Even the early Christians, who acknowledged the fact of creation, used the words agennEtos (unbegotten) and agEnetos (not made) without discrimination;8 and although Methodius and Origen, in the third century, introduced some clarity into the use of these two terms, the Arians, in the fourth century, re-introduced a kind of primitive obscurity and confusion.9 (Fs)

66b Fourthly, as Athanasius proposed a clear conception of con-substantiality, so he also had a clear and lucid notion of creation. For his distinction between creating and making is a profound one;10and he also established with precision the difference between being unbegotten and being created.11 So he could argue effectively: If he is Son, he is not a creature; and if he is a creature, then he is not Son.12 These clear ideas and sharp distinctions show plainly enough how closely connected are the two questions: Is the Son consubstantial with the Father? and, Is the Son a creature?13 (Fs)

66c Fifthly, if we accept this distinction, namely, that the Son is either consubstantial with the Father, or else he is a creature, then we must say that Origen's subordinationism, since it excludes consubstantiality in the strict sense, also implies that the Son is a creature. However, this kind of implication, which in fact is only an element of an objective dialectic, is not to be confused with a conclusion that somebody has actually drawn. The Arians drew such a conclusion, seeking to establish Origen as patron of their own position. So also did those who condemned Origen. But it is not at all clear that Origen either drew or could have drawn such a conclusion himself.14 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Arius, Arianismus: 3 Phasen (Konstantin)

Kurzinhalt: Arianism arose in Alexandria but spread rapidly ... In the earlier period there were three main phases ...

Textausschnitt: 68a Arianism arose in Alexandria but spread rapidly. Before long it had the whole Eastern part of the Roman Empire in a state of turmoil that was to last nearly fifty years; then, having spread to the external proletariat it was transported by the conquering barbarians into the Western part of the Empire. In the earlier period there were three main phases. During the first phase, under the Emperor Constantine the First, who died in 337, stubborn defenders of the Council of Nicea were deposed from their episcopal sees, because of many and various accusations brought against them by the Arians. The second phase, under the Emperor Constantius, who died in 361, was marked by a plethora of minor councils and a multiplicity of creeds. In the third and final phase the faith of Nicea began to find general acceptance and within a short time was in fact universally accepted. (Fs)

68b Although they share the same name, the Arians did not all share the same basic position. Arius himself held that the Son was a creature. But the followers of Eusebius, bishop of Caesarea, did not so much embrace the teaching of Arius as take a stand against the council of Nicea: they criticised the council for using non-scriptural language; they urged that the opinion of Marcellus, bishop of Ancyra, be accepted as the authentic exposition of the Nicene formula; and they themselves were content with the ambiguous doctrine of Origen, to which they appealed, namely, that the Son is, without difference, most like the Father. Then came those whom we may call the second-generation Arians: the Anomoeans, Aetius and Eunomius, who attempted a philosophically rigorous proof that the Son was a creature; the Homoeousians, such as Basil, bishop of Ancyra, who rejected the homoousion of Nicea, but held that the Son was truly Son, similar to the Father in substance (ousia) and in all things; and finally, the Homoeans, who said that the Son should be called the image of God, according to the usage of scripture, and that the very words ousia, homoousion, homoiusion, should be proscribed. (Fs) (notabene)

69a
1. The roots of Arianism are traced back to Lucian of Antioch, founder of the exegetical school at Antioch, who favoured subordinationism, spent a long time outside of the Church but then apparently underwent a conversion, and died a martyr's death in 312. Arius and his first followers studied under Lucian, but what his own teaching was-or indeed, whether there were two Lucian's or only one-can be established only by laborious historical reconstruction. For the literature on the subject, see Altaner, p. 242. (Fs)

2. Arius, an Alexandrian priest, having studied under Lucian, later became head of the exegetical school at Alexandria.1 He publicly attacked the teaching of Alexander, bishop of Alexandria, for which, in 318, he was excommunicated by the synod of Alexandria. In spite of this, he continued to spread his own doctrine, and even managed to find favour with other bishops. So again he was condemned, first by the synod of Antioch,2 in 325, and then, in the same year, by the ecumenical council of Nicea. He died in the year 336. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Arius; Brief an Alexander; der Sohn (logos ) geschaffen; Sohn: unvollkommene Erkenntnis des Vaters

Kurzinhalt: Arius and his companions wished to improve on the New Testament and the Apostles' Creed by excluding every metaphor and every anthropomorphism ...

Textausschnitt: 70a Arius' letter to Alexander was signed by two bishops, six priests and six deacons. The profession of faith that it contains is as follows:

"This, blessed father, is the faith that we received from our elders, and also learned from you. We acknowledge one God, who alone is unbegotten, who alone is eternal, who alone is without beginning, who alone is true, who alone is immortal, who alone is wise, who alone is good, who alone is full of power; it is he who judges all, who controls all things, who provides all things; and he is subject to no change or alteration; he is just and good; he is the God of the Law and of the Prophets and of the New Covenant:

"This one God, before all time, begot his only-begotten Son, through whom he made the ages and the universe. He begot him not just in appearance, but in fact; by his own will he made his son to subsist and he made him unchangeable and unalterable. God's perfect creature, he is unlike any other creature; begotten, yes, but unique in the manner of his begetting:

"This offspring of God is not, as Valentinus taught, an emission of the Father; neither is he, as Mani taught, a part of the Father, consubstantial with him; neither is he the same person as the Father, as Sabellius said, dividing the unity; nor is it, as Hieracas held, as if there were one torch from another or one lamp with two parts. Neither is it true to say that he who previously existed was then begotten, or constituted as son: you yourself, blessed Father, many times, in council and in the midst of the Church, refuted those who held these views:

"But we say that he was created, by God's will, before all ages; from the Father he received being and life, and in creating him the Father conferred his own glory on him. Yet the Father, in giving all things into his possession, did not despoil himself of them: he contains all things in himself in an unbegotten way, for he is the source of all things. Therefore there are three substances (hypostases). (Fs)

"But God, who is the cause of all things, is absolutely the only one who is without beginning. The son, born of the Father before all time, created and constituted in being before all ages, did not exist before he was begotten: born outside of time, generated before all else, he alone received being from the Father. He is not eternal, co-eternal with the Father, nor is he, as the Father is, unbegotten; neither, as some say of things that are related to each other, does he have being simultaneously with the Father. For thus there would be two unbegotten principles. But God, as he is a unity (monas) and source of all things, so he exists before all things. Therefore he also exists before the Son, as we have heard you preach to the whole people. Inasmuch, then, as the Son has being, glory and life from the Father, in so much is God his source. He is his Lord, as being his God and existing before him. (Fs)

"If some people understand the phrases from him, from the womb and I came forth from the Father and I come as implying that he is a consubstantial part of the Father, or a sort of emission, they make the Father composite, divisible and changeable; indeed God would be a body, if they had their way, and the incorporeal God would be affected in ways in which only bodies can be affected".1

71a We can gather from this that Arius and his companions wished to improve on the New Testament and the Apostles' Creed by excluding every metaphor and every anthropomorphism. The Father alone would be unbegotten, without any source, and eternal; the Son, because he has a source, would be neither unbegotten nor eternal, but would be a kind of supreme creature, made out of nothing through the will of the Father. Admittedly the phrase "out of nothing" does not occur in the long passage just cited, but Arius himself had earlier written to Eusebius of Nicomedia, a fellow-student of his at the school of Lucian, in the following vein:

"But what we say, and what we believe, is what we have taught, and still teach: namely, that the Son is neither unbegotten nor in any way a part of the unbegotten, and neither was he made from any pre-existing matter; by the decision and counsel (of the Father) he subsisted before all ages. He is fully God, God's only-begotten Son, and he is immutable; but before he was begotten, before he was created, before he was constituted in being by the Father, he did not exist. For he was not unbegotten. They persecute us because we say that the Son has a source and a beginning, but God has not. This is why they abuse us, and also because we use the phrase 'out of nothing' (ex non exstantibus); but we used this phrase because the Son is not a part of the Father, nor, on the other hand, was he made out of any preexisting matter".1 (notabene)

72a Here Arius says that the Son is immutable, but on earlier occasions he had taught that he was mutable, according to the letter of Alexander of Alexandria, written to all the Bishops of the Church, about the year 319:

"The language they have invented, which runs counter to the meaning of scripture, is as follows:


"God was not always Father, but there was a time when he was not Father. The Word of God did not always exist, but was made out of nothing. For God, who is, brought into existence, out of what was nonexistent, one who was non-existent, and so there was a time when he was not. For the Son is something created, something made. He is not similar to the Father in respect of substance (ousia); neither is he the true and natural Word of the Father, nor is he the Father's true wisdom, but belongs to the things that have been made and created. He is improperly called the Word and wisdom, since he himself was made through the word of God in the proper sense, and through the wisdom that is in God, in which wisdom God made not only all other things, but him as well. Therefore, he is mutable by nature, as all rational creatures are. The Word is outside of God's substance, other than God's substance, apart from God's substance. The Son cannot tell all about the Father; for he cannot see the Father perfectly, and his knowledge of the Father is imperfect and imprecise. Indeed, the Son does not even know his own substance, as it is in itself. For it was for our sakes that he was made, so that through his instrumentality, as it were, God might create us; and he would not have existed, if God had not wished to bring us into being. To the question, whether it is possible that the Word of God is such that he could be changed in the way that the devil was changed, they did not draw back from answering that it is indeed possible, because, being made and created, he is by nature changeable".1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: homoousion; Eusebius (Anhänger des Arius): Brief an Paulinus; eg: Dialektik: Geist körperhaft - Geist rationalistisch

Kurzinhalt: nor do we believe, that the one infinite (unbegotten) being was divided in two, or that anything at all happened to him, that can happen only to bodies. There is one who is unbegotten,

Textausschnitt: 3. Eusebius, bishop of Nicomedia, who had enjoyed great influence at the court of the Emperor Licinius, was more a politician than a theologian. He was a friend and supporter of Arius, having been a fellow-student of his at the school of Lucian of Antioch. He died in 341 or 342. For editions and studies of his writings see Altaner, p. 240. (Fs)

73b Among the extant writings of Eusebius there is a letter (written about 321-22) to Paulinus, bishop of Tyre, in which he said:

"We heard nothing, my Lord, about two infinite (unbegotten) beings; neither did we learn, nor do we believe, that the one infinite (unbegotten) being was divided in two, or that anything at all happened to him, that can happen only to bodies. There is one who is unbegotten, and one who is truly begotten of him, but not begotten of his substance, and in no way unbegotten. He was made, totally different in nature and in power, though constituted in a perfect likeness to the nature and the power of him who made him. We believe that the manner of his coming to be is not only beyond the power of words to express, but also beyond the capacity of any mind, whether human or superhuman, to grasp in thought. We are not affirming here what we have thought out for ourselves, but what we have learned from scripture. For we learned that he was created, constituted and born in his substance, in nature immutable and ineffable, and in the likeness of his maker, as the Lord himself says: 'God created me, the beginning of all his ways; before all ages he constituted me, and before all the hills he begot me' (Prov 8, 22). But if he had come out of the Father, in the sense that he was of the Father, namely, as a part of him or an outflow of his substance, then it would not be right to say that he had been established or constituted in being. ...".1

Kommentar (11/12/07): "... that can happen only to bodies." Dialektik zwischen Geist, irgendwie körperlich gedacht (Tertullian), und Geist, rationalistisch gedacht. das Homoousion ist für den Rationalisten undenkbar, weil er letztlich über das "Körperliche" nicht hinauszugehen vermag.

73c Holding such a view, Eusebius-and with him four other bishops, Theognis of Nicea, Maris of Chalcedon, Theonas of Marmarica and Secundus of Ptolemais-was unwilling to subscribe to the formula of Nicea, because it contained the word homoousion. Socrates explains their reasoning thus:

"They said that 'consubstantial' applies to what comes out of something else, either as a part of it, or as an outflow, or as an eruption from it. By eruption, as shoots sprout from roots; by outflow, as children come from parents; by division, as two or three philae are taken from a lump of gold. In none of these ways, they asserted, did the Son of God come from the Father, and therefore they could not assent to that teaching. ...".1 (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Doppeldeutigkeit; philosophisch, theologisch: homoousion, ousia, Substanz, konsubstantiell (consubstantial)

Kurzinhalt: Philosophically, the ambiguity arises from different views of human knowing ... The theological ambiguity ... lies in this, that creatures are said to be consubstantial when they belong to the same species

Textausschnitt: 88a
1. The term, homoousion,1 or consubstantial, is both philosophically and theologically ambiguous. Philosophically, the ambiguity arises from different views of human knowing: for what one means by ousia, or substance (and thus by homoousion, or consubstantial), will depend on whether one thinks that it is known by sense, or only through true judgment. The theological ambiguity, which presupposes the doctrine of the Trinity, lies in this, that creatures are said to be consubstantial when they belong to the same species, whereas the consubstantiality of the divine persons implies numerical identity of substance. (Fs) (notabene)

88b Thus, according to Athanasius, one man is of the same nature (homophyEs) and of the same substance (homoousios) as another, but a man and a dog are different from each other both in nature and in substance (heterophyEs, heteroousios).2 (Fs)

88c Now, one whose philosophical position is that of naive realism would say that one man is consubstantial with another because the matter of one is derived from the matter of the other. But if one has advanced beyond naive realism, at least to a dogmatic realism, one will attend not to what is sensible, but to what is truly affirmed; therefore one will say that one man is consubstantial with another because of each of them the same substantial attributes are truly affirmed. (Fs) (notabene)

88d The theological ambiguity will clearly appear if we compare Peter and Paul, on the one hand, and on the other, the Father and the Son. Peter and Paul are consubstantial; the Father and the Son are consubstantial. But Peter and Paul are consubstantial, not because they have numerically the same individual substance-for indeed they have not-but because the individual substance of Peter and the really distinct individual substance of Paul both belong to the same species: Peter and Paul are two particular instances of the species, man. The Father and the Son are also consubstantial, but the analogy with Peter and Paul breaks down because unlike the consubstantial Peter and Paul, who are two men, the consubstantial Father and Son are one and the same God: there is numerically only the one God, who is, nonetheless, truly Father and truly Son. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: homoousion; Folgen aus einem falschen Verständnis: Sabellianismus (Sabellianism) - Tritheismus (tritheism);

Kurzinhalt: we do not grasp by the power of our intellects, but believe by faith, that ... Others, however, go off in different directions, to end up in diametrically opposed positions:

Textausschnitt: 92a
5. If the philosophical ambiguity of the term, homoousion, arises from the fact that some take ousia to mean body, or matter,1 whereas others take it to mean that which is, that which is truly affirmed to be, the theological ambiguity, as we have remarked, is rooted in the real difference between the consubstantiality of the divine persons, on the one hand, and that of creatures, on the other. For the consubstantiality of the divine persons means that they have numerically the same substance, whereas consubstantiality in the realm of creation implies numerically distinct individual substances that are specifically the same. (Fs) (notabene)

92b One very familiar illustration of this theological ambiguity is the doctrine of Apollinaris, who denied that Christ had a human soul; therefore, according to him, the incarnate Word, as incarnate, is not consubstantial with us.1 The orthodox position, on the other hand, as expressed both in the Formula of Union (DS 272) and in the decree of Chalcedon (DS 301 f), is that the Son is consubstantial with the Father in respect of his deity, and consubstantial with us in respect of his humanity. Indeed, even the Severian Monophysites, who would allow no distinction whatever between hypostasis and nature, professed, of their own accord, this dual consubstantiality of the Son: with the Father in respect of his deity, and with us in respect of his humanity.2 In this whole discussion, however, the term homoousion is taken in a twofold sense, since the human substance of Christ, and that of Peter, and that of Paul, are numerically distinct from each other, whereas the divine substance of the Father and the Son is numerically one and the same. (Fs)

92c Underlying this ambiguity is the divine mystery itself: for we do not grasp by the power of our intellects, but believe by faith, that the substance of the Father and that of the Son is one and the same substance. For this reason, it is only those who believe in the Trinity, and then only by dint of clear and consistent reasoning, who can overcome every difficulty. Others, however, go off in different directions, to end up in diametrically opposed positions: homoousion, as applied to the divine Persons, is taken to mean (1) that there is no real distinction between the Father and the Son, and (2) that the Father and the Son are not only two distinct persons, but also two gods. For if one starts out with a materialistic understanding of consubstantiality and then, ruling out every materialistic connotation of the term, applies it to the divine persons, since it is matter that grounds the distinction between corporeal beings, the denial of matter in God can be taken to imply the negation of all distinction; and so, quite naturally, one will conclude that the term, homoousion, as applied to God, smacks of Sabellianism. If, on the other hand, one begins with an understanding of homoousion that is derived from attending to true judgment, so that in calling things consubstantial one means that they have the same essential or substantial definition, then, since in the world of our experience, there are as many human substances as there are human persons, one may be led to infer, by parity of reasoning, that since there are three divine persons, or hypostases, so there are also three gods; and so, again quite naturally, and again quite falsely, the term homoousion will be considered suspect, but now because it seems to imply a tritheism. (Fs)

93a
6. It seems, in fact, that in the earlier phase of Arianism, the opponents of the council of Nicea were unwilling even to utter the word, homoousion. For example, if we may go by the index appended by E. Klostermann to his edition of Eusebius of Caesarea's Against Marcellus and On Ecclesiastical Theology, in neither of these works does the word homoousion occur at all-neither as used by Eusebius himself, nor within the passages that he cites from Marcellus.3 Again, if we look at the multiplicity of creeds that emerged from the various minor councils between the years 340 and 360, we might almost say that the only difference between them is this, that whereas the earlier ones make no mention at all of the term homoousion, a number of the later ones explicitly exclude it.18 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Interpretation 1: Glaubensbekenntnis Nicäa (Nicea)

Kurzinhalt: In interpreting the decree of the council of Nicca one must distinguish between its explicit and its implicit content ...

Textausschnitt: 95a
7. In interpreting the decree of the council of Nicca one must distinguish between its explicit and its implicit content; with regard to its implicit content one must make a further distinction, between a merely logical implication, on the one hand, and on the other, a conclusion that was actually drawn. (Fs)

95b Now, the council of Nicea set itself in direct opposition to those who asserted that the Son was not God, but a creature. Explicitly, therefore, it affirmed its faith in one God, adding at once, the Father almighty; then it named the Son, calling him Lord, God of God, begotten, not made, of the Father's substance, and consubstantial with the Father (DS 125). However, the decree of the council does not teach, in so many words, that the substance of the Father and that of the Son is one and the same substance. (Fs) (notabene)

95c Still, the affirmation of a single substance is logically contained in the Nicene decree. For in the first place, the council Fathers were monotheists. But if there is only one God, and the Father is truly God, and the Son is also truly God, then it follows necessarily that the divinity of the Father, and that of the Son, is one and the same divinity. Secondly, according to Athanasius, the council Fathers at first thought of writing that the Son is the true image of the Father, in every way most like the Father, but then, having seen how the Arians could get around such phrases

"they were forced, first, to go back again to the scriptures, to establish their position, and then to state more unambiguously what they had stated before, and finally, to write that the Son is consubstantial with the Father, in order to signify that the Son is not just similar to the Father, but is the same thing in similitude out of the Father. ..."1

95d Athanasius thus testifies to the fact that the Nicene decree is intended to go beyond the affirmation of a mere similarity between the Father and the Son, to an affirmation of identity. (Fs)

95e However, where and when the identity in substance of the Father and the Son, which is logically implied by the Nicene decree, was actually deduced as a logical conclusion, can besettled only by historical investigation. [...]

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Athanasius (Textstellen über Konsubstantialität); Intelligibilität in den "Bildern" der Schrift; Metapher: Licht - Sonne, Helligkeit

Kurzinhalt: Athanasius: ... we must transcend the senses utterly ...; Therefore, because they are one, and because the divinity itself is also one, what is said of the Father is also said of the Son, except the name, Father ...

Textausschnitt: 99c It is clear enough, then, how Athanasius' own mind worked, and, at least by his account, also the minds of the ante-Nicene authors and of the council Fathers at Nicea. They began with the images, taken mostly from scripture, with which we are now so familiar; in these images they grasped a certain intelligibility, which they expressed in the concept of consubstantiality; then, taking this concept of consubstantiality, derived from what is sensible, they adapted it, mainly in accordance with sayings of scripture itself, to the best of their ability, in order to conceive the divine generation of the Son. (Fs)

100a Athanasius certainly insisted on the need for the final step of adaptation: as the meaning of the word, Son, had to be adapted, so too had the meaning of the word, consubstantial:

"When we speak of him as offspring, we do not understand this in a human way, and when we acknowledge God as Father, we do not attribute bodily characteristics to him: these words and images we apply to God in a fitting manner, for God is not like man. In the same way, when we hear him described as consubstantial, we must transcend the senses utterly and, following the Proverb (23, 1), understand spiritually what is laid before us, to know that as life comes from the source and brightness from the light, so he is truly Son, out of the Father, and like the Father".1

100b As an indication of the extent to which Athanasius himself achieved this adaptation and purification we may cite the following:

[...]
If, on the other hand, he is the Father's own illuminating and creative power, without which the Father neither creates nor is known (for through him, and in him, all things are held together), why do we refuse to use the word that expresses this understanding of him? What else does it mean, to be of the same nature as the Father, if not, to be con-substantial with him? For it is not as if God, needing somebody to help him, assumed a son from outside of himself; neither are the things that God made equal to him in dignity, so that they ought to be honoured as he is honoured, or that we should say that they and the Father are one. Besides, who will say that the sun and its brightness are two different lights, or different substances? Or who will say that the brightness of the sun is an accident of the sun, and not purely and simply the sun's offspring, in such manner that, while the sun and its brightness are two things, they are nonetheless the one light, because the brightness comes from the sun? Since the nature of the Son is even more inseparable from the Father than the brightness of the sun is from the sun itself, and since the divinity of the Son is not something added to him-but the divinity of the Father is in the Son, so that whoever sees the Son sees the Father in him-why should the Son, who is like this, not be called consubstantial with the Father"?1
"Thus, the Son is not another god, because he is not something from outside of God. If one were to think of any divinity outside of God, then one would be introducing several gods. For although the Son, as begotten, is other than the Father, still, as God he is the same as the Father; and so he and the Father are one, both as having the same nature and as sharing the same divinity, as we have said. For the brightness itself is also light; it does not come after the sun, nor is it another light, nor does it become light by participating in the sun's light, but it is, in the fullest sense, the sun's offspring. Where light, in this way, gives birth to light, there is, of necessity, only one light, and it cannot be said that the sun and its brightness are two different lights; the sun and its brightness are two things, but there is one light, born of the sun, which with its brightness illuminates the whole universe. Similarly, the Son's divinity is also that of the Father, and so there is but the one divinity; so also there is but one God, and no other God apart from him. Therefore, because they are one, and because the divinity itself is also one, what is said of the Father is also said of the Son, except the name, Father. Thus, therefore, the Son is called God: And the Word was God; he is also called the Omnipotent: Thus says the Omnipotent, who was, and who is, and who is to come; similarly, he is the Lord: The one Lord, Jesus Christ; and he is also called the Light: I am the Light; and further, he is said to take away sins: But that you may know, he says, that the Son of Man on earth has power to forgive sins; and there are many other similar sayings in scripture. For the Son himself says: All things that the Father has are mine; and again: What I have is yours".1

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Kultur, kulturelle Entwicklung: klassisch - empirisch; partikulares Gut, Ordnungsgut, Wert;

Kurzinhalt: patterns of culture and cultural development in general; particular goods, the good of order, and value

Textausschnitt: 106b There are two quite different views of culture. There is an older, classicist, normative view, according to which one draws a distinction between the cultured and the uncultured. But there is also a modern view, which is empirical and anthropological: it acknowledges a multiplicity of cultures, so that the lowliest and the most primitive of tribes have a culture, no less than the most advanced and highly-developed peoples. It is the latter, empirical view of culture that we adopt here. (Fs) (notabene)

106c What we might call the material element of culture is made up of human capacities, human dispositions and habits, and human operations and their products. Capacities, dispositions and habits, operations and products are all interrelated: dispositions and habits are perfections and determinations of capacities; operations proceed promptly, spontaneously and with ease from dispositions and habits; and products, finally, are the results of operations. (Fs)

106d Next, we must note a certain principle or law of combination and composition. For operations are such that they can be joined one to another, to yield a composite product; indeed, a certain few basic operations, taken in a great variety of permutations and combinations, can yield an enormous diversity of results. So, for example, once one has learnt how to write the comparatively few letters contained in the alphabet of any language, one has the necessary equipment for writing everything that is said in that language. The same principle applies to the other arts, whether liberal or practical: in all of these some basic operations are discovered, which can then be modified, in various measures and to varying degrees, and adapted to new circumstances, and so there arises the possibility of an immense range of permutations and combinations. And the same applies to the sciences. If, for example, one examines the geometry of Euclid, or the Contra Gentiles of St. Thomas, one will find that the separate theorems or conclusions proceed from a relatively small number of operations, differently modified and adapted to suit different circumstances. Finally, it is not, of course, only the operations of separate individuals that can combine in this way; every instance of whatever kind of human collaboration involves the combination of operations of different individuals, to yield a composite product. (Fs)

107a But the reason why we act, or operate, is in order to attain some good. Since our ultimate end is essential goodness, our proximate ends are good by participation, and they are of three kinds: particular goods, the good of order, and value. Particular goods are all those things that meet the needs of particular individuals in particular places at particular times. The good of order is a formal principle that ensures a continual flow of particular goods; for example, matrimonial systems, technological, economical and political systems, literary and scientific systems, educational and religious systems are all goods of order. The good of value, finally, is what inspires a rational choice between one good of order and another, for example, Christian marriage, capitalism, democracy, etc. (Fs)

107b One might infer from all of this that what happens is that different races, having different scales of value, choose different goods of order, so that they may enjoy a steady flow of such and such particular goods, arising from such and such particular operations. That, however, would be a somewhat abstract, atemporal way of viewing human affairs. Concretely, values are perceived only in the good of order itself, the good of order is perceived only in the particular goods that it ensures, and the only actual particular goods are those that men, by the operations that they have in fact carried out, have learnt how to produce or to acquire. And so, if one wants to understand how cultures emerge and develop, it is rather on the operations that one ought to focus, to discover how they are carried out, how they are combined with each other, how they gradually coalesce into larger complexes, until eventually a kind of dynamic structure emerges-a structure, however, which is, as it were, only implicitly informed by the good of order and actuated by value, its proximate manifestation being men and women, united in friendship or divided by discord, carrying out operations that are aimed at the attainment of particular goods. (Fs)

108a Let us move on rapidly now to the point that we want to make, which is that some cultures remain for centuries almost unchanged, while others, whether from some kind of internal tension or from the pressure of external circumstances, keep finding new modes of operation, introducing new modifications of operations, trying out new permutations and combinations and enjoying new particular goods, and so even come to experiment with the good of order itself and to perceive new human values. To this fundamental kind of cultural evolution another kind is added when, by the process of communication or by the intermingling of peoples, two different cultures flow into and unite with each other, each adapting to the other, so that a third culture emerges, which is a kind of composite of the other two. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Unterschied: griechische - hebräische Kultur

Kurzinhalt: ... that the Greeks achieved the differentiation of consciousness that created the world of theory ... The Hebrews, however, took quite a different route. They did not undermine myth by theory but, schooled by divine revelation,

Textausschnitt: 108b Going back, first, beyond all the differences between the Hebrews and the Greeks, and back beyond every difference between any one culture and any other, to what is at the root of all cultures, we recall B. Malinowski's1 contention, that primitives display no less intelligence and reasonableness than anybody else, as long as they are involved in the practical tasks of daily living; that it is only when they move outside the familiar sphere of immediate experience that myth and magic invade, envelop and dominate everything. (Fs)

109a But if we leave the primitive aside, and move on to the ancient high civilisations of Egypt, Mesopotamia and Crete, of the valleys of the Indus and the Hoang Ho, or, on the American continent, of the Incas, the Mayas and the Toltecs, we find that while the external circumstances are vastly different from those of the primitives, the basic pattern is more or less the same. The area over which man exercises his practical intelligence has increased enormously: all the arts of construction, of writing, of calculating, and of organisation, are being impressively cultivated; yet political and religious life is still dominated by myth and magic. According to K. Jaspers there came a turning-point, a kind of axial period, between the years 800 and 200 B.C., when, with the destruction of the great, stable empires, men were more or less forced to develop their individual use of reason, and, accepting their responsibility as persons, undermined the power of myth.2 (Fs)

109b There were, however, notable differences in the manner in which this development took place. It was through literature, philosophy and science that the Greeks achieved the differentiation of consciousness that created the world of theory, which then directed and controlled the everyday world of practical common sense. One might say, then, that the Greeks drew out and developed from natural human capacities the instrument that of its very nature is opposed to myth and magic. The Hebrews, however, took quite a different route. They did not undermine myth by theory but, schooled by divine revelation, they broke its power, while remaining within the common sense world of practical living and retaining its categories. For they conceived God as a person, whom they identified with and recognised in certain concrete events: it was God who, in the Patriarchs and in Moses, and through the prophets, performed such and such deeds, said such and such, gave such and such commands, made such and such promises and issued such and such threats to the people. In conceiving God in this way, the Hebrews did not manage to avoid all anthropomorphism, nor did they succeed in explaining that what was symbolic was only symbolic; yet they had a truer knowledge of God than did the Greeks, they were more fully liberated from myth, and they had available more efficacious means for living a good life.3 (FS)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Problem: naiver Realismus (Irenäus, Klemens von Alexandrien)

Kurzinhalt: ... it is characteristic of all men ... to suppose, at least implicitly, that the ultimate and basic categories are not those of being, or of substance, but of place and time ...

Textausschnitt: 5. The problem of naive realism

113a If the remedy for the improper use of symbols was true knowledge of actually existing things, then obviously one had to fix on some determinate notion of reality. We have already referred to the naive realism of Tertullian, who pictured to himself the unity of the divine substance as a kind of organic unity. The difficulty, however, is not Tertullian's alone; it is characteristic of all men, unless and until they become wiser, to suppose, at least implicitly, that the ultimate and basic categories are not those of being, or of substance, but of place and time. (Fs)

113b This point can be illustrated from the writings both of Clement of Alexandria and of Ireneus. First we shall take Ireneus, who, wanting to demonstrate that there was only one supreme God, appealed above all to the notions of containing and of being contained:

"For either there must be one who contains all things, who in his own domain made each and every thing that has been made, according to his own will; or else there must be many gods who created, each one of them starting where another ends, each one bordering on another. In the latter case, all the gods must be included in something greater than them all, containing them all; and each one will be confined to his own area; and so none of them can be God. For each one, compared with all the others taken together, will have only a tiny part, and none of them can be called the Omnipotent; and so this view leads necessarily to impiety".1

113c Then, as if to cut off an escape-route of the Gnostics, Ireneus continues:

"But if they say-as some of them do indeed say-that being inside and being outside of the Pleroma are to be understood in terms of knowing and of not-knowing respectively, since whoever knows something is within that which he knows, then they will have to admit that the Saviour himself (whom they call the All) was in a state of ignorance... If therefore, the Saviour went outside of the Pleroma, in order to search for the lost sheep, then he went outside of knowledge, and so he was in ignorance. For either they must admit that he was spatially outside of the Pleroma, and then we bring all our earlier arguments against them; or else, understanding inside and outside in terms of knowledge and ignorance respectively, they will have to admit that he whom they acknowledge as Saviour, and much earlier, Christ, were in ignorance, having gone outside of the Pleroma (that is, outside of knowledge), in order to form their mother".2

114a To reinforce the point, let us add the following passages from the Excerpta ex Theodoto, which recent editors ascribe not to Theodotus the Gnostic, but rather to Clement of Alexandria:3

"... 'for I say to you that their (the children's) angels look always on the face of God'... 'Blessed are the pure of heart, for they shall see God'. But how can he, who has no shape, have a face? The apostle spoke of heavenly bodies, beautiful and intelligent; how could he have given them their different names, unless they had shape and form, unless, indeed, they were clothed in some body? 'The splendor of the heavenly bodies is different from that of terrestrial bodies, the splendor of the angels' bodies is different from both, and the splendor of the archangels' is different again': compared with the terrestral bodies, or with the stars, the angels and archangels are without shape, and incorporeal, but compared with the Son they can be said to be determinate bodies, accessible to sense. And the same can be said of the Son, compared with the Father ...".4
[...]

115a Clearly enough, these passages from the Excerpta not only give expression to a naive realism, grounded in a confusion to which men are naturally prone;1 but they also appeal to the scriptures in support of this naive realism. And the same is to be said of Ireneus.2 But there is a further element to be mentioned, and that is the influence of the Stoics. For on the basis of their own naive realism the Stoics had elaborated a whole system of materialistic philosophy; and many of the ante-Nicene authors, having quite an affinity with the Stoics, were moved to borrow their technical terms, and to adapt their distinctions and their theorems to their own ends.3 (Fs)

116a Now if error seeks supporting arguments in scripture and, at the same time, decks itself out in the terms and the distinctions of a philosophy, it can hardly be overcome except by a doctrine of hermeneutics, combined with an opposing philosophy. And this, in fact, is what happened at Alexandria. Clement himself, having discoursed at length, and with an abundance of illustrations, on the use of symbols,4 boldly concluded: [...]

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen Gottes: Weltseele, Idee, Demirug, omnipotent (Stoa, Platoniker, Irenäus)

Kurzinhalt: In the early Christian centuries belief in one, supreme God was quite common among the educated classes. The Stoics, however, ...

Textausschnitt: 118b The movement away from a literal to an allegorical interpretation of scripture and the introduction of a kind of philosophic mode of inquiry could hardly fail to have some effect on the manner of conceiving God. To this topic we now turn, which brings us closer to the topic of trinitarian doctrine. (Fs)

119a In the early Christian centuries belief in one, supreme God was quite common among the educated classes. The Stoics, however, held that this one God was the soul of the world, an intelligent fire that burned without consuming, a part of the material universe, although its active and its principal part. The Platonists, on the other hand, identified God with the supreme, subsistent Idea of the Good; some of them identified this supreme Idea with the Demiurge, who made everything else, but others said that Plato, in the Timaeus, introduced the Demiurge only as a kind of mythical character.1 The Gnostics, for their part, were so insistent on the transcendence and unknowability of God that for them the Demiurge was an inferior being, outside of the Pleroma, belonging not to the class of the "pneumatics", who are saved necessarily, but to that of the "psychics", whose fate is uncertain. For the Marcionites, finally, the Demiurge was that severe God of the Old Testament, from whom the good God of the New Testament purchased us. (Fs)

119b Against all such conceptions of God Ireneus writes:

"... there is only this one God, who made all things, who alone is omnipotent, who alone is Father, making and establishing all things, visible and invisible 'in the word of his power', This is the one, only God, maker of the world, who is above every principality, and above all other supernatural powers. He is the Father, he is God, he is the creator who made all things through himself, that is, through his own Word and his own Wisdom-heaven and earth, and the seas, and all that is in them. He it is who is just and good; he it is who formed man and planted paradise, who made the world, who sent the flood, and saved Noah; he is the God of Abraham, the God of Isaac, and the God of Jacob, the God of the living, whom the Law proclaims, whose praises the Prophets sing, whom Christ reveals, about whom the Apostles teach, and in whom the Church believes. He is the Father of our Lord, Jesus Christ; through his Word, which is his Son, he is revealed and made manifest to those to whom he is revealed: for they know him, to whom the Son has revealed him ...".2

120a In the conception of God presented here by Ireneus there are three elements to be distinguished. In the first place, there was the traditional Hebrew notion that God became known as a person identified with certain historical events: he was the God of the Patriarchs, the God of the Law and the God of the Prophets. Secondly, there was the extension and amplification of this notion, contained in the New Testament: the same God is also the Father of our Lord, Jesus Christ, the God of the gospel, the God of the apostolic preaching, the God of the Church, and the God of each individual Christian's religious experience. Thirdly, there was the doctrine, common to the Old and the New Testaments, that this God is supreme, that he is the Lord, the maker and shaper and sustainer of absolutely all things, and of all persons without exception, to whom no one else can even be compared, much less be considered his equal. (Fs)

120ba Now all three of these elements can equally be conceived as objects of faith; the third, however, is not beyond the grasp of natural human reason, and this is a point that did not escape either Justin or Ireneus, both of whom had some inkling of the distinction between faith itself and the preambles of faith. For as Ireneus wrote:

"Justin says well, in his book against Marcion: 'For I would not have believed the Lord himself if he had announced some other God than him who created and sustains us. But because there came to us, from the one God who made this world and fashioned us, who holds and controls all things, because from this one God there came his only-begotten Son, drawing all things together in himself, therefore my faith in him is firm, and my love of the Father unshakeable, God himself bestowing both on us'".1

120c One must not, of course, transpose this into a much later theological context, to infer that these ancient Christian writers had drawn a sharp distinction between reason and faith, and between fundamental and dogmatic theology. On the other hand, neither can what they said be reduced to a mere fideism. What exactly was the content of this preliminary notion of God, that was somehow to be presupposed in every discussion, and in every later development? There are many indications that the basic notion was of God as omnipotent; this omnipotence, however, was considered rather in its actual exercise than in the range of its possible application, and (more or less in the biblical manner) with little or no distinction made between substance, active potency, and activity itself.2 For in the scriptures the Father is most commonly called the Lord [kypios], as is the Son, and the earliest Christians retained this usage. Next, according to Eusebius3 Justin composed a work (not extant) entitled On the Monarchy.4 Theophilus of Antioch also, and more than once, spoke of the monarchy of God. And the doctrine of the Patripassians, that the Father and the Son are the same person, is said to have been based not on the affirmation of the unity of the divine essence, but rather on their determination to safeguard the monarchy.5 Tertullian, however, saw a grave danger that the mass of simple Christians would be deceived by such an argument;6 he himself considered that it was a sufficient refutation of the Patripassians to say that monarchy consisted not in the oneness of a ruler, but in the oneness of rule.7 Dionysius of Rome, finally, called the doctrine of the monarchy the most august doctrine of the Church.8 And one might add that Ireneus, writing against the Gnostics about the one God, who is the creator of all, seems to come to his most fundamental point when he concludes that the opinion of his adversaries leads to "the voiding of the name, Omnipotent, and such an opinion necessarily ends up in impiety".9 Further, we have already seen the argument of Hippolytus, that the trinity does not destroy the divine unity, because the power of the three Persons is one. And Clement of Alexandria considered that other names of God (for example, One, Good, Mind, That-itself-which-is, Father, God, Creator, Lord) taken not singly, but all together, indicate the power of the Omnipotent.10 Finally, as we remarked before, the contribution of Origen to this whole discussion lies in the area of exegesis, rather than of metaphysics.11 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen Gottes: Origines (Origen)

Kurzinhalt: It is clear from this passage that Origen was not enough of a speculative thinker to conceive that there could be anything incorporeal in God's creation. It is also clear that ...

Textausschnitt: 123b Origen, following in Clement's footsteps, and as if suspecting that there could still be some lingering doubt about the matter in some people's minds, undertook a systematic refutation of the notion that God was a body.1 He called the Son wisdom itself, in order to make it understood that he was neither something unsubstantial nor, on the other hand, a body;2 and although in general he doubted that any rational creature could live entirely without a body-at least some finer, less crass kind of body-he totally excluded the Blessed Trinity from this general rule. The following passage is rather long, but it is worth transcribing here, so well does it reveal both the mind and the method of Origen:

"At this point some ask whether, as the Father generates the Son and brings forth the Spirit, but not in the sense that they did not previously exist-since in the Trinity there is no before and after-but in the sense that the Father is the origin and source of the Son and the Spirit, whether there might not be a similar sort of communion or closeness between rational creatures and corporeal matter. To investigate the matter more fully and carefully, they begin by asking whether this corporeal nature itself, which supports the life and contains the motions of spiritual and rational minds, will also share in their eternity, or whether, separated from them, it will perish and go to earth. To get a more precise grasp of the matter, it seems that we must first ask, whether it is at all possible for rational natures, when they have come to the peak of holiness and blessedness, to remain without bodies-which to me seems very difficult, if not impossible, to maintain-or whether they must always remain joined to bodies. If someone were to explain how they could in fact be entirely without bodies, then it would follow that corporeal nature was created from nothing, for periods of time, so that, just as from not-being it came into being, in the same way, when its service was no longer required, it ceased to be. (Fs)

"However, if it cannot at all be affirmed that any nature, excepting the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, can live apart from the body, then, led by reason, we are forced to the conclusion that while it is, first and foremost, rational creatures that were created, still it is only in thought that material substance can be separated from them; to our way of thinking, it was made for them and after them, but they never did and never do live without it, for only the life of the Trinity can be rightly thought to be incorporeal. Therefore, as we have said above, that material substance, being by nature such that it is transformed from one thing into another, when it is drawn to beings of a lower order, becomes a more crass and solid kind of body and serves to distinguish the visible species of this world in all their variety; but when it is at the service of more perfect and more blessed beings, it shines in the splendor of the 'heavenly bodies', and, in the vesture of 'the spiritual body', it adorns 'the angels of God' or 'the children of the resurrection', all of whom together will fill out the variety and the diversity of the one world. (Fs)
[...]

125a It is clear from this passage that Origen was not enough of a speculative thinker to conceive that there could be anything incorporeal in God's creation. It is also clear that he was so much an exegete that he considered that a fuller understanding of the matter was to be sought, with all due fear of God and with all due reverence, in the scriptures themselves. Let us look, at least, at a single sample of the method he used, and the great care he took, in examining the scriptures himself. Commenting on the first verse of the prologue to St. John's Gospel, he asserted that it is not enough to ask in what sense Christ is the Word, while leaving out of account all of his other titles, such as, the light of the world, the way, the truth and the life, the good shepherd, I am he, who speaks with you, the master, the Lord, the Son of God, the door, the true vine, the bread of life, the living bread, the first and the last, Alpha and Omega, the beginning and the end, the light of the gentiles, the servant of Jahwe, and, as he said, thousands more.1 Origen himself looked for a synthesis of all of these; he recognised that there was a distinction of reason between them;2 he affirmed that "Wisdom" was older than all of the other titles;3 and he went, more or less systematically, through the whole list of titles.4 (Fs)

126a However, no one who reflects at all can assemble and order titles in this way, without at least giving some hint as to what that reality is, to which the titles are to be attributed. Origen's solution to this fundamental problem was predominantly Platonist: the Father was divinity itself and goodness itself; the Son, on the other hand, was the Word itself, wisdom itself, truth itself, the resurrection-and-the-life itself, but the Father was something better than all of these, something unknown to us.5 If one asks how these Platonic ideas could then be brought together and united with each other, while being associated with the two distinct hypostases of the Father and the Son, the answer would seem to lie in the eclecticism of that time:6 as well as taking over the categories of the Platonists, Origen also borrowed from Stoic materialism the notions of ousia and hypostasis.7 If one urges that this is hardly consistent, then one has come to the basic difficulty, which can be explained in two ways. For, in the first place, as we remarked above, Hal Koch believes that one cannot insist too strongly that Origen was not a metaphysician, in the proper sense of the term. Secondly, however, the point must be made differently, more from a theological point of view. For, while Origen accepted with his whole heart both the truth of the scriptures and the preaching of the Church,8 what he sought above all was a spiritual meaning, going beyond the totality of literal meaning.9 Unfortunately, however, neither in the philosophers nor by his own efforts did he find any sure criterion by which to judge the truth of this spiritual meaning. This failure of his should cause us no surprise, since the doctrine expounded in Plato's dialogues is aimed essentially at raising the mind above the things of sense, generating enthusiasm for spiritual things and replacing myth with better myths; but it contains so little understanding of the Yes, Yes, and No, No of the gospel, that both being and non-being are also reduced to ideas.10 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen 1: Trinität; Herr: Bezug zu uns - konsubstantiell: Bezug zu Gott; dogmatischer Realismus (keine philosophische Spekulation)

Kurzinhalt: ... to speak of the Son as consubstantial with the Father is to consider the divinity in itself, going beyond religious experience ... this kind of realism is dogmatic ... in the sense that it is not the product of any philosophic reflection ...

Textausschnitt: 7. The Development of Trinitarian Doctrine

127a If we examine the doctrine of the Blessed Trinity in the developed form represented by the determinations of the council of Nicea we can distinguish in it three main elements. In the first place there was the revealed name, Son; many other titles were applied to Christ but from the beginning he was called "Son" in a very special sense. The second element, derived from both the Old and the New Testaments, is the insistence, against the Gnostics and the Marcionites, that there is no distinction between God the Creator and the true God, and the insistence that the one, true God is radically distinct from all creatures.1 From both of these elements taken together it follows that the Son, who was also acknowledged as maker and Lord and judge of all, is truly Son, born of the Father, and cannot be considered a part of creation.2 (Fs)

127b However, the decree of Nicea would appear to contain a third element quite distinct from the first two, namely, the ontological mentality that finds expression in the affirmation that the Son is consubstantial with the Father. For to speak of God as creator, to speak of him as "Lord of all' is to speak in terms of his relative attributes, using categories that resonate with religious experience: when we speak of God in this way we also affirm our total dependence on him. On the other hand, to speak of the Son as consubstantial with the Father is to consider the divinity in itself, going beyond religious experience to employ or to suppose the scientific categories of an ontology. And since this mode of speech has long been a major stumbling block, giving many people the impression that the Church at Nicea had abandoned the genuine Christian doctrine, which was religious through and through, in order to embrace some sort of hellenistic ontology, we must examine the matter with some care.1 (Fs)

128a In the first place, there is nothing in the Old or in the New Testament that is clearer than this, that the word of God, the word announced by the prophets when they said, "Thus says the Lord ..." is to be preserved intact by the Apostles in accordance with the precept, "Let your word be 'Yes, Yes' and 'No, No'" (Mt 5,37), and that this same word not only was preached by the apostles but was also to be preserved in all its purity, even to the extent that any other word, even if preached by an angel, was to be anathema (Gal 1,8).1 (Fs)
128b Now this word of God not only grounds the dogmatism of the Church, which cuts off heretics with the celebrated formula, "If anyone says ... let him be anathema"; it also contains implicitly a certain dogmatic realism. In order to explain what this means we shall have to consider in turn the words "realism", "dogmatic" and "implicitly". (Fs)

128c In the first place, then, the word of God contains a realism, both because it is to be believed and not contradicted, and also because it is a true word, telling of things as in fact they are. For realism consists in this, that the truth that is acknowledged in the mind corresponds to reality. But whoever believes the true word of God certainly acknowledges truth in his mind-indeed his adherence to this truth is so complete that he banishes from his thoughts even the slightest suspicion that things might be other than as God has revealed them to be. (Fs)

129a Secondly, this kind of realism is dogmatic, not only in the sense that it belongs to the very essence of dogma, but also in the sense that it is not the product of any philosophic reflection. To the extent that one is a philosopher one will make no affirmation for which one cannot assign sufficient and cogent reasons. But the realism that is found in the word of God as revealed, preached and accepted does not consist in any further philosophic reflection; it is simply a matter of sincere acceptance of the word of God that has been revealed and preached. (Fs) (notabene)

129b Thirdly, while this dogmatic realism is contained in the word of God, it is present only implicitly, not acknowledged explicitly. We are not saying that Isaiah, Paul and Athanasius knew that they were dogmatic realists. We are not saying that they made clear distinctions between the good and the true, and the will and the mind, and so between the mind itself and the reality to which the mind's truth corresponds. Much less are we saying that they drew all the consequences that would follow from these distinctions. What in fact we are saying is that these men had minds, that they knew the word of God and that they lived according to the reality that they came to know through God's true word. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen 2: Trinität; religiöse Erfahrung - Wort Gottes

Kurzinhalt: ... the categories of religious experience are not the same as those contained implicitly in the word of God ... the Nicene concept of consubstantiality does not go beyond the dogmatic realism that is contained implicitly in the word of God

Textausschnitt: 129c After these preliminary remarks we may return to the question whether the Church, in the decree of the council of Nicea, went beyond the categories of religious experience to embrace a hellenistic ontology. The question, of course, has its own presuppositions: leaving out of account the word of God, it makes a disjunction between religious experience on the one hand and hellenistic ontology on the other. However, if such presuppositions are appropriate to rationalists and liberal theologians, for whom the word of God is but an archaic, not to say mythical, mode of speech, they cannot be admitted by those who accept the word of God in faith; neither can they be admitted by those historians who conceive history not as a disguised polemic but as a science that seeks to understand the mentality of another age. For what Isaiah felt compelled to announce, and Paul to preach, and Athanasius to defend, was not just a personal religious experience, but the word of God, and the categories of religious experience are not the same as those contained implicitly in the word of God. For there is no doubt that the categories derived from religious experience will contain a reference to the subject who has the experience, but "the word of God is not tied", restricted to speaking of things as related to us and unable to speak of things as they are in themselves. For one cannot exclude, a priori, from the range of God's word anything that can be affirmed or denied through human words, on the ground that a particular kind of affirmation or denial does not fit into the categories of what we call religious experience. (Fs) (notabene)

130a Moreover, the Nicene concept of consubstantiality does not go beyond the dogmatic realism that is contained implicitly in the word of God. For it means no more than this, that what is said of the Father is to be said also of the Son, except that the Son is Son and not Father. But what is said of the Father is certainly said: there are propositions that are to be believed and that, being true, correspond to reality. Equally, what is said of the Son are certain propositions that are to be believed and that correspond to reality. And if, excluding from the former set the propositions that apply to the Father, one affirms that the remainder coincide with those that apply to the Son, this further affirmation also remains entirely within the field of dogmatic realism. But in making this further affirmation one has affirmed that the Son is consubstantial with the Father. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen 3: Trinität; hellenistische Ontologie; Realismus: naiver, dogmatischer, kritischer; Mischung: dogmatischer, kritischer Realismus

Kurzinhalt: There is no need, then, to speak of the importation of a hellenistic ontology ... we must compare three different kinds of realism: naive realism, dogmatic realism and critical realism ...

Textausschnitt: 130b There is no need, then, to speak of the importation of a hellenistic ontology.1 Indeed, the more carefully one examines the brands of hellenistic ontology that were actually available at the time, the more obviously superfluous does any such hypothesis appear. In Tertullian one can detect a hellenistic ontology of Stoic inspiration, but the measure of its presence is precisely the measure of Tertullian's removal from the Nicene notion of consubstantiality. In Origen too one can find a hellenistic ontology, derived rather from Platonism, but its tendency is to place Origen at an even greater remove than Tertullian from the doctrine of Nicea. And Arius, no less than Athanasius, rejected both the Valentinian notion of emission and the Manichean notion of consubstantial part. (Fs)

131a We do not mean to suggest that the dogmatic realism, contained implicitly in the word of God, became an explicit realism, without any contributory influence of hellenistic culture. It is one thing to seek the source of dogmatic realism and quite another to assign the causes whereby an implicit philosophic position became to some extent explicit. If there had been no Gnostics, no Marcionites, no Sabellians and no Arians and, on the other hand, no bishops who thought that heretics were to be answered not only by excommunication but also by a precisely formulated profession of Faith, then the formula for the consubstantiality of the Son would scarcely have been discovered. And one cannot explain the Gnostics, the Marcionites, the Sabellians, the Arians, or the bishops who reasoned as they did, without acknowledging the influence on all of them of hellenistic culture. This influence, however, has been recognised and affirmed since the Patristic age; far from supplying proof that the Church substituted for the Christian religion some other kind of religion, it merely assigns the cause, prepared by divine providence, whereby the Christian religion itself was enabled to make explicit what from the beginning was contained implicitly in the word of God itself. (Fs)

131b To make this process of increasing explicitness a little clearer we must compare three different kinds of realism: naive realism, dogmatic realism and critical realism. All men claim to know the real, but when it comes to assigning the grounds for this common conviction it appears very clearly that different people have different criteria of reality. For example, naive realists say they know that this very obvious mountain is real because with their eyes they can see it, with their feet they can tread on it, with their hands they can handle it, and since to them the matter is so patently clear, they will attribute either to silliness or to perversity every effort to find, or urge to offer, any further ground for their conviction. Critical realists, on the other hand, while conceding that this same mountain is indeed visible to the eye, firm under foot and palpable to the hand, nonetheless add that as visible, firm and palpable it is only sensed-that it is not known as real until by a true judgment it is affirmed to exist. Since this-at least to naive realists-is anything but obvious, critical realists go on to investigate the matter thoroughly, piling up convincing reasons for each of their assertions and cutting off all avenues of escape from their position. Dogmatic realists, finally, whether in virtue of a strong natural endowment of reasonableness (this would appear, however, to be the exception) or else being schooled implicitly by the revealed word of God, agree with the critical realists, but without being able to explain just why they do, whence it can quite easily come about that, mixing naive realism in with their dogmatic realism, they land themselves in inconsistency. (Fs)

132a This kind of mixture of dogmatic and naive realism is easily detectable in the ante-Nicene Christian authors. For they who were so committed to the word of God that they spread the Christian Faith throughout the Roman empire, at the cost, for so many of them, of dying martyrs' deaths, were assuredly, if implicitly, dogmatic realists: far from taking as the sole reality the world revealed to the senses, they clung above all else to that reality made known to them by God's true word. The dogmatic realist, however, is unable, as we have have said, to explain his own position adequately; likewise, he has little or no grasp of the implications of that position. He is sure that the real is known through true judgment but at the same time he adds that by its bulk it occupies a determinate part of space. He has no doubt that those things are distinct of which one is not the other, but he also adds that those things are distinct that are in different places and as well, perhaps, at different times. It is quite clear to him that effects depend on causes, but he also has a need to see the dependence of effect on cause: branches growing out of a tree, or offspring born of parent, or brightness emitted by the sun, or a torch lit from another torch. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen 3: Trinität; Dialektik: Materialprinzip, Formalprinzip; Dialektik: Gesetz - Botschaft; Lösung ohne Durchbruch

Kurzinhalt: The formal principle ... consists in the light of natural reason, either illumined or unillumined by Faith

Textausschnitt: 133a This internally inconsistent mixture of dogmatic and naive realism provides what we called above1 the material foundation for the process of dialectic. (Fs) (notabene)

133b The formal principle of that same dialectic cannot fail to be at hand-it consists in the light of natural reason, either illumined or unillumined by Faith. Therefore, given the appropriate occasions, which heretics are apt to provide, the objective dialectic process itself is calculated to drive out naive realism and in so doing to bring dogmatic realism to a greater self-consciousness. (Fs) (notabene)

133c However, since the dogmatic realism that we speak of was only implicit, the dialectic process also was only implicit; it was not grounded philosophically, but worked itself out in the handling of religious and theological questions. Or, to express the matter differently: from the beginning the word of God contained within it an implicit epistemology and ontology, but what was there implicitly became known explicitly only through dialectic process that was spread over time; and this dialectic process was all the more complex, as the real roots of the problem were touched only indirectly. (Fs)


133d There was a first movement, begun in the New Testament itself, that was an exploration of the mutual relationships of the Law and the Gospel, according to the familiar principle that the New Testament lies concealed in the Old and the Old is made plain in the New; and to this were added the various apologies, some addressed to the Jews and some to the Gentiles. But among the new converts to Christianity there were, on the one hand, Jews who were as yet unable to transcend the Old Testament categories and kept insisting that Jesus was no more than a teacher, a prophet, or an angel. At the opposite pole there were the Gentile converts, to whom the Old Testament seemed sheer nonsense and who, therefore, basing themselves on the symbolic speculations of the Gnostics or the biblical criticism of the Marcionites, made a distinction between the much inferior Creator God and the supreme, good God. Thus arose two related problems about the manner of conceiving God, one a problem of hermeneutics and the other a problem of theology. Soon there was added a trinitarian problem; for when the Creator God of the Old Testament and God the Father of the New Testament and the supreme God, known by natural reason, had all three been identified with each other, along came those who were variously called Patripassians, Monarchians, Sabellians, to say that God the Father was the same person as God the Son. (Fs)

134a To the challenge thus posed the Western Church responded in one way and the Alexandrians in quite another. The Western Fathers, hardly broaching at all the hermeneutical problem, insisted on the distinction between God the Creator and his Son; in the process of defending this distinction they manifested objectively their naive realism and they discovered the trinitarian formula, "of one substance". The Alexandrians, on the other hand, attacked the hermeneutical problem methodically and scientifically, they sought a way of getting beyond the scriptural symbols to the reality that they symbolised, and they overcame naive realism by adopting a form of Platonism, and so Origen would say that the Father was truly God, while the Son was God by participation. (Fs)

134b Now if it is clear enough that the theology that arose in Alexandria and was brought by Origen to Caesarea was less than perfect, it is no less clear that the theology of Tertullian, Hippo-lytus, Novatian and Dionysius of Alexandria was not entirely without defect. What was needed was a kind of breakthrough, and this was finally brought about through the protracted Arian controversies. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Entwicklung im Verstehen 4: Arius

Kurzinhalt: Arius did three main things: 1) by ruling out all anthropomorphic or metaphorical language ...

Textausschnitt: 134c Arius did three main things: 1) by ruling out all anthropomorphic or metaphorical language he took the ground from under naive realism; 2) setting aside the Platonic categories introduced by Origen, he posed the question at issue in the Christian categories of Creator and creature; 3) having thus set up the problem, he resolved it by arguing, in a more or less rationalistic manner, to the conclusion that the Son was a creature. (Fs) (notabene)

135a The Council of Nicea employed dogmatic realism. While it did not explicitly repudiate naive realism, it did so implicitly.1 The council Fathers considered those phrases that might suggest Platonic participation, as for example that the Son is without difference most similar to the Father, but when they saw how the Arians could get around all such phrases, they rejected them.2 Then, in direct opposition to the Arians, they laid down that the Son is not a creature, that he is not temporal, and that he is not mutable. Finally, in order to issue a positive statement of Catholic doctrine, they declared that the Son is both born of the Father and consubstantial with him. (Fs)

135b The subsequent controversies show how inevitable all of this was. Within the council itself there were those who held that it was impossible for anything that was not a material, corporeal thing to be consubstantial with anything else; by parity of reasoning they would have said that it is impossible for anything that is not a material, corporeal thing to be a son; and the very use of the category of impossibility reveals a rationalistic turn of mind, with too little appreciation of the fact that there are mysteries in God. (Fs)

135c Equally rationalistic were the Eusebians and Homoeousians, who could understand the Son's consubstantiality with the Father only in a Sabellian sense; more seriously so were the Anomoeans who, by fallacious syllogisms, attempted to demonstrate the impossibility of the Blessed Trinity. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J. F.

Buch: The Way to Nicea

Titel: The Way to Nicea

Stichwort: Konzil von Nicäa: Resumee

Kurzinhalt: the Nicene dogma ... marks a transition from multiplicity to unity... a transition from things as related to us to things as they are in themselves ... a transition from the word of God as accommodated to particular people ...

Textausschnitt: 136d Now if, when it emerged, the Nicene dogma was inevitable, it was nonetheless new. For it marks a transition from multiplicity to unity: from a multiplicity of symbols, titles and predicates to the ultimate ground of all of these, namely, the Son's consubstantiality with the Father. Equally, it marks a transition from things as related to us to things as they are in themselves, from the relational concepts of God as supreme agent, Creator, Omnipotent Lord of all, to an ontological conception of the divine substance itself. It marks, no less, a transition from the word of God as accommodated to particular people, at particular times, under particular circumstances, to the word of God as it is to be proclaimed to all people, of all times, under whatever circumstances-the transition from the prophetic oracle of Yahweh, the gospel as announced in Galilee, the apostolic preaching and the simple tradition of the Church, from all of these to Catholic dogma. It also marks a transition from the mystery of God as hidden in symbols, hinted at by a multiplicity of titles, apprehended only in a vague and confused manner in the dramatico-practical pattern of experience, to the mystery of God as circumscribed and manifested in clear, distinct and apparently contradictory affirmations. Finally it marks a transition from a whole range of problems to a basic solution of those problems. For a definitive step was taken from naive realism, beyond Platonism, to dogmatic realism and in the direction of critical realism. To the hermeneutical question, what it is that symbols symbolise, it was answered that what they symbolise is that which is, that which is truly affirmed. To the theological question, how God was to be conceived, an answer was given that set aside the sublime Platonic Ideas, reaffirmed the omnipotent Creator and went beyond the notion of God as agent to think of him in terms of the substance that causes all substances, the being that is for all beings the source of their being. To the trinitarian question, finally, an answer was given that laid the foundation on which, of its own accord, as it were, the whole systematisation of Catholic theology would arise. Given that later systematisation, however, it is only with the greatest difficulty that we who have inherited it can come to understand how the ante-Nicene authors could in fact have said what in fact they did say. (E07; 15.01.2008)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Grundfrage: Änderungen in der Kirche; Positionen: konservativ - liberal

Kurzinhalt: Between these extremes there are two positions. One may be named classicist, conservative, traditional; the other may be named modern, liberal ...

Textausschnitt: 2a I do not think any Catholic would exclude all change on a priori grounds. Even the most embattled conservative would grant that circumstances alter cases, that positive Church law has not the same immutability as divine law or natural law, that besides the substance of things there are the accidents; that, salva substantia, the accidents may at times be modified, provided, of course, that the change is made prudently and, above all, that one keeps ever in mind that human nature is always the same. (Fs)

2b At the other extreme I am not certain it should be maintained that change in the Church’s forms, structures, methods, etc., should be a continuous, irreversible, ongoing process. There are static periods in most cultures and civilizations and, while the rest of society is quiescent, it is not clear that the Church must keep on initiating change. (Fs)

2c Between these extremes there are two positions. One may be named classicist, conservative, traditional; the other may be named modern, liberal, perhaps historicist (though that word unfortunately is very ambiguous). The differences between the two are enormous, for they differ in their apprehension of man, in their account of the good, and in the role they ascribe to the Church in the world. But these differences are not immediately theological. They are differences in horizon, in total mentality. For either side really to understand the other is a major achieve­ment and, when such understanding is lacking, the interpretation of Scripture or of other theological sources is most likely to be at cross-purposes. (Fs)

3a Accordingly, though I have been asked for a theological opinion, I must proceed in roundabout fashion. Only after the differences between classicist and historicist viewpoints have been indicated, can their respective merits in the eyes of the Christian be estimated. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Natur - Geschichtlichkeit, Intentionalität; abstrakt - konkret; Ausschluss des Konkreten: nicht theologisch

Kurzinhalt: If one abstracts from all respects in which one man can differ from another, there is left a residue named human nature ... One can begin from people as they are

Textausschnitt: 3b If one abstracts from all respects in which one man can differ from another, there is left a residue named human nature and the truism that human nature is always the same. One may fit out the eternal identity, human nature, with a natural law. One may complete it with the principles for the erection of positive law. One may hearken to divine revelation to acknowledge a super­natural order, a divine law, and a positive ecclesiastical law. So one may work methodically from the abstract and universal towards the more concrete and particular, and the more one does so, the more one is involved in the casuistry of applying a variety of universals to concrete singularity. (Fs)

3c It seems most unlikely that in this fashion one will arrive at a law demanding the change of laws, forms, structures, methods. For universals do not change; they are just what they are defined to be; and to introduce a new definition is, not to change the old universal, but to place another new universal beside the old one. On the other hand, casuistry deals with the casus, with the way things chance to fall. But every good Aristotelian knows that there is no science of the accidental (Aristotle, Metaphysics VI [E], 2, 1027a 19f.), and so from casuistry’s cases one can hardly conclude to some law about changing laws. (Fs) (notabene)

3c Still, the foregoing is not the only possible approach. One can begin from people as they are. One can note that, apart from times of dreamless sleep, they are performing intentional acts. They are experiencing, imagining, desiring, fearing; they wonder, come to understand, conceive; they reflect, weigh the evidence, judge; they deliberate, decide, act. If dreamless sleep may be compared to death, human living is being awake; it is a matter of performing intentional acts; in short, such acts informed by meaning are precisely what gives significance to human living and, conversely, to deny all meaning to human life is nihilism. (Fs)

[...]
5a I have been contrasting two different apprehensions of man. One can apprehend man abstractly through a definition that applies omni et soli and through properties verifiable in every man. In this fashion one knows man as such; and man as such, precisely because he is an abstraction, also is unchanging. It follows in the first place, that on this view one is never going to arrive at any exigence for changing forms, structures, methods, for all change occurs in the concrete, and on this view the concrete is always omitted. But it also follows in the second place, that this exclusion of changing forms, structures, methods, is not theological; it is grounded simply upon a certain conception of scientific or philosophic method; that conception is no longer the only conception or the commonly received conception; and I think our Scripture scholars would agree that its abstractness, and the omissions due to abstraction, have no foundation in the revealed word of God. (Fs) (notabene)

5b On the other hand, one can apprehend mankind as a concrete aggregate developing over time, where the locus of development and, so to speak, the synthetic bond is the emergence, expansion, differentiation, dialectic of meaning and of meaningful per­formance. On this view intentionality, meaning, is a constitutive component of human living; moreover, this component is not fixed, static, immutable, but shifting, developing, going astray, capable of redemption; on this view there is in the historicity, which results from human nature, an exigence for changing forms, structures, methods; and it is on this level and through this medium of changing meaning that divine revelation has entered the world and that the Church’s witness is given to it. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: K. Rahner; Naturgesetz - transzendentale Methode; (verum et falsum sunt in mente, bonum et malum sunt in rebus

Kurzinhalt: Karl Rahner observed that natural law should be approached through a transcendental method

Textausschnitt: 6a In the article on Naturrecht in the Lexikon für Theologie und Kirche (7: 827) Father Karl Rahner observed that natural law should be approached through a transcendental method. (Fs)

6b Any serious elaboration of this remark would take us too far afield, but three assertions may perhaps be permitted. (Fs)

First, just as the abstract apprehension of man provides itself with abstract ontological and ethical foundations in primitive propositions from which its doctrines, criteria, norms, etc., are deduced or somehow proved, so the more concrete and historical apprehension of man provides itself with its appropriately concrete foundations in structural features of the conscious, operating subject, by a method that has come to be named transcendental. (Fs)

Secondly, the stock objections that historical-mindedness involves one in relativism and situation ethics are to be met by adverting to the distinction just drawn. One cannot ground a concrete historical apprehension of man on abstract foundations: but this does not establish the inadequacy of the quite different foundations provided by a transcendental method. (Fs)

Thirdly, what moves men is the good, and good in the concrete (verum et falsum sunt in mente, bonum et malum sunt in rebus; bonum ex integra causa, malum ex quocumque defectu). If at one time law was in the forefront of human development, as one might infer from the language of the Deuteronomist, from the fervent praise of law in the Psalms, from the role of law in the history of the clarification of such concepts as justice, responsibility, guilt; still, at the present time it would seem that the immediate carrier of human aspiration is the more concrete apprehension of the human good effected through such theories of history as the liberal doctrine of progress, the Marxist doctrine of dialectical materialism and, most recently, Teilhard de Chardin’s identi­fication of cosmogenesis, anthropogenesis, and christogenesis. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Geschichte: theologische Perspektive; Fortschritt, Niedergang, Erlösung; Blindheit der Faktizität; Sünde: Leid, Tod (Textstellen)

Kurzinhalt: Progress results from the natural development of human intelligence ... a flight from understanding results in a similarly cumulative process of decline

Textausschnitt: The People of God in the World of Today

7a I have been asked for "a theological perspective on how a community of love adapts and directs itself for effective mission and witness." Presumably the reason for the request lies in points I have made elsewhere. There is in my book Insight1 a general analysis of the dynamic structure of human history, and in my mimeographed text De Verbo Incarnato2 a thesis on the lex crucis that provides its strictly theological complement. (Fs)

The analysis distinguishes three components: progress, decline, and redemption. (Fs)

7b Progress results from the natural development of human intelligence: "... concrete situations give rise to insights which issue into policies and courses of action. Action transforms the existing situation to give rise to further insights, better policies, more effective courses of action. It follows that if insight occurs, it keeps recurring; and at each recurrence knowledge develops, action increases its scope, and situations improve" (Insight, p. xiv). (Fs)

7c Next, a flight from understanding results in a similarly cumulative process of decline. (Fs)

For the flight from understanding blocks the insights that concrete situations demand. There follow unintelligent policies and inept courses of action. The situation deteriorates to demand still further insights and, as they are blocked, policies become more unintelligent and action more inept. What is worse, the deteriorating situation seems to provide the uncritical, biased mind with factual evidence in which the bias is claimed to be verified. So in ever increasing measure intelligence comes to be regarded as irrelevant to practical living. Human activity settles down to a decadent routine, and initiative becomes the privilege of violence (Insight, p. xiv). (Fs)

8a If human historical process is such a compound of progress and decline, then its redemption would be effected by faith, hope, and charity. For the evils of the situation and the enmities they engender would only be perpetuated by an even-handed justice: charity alone can wipe the slate clean. The determinism and pressures of every kind, resulting from the cumulative surd of unintelligent policies and actions, can be withstood only through a hope that is transcendent and so does not depend on any human prop. Finally, only within the context of higher truths accepted on faith can human intelligence and reasonableness be liberated from the charge of irrelevance to the realities produced by human waywardness (Insight, chap. XX). (Fs)

8b This analysis fits in with scriptural doctrine, which understands suffering and death as the result of sin yet inculcates the transforming power of Christ, who in himself and in us changes suffering and death into the means for attaining resurrection and glory. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Leslie Dewart: Kritik an adaequatio rei et intellectus; Lonergan: Antwort darauf; Widerlegung der Kohärenztheorie; Korrespondentzeorie - Dogma

Kurzinhalt: "... truth is no longer the adaequatio rei et intellectus.... But truth remains, and this truth that remains is living and active ..." To deny correspondence is to deny a relation between meaning and meant ...

Textausschnitt: 14a To conclude with a citation from Maurice Blondel's Carnets intimes: "... truth is no longer the adaequatio rei et intellectus.... But truth remains, and this truth that remains is living and active. It is the adaequatio mentis et vitae" (p. 118). (Fs)

14b Prof. Dewart's grounds for his view on truth seem to be partly the flood of light he has derived from phenomenological and existential thought and partly the inadequacy of his interpretation of Scholasticism. (Fs)

14c To the light I have no objection. I would not deny that the authenticity of one's living, the probity of one's intellectual endeavors, the strategy of one's priorities are highly relevant for the truth by which one is truly a man. I have no doubt that concepts and judgments (on judgments I find Dewart strangely silent) are the expression of one's accumulated experience, developed understanding, acquired wisdom; and I quite agree that such expression is an objectification of one's self and of one's world. (Fs)

14d I would urge, however, that this objectification is intentional. It consists in acts of meaning. We objectify the self by meaning the self, and we objectify the world by meaning the world. Such meaning of its nature is related to a meant, and what is meant may or may not correspond to what in fact is so. If it corresponds, the meaning is true. If it does not correspond, the meaning is false. Such is the correspondence view of truth, and Dewart has managed to reject it without apparently adverting to it. So eager has he been to impugn what he considered the Thomist theory of knowledge that he overlooked the fact that he needed a correspondence view of truth to mean what he said. (Fs) (notabene)

15a Let me stress the point. Dewart has written a book on the future of belief. Does he mean the future of belief, or something else, or nothing at all? At least, when he asserts that God is not a being, he assures us that what his statement "means is literally what it says, that God is not a being at all" (p. 175). Again, he wants his proposals tried by the touchstone of public examination (p. 50). But what is that examination to be? What can the public do but consider what he means and try to ascertain how much of what he says is certainly or probably true or false? (Fs) (notabene)

1.Kommentar (17.01.08): Gute Widerlegung der Kohärenztheorie.

15b Dewart urges that the correspondence view of truth supposes what is contrary to both logic and observation, "as if we could witness from a third, 'higher' viewpoint, the union of two lower things, object and subject" (p. 95). But such a statement is involved in a grave confusion. The witnessing from a higher viewpoint is the nonsense of naive realism, of the super-look that looks at both the looking and the looked-at. On the other hand, the union of object and subject is a metaphysical deduction from the fact of knowledge, and its premise is the possibility of consciousness objectifying not only itself but also its world. (Fs)

15c Again, Dewart urges that a correspondence view of truth implies an immobility that precludes development (p. 95) and, in particular, the development of dogma (p. 109). Now I would not dispute that a wooden-headed interpretation of the correspondence view of truth can exclude and has excluded the possibility of development. But that is no reason for rejecting the correspondence view along with its misinterpretation. Least of all is that so at present, when "hermeneutics" has become a watchword and the existence of literary forms is generally acknowledged. For the root of hermeneutics and the significance of literary forms lie precisely in the fact that the correspondence between meaning and meant is itself part of the meaning and so will vary with variations in the meaning. (Fs)

16a Just as he discusses truth without adverting to hermeneutics, so Dewart discusses the development of dogma without adverting to the history of dogma. But the development of dogma is a historical entity. Its existence and its nature are determined by research and interpretation. Moreover, on this approach there are found to be almost as many modes of development, almost as many varieties of implicit revelation, as there are different dogmas, so that a general discussion of the possibility of cultural development, such as Dewart offers, can provide no more than philosophic prolegomena. (Fs)

16a Unfortunately, it seems of the essence of Dewart's prolegomena to exclude the correspondence view of truth. Such an exclusion is as destructive of the dogmas as it is of Dewart's own statements. To deny correspondence is to deny a relation between meaning and meant. To deny the correspondence view of truth is to deny that, when the meaning is true, the meant is what is so. Either denial is destructive of the dogmas. (Fs)

16b If there is no correspondence between meaning and meant, then, in Prof. McLuhan's phrase, it would be a great mistake to read the dogmas as if they were saying something. If that is a great mistake, it would be another to investigate their historical origins, and a third to talk about their development. (Fs)

16c If one denies that, when the meaning is true, then the meant is what is so, one rejects propositional truth. If the rejection is universal, then it is the self-destructive proposition that there are no true propositions. If the rejection is limited to the dogmas, then it is just a roundabout way of saying that all the dogmas are false. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Leslie Dewart; christologische Dogmen -> Ausdruck hellenistischen Denkens; Lonergan: Antwort, 5 Bemerkungen zur griechischen Methode; "second-level propositions"

Kurzinhalt: The second is that, when reality and being are contrasted, the technique decides for being; My fourth observation is that the Hellenic technique of second-level propositions is not outworn

Textausschnitt: 22a Prof. Dewart conceives the development of the Trinitarian and Christological dogmas to have been a matter of taking over Hellenic concepts for the expression of Christian doctrine; for he feels "it would be unhistorical to suppose that at the first moment of the development of Christian consciousness this consciousness could have created the concepts whereby to elaborate itself-it is not until our own day that such a possibility has begun to emerge" (p. 136). Further, he laments that the Church still retains such outworn tools, for today this results in a crypto-tritheism (p. 147) and in a crypto-docetism (p. 152). (Fs)

22b It is, I should say, quite unhistorical to suppose that the development of Catholic dogma was an effort of Christian consciousness to elaborate, not the Christian message, but Christian consciousness. Further, it is unhistorical to suppose that Greek philosophy supplied all the principal elements in which we have for centuries conceptualized the basic Christian beliefs of the Trinity and the Incarnation (cf. America, Dec. 17, 1966, p. 801). My first contention needs no elaboration, and so I turn to the second. (Fs)

[...]

23b Let me add five observations on this typically Hellenic technique. The first is that it offers an open structure: it does not determine what attributes are to be assigned to the Father and so must be assigned to the Son as well; it leaves the believer free to conceive the Father in scriptural, patristic, medieval, or modern terms; and of course contemporary consciousness, which is historically minded, will be at home in all four. (Fs) (notabene)

23c The second is that, when reality and being are contrasted, the technique decides for being; for being is that which is; it is that which is to be known through the true proposition; and the technique operates on true propositions. On the other hand, reality, when contrasted with being, denotes the evident or present that provides the remote grounds for rationally affirming being, but, unlike being, is in constant flux. (Fs)

24a The third is that specifically Christian thought on being came into prominent existence in Athanasius' struggle against Arianism and, in particular, in his elucidation of natum non factum, of the difference between the Son born of the Father and the creature created by Father and Son. No doubt, such an explanation presupposes a Hellenic background for its possibility. But the problem and the content are specifically Christian. A divine Son was simply a scandal to the Hellenist Celsus; and the Christian notion of creation is not to be found in Plato or Aristotle, the Stoics or the Gnostics. When Dewart talks about the God of Greek metaphysics (p. 170), one wonders what Greek metaphysician he is talking about. (Fs)

24b My fourth observation is that the Hellenic technique of second-level propositions is not outworn. The modern mathematician reflects on his axioms and pronounces them to be the implicit definitions of his basic terms. This technique, then, pertains not to the limitations of Hellenism antiquated by modern culture but to the achievements of Hellenism that still survive in modern culture and, indeed, form part of it. (Fs)

24c My fifth and last observation is that the technique is not within everyone's competence. The matter seems to have been settled with some accuracy; for, in his celebrated studies of educational psychology, Jean Piaget has concluded that only about the age of twelve (if my memory is correct) do boys become able to operate on propositions. It follows that other means have to be found to communicate the doctrine of Nicea to less-developed minds. So much for my five observations. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Leslie Dewart; Person: Begriff aus der hellenistischen Welt; Augustinus: Person - heuristischer Rahmen; Lonergan

Kurzinhalt: For Dewart, "person" is a concept taken over from Hellenic thought ... For Augustine, persona or substantia was an undefined, heuristic concept; Lonergan: three subjects of a single, dynamic, existential consciousness

Textausschnitt: 24d For Dewart, "person" is a concept taken over from Hellenic thought and, though we have not managed to improve on it, we must do so (pp. 143 f.). I find this a rather inadequate account of the matter. (Fs)


25a For Augustine, persona or substantia was an undefined, heuristic concept. He pointed out that Father, Son, and Spirit are three. He asked, Three what? He remarked that there are not three Gods, three Fathers, three Sons, three Spirits. He answered that there are three persons or substances, where "person" or "substance" just means what there are three of in the Trinity (De trin. 7, 4, 7 [PL 42, 939]). Obviously, such an account of the notion of "person" does no more than indicate, so to speak, the area to be investigated. It directs future development but it cannot be said to impede it. The only manner in which it could become outworn would be the rejection of the Trinity; for as long as the Trinity is acknowledged, there are acknowledged three of something. (Fs)

25b Moreover, the original heuristic structure, while it has remained, has not remained indeterminate. It has been developed in different ways at different times. There was the stage of definitions, indeed, of the three main definitions contributed by Boethius, Richard of St. Victor, and Thomas Aquinas. There was the Trinitarian systematization that conceived the three Persons as subsistent relations and based the relations upon psychologically conceived processions. If I may cite my own views, I have maintained not only in my classes but also in a textbook that the three Persons are the perfect community, not two in one flesh, but three subjects of a single, dynamic, existential consciousness. On the other hand, I am of the opinion that the Christological systematization, from Scotus to de la Taille, had bogged down in a precritical morass. For the past thirty years, however, attention has increasingly turned to the consciousness of Christ, and my own position has been that the doctrine of one person with two natures transposes quite neatly into a recognition of a single subject of both a divine and a human consciousness. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Leslie Dewart; Kritik: Hypostase, 2 Naturen

Kurzinhalt: Dewart roundly asserts that no Christian believer today ... can intelligently believe that in the one hypostasis of Jesus two real natures are united

Textausschnitt: 26a So much for the process of Hellenizing Christian doctrine. Let us add a few words on the meaning of the technical terms; for Dewart roundly asserts that no Christian believer today (unless he can abstract himself from contemporary experience) can intelligently believe that in the one hypostasis of Jesus two real natures are united (p. 150). Let me put the prior question. Does Dewart's Christian believer today accept the positive part of the Nicene decree, in which neither the term "hypostasis" nor the term "nature" occurs? If so, in the part about Jesus Christ, does he observe two sections, a first containing divine predicates, and a second containing human predicates? Next, to put the question put by Cyril to Nestorius, does he accept the two series of predicates as attributes of one and the same Jesus Christ? If he does, he acknowledges what is meant by one hypostasis. If he does not, he does not accept the Nicene Creed. Again, does he acknowledge in the one and the same Jesus Christ both divine attributes and human attributes? If he acknowledges both, he accepts what is meant by two natures. If he does not, he does not accept the Nicene Creed. (Fs)

26b What is true is that Catholic theology today has a tremendous task before it, for there are very real limitations to Hellenism that have been transcended by modern culture and have yet to be successfully surmounted by Catholic theology. But that task is not helped, rather it is gravely impeded, by wild statements based on misconceptions or suggesting unbelief. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Person, Reife; vom naiven Realismus zur Reife der Vernunft

Kurzinhalt: ... criteria for distinguishing between the "really real" and the merely imagined, desired, feared, dreamt, the sibling's trick, joke, fib

Textausschnitt: 29a Thirdly, maturity is comprehensive. It does not refuse to acknowledge any part of man but embraces all from the entities of Freud's psychic embryology to the immanent norms of man's intellectual, rational, existential consciousness. As it does not deny prepositional truth, so it does not disregard or belittle religious experience. On the contrary, it is quite ready to claim with Karl Rahner that a mystagogy will play a far more conspicuous role in the spirituality of the future (Geist und Leben, 39 [1966], 335), and it is fully aware that spiritual advance brings about in prayer the diminution and at times the disappearance of symbols and concepts of God, Still, this differentiation and specialization of consciousness does not abolish other, complementary differentiations and specializations, whether social, sexual, practical, aesthetic, scientific, philosophic, historical, or theological. Nor is this multiplicity in any way opposed to integration. For in each of such diverse patterns of conscious operation one is oneself in accord with some facet of one's being and some part of one's universe; and while one lives in only one pattern at a time in some cycle of recurrence, still the subject is over time, each pattern complements, reinforces, liberates the others, and there can develop a differentiation of consciousness to deal explicitly with differentiations of consciousness. That pattern is, of course, reflective subjectivity in philosophy and in theology. It follows the Hellenic precept "Know thyself." It follows the example of Augustinian recall, scrutiny, penetration, judgment, evaluation, decision. It realizes the modern concern for the authenticity of one's existing without amputating one's own rational objectivity expressed in prepositional truth. (Fs)

29b Fourthly, maturity understands the immature. It has been through that, and it knows what it itself has been. It is aware that in childhood, before reaching the age of reason, one perforce works out one's quite pragmatic criteria for distinguishing between the "really real" and the merely imagined, desired, feared, dreamt, the sibling's trick, joke, fib. Still more clearly is it aware of the upset of crisis and conversion that is needed to purge oneself of one's childish realism and swing round completely and coherently to a critical realism. So it understands just how it is that some cling to a naive realism all their lives, that others move on to some type of idealism, that others feel some liberation from idealism in a phenomenology or an existentialism while, at the opposite extreme, there is a conceptualist extrinsicism for which concepts have neither dates nor developments and truth is so objective that it gets along without minds. (Fs) (notabene)

30a Such is the disorientation of contemporary experience, its inability to know itself and its own resources, the root of not a little of its insecurity and anxiety. Theology has to take this fact into consideration. The popular theology devised in the past for the simplices fideles has to be replaced. Nor will some single replacement do; for theology has to learn to speak in many modes and on many levels and even to minister to the needs of those afflicted with philosophic problems they are not likely to solve. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Leslsie Dewart: unüberbrückbar: Gott in sich selbst - Gott in unserem Wissen; Lonergan: Differenz: Gott in unserem Denken - Wissen

Kurzinhalt: Dewart asserts an unbridgeable difference between the way in God is in himself and the way in which he is in our knowledge

Textausschnitt: 31a Now this argument has a certain validity if in fact human knowing consists in concepts and empirical intuitions. But empirical intuition is just a misleading name for the givenness of the data of sense and of consciousness. In linking data to conception, there are inquiry and gradually developing understanding. The result of all these together is not knowledge but just thinking. To reach knowledge, to discern between astronomy and astrology, chemistry and alchemy, history and legend, philosophy and myth, there are needed the further activities of reflection, doubting, marshalling and weighing the evidence, and judging, Finally, this process of judging, in an important because clear instance, is like scientific verification, not as verification is imagined by the naive to be a matter of looking, peering, intuiting, but as verification in fact is found to be, namely, a cumulative convergence of direct and indirect confirmations any one of which by itself settles just nothing. (Fs) (notabene)

31b I quite agree, then, that our concepts are in principle unable to make known to us the actual existence of God. I would add that they are in principle unable to make known to us the actual existence of anything. For concepts are just thinking; thinking is not knowing; it is only when we reach judgment that we attain human knowledge of anything whatever, whether of essence or existence, whether of creature or Creator. (Fs)

31c There is, however, a further point; for Dewart asserts an unbridgeable difference between the way in God is in himself and the way in which he is in our knowledge. This, of course, while absolutely possible, is not possibly known within our knowledge, and so the reader may wonder how Dewart got it into his knowledge. The fallacy seems to be Dewart's confusion of thinking and knowing. In our thinking we may distinguish a concept of divine existence from a concept of divine essence. In our knowing we may affirm (1) that we think in the above manner and (2) that there is no distinction between the reality of the divine essence and the reality of the divine existence. The contrast is, then, not between God in Himself and God in our knowledge, but between God in our knowledge and God in our thinking. Nor is there anything unbridgeable about this contrast or difference; for the thinking and judging occur within one and the same mind, and the whole function of our judging may be described as determining how much of our thinking is correct. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Unterschied: inquiry - investigation

Kurzinhalt: I think it will be helpful to draw a distinction ... between inquiry and investigation; inquiry is the active principle. It takes one beyond whatever is given, perceived, known, ascertained

Textausschnitt: 33b I think it will be helpful to draw a distinction, at least for present purposes, between inquiry and investigation. By investigation I would mean the process that is initiated in the subject by intellectual wonder or curiosity, that methodically seeks, accumulates, classifies possibly relevant data, that gradually through successive insights grows in understanding and so formulates hypotheses that are expanded by their logical presuppositions and implications to be tested by further observation and perhaps experiment. (Fs)

33c Within this process there occur both insight and inquiry, with insight responding to inquiry, and further insight to further inquiry. Inquiry is the active principle. It takes one beyond whatever is given, perceived, known, ascertained. It does so, not by perceiving or knowing anything more, but simply by intending something more. What it intends is an unknown. By the intending it becomes a to-be-known. An unknown that is to be known may be named. In algebra it is named "x"; in physics it will be some indeterminate function such as "F (X, Y, Z, T) = O"; in common English usage it is named "nature"; so we may speak of the nature of light or the nature of life, not because we know these natures, but because we name what we would know if we understood light or life. (Fs) (notabene)

34a Now this intending is also a striving, a tending, and its immediate goal is insight. When insight occurs, the immediate goal is reached, and so the striving for insight, the tending to insight, ceases or, perhaps better, it is transformed. It becomes a striving to formulate, to express in concepts and in words, what has been grasped by the insight. Once this is achieved, it is again transformed. It becomes a striving to determine whether or not the insight is correct. (Fs)

34b Inquiry, then, and insight both occur within the larger process that is learning or investigating. Inquiry is the dynamic principle that gradually assembles all the elements in the compound that is human knowing. Among these elements insight is the most central. Like the others, insight too responds to inquiry. But it is not the total response. (Fs)

34c May I add a final word on definition? All defining presupposes undefined terms and relations. In the book Insight the undefined terms are cognitional operations and the undefined relations are the dynamic relations that bind cognitional operations together. Both the operations and their dynamic relations are given in immediate internal experience, and the main purpose of the book is to help the reader to discover these operations and their dynamic relations in his own personal experience. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Nowak; Lonergan, Ethik;

Kurzinhalt: Though I did not in Insight feel called upon to work out a code of ethics, neither did I exclude such a code. On the contrary ....

Textausschnitt: 39a Professor Novak has given a subtly accurate account of my position on philosophic ethics. I quite agree (1) that, as I base metaphysics, so also I base ethics not on logically first propositions but on invariant structures of human knowing and human doing, (2) that this basis leaves room for a history and, indeed a development of morals, (3) that there is a concrete level of intelligibility reached by insight but missed when universal concepts are applied to particular instances, and (4) that such concrete intelligibility is relevant not only to science but also to conduct. (Fs)

39b I have said, however, that Professor Novak's account was not just accurate but subtly accurate. The fact is that Professor Novak is an apostle as well as a scholar and I have the feeling that he is inviting or nudging or even perhaps pushing me a little farther than I have gone on my own initiative. (Fs)

39c He attributes to me the rejection of an "objective code of ethics out there." This is quite true inasmuch as I reject naive realism and so reject the "out there" as a measure and standard of objectivity. It is quite true inasmuch as I reject an anti-intellectual conceptualism and so reject an anti-historical immobilism. It is quite true, further, that I do not base a code of conclusions upon a code of verbal propositions named first principles. It is quite true, again, that while I assigned invariant structures as the basis for the possibility of ethics, I did not proceed to work out a code from such a basis. It is quite true, finally, as Professor Novak contends, that the basis I offer in invariant structures provides foundations for personal ethical decision and for personal concern with the concrete good in concrete situations. (Fs) (notabene)

39d Now I am completely at one with Professor Novak in his concern for personal ethical decision about the concrete good. But I wish to forestall any misapprehension about my position. Though I did not in Insight feel called upon to work out a code of ethics, neither did I exclude such a code. On the contrary I drew a parallel between ethics and metaphysics. In metaphysics I not only assigned a basis in invariant structures but also derived from that basis a metaphysics with a marked family resemblance to traditional views. A similar family resemblance, I believe, would be found to exist between traditional ethics and an ethics that, like the metaphysics, was explicitly aware of itself as a system on the move. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan: Analyse der Frage (eg: Anklänge an Rahner); Gottesbeweis, Fr. Burrell

Kurzinhalt: It follows that to say that being is completely intelligible is not an idle empty phrase. It is true that we have no immediate knowledge of complete intelligibility ...

Textausschnitt: 40b Father Burrell has given a most helpful account of my position and he has followed it up with a forcefully presented objection to an argument for the existence of God. The argument began: If the real is completely intelligible, God exists. (Fs)
40c The objection is to the expression "completely intelligible." He grants that anything we know is known through its intelligibility, so that any reality we know must be intelligible. But he urges that we have no acquaintance with complete intelligibility; indeed, we cannot know it since knowing it would be enjoying an unrestricted infinite act of understanding. It follows that the minor premiss must be mistaken. If we cannot know complete intelligibility, then we cannot know that the real is completely intelligible. (Fs)

40d My answer would be that, besides knowing, there is intending. Whenever one asks a genuine question, one does not know the answer. Still, one does intend, desire, ask for the answer; one is able to tell when one gets an appropriate answer; and one is able to judge whether the appropriate answer is also correct. So between not knowing and knowing there is the process of coming to know. That process is intentional. It starts from experience but goes beyond it to understanding and judgment. Such going beyond is not blind. It is aware of itself as a going beyond the given, the incompletely known. This awareness consists in a conscious intending of an unknown that is to be known. (Fs)

1.Kommentar (26/01/08): Lonergans Analyse der Frag zeigt Anklänge an Rahners.

41a Now such intending has to be channelled and controlled. A fool can ask more questions than a wise man can answer. Even the wise man has to advert to the strategy that asks questions in a proper order, that selects the questions that can be answered now, that prefers the questions that once solved, lead to the solution of other questions. (Fs)

41b Behind this need for control and planning is the fact that the intending is of itself unrestricted. Our libraries are too small, yet more books keep being published. Our numerous and vast research projects only open the way for further research. To answer questions only gives rise to still further questions, and there is no prospect of this stream drying up from lack of further questions. (Fs)

41c Moreover, while questions can and must be criticized, they may not be arbitrarily brushed aside. Such arbitrary refusal is obscurantism, and to be an obscurantist is to cease to be an authentic human being. (Fs)

41d It follows that our intending intends, not incomplete, but complete intelligibility. If it intended no more than an incomplete intelligibility, there would be a point where further questions could arise but did not, where the half-answer appeared not a half-answer but as much an answer as human intelligence could dream of seeking. If the dynamism of human intellect intended no more than incomplete intelligibility, the horizon not merely of human knowledge but also of possible human inquiry would be bounded. Whether or not there were anything beyond that horizon, would be a question that could not even arise. (Fs) (notabene)

41e It follows that to say that being is completely intelligible is not an idle empty phrase. It is true that we have no immediate knowledge of complete intelligibility, for we have no immediate knowledge of God. It remains that our intelligence, at its living root, intends intelligibility but not incomplete intelligibility and so complete intelligibility. Further, since intending is just another name for meaning, it follows that complete intelligibility, so far from being meaningless to us, is in fact at the root of all our attempts to mean anything at all. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Thomas, Thomismus der Zukunft; 5 notwendige Änderungen; von Logik -> Methode, Wissenschaft: von Notwendigkeit -> verfizierbare Möglichkeit, von Seele -> Subjekt ...

Kurzinhalt: A Thomism for tomorrow has to move from logic to method; from science as conceived in the Posterior Analytics to science as it is conceived today; from the metaphysics of the soul ...

Textausschnitt: 49b To begin from the second point, the technique of the quaestio aimed at a logically coherent reconciliation of conflicting authorities. It met the demands of human intelligence seeking some understanding of its faith, and it did so in the grand manner. But its scrutiny of the data presented by Scripture and tradition was quite insufficient. On the whole it was unaware of history: of the fact that every act of meaning is embedded in a context, and that over time contexts change subtly, slowly, surely. A contemporary theology must take and has taken the fact of history into account. Inasmuch as it does so, St. Thomas ceases to be the arbiter to whom all can appeal for the solution of contemporary questions; for, by and large, contemporary questions are not the same as the questions he treated, and the contemporary context is not the context in which he treated them. But he remains a magnificent and venerable figure in the history of Catholic thought. He stands before us as a model, inviting us to do for our age what he did for his. And, if I may express a personal opinion of my own, a mature Catholic theology of the twentieth century will not ignore him; it will learn very, very much from him; and it will be aware of its debt to him, even when it is effecting its boldest transpositions from the thirteenth century to the twentieth. (Fs)

49c What are such transpositions? I have prepared my answer to that question by my list of five emphases of classical Thomism. A Thomism for tomorrow has to move from logic to method; from science as conceived in the Posterior Analytics to science as it is conceived today; from the metaphysics of the soul to the self-appropriation of the subject; from an apprehension of man in terms of human nature to an apprehension of man through human history; and from first principles to transcendental method. Before considering these transitions singly, let me remark in general that they are not exclusive; a transition from logic to method does not drop logic, and similarly in most of the other cases. (Fs)

50a First, then, from logic to method. Today we frequently hear complaints about metaphysics as static. But what is static is not metaphysics as such but a logically rigorous metaphysics. Indeed, anything that is logically rigorous is static. Defined terms are abstract and abstractions are immobile. Presuppositions and implications, if rigorous, cannot shift a single iota. Logic embodies an ideal of clarity, coherence, and rigor. It is an ideal that we must ever pursue, but the pursuit is a matter not of logic but of method. A method is a normative pattern of related and recurrent operations. There are operations: for instance, to take the simplest example, in natural science there are observing, describing, defining problems, making discoveries, formulating hypotheses, working out their presuppositions and implications, devising experiments, testing hypotheses by experiments, determining whether the hypothesis so far is satisfactory or already is unsatisfactory, and so proceeding to new questions or to a revision of the hypothesis already made. All such operations are related, for each leads to the next. They are recurrent, for they form a circle that is repeated over and over and cumulatively extends the mastery of human intelligence over ever broader fields of data. The pattern of such related and recurrent operations is normative, for that is the right way to do the job. Finally, while this pattern includes all logical operations, it also includes many operations that lie outside a formal logic, such as observing, discovering, experimenting, verifying. (Fs)

51a Secondly, from the conception of science in the Posterior Analytics to the modern conception of a science. On point after point the two conceptions are opposed. In the Aristotelian notion necessity was a key category; in modern science it is marginal; it has been replaced by verifiable possibility. For the Aristotelian, science is certain; for the modern, science is no more than probable, the best available scientific opinion. For the Aristotelian, causality was material, formal, efficient, exemplary, or final; for the modern, causality is correlation. For the Aristotelian, a science was a habit in the mind of an individual; for the modern, science is knowledge divided up among the scientific community; no one knows the whole of modern mathematics, of modern physics, of modern chemistry, or modern biology, and so on. (Fs)

51b Thirdly, from soul to subject. I do not mean that the metaphysical notion of the soul and of its properties is to be dropped, any more than I mean that logic is to be dropped. But I urge the necessity of a self-appropriation of the subject, of coming to know at first hand oneself and one's own operations both as a believer and as a theologian. It is there that one will find the foundations of method, there that one will find the invariants that enable one to steer a steady course, though theological theories and opinions are subject to revision and change. Without such a basis systematic theology will remain what it has been too often in the past, a morass of questions disputed endlessly and fruitlessly. (Fs)

51c Fourthly, from human nature to human history. The point here is that meaning is constitutive of human living. Just as words without sense are gibberish, so human living uninformed by human meaning is infantile. Next, not only is meaning constitutive of human living but also it is subject to change; cultures develop and cultures decline; meaning flowers and meaning becomes decadent. Finally, Christianity is an historical religion; it is a statement of the meaning of human living; it is a redeeming statement that cures decadence and fosters growth. (Fs)

51d Fifthly, from first principles to transcendental method. First principles, logically first propositions, are the foundations for a mode of thought that is inspired by logic, by necessity, by objectivity, by nature. But the contemporary context, the tasks and problems of a theology that would deal with the issues of today, call for method, verified possibility, full awareness of the subject, and a thorough grasp of man's historicity. Its foundations lie, not in abstract propositions called first principles, but in the structural invariants of the concrete human subject. When the natural and the human sciences are on the move, when the social order is developing, when the everyday dimensions of culture are changing, what is needed is not a dam to block the stream but control of the river-bed through which the stream must flow. In modern science, what is fixed is not the theory or system but the method that keeps generating, improving, replacing theories and systems. Transcendental method is the assault on the citadel: it is possession of the basic method, and all other methods are just so many extensions and adaptations of it. (Fs)

1.Kommentar (27/01/08): "... Its foundations lie, not in abstract propositions called first principles, but in the structural invariants of the concrete human subject." Lonergan scheint mir die Methode etwas überzubetonen im Hinblick auf die Resultate, zu denen eine Methode führt. In der Philosophie gelangt zu "unwandelbaren" Einsichten, wie immer man sie auch in Begriffe fassen mag. Die invariante Struktur des Menschen ist leer; wenn die Methode wichtiger erscheint als das Ziel, zu dem sie führt, ist die Folge eine Beliebigkeit.

52a Finally, let me note that, when such transpositions are effected, theology will be more strictly theology than it has been. The development of method makes an academic discipline stick to its own business. Religion is one thing, and theology is another. Religion is necessary for salvation and theology is not. It is the office of the bishop to teach religious truth. It is the task of the theologian to reflect on the religious fact, and it is the task of the Christian theologian to reflect on the Christian religious fact. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Erneuerung der Theologie, aggiornamento; 1680, Butterfield: Naturwissenschaft; "dogmatische" Theologie, Melchior Cano

Kurzinhalt: ... if theology is to be brought up to date, it must have fallen behind the times. Again, if we are to know what is to be done to bring theology up to date, ...

Textausschnitt: 55a Any theology of renewal goes hand in hand with a renewal of theology. For "renewal" is being used in a novel sense. Usually in Catholic circles "renewal" has meant a return to the olden times of pristine virtue and deep wisdom. But good Pope John has made "renewal" mean "aggiornamento," "bringing things up to date." (Fs)

55b Obviously, if theology is to be brought up to date, it must have fallen behind the times. Again, if we are to know what is to be done to bring theology up to date, we must ascertain when it began to fall behind the times, in what respects it got out of touch, in what respects it failed to meet the issues and effect the developments that long ago were due and now are long overdue. (Fs)

55c The answer I wish to suggest takes us back almost three centuries to the end of the seventeenth century and, more precisely, to the year 1680. For that, it seems, was the time of the great beginning. Then it was that Herbert Butterfield placed the origins of modern science, then that Paul Hazard placed the beginning of the Enlightenment, then that Yves Congar placed the beginning of dogmatic theology. When modern science began, when the Enlightenment began, then the theologians began to reassure one another about their certainties. Let me comment briefly on this threefold coincidence. (Fs)

55d When Professor Butterfield placed the origins of modern science at the end of the seventeenth century, he by no means meant to deny that from the year 1300 on numerous discoveries were made that since have been included within modern science and integrated with it. But he did make the point that, at the time of their first appearance, these discoveries could not be expressed adequately. For, the dominant cultural context was Aristotelian, and the discoverers themselves had Aristotelian backgrounds. Thus there existed a conflict between the new ideas and the old doctrines, and this conflict existed not merely between an old guard of Aristotelians and a new breed of scientists but, far more gravely, within the very minds of the new scientists. For new ideas are far less than a whole mentality, a whole climate of thought and opinion, a whole mode of approach, and procedure, and judgment. Before these new ideas could be formulated accurately, coherently, cogently, they had to multiply, cumulate, coalesce to bring forth a new system of concepts and a new body of doctrine that was somehow comparable in extent to the Aristotelian and so capable of replacing it. (Fs)

56a In brief, Professor Butterfield distinguished between new ideas and the context or horizon within which they were expressed, developed, related. From about the beginning of the fourteenth century the new ideas multiplied. But only towards the close of the seventeenth century did there emerge the context appropriate to these ideas. The origin of this context is for Professor Butterfield the origin of modern science and, in his judgment, "it outshines everything since the rise of Christianity and reduces the Renaissance and the Reformation to the rank of mere episodes, mere internal displacements, within the system of medieval Christendom."1 (Fs) (notabene)

56b Coincident with the origins of modern science was the beginning of the Enlightenment, of the movement Peter Gay recently named the rise of modern paganism.2 Moreover, while this movement is commonly located in the eighteenth century, the French academician Paul Hazard has exhibited already in full swing between the years 1680 and 1715 a far-flung attack on Christianity from almost every quarter and in almost every style.3 It was a movement revolted by the spectacle of religious persecution and religious war. It was to replace the God of the Christians by the God of the philosophes and, eventually, the God of the philosophes by agnosticism and atheism. It gloried in the achievements of Newton, criticized social structures, promoted political change, and moved towards a materialist, mechanist, determinist interpretation no less of man than of nature.4 (Fs)

57a It would be unfair to expect the theologians of the end of the seventeenth century to have discerned the good and the evil in the great movements of their time. But at least we may record what in fact they did do. They introduced "dogmatic" theology. It is true that the word "dogmatic" had been previously applied to theology. But then it was used to denote a distinction from moral, or ethical, or historical theology. Now it was employed in a new sense, in opposition to scholastic theology. It replaced the inquiry of the quaestio by the pedagogy of the thesis. It demoted the quest of faith for understanding to a desirable, but secondary, and indeed, optional goal. It gave basic and central significance to the certitudes of faith, their presuppositions, and their consequences. It owed its mode of proof to Melchior Cano and, as that theologian was also a bishop and inquisitor, so the new dogmatic theology not only proved its theses, but also was supported by the teaching authority and the sanctions of the Church.5 (Fs)

1.Kommentar (31.01.08): Cf. David Walsh über den Nominalismus.

57b Such a conception of theology survived right into the twentieth century, and even today in some circles it is the only conception that is understood. Still, among theologians its limitations and defects have been becoming more and more apparent, especially since the 1890's. During the last seventy years, efforts to find remedies and to implement them have been going forward steadily, if unobtrusively. The measure of their success is the radically new situation brought to light by the Second Vatican Council. (Fs)

58a There is, perhaps, no need for me here to insist that the novelty resides not in a new revelation or a new faith, but in a new cultural context. For a theology is a product not only of the religion it investigates and expounds but also of the cultural ideals and norms that set its problems and direct its solutions. Just as theology in the thirteenth century followed its age by assimilating Aristotle, just as theology in the seventeenth century resisted its age by retiring into a dogmatic corner, so theology today is locked in an encounter with its age. Whether it will grow and triumph, or whether it will wither to insignificance, depends in no small measure on the clarity and the accuracy of its grasp of the external cultural factors that undermine its past achievements and challenge it to new endeavors. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Theologie, neue Grundlage; Konversion

Kurzinhalt: The new largely empirical approach to theology can too easily be made into a device for reducing doctrines to probable opinions ... If our renewed theology is not to be the dupe of every fashion, it needs a firm basis ...

Textausschnitt: 63a I have been speaking of our renewed theology and now I must add that a renewed theology needs a renewed foundation. The old foundation will no longer do. But we cannot get along with no foundation at all. So a new foundation and, I should say, a new type of foundation is needed to replace the old. (Fs)

63b First, some foundation is needed. If change is to be improvement, if new tasks are to be accomplished fruitfully, discernment is needed and discrimination. If we are to draw on contemporary psychology and sociology, if we are to profit from the modern science of religions, if we are to revise scholastic categories and make our own the concepts worked out in historicist, personalist, phenomenological, or existentialist circles, then we must be able to distinguish tinsel and silver, gilt and gold. No less important than a critique of notions and conclusions is a critique of methods. The new largely empirical approach to theology can too easily be made into a device for reducing doctrines to probable opinions. A hermeneutics can pretend to philosophic neutrality yet force the conclusion that the content of revelation is mostly myth. Scientific history can be so conceived that a study of the narrative of salvation will strip it of matters of fact. If our renewed theology is not to be the dupe of every fashion, it needs a firm basis and a critical stance. (Fs)

63d Secondly, the old foundations will no longer do. In saying this I do not mean that they are no longer true, for they are as true now as they ever were. I mean that they are no longer appropriate. I am simply recalling that one must not patch an old cloak with new cloth or put new wine in old wineskins. One type of foundation suits a theology that aims at being deductive, static, abstract, universal, equally applicable to all places and to all times. A quite different foundation is needed when theology turns from deductivism to an empirical approach, from the static to the dynamic, from the abstract to the concrete, from the universal to the historical totality of particulars, from invariable rules to intelligent adjustment and adaptation. (Fs) (notabene)

[...]

65a So much for our first approximation. It illustrates by an example what might be meant by a foundation that lies not in a set of verbal propositions named first principles, but in a particular, concrete, dynamic reality generating knowledge of particular, concrete, dynamic realities. It remains that we have to effect the transition from natural science to theology, and so we turn to our second approximation. (Fs)

65b Fundamental to religous living is conversion. It is a topic little studied in traditional theology since there remains very little of it when one reaches the universal, the abstract, the static. For conversion occurs in the lives of individuals. It is not merely a change or even a development; rather, it is a radical transformation on which follows, on all levels of living, an interlocked series of changes and developments. What hitherto was unnoticed becomes vivid and present. What had been of no concern becomes a matter of high import. So great a change in one's apprehensions and one's values accompanies no less a change in oneself, in one's relations to other persons, and in one's relations to God. (Fs) (notabene)

66a Not all conversion is as total as the one I have so summarily described. Conversion has many dimensions. A changed relation to God brings or follows changes that are personal, social, moral and intellectual. But there is no fixed rule of antecedence and consequence, no necessity of simultaneity, no prescribed magnitudes of change. Conversion may be compacted into the moment of a blinded Saul falling from his horse on the way to Damascus. It may be extended over the slow maturing process of a lifetime. It may satisfy an intermediate measure. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Subjekt - objektive Wahrheit; veritas formaliter est in solo iudicio

Kurzinhalt: truth exists formally only in judgments ... What God reveals is a truth in the mind of God and in the minds of believers, but it is not a truth in the minds of nonbelievers

Textausschnitt: 69c In contemporary philosophy there is a great emphasis on the subject, and this emphasis may easily be traced to the influence of Hegel, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Buber.1 This fact, however, points to a previous period of neglect, and it may not be amiss to advert to the causes of such neglect, if only to make sure that they are no longer operative in our own thinking. (Fs)

70a A first cause, then, is the objectivity of truth. The criterion, I believe, by which we arrive at the truth is a virtually unconditioned.2 But an unconditioned has no conditions. A subject may be needed to arrive at truth, but, once truth is attained, one is beyond the subject and one has reached a realm that is non-spatial, atemporal, impersonal. Whatever is true at any time or place, can be contradicted only by falsity. No one can gainsay it, unless he is mistaken and errs. (Fs)

70b Such is the objectivity of truth. But do not be fascinated by it. Intentionally it is independent of the subject, but ontologically it resides only in the subject: veritas formaliter est in solo iudicio. Intentionally it goes completely beyond the subject, yet it does so only because ontologically the subject is capable of an intentional self-transcendence, of going beyond what he feels, what he imagines, what he thinks, what seems to him, to something utterly different, to what is so. Moreover, before the subject can attain the self-transcendence of truth, there is the slow and laborious process of conception, gestation, parturition. But teaching and learning, investigating, coming to understand, marshalling and weighing the evidence, these are not independent of the subject, of times and places, of psychological, social, historical conditions. The fruit of truth must grow and mature on the tree of the subject, before it can be plucked and placed in its absolute realm. (Fs)

71a It remains that one can be fascinated by the objectivity of truth, that one can so emphasize objective truth as to disregard or undermine the very conditions of its emergence and existence. In fact, if at the present time among Catholics there is discerned a widespread alienation from the dogmas of faith, this is not unconnected with a previous one-sidedness that so insisted on the objectivity of truth as to leave subjects and their needs out of account. (Fs)

71b Symptomatic of such one-sidedness was the difficulty experienced by theologians from the days of Suarez, de Lugo, and Bañez, when confronted with the syllogism: What God has revealed is true. God has revealed the mysteries of faith. Therefore, the mysteries of faith are true.3 There is, perhaps, no need for me to explain - why this syllogism was embarrassing, for it implied that the mysteries of faith were demonstrable conclusions. But the point I wish to make is that the syllogism contains an unnoticed fallacy, and the fallacy turns on an exaggerated view of the objectivity of truth. If one recalls that truth exists formally only in judgments and that judgments exist only in the mind, then the fallacy is easily pinned down. What God reveals is a truth in the mind of God and in the minds of believers, but it is not a truth in the minds of nonbelievers; and to conclude that the mysteries of faith, are truths in the mind of God or in the minds of believers in no way suggests that the mysteries are demonstrable. But this simple way out seems to have been missed by the theologians. They seem to have thought of truth as so objective as to get along without minds. Nor does such thinking seem to have been confined to theoretical accounts of the act of faith. The same insistence on objective truth and the same neglect of its subjective conditions informed the old catechetics, which the new catechetics is replacing, and the old censorship, which insisted on true propositions and little understood the need to respect the dynamics of the advance toward truth. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Subjekt - Seele (Aristoteles); metaphysische Analyse der Seele - Analyse des Bewusstseins

Kurzinhalt: The study of the subject is quite different, for it is the study of oneself inasmuch as one is conscious. It prescinds from the soul, its essence ...

Textausschnitt: 72b A third source of neglect of the subject is the metaphysical account of the soul. As plants and animals, so men have souls. As in plants and animals, so in men the soul is the first act of an organic body. Still the souls of plants differ essentially from the souls of animals, and the souls of both differ essentially from the souls of men. To discern these differences we must turn from the soul to its potencies, habits, acts, objects. Through the objects we know the acts, through the acts we know the habits, through the habits we know the potencies, and through the potencies we know the essence of soul. The study of the soul, then, is totally objective. One and the same method is applied to study of plants, animals, and men. The results are completely universal. We have souls whether we are awake or asleep, saints or sinners, geniuses or imbeciles. (Fs)

73a The study of the subject is quite different, for it is the study of oneself inasmuch as one is conscious. It prescinds from the soul, its essence, its potencies, its habits, for none of these is given in consciousness. It attends to operations and to their centre and source which is the self. It discerns the different levels of consciousness, the consciousness of the dream, of the waking subject, of the intelligently inquiring subject, of the rationally reflecting subject, of the responsibly deliberating subject. It examines the different operations on the several levels and their relations to one another. (Fs)

73b Subject and soul, then, are two quite different topics. To know one does not exclude the other in any way. But it very easily happens that the study of the soul leaves one with the feeling that one has no need to study the subject and, to that extent, leads to a neglect of the subject.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Konzeptualismus: 3 Kennezeichen: Immobilität, Abstraktheit,

Kurzinhalt: As insights fulfil three functions, so conceptualism has three basic defects.

Textausschnitt: 74a But there are less gross procedures. One can accept an apparently reasonable rule of acknowledging what is certain and disregarding what is controverted. Almost inevitably this will lead to an oversight of insight. For it is easy enough to be certain about concepts; their existence can be inferred from linguistic usage and from scientific generality. But it is only by close attention to the data of consciousness that one can discover insights, acts of understanding with the triple role of responding to inquiry, grasping intelligible form in sensible representations, and grounding the formation of concepts. So complex a matter will never be noticed as long as the subject is neglected, and so there arises conceptualism: a strong affirmation of concepts, and a skeptical disregard of insights. As insights fulfil three functions, so conceptualism has three basic defects. (Fs)

74b A first defect is an anti-historical immobilism. Human understanding develops and, as it develops, it expresses itself in ever more precise and accurate concepts, hypotheses, theories, systems. But conceptualism, as it disregards insight, so it cannot account for the development of concepts. Of themselves, concepts are immobile. They ever remain just what they are defined to mean. They are abstract and so stand outside the spatio-temporal world of change. What does change, is human understanding and, when understanding changes or develops, then defining changes or develops. So it is that, while concepts do not change on their own, still they are changed as the mind that forms them changes. (Fs)

74c A second defect of conceptualism is an excessive abstractness. For the generalities of our knowledge are related to concrete reality in two distinct manners. There is the relation of the universal to the particular, of man to this man, of circle to this circle. There is also the far more important relation of the intelligible to the sensible, of the unity or pattern grasped by insight to the data in which the unity or pattern is grasped. Now this second relation, which parallels the relation of form to matter, is far more intimate than the first. The universal abstracts from the particular, but the intelligibility, grasped by insight, is immanent in the sensible and, when the sensible datum, image, symbol, is removed, the insight vanishes. But conceptualism ignores human understanding and so it overlooks the concrete mode of understanding that grasps intelligibility in the sensible itself. It is confined to a world of abstract universals, and its only link with the concrete is the relation of universal to particular. (Fs)

75a A third defect of conceptualism has to do with the notion of being. Conceptualists have no difficulty in discovering a concept of being, indeed, in finding it implicit in every positive concept. But they think of it as an abstraction, as the most abstract of all abstractions, least in connotation and greatest in denotation. In fact, the notion of being is not abstract but concrete. It intends everything about everything. It prescinds from nothing whatever. But to advert to this clearly and distinctly, one must note not only that concepts express acts of understanding but also that both acts of understanding and concepts respond to questions. The notion of being first appears in questioning. Being is the unknown that questioning intends to know, that answers partially reveal, that further questioning presses on to know more fully. The notion of being, then, is essentially dynamic, proleptic, an anticipation of the entirety, the concreteness, the totality, that we ever intend and since our knowledge is finite never reach. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Objektivität - Immanenz; Picture-thinking - Kant

Kurzinhalt: Once picture-thinking takes over, immanence is an inevitable consequence; "Object" is what one looks at; looking is sensitive intuition

Textausschnitt: 76a The key to doctrines of immanence is an inadequate notion of objectivity. Human knowing is a compound of many operations of different kinds. It follows that the objectivity of human knowing is not some single uniform property but once more a compound of quite different properties found in quite different kinds of operation.1 There is an experiential objectivity in the givenness of the data of sense and of the data of consciousness. But such experiential objectivity is not the one and only ingredient in the objectivity of human knowing. The process of inquiry, investigation, reflection, coming to judge is governed throughout by the exigences of human intelligence and human reasonableness; it is these exigences that, in part, are formulated in logics and methodologies; and they are in their own way no less decisive than experiential objectivity in the genesis and progress of human knowing. Finally, there is a third, terminal, or absolute type of objectivity, that comes to the fore when we judge, when we distinguish sharply between what we feel, what we imagine, what we think, what seems to be so and, on the other hand, what is so. (Fs)

76b However, though these three components all function in the objectivity of adult human knowing, still it is one thing for them to function and it is quite another to become explicitly aware that they function. Such explicit awareness presupposes that one is not a truncated subject, aware indeed of his sensations and his speech, but aware of little more than that. Then, what is meant by "object" and "objective," is something to be settled not by an scrutiny of one's operations and their properties, but by picture-thinking. An object, for picture-thinking, has to be something one looks at; knowing it has to be something like looking, peering, seeing, intuiting, perceiving; and objectivity, finally, has to be a matter of seeing all that is there to be seen and nothing that is not there. (Fs)

77a Once picture-thinking takes over, immanence is an inevitable consequence.2 What is intended in questioning, is not seen, intuited, perceived; it is as yet unknown; it is what we do not know but seek to know. It follows that the intention of questioning, the notion of being, is merely immanent, merely subjective. Again, what is grasped in understanding, is not some further datum added on to the data of sense and of consciousness; on the contrary, it is quite unlike all data; it consists in an intelligible unity or pattern that is, not perceived, but understood; and it is understood, not as necessarily relevant to the data, but only as possibly relevant. Now the grasp of something that is possibly relevant is nothing like seeing, intuiting, perceiving, which regard only what is actually there. It follows that, for picture-thinking, understanding too must be merely immanent and merely subjective. What holds for understanding, also holds for concepts, for concepts express what has been grasped by understanding. What holds for concepts, holds no less for judgments, since judgments proceed from a reflective understanding, just as concepts proceed from a direct or inverse understanding. (Fs)

77b This conclusion of immanence is inevitable, once picture-thinking is admitted. For picture-thinking means thinking in visual images. Visual images are incapable of representing or suggesting the normative exigences of intelligence and reasonableness, and, much less, their power to effect the intentional self-transcendence of the subject. (Fs)

77c The foregoing account, however, though it provides the key to doctrines of immanence, provides no more than a key. It is a general model based on knowledge of the subject. It differs from actual doctrines of immanence, inasmuch as the latter are the work of truncated subjects that have only a partial apprehension of their own reality. But it requires, I think, no great discernment to find a parallel between the foregoing account and, to take but a single example, the Kantian argument for immanence. In this argument the effective distinction is between immediate and mediate relations of cognitional activities to objects. Judgment is only a mediate knowledge of objects, a representation of a representation.3 Reason is never related right up to objects but only to understanding and, through understanding, to the empirical use of reason itself.4 (Fs)

78a Since our only cognitional activity immediately related to objects is intuition,1 it follows that the value of our judgments and our reasoning can be no more than the value of our intuitions. But our only intuitions are sensitive; sensitive intuitions reveal not being but phenomena; and so our judgments and reasoning are confined to a merely phenomenal world.2 (Fs)

78b Such, substantially, seems to be the Kantian argument. It is a quite valid argument if one means by "object" what one can settle by picture-thinking. "Object" is what one looks at; looking is sensitive intuition; it alone is immediately related to objects; understanding and reason can be related to objects only mediately, only through sensitive intuition. (Fs)

78c Moreover, the neglected and truncated subject is not going to find the answer to Kant, for he does not know himself well enough to break the hold of picture-thinking and to discover that human cognitional activities have as their object being, that the activity immediately related to this object is questioning, that other activities such as sense and consciousness, understanding and judgment, are related mediately to the object, being, inasmuch as they are the means of answering questions, of reaching the goal intended by questioning. (Fs)

79a There is a final point to be made. The transition from the neglected and truncated subject to self-appropriation is not a simple matter. It is not just a matter of finding out and assenting to a number of true propositions. More basically, it is a matter of conversion, of a personal philosophic experience, of moving out of a world of sense and of arriving, dazed and disorientated for a while, into a universe of being. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Das existentielle Subject; Analyse des Bewusstsein - metaphysische Psychologie (faculty psychology); 6 Grade des Bewusstseins; Hegel: sublation

Kurzinhalt: Existential Subject ... intellect and will, or different uses of the same faculty, such as speculative and practical intellect ... None of these distinctions adverts to the subject as such ...

Textausschnitt: 79b So far, our reflections on the subject have been concerned with him as a knower, as one that experiences, understands, and judges. We have now to think of him as a doer, as one that deliberates, evaluates, chooses, acts. Such doing, at first sight, affects, modifies, changes the world of objects. But even more it affects the subject himself. For human doing is free and responsible. Within it is contained the reality of morals, of building up or destroying character, of achieving personality or failing in that task. By his own acts the human subject makes himself what he is to be, and he does so freely and responsibly; indeed, he does so precisely because his acts are the free and responsible expressions of himself. (Fs)

79c Such is the existential subject. It is a notion that is overlooked on the schematism of older categories that distinguished faculties, such as intellect and will, or different uses of the same faculty, such as speculative and practical intellect, or different types of human activity, such as theoretical inquiry and practical execution. None of these distinctions adverts to the subject as such and, while the reflexive, self-constitutive element in moral living has been known from ancient times, still it was not coupled with the notion of the subject to draw attention to him in his key role of making himself what he is to be. (Fs) (notabene)

79d Because the older schemes are not relevant, it will aid clarity if I indicate the new scheme of distinct but related levels of consciousness, in which the existential subject stands, so to speak, en the top level. For we are subjects, as it were, by degrees. At a lowest level, when unconscious in dreamless sleep or in a coma, we are merely potentially subjects. Next, we have a minimal degree of consciousness and subjectivity when we are the helpless subjects of our dreams. Thirdly, we become experiential subjects when we awake, when we become the subjects of lucid perception, imaginative projects, emotional and conative impulses, and bodily action. Fourthly, the intelligent subject sublates the experiential, i.e., it retains, preserves, goes beyond, completes it, when we inquire about our experience, investigate, grow in understanding, express our inventions and discoveries. Fifthly, the rational subject sublates the intelligent and experiential subject, when we question our own understanding, check our formulations and expressions, ask whether we have got things right, marshal the evidence pro and con, judge this to be so and that not to be so. Sixthly, finally, rational consciousness is sublated by rational self-consciousness, when we deliberate, evaluate, decide, act. Then there emerges human consciousness at its fullest. Then the existential subject exists and his character, his personal essence, is at stake. (Fs)

80a The levels of consciousness are not only distinct but also related, and the relations are best expressed as instances of what Hegel named sublation, of a lower being retained, preserved, yet transcended and completed by a higher.1 Human intelligence goes beyond human sensitivity yet it cannot get along without sensitivity. Human judgment goes beyond sensitivity and intelligence yet cannot function except in conjunction with them. Human action finally, must in similar fashion both presuppose and complete human sensitivity, intelligence, and judgment. (Fs)

80b It is, of course, this fact of successive sublations that is denoted by the metaphor of levels of consciousness. But besides their distinction and their functional interdependence, the levels of consciousness are united by the unfolding of a single transcendental intending of plural, interchangeable objectives.2 What promotes the subject from experiential to intellectual consciousness is the desire to understand, the intention of intelligibility. What next promotes him from intellectual to rational consciousness, is a fuller unfolding of the same intention: for the desire to understand, once understanding is reached, becomes the desire to understand correctly; in other words, the intention of intelligibility, once an intelligible is reached, becomes the intention of the right intelligible, of the true and, through truth, of reality. Finally, the intention of the intelligible, the true, the real, becomes also the intention of the good, the question of value, of what is worthwhile, when the already acting subject confronts his world and adverts to his own acting in it. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Operatio intellectus: prima, secunda; Bedeutung: Objekt einer Tätigkeit

Kurzinhalt: ... first and a second operation of the intellect; ... several meanings of the notion 'the object of an operation' ... It can mean what moves us to the operation, or the term immanently produced by the operation ...

Textausschnitt: 11b After speaking of the goal, we move to the act by which we attain it. That act requires our attention because, even though our aim is understanding and not certitude, still we hardly want an understanding that is uncertain rather than certain, or false rather than true. Therefore we must accurately grasp what the act of understanding is, what its properties are, and how this act is connected with what is true and what is certain.1 (Fs)

11c Ever since Aristotle, a distinction has been recognized between a first and a second operation of the intellect. In the first operation we ask, 'What is it?' or 'Why is it so?' and we grasp some reason or cause, and we conceive a definition or a hypothesis; but in the second operation we ask, 'Is it?' or 'Is it so?' and we weigh the evidence, and because of the evidence we utter a true judgment, and through the true as through a medium we contemplate being. (Fs)

11d The distinction of first and second operations does not regard a difference in time. Although the first spontaneously gives rise to the second (for we immediately ask whether what we conceive really is so), still the second operation also invites us to a further and better exercise of the first, since we want to understand better what we already know is so. Thus, in order to distinguish these two operations, we have to pay attention to their objects.2 (Fs) (notabene Fußnote)

13a There are several meanings of the notion 'the object of an operation.' It can mean what moves us to the operation, or the term immanently produced by the operation, or the objective of the operation. In the first operation the proper object, the object that moves, is, in the conditions of this present life, an intelligibility or nature that exists as embodied in corporeal matter;1 and the object as term is the conceived definition or hypothesis. In the second operation the object that moves is sufficient evidence, and the object as the immanently produced term is the true. But with each operation the object as the objective is being, which is intended throughout the entire intellectual process.2 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Theologisches Verstehen (Glaubensgeheimnisse ): vermittelt, unvollkommen, analog ... 10 Punkte

Kurzinhalt: theological understanding ... imperfect, analogical, obscure, gradually developing, synthetic, and highly fruitful

Textausschnitt: 15e First, then, the object that moves us to theological understanding is not some intelligibility embodied in corporeal matter, but the intelligibility of God, in whom the mysteries are hidden. This intelligibility moves us, not immediately as in the beatific vision, but mediately through the truth that God has revealed and that we have accepted in faith. (Fs)

15f Second, theological understanding is imperfect. It is a finite act, limited by a finite species. But a finite act is in no way proportionate to understanding perfectly the infinitely perfect God. Therefore, since its object is some mystery hidden in God, theological understanding cannot possibly ever be perfect in this life, this side of the beatific vision. (Fs)

17a Third, this imperfect understanding is analogical. For a finite act of understanding bears directly on something finite; but what bears directly on something finite can be extended only analogically to whatis infinite. (Fs)

17b Fourth, this imperfect and analogical understanding is obscure. For analogy is valid to the extent that there is a similarity between Creator and creature, and 'any similarity, however great, that is discovered between Creator and creature will always leave a still greater dissimilarity to be discovered' (DB 432, DS 806, ND 320). Thus, just as from the similarity comes some light, so from the dissimilarity comes a still greater darkness. (Fs)

17c Fifth, this imperfect, analogical, and obscure theological understanding develops over time. The human mind is such that it advances one step at a time through intermediate acts to acts that are more perfect. As in all else, so in theology, grace does not destroy nature but perfects it. This is clear from the history of theology. So it must be said that theological understanding develops in the course of time. (Fs)

17d Sixth, this imperfect, analogical, obscure, and gradually developing theological understanding is also synthetic. For the human mind is such that it does not wonder about things just individually but, understanding individual elements, goes on to ask how they are connected with one another. And so after the individual mysteries have been considered on their own, further questions arise about how they are connected with one another and with our last end. Answering these questions provides a synthetic understanding. (Fs)

17e Seventh, this synthesis is itself imperfect, analogical, obscure, and gradually developing. For a synthesis is no more than the understanding of many things together. The same reasons that prove that our understanding of individual matters is imperfect, analogical, obscure, and gradually developing also prove that the same will be true of understanding all those matters together. (Fs)

17f Eighth, although even synthetic theological understanding is imperfect, analogical, obscure, and gradually developing, still it is highly fruitful. The condition of one who understands is always better than the condition of one who does not, whether it be in apprehending truth or in teaching it to others or in moving one's inmost will or in counseling and directing others. The more theological understanding is extended to all that has been revealed, the more fully then are those revealed matters apprehended, the more effectively are they taught, and the more faithfully is the whole of human life in all its aspects directed to its final supernatural end. (Fs) (notabene)

19a Ninth, the benefit derived by someone who seriously strives for theological understanding but attains it only in small measure is neither slight nor to be disparaged. Whoever searches for theological understanding has to attend to everything that can lead to such understanding, and that means attending to what God has revealed to us and what the church of God proposes to be believed by all. But neither slight nor to be disparaged is the benefit that is derived from a serious, lengthy, careful, exact consideration of the truths that God has revealed and we are to believe, both in themselves and in all that follows from them. And so it is a mistake to conclude that, unless each one of us actually arrives at an understanding of the mysteries, time is being wasted. (Fs)

20a Tenth, does such theological understanding exist - imperfect, analogical, obscure, gradually developing, synthetic, and highly fruitful? Vatican I has answered that question authoritatively. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Wert: transzendentaler "Begriff" (wie Sein); Intention des Wertes, aber kein Wissen davon; das gute Subjekt; Sündenkatalog

Kurzinhalt: What, then, is value? I should say that it is a transcendental notion like the notion of being ... can catalogue sins in almost endless genera and species yet always remain rather vague about the good ...

Textausschnitt: 81a I am suggesting that the transcendental notion of the good regards value. It is distinct from the particular good that satisfies individual appetite, such as the appetite for food and drink, the appetite for union and communion, the appetite for knowledge, or virtue, or pleasure. Again, it is distinct from the good of order, the objective arrangement or institution that ensures for a group of people the regular recurrence of particular goods. As appetite wants breakfast, so an economic system is to ensure breakfast every morning. As appetite wants union, so marriage is to ensure life-long union. As appetite wants knowledge, so an educational system ensures the imparting of knowledge to each successive generation. But beyond the particular good and the good of order, there is the good of value. It is by appealing to value or values that we satisfy some appetites and do not satisfy others, that we approve some systems for achieving the good of order and disapprove of others, that we praise or blame human persons as good or evil and their actions as right or wrong. (Fs)

82a What, then, is value? I should say that it is a transcendental notion like the notion of being. Just as the notion of being intends but, of itself, does not know being, so too the notion of value intends but, of itself, does not know value. Again, as the notion of being is dynamic principle that keeps us moving toward ever fuller knowledge of being, so the notion of value is the fuller flowering of the same dynamic principle that now keeps us moving toward ever fuller realization of the good, of what is worth while. (Fs)

82b This may seem nebulous, so I beg leave to introduce a parallel. There is to Aristotle's Ethics an empiricism, that seems almost question-begging. He could write: "Actions ... are called just and temperate when they are such as the just or the temperate man would do; but it is not the man who does these that is just and temperate, but the man who also does them as just and temperate men do them."1 Again, he could add: "Virtue ... is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean, i.e. the mean relative to us, this being determined by a rational principle, and by that principle by which the man of practical wisdom would determine it."2 Aristotle, it seems to me, is refusing to speak of ethics apart from the ethical reality of good men, of justice apart from men that are just, of temperance apart from men that are temperate, of the nature of virtue apart from the judgment of the man that possesses practical wisdom. (Fs)

82c But, whatever may be the verdict about Aristotle, at least the approach I have just noted fits in admirably with the notion of the good I am outlining. Just as the notion of being functions in one's knowing and it is by reflecting on that functioning that one comes to know what the notion of being is, so also the notion or intention of the good functions within one's human acting and it is by reflection on that functioning that one comes to know what the notion of good is. Again, just as the functioning of the notion of being brings about our limited knowledge of being, so too the functioning of the notion of the good brings about our limited achievement of the good. Finally, as our knowledge of being is, not knowledge of essence, but only knowledge of this and that and other beings, so too the only good to which we have firsthand access is found in instances of the good realized in themselves or produced beyond themselves by good men. (Fs) (notabene)

83a So the paradox of the existential subject extends to the good existential subject. Just as the existential subject freely and responsibly makes himself what he is, so too he makes himself good or evil and his actions right or wrong. The good subject, the good choice, the good action are not found in isolation. For the subject is good by his good choices and good actions. Universally prior to any choice or action there is just the transcendental principle of all appraisal and criticism, the intention of the good. That principle gives rise to instances of the good, but those instances are good choices and actions. However, do not ask me to determine them, for their determination in each case is the work of the free and responsible subject producing the first and only edition of himself. (Fs)

83b It is because the determination of the good is the work of freedom that ethical systems can catalogue sins in almost endless genera and species yet always remain rather vague about the good. They urge us to do good as well as to avoid evil, but what it is to do good does not get much beyond the golden rule, the precept of universal charity, and the like. Still the shortcomings of system are not an irremediable defect. We come to know the good from the example of those about us, from the stories people tell of the good and evil men and women of old, from the incessant flow of praise and blame that makes up the great part of human conversation, from the elation and from the shame that fill us when our own choices and deeds are our own determination of ourselves as good or evil, praiseworthy or blameworthy. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Das existentielle Subjekt: kein Primat der Resultate (Wille Vernunft; Primat des Subjekts als: überlegend, abwägend, entscheidend, handelnd

Kurzinhalt: Results proceed from actions, actions from decisions, decisions from evaluations, evaluations from deliberations, and all five from the existential subject, the subject as deliberating, evaluating ...

Textausschnitt: 84a I have been affirming a primacy of the existential. I distinguished different levels of human consciousness to place rational self-consciousness at the top. It sublates the three prior levels of experiencing, of understanding, and of judging, where, of course, sublating means not destroying, not interfering, but retaining, preserving, going beyond, perfecting. The experiential, the intelligible, the true, the real, the good are one, so that understanding enlightens experience, truth is the correctness of understanding, and the pursuit of the good, of value, of what is worthwhile in no way conflicts with, in every way promotes and completes, the pursuit of the intelligible, the true, the real. (Fs)

84b It is to be noted, however, that we are not speaking of the good in the Aristotelian sense of the object of appetite, id quod omnia appetunt. Nor are we speaking of the good in the intellectual, and, indeed, Thomist sense of the good of order. Besides these there is a quite distinct meaning of the word "good"; to it we refer specifically when we speak of value, of what is worthwhile, of what is right as opposed to wrong, of what is good as opposed not to bad but to evil. It is the intention of the good in this sense that prolongs the intention of the intelligible, the true, die real, that founds rational self-consciousness, that constitutes the emergence of the existential subject. (Fs)

84c Finally, let me briefly say that the primacy of the existential does not mean the primacy of results, as in pragmatism, or the primacy of will, as a Scotist might urge, or a primacy of practical intellect, or practical reason, as an Aristotelian or Kantian might phrase it. Results proceed from actions, actions from decisions, decisions from evaluations, evaluations from deliberations, and all five from the existential subject, the subject as deliberating, evaluating, deciding, acting, bringing about results. That subject is not just an intellect or just a will. Though concerned with results, he or she more basically is concerned with himself or herself as becoming good or evil and so is to be named, not a practical subject, but an existential subject. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Das entfremdete Subjekt; Grenzen der Intentionalitätsanalyse; Leugnung des Subjektes durch Immanentismus

Kurzinhalt: The Alienated Subject; the very wealth of existential reflection can turn out to be a trap ... there are those that resentfully and disdainfully brush aside the old questions of cognitional theory, epistemology, metaphysics

Textausschnitt: The Alienated Subject

85a Existential reflection is at once enlightening and enriching. Not only does it touch us intimately and speak to us convincingly but also it is the natural starting-point for fuller reflection on the subject as incarnate, as image and feeling as well as mind and will, as moved by symbol and story, as intersubjective, as encountering others and becoming "I" to "Thou" to move on to "We" through acquaintance, companionship, collaboration, friendship, love. Then easily we pass into the whole human world founded on meaning, a world of language, art, literature, science, philosophy, history, of family and mores, society and education, state and law, economy and technology. That human world does not come into being or survive without deliberation, evaluation, decision, action, without the exercise of freedom and responsibility. It is a world of existential subjects and it objectifies the values that they originate in their creativity and their freedom. (Fs)

85b But the very wealth of existential reflection can turn out to be a trap. It is indeed the key that opens the doors to a philosophy, not of man in the abstract, but of concrete human living in its historical unfolding. Still, one must not think that such concreteness eliminates the ancient problems of cognitional theory, epistemology, and metaphysics, for if they occur in an abstract context, they recur with all the more force in a concrete context. (Fs) (notabene)

85c Existential reflection, as it reveals what it is for man to be good, so it raises the question whether the world is good. Is this whole process from the nebulae through plants and animals to man, is it good, a true value, something worthwhile? This question can be answered affirmatively, if and only if one acknowledges God's existence, his omnipotence, and his goodness. Granted those three, one can say that created process is good because the creative fiat cannot but be good. Doubt or deny any of the three, and then one doubts or denies any intelligent mind and loving will that could justify anyone saying that this world is good, worthwhile, a value worthy of man's approval and consent. For "good" in the sense we have been using the term is the goodness of the moral agent, his deeds, his works. Unless there is a moral agent responsible for the world's being and becoming, the world cannot be said to be good in that moral sense. If in that sense the world is not good, then goodness in that sense is to be found only in man. If still man would be good, he is alien to the rest of the universe. If on the other hand he renounces authentic living and drifts into the now seductive and now harsh rhythms of his psyche and of nature, then man is alienated from himself. (Fs) (notabene)

86a It is, then, no accident that a theatre of the absurd, a literature of the absurd, and philosophies of the absurd flourish in a culture in which there are theologians to proclaim that God is dead. But that absurdity and that death have their roots in a new neglect of the subject, a new truncation, a new immanentism. In the name of phenomenology, of existential self-understanding, of human encounter, of salvation history, there are those that resentfully and disdainfully brush aside the old questions of cognitional theory, epistemology, metaphysics. I have no doubt, I never did doubt, that the old answers were defective. But to reject the questions as well is to refuse to know what one is doing when one is knowing; it is to refuse to know why doing that is knowing; it is to refuse to set up a basic semantics by concluding what one knows when one does it. That threefold refusal is worse than mere neglect of the subject, and it generates a far more radical truncation. It is that truncation that we experience today not only without but within the Church, when we find that the conditions of the possibility of significant dialogue are not grasped, when the distinction between revealed religion and myth is blurred, when the possibility of objective knowledge of God's existence and of his goodness is denied. (Fs)

86b These are large and urgent topics. I shall not treat them. Yet I do not think I am neglecting them entirely, for I have pointed throughout this paper to the root difficulty, to neglect of the subject and the vast labor involved in knowing him. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Arten von Fragen: Kohärenz, Einsicht, Existenz; Abälard, Sic et Non

Kurzinhalt: In a first way, the question can be understood to express a problem of coherence ...

Textausschnitt: 21c In a first way, the question can be understood to express a problem of coherence, and so, on hearing die question, one at once answers no (Videtur quod non), because the Holy Spirit is from the Father and die Son, and what is from others is not from itself; but then one remembers (Sed contra est) that the Holy Spirit is God, and God is a se, and so the Holy Spirit is a se. Two arguments are used, to prove each side of a contradiction. That is a problem of coherence. (Fs)

21d In a second way, the question can be understood to express a problem for understanding. Granted that the Holy Spirit is both a se and not a se, how can both statements simultaneously be true? The matter would be quite simple if die Holy Spirit were composite; then the Holy Spirit could be a se in one respect and not a se in another. But the Holy Spirit is utterly simple, and so there arises a very serious problem for understanding. (Fs)

21e In a third way, the question can be understood to express a problem of fact, such that the meaning of the question is, Does there really exist a third divine person? Is this really taught in the sources of revelation? Is it understood in the same sense in the sources of revelation as it was later in the councils and among theologians? (Fs)

21f Furthermore, although diese three kinds of problems are very closely interconnected, still in any particular period more attention might be paid to one kind than to another. Thus, in the early stages of scientific inquiry when it is still necessary to persuade people to devote themselves to science, it might be extremely useful to focus on the problem of coherence; and so Abelard, continuing in the footsteps of some canonists, composed his Sic et non (ML 178, 1339-1610), in which he presented supporting reasons for both the affirmative and the negative side of 158 theological propositions. But it would be of little value to prove the existence of questions yet never attempt to solve them. Hence some people composed books of Sentences to collect and organize, from scripture and the Fathers, material for problems. Others began working out answers, either in the form of commentary on those books of Sentences or independently in shorter collections of questions or in larger works that expounded a summa of the whole of theology. (Fs)

23a Seeking answers moved theologians beyond the problem of coherence to the problem of understanding. Working on that problem, they soon discovered that questions cannot be put in any order whatsoever. Some questions simply cannot be answered until others have been resolved. And sometimes the answers to one question immediately provide the answers to others. This discovery lies behind the differing order of the questions in St Thomas's commentary on the Sentences and his Summa theologiae. He indicated the difference in the prologue to the first part of the Summa, where he distinguished the order of learning from the order demanded by running commentaries. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Unterschied: theologische Schlussfolgerung - Urteil über theologisches Verstehen

Kurzinhalt: The judgment about a theological understanding differs, then, from any and all theological conclusions ... In contrast, a judgment about a theological understanding is not easy ...

Textausschnitt: 47b Ninth, a judgment as to the consequent truth of theological understanding appears to rest chiefly on three considerations. First, we can examine this understanding in terms of what issues from it precisely as understanding. Does it solve some problem? Is the problem that it solves a divine mystery, something that can be understood by us in this life mediately, imperfecdy, analogically, obscurely? Is the understanding fruitful in the sense that it provides a virtual solution to other connected problems? Is there another analogy that is better or at least as good in resolving all the same problems, or is there no other analogy that can be known by us in this life?

47c Second, we can examine the same understanding not in itself but by way of historical comparison. Has the same problem been considered before? Was it considered directly or only indirectly? Was it considered in the same complex of problems or in a different one? Was the same analogy used or a different one? If the same one, is the analogy now being grasped more profoundly? Are new aspects being added to it, whether because of progress in the natural and human sciences or because of progress in studies of scripture, the councils, the Fathers, the medievals, and so on? Does understanding the principle really ground all the other conclusions deduced later in the treatise? Are more and more complete conclusions being deduced now than before? Is an overall view of the whole material now more easily reached? Can we now see further problems that call for and practically demand further progress in understanding, knowledge, and wisdom? (Fs)

49a Third, we can examine the same understanding by comparing it with the pseudo-problems and pseudo-systems that may have arisen with regard to this subject matter, that may have spread abroad, and that may still to some extent prevail. Are all the questions that have ever been considered with regard to this subject matter being given equal treatment, or is a selection perhaps being made, so that certain questions are given priority, others are treated as secondary, and still others are left unmentioned? And if a selection is being made, is it made on the basis of custom, or on the basis of some principle? Is the principle found in the fact that what is being sought is some understanding of divinely revealed mystery, and that problems that have arisen from misunderstanding are not to be considered except where treating them is the only way to remove certain widely held obstacles to understanding the mystery?

49b Tenth, if it is true that one major fruit of education is that we learn to use different criteria of judgment for different materials, then it is useful to compare the judgment regarding a theological understanding with other judgments that are made in theology. (Fs)

49c The judgment about a theological understanding differs, then, from any and all theological conclusions. Nothing is easier than to conclude correctly: once the premises are posited, the conclusion either follows necessarily or it does not; if it does not, it is not valid; if it does, it is no less true than the premises. (Fs)

49d In contrast, a judgment about a theological understanding is not easy; it is extremely difficult. What is in question is not a conclusion but a principle. The principle may be merely possible. It may be more or less probable. Sometimes all we can say about it is that at least it may be on the line or along the way that alone leads to the understanding that Vatican I referred to. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Glaube - Vernunft; Schlussfolgerungen aus Glaubensgeheimnissen vs. Verstehen derselben;
"Schlusstheologie" (conclusions theology)

Kurzinhalt: What happens when deductions are made from revealed mysteries is that the problems clearly and distinctly emerge. The more numerous and the more exact the deductions ...

Textausschnitt: 55d Again, the way in which this understanding of mysteries is compared to conclusions, whether pure or mixed, is also not in the least obscure. What happens when deductions are made from revealed mysteries is that the problems clearly and distinctly emerge. The more numerous and the more exact the deductions, the more numerous and the more difficult are the problems that emerge; and since the problems stand forth the way they do because the premises of the deductions tell of divine mysteries, the problems can never be solved unless some understanding of the mysteries is attained.1 (Fs) (notabene)

55e Again, when this understanding is attained 'from the analogy of what the mind knows naturally,' a certain hypothetical element is introduced. Materially speaking, it is possible that the same analogy is hinted at, insinuated, or suggested in the sources of revelation; it may even be clearly indicated. But one can never prove that the formally identical analogy along with all its systematic implications is present in the sources. (Fs)

55f It follows that the idea that theology deals only with pure and mixed conclusions is simply mistaken. Logic applied to revealed mysteries leads to problems, the solutions of which can come only through some understanding of the mysteries. When these solutions introduce a hypothetical element (and at least the system virtually contained in a fruitful understanding is hypothetical), then there is posited a specifically theological principle that comes neither from faith alone nor from reason alone, but from reason enlightened by faith and inquiring diligently, reverently, and judiciously. (Fs)

57a We need, then, to indicate the extent to which 'conclusions theology' does harm to theology as a science. (Fs)
57b First, it fosters a tendency to impose on earlier authors the systematic discoveries of a later time. Those who love system and know no other method of verification but deduction from the sources generally find their system in the scriptural, patristic, or medieval sources. (Fs)

Second, since not all systematic theologians are of one mind and heart, in the end not one but many different systems will be read into the sources. (Fs)

Third, since the real criterion of the validity of a system is not deduction from the sources, then if 'conclusions theology' prevails, it will hardly be possible to refute inept systems and seriously argue the case for more adequate ones. (Fs)

Fourth, now that scriptural exegesis, patristics, and medieval historical studies abound, theologians who deduce systems generally earn criticism for their ignorance of the scriptures, the Fathers, and medieval history. (Fs)

Fifth, as long as scripture scholars, patristic scholars, and medievalists are aware of no kind of systematic verification other than deduction from the sources, they will regard every system as so much empty speculation. (Fs)

57c On the other hand, if we abandon the idea that theology is about pure or mixed conclusions, not only will there be no real conflict between positive theologians and systematic theologians, but they will actually be of enormous assistance to one another. Understanding a doctrine is really not that far removed from understanding the history of the doctrine. If the doctrine is always the same, that is, the same dogma, the same meaning, the same view, and if moreover understanding, knowledge, and wisdom about the same doctrine grow and progress from age to age, then no valid reason remains why positive and systematic theologians should oppose one another. What is now understood by systematic theologians has been a long time in preparation, and so by understanding the history, systematic theologians will come to understand their task fully and exactly, just as by understanding later solutions positive theologians will be able to grasp more clearly and judge more accurately what really were the earlier states of affairs and in what direction they tended. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Kriterien für theologisches Verstehen: menschliche Natur, Ursprung der Offenbarung; Erbsünde, intellektuelle Konversion; Autorität der Kirche

Kurzinhalt: ... the two supreme criteria by which the truth of a theological understanding has to be judged. One has to do with human nature ...

Textausschnitt: 57d Twelfth, we still have not mentioned the two supreme criteria by which the truth of a theological understanding has to be judged. One has to do with human nature, the other with the divine source of revelation. (Fs)

57e When we speak of human nature, we must not overlook the wound of original sin. Because of it human beings, immersed in sensible things, more or less create for themselves their own special kind of problems. The questions and the solutions that theology presents1 are generally outside the horizon of wounded human beings, to whom such things seem to wander far from reality, from serious living, and from any kind of usefulness. What people want and need, they say, is completely different from what they are taught and almost feel compelled to parrot. The existential problem is this: people have to emerge from the sensible, so as not only to say but also to agree and, as it were, to feel that the real becomes known not in the 'given' but in the 'true.' But if this existential problem is transferred to the objective level, if it is presupposed that the issue is not the intellectual conversion of the subject but theology itself, a very serious deviation, easily finding large numbers of adherents, has begun. (Fs) (notabene)

59a As for the divine source of revelation, it is clear that the meaning of any truth has to be measured by the understanding of the one from whom the truth proceeds. A revealed truth proceeds from divine understanding and therefore it is measured only by divine understanding. Moreover, since here on earth God has entrusted divine revelation to none other than the church to guard it faithfully and declare it infallibly, it is clear that theologians cannot rely ultimately on their own wisdom but ought always to acknowledge that the church's teaching alone is determinative of the meaning of revealed truth and of sacred dogmas (DB 1788, 1800, 1818; DS 3007, 3020, 3043; ND 217, 136, 139). (Fs) (notabene)

59b Theologians who, as the very nature of the material demands, promptly and gladly submit their own wisdom to that of the church will find in so doing a remedy for the disease, the wound of sin discussed in the preceding point. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Wissenschaft: Erkenntnis aus Gründen; Ziel, zwei Wege: Analyse, Resolution ... (Dogmatik, dogmatische Theologie) - Synthese, Komposition ... (systematische Th.); Theologen: Missverständnis der differenzierten Einheit

Kurzinhalt: It follows that the dogmatic way can be conceived as similar to the analytic way ... for like reasons the systematic part of theology can be conceived as similar to the way of synthesis ...

Textausschnitt: 59d How these two movements are related to each other can be clarified from the very notion of science. Science is the certain knowledge of things through their causes; but before things are known through their causes, the causes have to be discovered; and as long as the causes have not yet been discovered we rely on the ordinary prescientific knowledge by which we apprehend things and describe them even before knowing their causes. (Fs)

61a So the first movement toward acquiring science begins from an ordinary prescientific description of things and ends in the knowledge of their causes. This first movement has been called:

(1) analysis, because it starts from what is apprehended in a confused sort of way and moves to well-defined causes or reasons,
(2) the way of resolution, because it resolves things into their causes,
(3) the way of discovery, because previously unknown causes are discovered,
(4) the way of certitude, because the ordinary prescientific knowledge of things is most obvious to us, and so the arguments we find most certain begin from such knowledge and go on to demonstrate matters that are more remote and more obscure to us, and
(5) the temporal way, because causes are not usually discovered instantaneously, any more than they are discovered by just anyone or without a certain amount of good luck.1 (Fs)

61b The other movement starts from the causes that have been discovered and ends by understanding things in their causes. This movement is called:

(1) synthesis, because fundamental reasons2 are employed both to define things and to deduce their properties,
(2) the way of composition, because causes are employed to produce things or to constitute them,
(3) the way of teaching or of learning, because it begins with concepts that are fundamental and especially simple, so that by adding a step at a time it may proceed in an orderly way to the understanding of an entire science,
(4) the way of probability, partly because it often attains no more than probability, but also because people frequently have no clear discernment of just where or when they have reached certitude, and
(5) the way of logical simultaneity, because, once the principles have been clearly laid down, all the rest takes comparatively little time; it can be accomplished in a few short deductions and applications. (Fs)

61c For examples of the two ways, compare the history of a science like physics or chemistry with the textbooks from which these sciences are taught. History reveals that these sciences worked out their various demonstrations starting from the most obvious sensible data. But when one goes to a textbook, one finds at the beginning of the book, in chemistry, only the periodic table of elements from which three hundred thousand compounds are derived, or, in physics, Newton's laws, Riemannian geometry, or those remarkable quantum operators. The reason for this difference is, of course, that inquiring, investigating, and demonstrating begin with what is obvious, while teaching begins from those concepts that can be understood without understanding other elements. (Fs)

63a Now since theology is analogously a science, its dogmatic part is not completely different from the way of analysis, nor is its systematic part completely different from the way of synthesis. Just as in the natural order we begin from ordinary prescientific knowledge, so also in theology we begin from what God has revealed in particular historical circumstances. Just as in the natural order we proceed to the discovery of causes, so theology states universally in the same meaning the same truth that was once biblically3 revealed. Just as in the natural order the discovery of causes leads to the knowledge of things through the causes, so in theology once the divine mysteries have been declared or defined universally, they can be imperfectly and obscurely but still most fruitfully understood. (Fs)

63b It follows that the dogmatic way can be conceived as similar to the analytic way. It is a way of certitude in that it expresses the same truth with the same meaning as what was revealed by God. Second, it is a way of discovery in that it finds an expression appropriate to the needs of a universal church that is to endure till the end of time. Third, it is a way of analysis in that it moves from historical Hebraic particularity to generally known and well-defined reasons. Fourth, it is a way of resolution in that it discerns the divine mysteries in the multiplicity of what has been revealed, and gives expression to those mysteries. Finally, it is a temporal way because a universal expression of the mysteries is attained only in the course of time. (Fs)

63c In like manner and for like reasons the systematic part of theology can be conceived as similar to the way of synthesis. For it is the way in which teachers teach and students learn, at least if it is true that for something truly to be learned it must be understood and that the only way to reach understanding is to start with that whose understanding does not require the understanding of anything else. It is, moreover, a way of synthesis in that, starting from one principle or another, it lays out all the rest in an orderly fashion. Third, it is a way of composition in that it composes the whole of a divine mystery from a series of aspects and a multiplicity of reasons. Fourth, it is a way of probability because, rather than deducing certainties from what has been revealed, it derives what has been revealed from some prior hypothetical supposition. Finally, it is a way of logical simultaneity in that, once in one's wisdom one discovers the order of the questions, and once in one's understanding one grasps a principle, then the conclusions and the applications follow of their own accord. This derivation of conclusions may be deficient in terms of logical rigor, since it proceeds from a principle that is only imperfectly and obscurely understood; but that does not mean that the process of arriving at conclusions from a systematic principle is the kind of thing that proceeds one step at a time over a long stretch of years, with a certain amount of luck. (Fs)

65a While we have acknowledged in the dogmatic way something of the process of analysis, of resolution, of discovery, of certitude, and of a temporal way, and in the systematic way something of the process of synthesis, of composition, of teaching and learning, of probability, and of logical simultaneity, we cannot ignore the fact that these terms are used analogously. Analysis and synthesis are understood in one way in physics and in another way in chemistry; they are understood in one way in the natural sciences, in another way in the human sciences, and in another way in theological disciplines. The way we understand the nature of material things is different from the way we understand the words of Plato; and when we understand Plato, we next judge whether what Plato held is true. But we believe that the word of God is true even before we investigate what it teaches. Therefore the dogmatic way has its own mode of being a way of analysis, of resolution, of discovery, of certitude, and a temporal way, and the systematic way has likewise its own mode of being a way of synthesis, of composition, of teaching or learning, of probability, and of logical simultaneity. (Fs)

65b How intimately these two ways are linked must be particularly stressed because there never seem to be lacking those whose diminished wisdom is ready and eager to take a part for the whole and to pass it on as such to others. Analysis and synthesis, resolution and composition, discovery and teaching, certitude and the understanding of what is certain, lengthy investigation and a brief compendium of results - these constitute a single whole. Those who choose but one part and neglect the other not only lose the whole but also spoil even the part that they have chosen. Those who neglect the dogmatic part in order to cultivate the systematic more profoundly are in fact neglecting what they are seeking to understand. Soon pseudo-problems emerge and pseudo-systems start to sprout, systems that dispute ever so subtly about everything while overlooking the understanding of the mysteries. But those who neglect the systematic part in order to hold faithfully and exactly to the dogmatic so resolve the one divine revelation into many different mysteries that no move can be made back from this multiplicity to unity; from what God has revealed for all to understand, they devise in the course of time a technical expression of that revelation, but they do not grasp how these technical matters are to be taught and learned. They know with certainty many technical matters, but choose to overlook the understanding of what they are certain of. They rummage through the past collecting and accumulating technically established information concerning the councils, papal documents, the Fathers, the theologians, but they avoid the task of assembling a wisely ordered, intelligible compendium of all these matters. And after all this, they stand amazed that devout people reject dogmatic theology and take refuge in some form of biblicism that is itself hardly secure. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Fachgeschichte (technical history); Collingwood; Unterschied zu occasional history

Kurzinhalt: That type of historical work I venture to call technical history ... There are points at which that technique can be applied; but there are equally the lacunae ...

Textausschnitt: 55b History as a scientific subject had its principal development in the nineteenth century, say, since von Ranke; and I will now try to suggest the notion of technical history. (Fs)

55c History begins as belief; the historian is not at all places at all times. He does not see and hear everything, he needs the reports of other people, and he takes the word of others for what happened elsewhere and at other times. There can arise conflicting testimonies, and in a conflict between what the witnesses say and what the historian believes could really happen, there will arise a critique of witnesses - of what they could know, how accurate their knowledge is likely to be, how truthful they are, whether they have ulterior motives, and so forth. However, as Collingwood points out in a fable in his The Idea of History, the historian need not be simply a believer. Collingwood composed a detective story in which all the witnesses were lying and all the clues were planted and yet the detective could figure out what really happened. He was not believing any of the witnesses, he was not trusting any of the clues, yet he could determine just what happened, who was the criminal.1 (Fs)

56a With that point reached, history turns over from a collection of beliefs to something analogous to an empirical science. It is concerned not with testimonies but, if I may use the word of Professor Renier, with 'traces.'2 Everything that exists in the present and had its origin in the past constitutes a trace of the past. It may be a document; it may be anything else in the way of ruins, buildings, coins, inscriptions, folkways, traditions, and so forth. All that comes from the past into the present is so much raw material. To the historian it is data, it constitutes data, and as a datum it is valid. It is irrelevant as yet whether it is going to be classified as something truthful or as a lie, as a genuine moment of the past or as a fake. That will depend upon how we classify it, what period it will be attributed to, what value will be placed upon it. All of that will depend upon the judgment of the historian. Just as the physicist considers all the colors he sees in the spectroscope and all the measurements obtained, and so on, as so much data in which he seeks an understanding and as the start of the hypothetico-deductive process, so in somewhat similar fashion the historian is not simply a believer of what other people have told him, a shrewd believer sizing up, accepting some, discounting others, but something like a scientist seeking an understanding of all the traces of the past that are existing into the present. (Fs)

56b That understanding reached by the historian is a thing that develops as do the empirical sciences. If one historian interprets the data a certain way, another, by pointing to data that have been overlooked or misinterpreted, can challenge his conclusions and set up a new view on the subject, which can be a progressively improving interpretation of what happened in the past. However, history differs from the empirical sciences in two ways. First of all, historical understanding is not of general laws. It is of the particular and the concrete. Consequently, following upon this first difference, it is not possible for the historian to check his understanding of this case by appealing directly to other cases. If the physicist says that the ratio between the angle of incidence and the angle of refraction of a ray of light is some constant which he applies to this particular case, well, he can appeal to all similar cases to check his interpretation, his account of the phenomena. The historian is interpreting just this particular case; other cases may all differ; he does not have the type of check which the empirical scientist has. On the other hand, he does have something similar insofar as the historical interpretation of a period, of all the particular cases in a given section of space-time, has to present something of a coherent picture; an interpretation of one set of events has to be able to fit in with another closely related set of events; so there is a fair analogy between the understanding the historian seeks of the traces of the past and the procedure of the empirical scientist. That type of historical work I venture to call technical history. (Fs)

[...]

58b On the other hand, technical history has its weakness. That type of interlocking of the data is not something that can be applied along the whole historical continuum. There are points at which that technique can be applied; but there are equally the lacunae, and the lacunae can occupy many more places than the points. Consequently, there remains a permanent temptation for the historian to fill in the blanks, and there is a fundamental problem in historical method with regard to these periods in which there are some data but not enough to give you that interlocking of a whole series of considerations that pins down the meaning of the event. Herbert Butterfield takes the stand that history is a limited undertaking.1 We do what we can; we do not undertake to answer all questions; and that is pretty much the common sense of the historian. He will indicate his various degrees of confidence in the exactitude of what he is saying, point out that he is not quite sure of that, and so forth. One does not hesitate to say one does not know, is not sure. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Fachgeschichte (technical history; Relativismus (Huizinga); Bultmann (Verständnis, Vorverständnis)

Kurzinhalt: Huizinga, and his definition was that history is a people interpreting to itself its past ... Bultmann ... The historian's view of human nature, of human destiny, plays a fundamental role in the selection ...

Textausschnitt: 59a A second view is relativism. Now that is an extremely large doctrine. I will just take a single and rather simple example of it, using one of the set of papers in a Festschrift presented to Ernst Cassirer on his sixtieth birthday, about 1936, with the title Philosophy and History.1 If I remember rightly, the first essay was by Johan Huizinga,2 and his definition was that history is a people interpreting to itself its past. But the people of today who do the interpreting are not the people who did the interpreting fifty years ago, and they have quite a different slant on things. A lot of water has gone under the bridge, and consequently the interpretation of the past in the present history is not the interpretation of the past of fifty years ago, and much less of a hundred years ago, and so on. There are several histories. This relativism can come out in many ways. You can have the English history of England, the French history of England, the German history of England, and the three are not exactly the same; and similarly, you can have several other combinations. The possibility of that arises insofar as history is not simply the strict technical history, insofar as it fills in the blanks or holes, or leans rather heavily on qualities and probabilities that depend a good deal upon the subject who is writing the history. (Fs)

59b A third view comes out in Rudolph Bultmann. He distinguishes between understanding and preunderstanding, Verständnis and Vorverständnis.1 The understanding, the Verständnis, is this interlocking of the data (although he expresses himself somewhat differently). But the preunderstanding, the Vorverständnis, is a philosophy, and his philosophy for interpreting the New Testament is Heidegger's. I think he has the better part of the argument against the less sophisticated New Testament scholars, insofar as they say he is using a philosophy to interpret the New Testament. 'But so are you,' he says, 'and I know what my philosophy is; yours is just a set of unconscious assumptions. I am making it quite plain to people what I am presuming. You are unconsciously - perhaps deliberately, but then you are just trying to fool them - passing off your assumptions without letting them know.' Again it is a case of the interlocking of the data; give one, take one, so far, but the questions that are raised about history, and especially about a history such as that of the New Testament, are not easily settled in that manner. The historian's view of human nature, of human destiny, plays a fundamental role in the selection, first of all, of the field that he studies (why is he interested in the New Testament?) as well as in the way he goes about it, the types of thought he appeals to to illuminate the New Testament, the selection of topics, and so on. (I suppose there is no element in history that has been studied with such intensity and such a terrific flow of volumes during the past century as all that is concerned with the New Testament. It is an overworked field, in many ways.) There is very clearly in the New Testament, taken as a historical document, the problem of how far does our understanding of the text take us, and how much does that understanding of the text depend upon other factors. (Fs)

60a Finally, of course, there is the naive approach, unaware of the issue. People have their own minds, and that's good common sense; when the odier fellow's assumptions begin to appear and reveal differences of interpretation, well, he's wrong. But they have not too much consciousness that they are doing the same sort of thing themselves. (Fs)
So much for technical history. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Erklärende Geschichte (explanatory history) in der empirischen Wissenschaft; Lonergan's Schere (lower, upper blade)

Kurzinhalt: A man who really understands his mathematics can write an extremely intelligible history of mathematics, and similarly for these other subjects. The subject can be put together as a whole ...

Textausschnitt: 1.3 Explanatory History

60b Next, explanatory history. Technical history, I said, had a clear assimilation to empirical science, but there is a very important and a very fundamental difference methodologically, and we have been heading to that difference in our discussion, for example, of Bultmann. (Fs)

1.3.1 In Empirical Science

60c In empirical science, the most conspicuous part is the work of observation, of measurement, of collecting measurements, putting them on a graph, curve-fitting, finding a formula; but that is what I call insights, simply the lower blade of the method. The method is a pair of scissors, and it has not only a lower blade but also an upper blade, and the two come together. Galileo proceeded from falling bodies, bodies falling from the leaning tower of Pisa and bodies sliding down inclined planes. He also had an upper blade: the understanding of nature was going to fit into Euclidean geometry. That general assumption was just as much a determinant of his results as the observations and measurements. Newton substitutes for Euclidean geometry a similar deductive science called mechanics. It was a matter of setting down definitions and axioms and deducing things like movement of bodies in central fields of force, discovering that bodies moved just as Kepler had found the planets to move. Again, that mechanics is an upper blade that combines with the lower blade and gives you empirical science. Later, there came, in the place of Newton's mechanics, Einstein's relativity mechanics; and the quantum theory introduces notions of discontinuity and indeterminacy. (Fs) (notabene)

61a There is always operative an upper blade; and the same holds in the other empirical sciences. There is not just simply a matter of proceeding from the data; there is also always operative an upper blade, usually expressed in differential equations or something like that. Can the weakness of technical history, the problem of going beyond the sure points where the data interlock, of having a systematic type of bridgework between those strong points, those piers as it were, be met by the introduction of an upper blade into historical method? (Fs)

61b Now in particular fields that is not only possible but achieved. If you think of such a subject as the history of mathematics, the history of physics, the history of chemistry, of astronomy, geology, biology, technology, medicine, economics, it is quite possible in such a limited field of history to write an explanatory history that goes beyond the interlocking points in the data and satisfies everyone; and that is quite possible because there is a science of mathematics, physics, chemistry, and so on, on which everyone agrees. You cannot write the history of mathematics unless you are a mathematician, you cannot write the history of medicine unless you are a medical doctor; of course, you have to be a historian and know the techniques of the historian, but you also have to have this specialized knowledge, and without it you would be lost. You would not be able to pick out what are data relevant to a history of the field unless you know the subject inside out; you would not be able to pick out what is significant, or when what is significant arose, or what section is fulfilling its promises immediately, and so on. A man who really understands his mathematics can write an extremely intelligible history of mathematics, and similarly for these other subjects. The subject can be put together as a whole, and you have operating in your method not only the lower blade that comes from the interlocking of the data but also the upper blade which is derived from the science at the present time. And that type of history, too, is subject to revision. Insofar as mathematics or physics will further develop, new points will become significant in the future that previously were not; and similarly, insofar as new data come to light, you will have fuller data to connect your history. It is a type of change; it is not falling into a relativism of any sort, but rather it is the same sort of 'subject to change' that is found in the empirical sciences themselves. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Erklärende Geschichte (explanatory history) in: Philosophie, Kunst, allgemeine Geschichte; Sorokin

Kurzinhalt: ... but the trouble is that you get many histories because you have many different upper blades.

Textausschnitt:
62a Now we go a little further into the complexity of the problem. We ask about the history of philosophy. A philosopher from the viewpoint of his philosophy can write an explanatory history of philosophy, and he can fill in the lacunae. But another philosopher with a different philosophy can do the same thing, and you get different results, because any philosophy will supply an upper blade if it is sufficiently developed, and it can take on the form of a philosophy of philosophies. Also, it can take on the task of fulfilling the function of an upper blade in the history of philosophy. The trouble is that there are many philosophies, and the debate here obviously shifts. It is not to be settled so much by historical criteria as by the debate between the philosophies themselves. (Fs)

1.3.3 In Art and Culture

62b The problem of relativism is illustrated in reduced form by the problem of the history of philosophy. A third instance,1 where a further complication arises, occurs when you come to the history of art, the history of a literature or literatures, the history of culture, the history of religions. The further complication is not only that there are many types of religious belief, many types of literature, and so on - there are many philosophies, and the multiplicity of the philosophies is also reflected in the religions and the arts and the cultures - but also that in this case there is a concreteness, and so a resistance to the systematic conceptualization which is of the essence, as it were, of such subjects as mathematics or physics. (Fs)

1.3.4 In General History

63a Now one comes to the final question on this point of explanatory history. There can be an upper blade for things like mathematics and medicine, and to get, as it were, unambiguous results, not a multiplicity of results, you can write explanatory history, you can complement technical history with explanatory. Secondly, you can write explanatory history of philosophy and similar things, or of theology, but the trouble is that you get many histories because you have many different upper blades. History of art and culture introduces a further complexity in its concreteness. Can there be an upper blade for general history, history in the ordinary sense as contrasted with, say, a history of capitalism?2 (Fs) (notabene)

63b A contender for the position is sociology. Sociology is the study of human society at a given time and place, but this sociology over time should provide history with an upper blade, should do for history what the science of mathematics does for the history of mathematics. Something along that line was attempted by a sociologist, a Russian emigre, Pitirim Sorokin. In the thirties, he published four large volumes of Social and Cultural Dynamics.3 It is largely artistic but deals also with several other types of things that he was classifying. What he was proving was the existence of a cycle, and it was applied to Hellenistic and Western culture extended over 2500 years. All I know about this work is that, to do a thing like this, you have to introduce categories, such as a field, and Sorokin's categories were not properly sociological; rather they were philosophic. His fundamental division was of cultures: were they sensate, idealistic, or ideational? These categories correspond roughly to Kierkegaard's three spheres of existential subjectivity: the aesthetic, the ethical, and the religious;4 and again, they correspond to the three spheres you get from Insight according as your emphasis is on experience, understanding, or judgment.5 (Fs)

64a What Sorokin really was doing was using philosophic categories rather than sociological categories. Sociological categories would be something much more precise, and would find an application (say, of a cycle, if it were defined sociologically) without going over tremendous amounts of time. And, of course, in the human sciences there is quite a leap from the merely descriptive type of science to explanatory science - even greater than moving in empirical science from talking about things being heavy, hot, and so on, to talking about mass (which is something quite distinct from weight) or temperature (something quite distinct from being hot). That, perhaps, in sociology, is coming out at the present time in a work by Robert Merton, Social Theory and Social Structure (which the people at the Gregorian University in Rome who are teaching sociology speak of as 'the bible for sociologists').6 Merton seems to be introducing explanatory categories. Insofar as he is successful, there perhaps will be from sociology a tool that will supply an upper blade. We will discuss that further in this course, and many questions will be raised. (Fs)

64b Another illustration or contender as an upper blade in explanatory history is provided by Arnold Toynbee's A Study of History.7 What is history about? Is it like the history of Canada, or the history of England, or the history of Czechoslovakia? History, says Toynbee, is history of civilizations. The unit of study is the civilization. He pins the subject down to one object, what he calls the civilization; he defines the civilization as a field of interdependence. You cannot write the history of Canada and prescind from the history of France and England. You cannot write the history of a European country and prescind from the history of the neighboring Europeans. But you can write the history of Modern Europe (great parts of it, anyway) and allow for merely incidental contacts between it and, say, China. Consequently, there is here a norm of what he means by civilization - the functional concept of civilization. He uses this to say that there are many civilizations, and he makes a guess at the number. Each has its origin, its development, its breakdowns, its decline, its decay. There are relations in space and time between different civilizations. Finally, in volumes 7 to 10 the push, the moving thing behind the whole business, behind the whole of history, is religion; the basic carrier wave is religion. There you have, taken out of historical study, a set of explanatory categories and a set of principal questions for the historian to deal with. Does that set of categories stand to explanatory history as differential equations stand to physical theory, physical explanation? That is the question. (Of course, I am not supposed to answer them all!) (Fs)

65a Now that is not the whole of Toynbee. There is something else besides that fundamental conceptualization of what history is about (namely, about civilization's distinctive developments). This 'something else' is a set of humanistic categories. I spoke a moment ago about terms like weight, something heavy, and terms like mass, which can be defined only by relation to other masses, and ultimately by the inverse-square law of gravitation. And that is a step which is a purely theoretical type of conceptualization. Again, in scholastic philosophy the fundamental terms come out in pairs: potency and act, matter and form, substance and accident; and their meaning is contained in their relations to one another; you have a closed conceptual system. Now humanistic categories are not of that type. A large part of Toynbee's thinking is in categories drawn from the Greek tragedies, from Shakespeare and the Bible, of course, and from Goethe. It is a type of systematic conceptualization that has a meaning to the cultured Westerner, but it is not a type of systematic conceptualization that you have in explanatory science. (Fs) (notabene)

65b Another try along this line is that of Eric Voegelin. His Order and History has, so far - after the mid-fifties - three volumes published by the Louisiana State University Press.8 He has since gone to Munich. Before that, in the early fifties, the University of Chicago Press published his New Science of Politics.9 In these works, the upper blade is a philosophy of man, a philosophy of man of the type that is not just tied down to Heidegger, but is very much in the movement in which you find Heidegger and historians of religion of the type of Mircea Eliade and Ernst Cassirer - Cassirer's Philosophy of Symbolic Forms10 - and so on. (Fs)

66a Well, this discussion of history as a subject provides perhaps a step towards philosophy of history. I mentioned an occasional history, which we did not bother to analyze, to set up in opposition; technical history, which is very much down to earth and very solid but appeals to professors; it does not appeal so much to students and even less to the man on the street - he wants 'meaningful' answers to questions! Also, there is explanatory history, which has a great appeal and is beset with very fundamental difficulties. The difficulty that has been most conspicuous is the problem of relativism; it becomes conspicuous in dated history ('that was a fine historical work, but for 1850 or 1910; it does not count any more') or national history, or history that is acceptable to people of certain philosophic convictions or of certain religious convictions - Catholic history, Protestant history, Jewish history, history that will satisfy Arabs, and so on. That problem of relativism, and the possibility of surmounting it somewhat on the historical level, was raised in connection with the notion of explanatory history. I will now attempt to handle briefly my second topic, namely, philosophy of... (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vergleich: dogmatische - systematische Methode

Kurzinhalt: Thus, in the dogmatic way ... there are first the missions of the Son and of the Holy Spirit ... In the systematic way ... the first consideration is of the one God

Textausschnitt: 6 Comparison of the Dogmatic Way and the Systematic Way

67a We have stated that the dogmatic way and the systematic way are distinct yet connected. Now we will state in greater detail how they are compared to each other. And for concrete examples, we will draw on the brief basic outlines of trinitarian theology. (Fs)

67b Thus, in the dogmatic way (which we have said is a way of analysis, of resolution, of discovery, of certitude, and a temporal way), there are first the missions of the Son and of the Holy Spirit narrated in the New Testament. Second, there is the trinitarian dogma, which affirms, simultaneously, against the Sabellians three who are really distinct and against the subordinationists one sole God (DB 48-51, DS 112-15, ND 301-303). Third, there is the consubstantiality of the three (DB 54, 86; DS 125, 150; ND 7, 305). Fourth, there are the real personal properties, which were worked out by the Cappadocians. Fifth, there is the recognition that these properties are relative and that the relations are relations of origin. Sixth, an understanding of these relations of origin is sought, and in particular an appeal is made to a psychological analogy. (Fs) (notabene)

67c In the systematic way (which we have said is a way of synthesis, of composition, of teaching, of learning, of probability, and of logical simultaneity), the first consideration is of the one God.1 Second, in the one God, who understands, knows, and loves, there are posited intellectual emanations.2 Third, on the emanations are based the relations.3 Fourth, supposing the emanations and the relations,4 the persons are considered all together.5 Fifth, the persons are considered individually.6 Sixth, the persons are related to each of the items considered before the persons were discussed: namely, to the divine essence,7 to the relations or properties,8 and to the notional acts or emanations.9 Seventh, the persons are related to one another10 and to us.11 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vergleich 2: dogmatische - systematische Methode; 8 Unterschiede; Verwirrung durch fehlende Unterscheidung zw. Dogmatik und Systematik

Kurzinhalt: What is prior in one is subsequent in the other ... The reason for this inversion is completely universal ... it is not always grasped how much confusion results from not keeping the dogmatic and systematic ways sufficiently distinct

Textausschnitt: 69a That said, let us proceed to the comparison. (Fs)

In the first place, it is clear that the dogmatic and the systematic ways are concerned with the same realities. The missions of the Son and of the Spirit narrated in the New Testament are identical with the missions discussed by St Thomas in question 43 of the Prima pars of the Summa. The divine generation that St Athanasius wrote about is the same generation that St Thomas spoke of both in question 27, before he had presented his systematic conception of the persons, and in question 41, after he had completed that presentation. This kind of identity will be found all across the board, since the synthetic movement is simply an orderly exposition of what was discovered and demonstrated in the analytic process. (Fs)

69b Second, although each movement treats the same realities, still each posits realities in a different order. What is prior in one is subsequent in the other. Thus, Aquinas ends with the missions, while the New Testament starts with them. Again, the patristic inquiry ends with the psychological analogy, while Aquinas starts with it. The reason for this inversion is completely universal: anyone who inquires or removes doubts starts from what is most obvious in order to conclude to what is more remote and more obscure; but anyone who is teaching starts with those notions that can be understood without presupposing the understanding of other notions, so that, by gradually increasing the complexity, one might arrive at an understanding of the concrete. (Fs)

69c Third, although the same realities are treated in each movement, they are conceived differently in each. The concept of a divine mission that is put forward in a Summa of theology, namely, the relation of the one sent both to the sender and to the term, is hardly what came explicitly to the mind of the first Christians as they read the letters of St Paul. Again, the Creed Quicumque teaches that mere are three persons, but it does not mention three subsisting relations. There is also a universal reason for this difference: included in the way of synthesis is the entire explanatory element toward which the way of analysis proceeds one step at a time. This is behind the common distinction in the manuals between 'the fact,' which they prove from authorities, and 'the understanding of the fact,' in regard to which more often than not they show theologians arguing with one another. (Fs)

71a Fourth, this formal difference of concepts increases as we compare the elements that are prior in the dogmatic way with the elements that are subsequent in the systematic. The later an element is posited in the systematic movement, the more it presupposes and includes the whole previous cumulative understanding. But the earlier an element is posited in the dogmatic movement, the more it expresses a simple narration of fact and the more it avoids any controversial understanding. (Fs)

71b Fifth, the same formal difference of concepts diminishes as we compare the elements that are subsequent in the dogmatic way with the elements that are prior in the systematic. For the dogmatic way moves toward the attainment of understanding, and once it has attained understanding it holds onto it and adds it to previous achievements; and the systematic way does not immediately express all of this understanding at the very beginning. Thus, there is no great difference between the psychological analogy at which the dogmatic way concludes and the same psychological analogy from which the systematic way begins. (Fs)

71c Sixth, the proofs of the two ways differ, partly because of the formally different concepts, but also because of the different goals intended. The dogmatic way proves that relations certainly exist in God, arguing from the names of 'Father' and 'Son,' from the necessity that any distinctions in God be purely relative, and from the notional acts. But the dogmatic way is not aware of the relations insofar as they are somehow known prior to the persons;1 nor does it begin to think about the basis of the relations until it has established the fact that relations do exist. The systematic way, in contrast, proceeds from the foundation of the processions to posit the relations, and since it has not yet formed a systematic conception of the persons, it is only by an inappropriate anticipation that it would argue from the names, properties, and notional acts of the persons. The difference is completely universal: every argument proceeds from something prior and moves to something subsequent; but what are prior in the systematic way are subsequent in the dogmatic; and what are subsequent in the systematic way are prior in the dogmatic. Thus, anyone who tries to use a blend of the two at the same time will be compelled to run through practically the entire treatise in every individual thesis. (Fs)

[...]

75a We have distinguished two ways, the dogmatic and the systematic. While they investigate the same realities, they proceed in contrary and opposed orders', they use formally distinct concepts, they employ different methods of proof, they have different relations to theological notes and censures, and they consider opponents and errors in different ways. Why all this? Because 'every act should be performed in a way adapted to its end. Now an argument can be directed to either of two ends.'1 Although it is the one same being that has essence and the act of existence, although it is the same proposition by which there is expressed the intelligible (which is true) and the true (which is intelligible), and although we cannot without reduplication distinguish between intelligible truth as true and intelligible truth as intelligible, nevertheless there is one operation of the mind that attains intelligible truth as true, and a really distinct operation that attains intelligible truth as intelligible. But if the operations are different, so are the methods by which one proceeds to the operations. It follows that if you seek certitude, you begin from those items that are most manifest and gradually arrive at a demonstration of those that are more obscure; but if you seek understanding, you start from those items which you can understand without presupposing the understanding of others; if, however, what you prefer is confusion, then you demand understanding where certitude is the issue, and certitude where what matters most is understanding. (Fs)

77a I trust no one really wants confusion. But it is not always grasped how much confusion results from not keeping the dogmatic and systematic ways sufficiently distinct. Where the goals are different, where the formal objects are different, where the operations by which the different goals are attained are different, where the orders by which one moves toward the goals are different, where different formal concepts are employed, and different proofs and different ways of considering errors, it makes little sense to judge theological works as if they all had but one goal, one formal object, one kind of operation, one ordering of questions, one type of formal concept, one way of proving, and one way of considering errors. And if it makes little sense when the issue regards simply the dogmatic and systematic ways, it makes even less sense when the consideration of history is added. To that we now turn. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Titel: Philosophical and Theological Papers 1958-1964

Stichwort: Philosophie von []; Philosophie und Geschichte, die geschrieben wird (History That Is Written); Philosophie als Grundsatz von Tätigkeiten

Kurzinhalt: 'philosophy of' as the basic group of operations; what would be true about those operations and their products; will all be true of the operations conducted by the historian

Textausschnitt: 3.1 Philosophy and History That Is Written

70a Insofar as one is concerned with the relations between philosophy and the history that is written, our first topic was largely engaged in exploring this relationship. I was using my own philosophic categories to clarify notions of history as a science, its problems, and its possibilities. The indication of the distinctions among occasional, technical, and explanatory history came right out of notions of what the nature of human understanding is as developed in Insight. There is a further point: just as metaphysics is conceived in Insight as the integrating subject, just as the notion of being is conceived as the notion that underpins, penetrates, and goes beyond all other notions, so metaphysics is, as it were, the science of fundamental inquiry. This inquiry is broken up into the inquiries of the several sciences. It is an inquiry that also criticizes the inquiry of the several sciences. It is an inquiry that also criticizes the results of those inquiries and integrates them and goes beyond them. So too, there is, from that view of metaphysics, a connection with history. Insofar as the historian is operating in the light of a philosophy, he can deal with concepts, and raise questions, that people are interested in, even though those concepts and questions do not pertain to a specialized notion of history (such notions as the good, what is right, what is wrong, and so on). Again, insofar as you conceive your 'philosophy of' as the basic group of operations - experiencing, understanding, and judging - what would be true about those operations and their products will all be true of the operations conducted by the historian: his experiencing the traces now existing from the past, his understanding them, and his passing judgments. (Fs)

70b That conception of 'philosophy of,' on the one hand, involves no intrusion into the specific procedures, the autonomy, of the historian qua historian; and at die same time it facilitates either his or his critics' discussion of the fundamental notions involved, and the valuation of his mode of conceiving them, and the relation of his work to other works. Again, that philosophic background makes it possible to relieve the historian of problems that really are not his concern qua historian. (Historians have been greatly troubled by the problem of relativism, and this has been rather pronounced since large numbers of them were expelled from Nazi Germany, and they could not say, 'Well, one opinion is just as good as another, they are all just so many opinions.' Experience was a little too deep for that. Particularly notable is Karl Mannheim, who did his work especially on the sociology of knowledge.)1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: univok - äquivok: das Erste für uns; Naturwissenschaften - Human- Geisteswissenschaften; Ausweg aus Relativismus (Objektseide): Tiefenpsychologie, Geschichte

Kurzinhalt: the difference between nature and spirit, between the natural sciences and the properly human sciences, is that, for all practical purposes, those realities that are prior for us ...

Textausschnitt: 77c If we want to see what this historical movement really was like, two considerations are necessary. First, we need to form those concepts that will help us grasp clearly and distinctly the intelligibility of historical reality both in general and in those matters that touch the Catholic faith more intimately. Second, after proposing those concepts in this seventh section, we will seek in the next section some understanding of this theological movement, a movement which is intimately connected with what has been called the development of dogma. (Fs)

77d Again, to begin from general notions, the difference between nature and spirit, between the natural sciences and the properly human sciences, is that, for all practical purposes, those realities that are prior for us, better known to us, more obvious to us seem in the natural sciences to remain stable, whereas in the human sciences they undergo slight but continual changes. Colors and sounds, the heavy and the light, the hot and the cold, the dry and the moist, the smooth and the rough, the hard and the soft, and everything else that becomes known to the senses seem to share a kind of immutability with the unchanged character of the human body. As a result, in the natural sciences the categories that express what is prior for us are univocal. But the law of the spirit is different from the law of nature. Languages and customs, domestic, economic, and political structures, the mechanical and liberal arts, religions and sciences not only are multiplied with great diversity, but they also go through recurrent patterns of increase, flourishing, and decay with an astounding fertility and restlessness. For individual human beings, what is prior, better known, and more obvious is whatever they were seeing, hearing, and doing when they were infants or children or adolescents or young adults. And so, as a result of the very variety and inconstancy of human affairs, the categories that indicate what is prior for us become equivocal in the extreme. The us in question is not something fixed and changeless. There are as many remarkable and deep differences in what are spontaneously counted as prior, better known, and more obvious in human affairs as there are periods, ages, cultures, nations, social classes - in fact, almost as many as there are individual human beings. (Fs) (notabene)

79a These differences, which we may for brevity's sake designate as 'cultural,' give rise at once to a fundamental problem: the problem of finding a transcultural principle that would enable us to pass systematically from what is prior for one person to what is prior for another. (Fs)

79b A first element in the solution is appropriated from depth psychology. Human beings are alike not just in their senses but also in those spontaneous symbols in which sensibility both manifests its own finality to spirit and conversely discloses to itself [...]

79c A second element in the solution is the slower and more difficult process by which scholars manage gradually to acquire the culture and almost the mentality of another place and time. [...]

79d A third element in the solution is that not only can narratives of past events be read, compared, and woven together into a single coherent account, but also everything we know from other sciences can be used to help us reach as full an understanding as possible of the whole life of another age in all its aspects: mechanical, artistic, economic, political, social, scientific, philosophical, religious. (Fs)

81a Still, these three elements, even when taken together, hardly provide a full solution to the problem. They help individual researchers cross over from their own culture to a foreign culture. They allow individual scholars somehow to make their own whatever belongs to the foreign culture. They even make it possible that many investigators, provided they belong to the same culture, age, and school of thought, might agree on the objective sequence and significance of historical events. But that hardly overcomes the very serious and most inconvenient fact that there are as many accounts of what was done and as many interpretations of what was said and written as there are cultures, schools, and tendencies of thought. The transcultural problem may indeed be solved, so to speak, on the side of the object, but on the side of the subject it remains unsolved. And that is why we are often told that there are two types of questions: those that deal with material reality can be settled scientifically, while those that touch rather on human principles, judgments, and decisions are left exposed to an inevitable relativism. (Fs) (notabene)

81b This division of questions can be accounted for partly from what we have said already, and partly from certain philosophical or methodological principles. Certitude is allowed regarding what is more material, because what is prior for us, better known to us, more obvious to us in the realm of nature is for all practical purposes univocal. But skepticism prevails in regard to whatever is cultural and spiritual, because in the properly human realm there is considerable equivocity regarding what is prior for some and prior for others, better known to some and better known to others, more obvious to some and more obvious to others.1 Still, suppose one asks, 'Why do historical scholars settle for the merely relative? Why do they put so much study and so much labor into passing simply from what is relative-to-others to what is relative-to-themselves? Why do they not put their effort into uncovering what is prior, more knowable, more obvious in itself?' The frequent response is either that it is safer to avoid all the opinions of philosophers or that some relativistic philosophy is true. (Fs)

81c This kind of 'historicism,' whether in itself or in its philosophical presuppositions or in the theological consequences of these presuppositions, was condemned again and again by Pius XII in his encyclical Humani generis?2 In another work I have discussed the way to attack the real root of relativism and sketched the method by which one can proceed scientifically to the true interpretation of documents.3 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Kirche, Theologie, Geschichte, transkulturelles Problem; das Erste: für uns, in sich; Bewegung: transkulturell, theologisch, dogmatisch; patristisches, mittelalterliches ... prior

Kurzinhalt: Furthermore, we can distinguish a transcultural movement, a theological movement, and a dogmatic movement. A transcultural movement is a movement from a 'scriptural prior' to a 'patristic prior,' or ...

Textausschnitt: 83b Now let us come to the theological question. It was inevitable that a transcultural problem arise among Christians. On the one hand, divine revelation was given to a particular people at definite times and under definite circumstances; thus, the words of scripture and the apostolic preaching of the gospel were directed to particular human beings and so were necessarily implicated in and bound up with their cultural conditions. Yet, on the other hand, the church of God is for all people, at every place, in every culture. Therefore our transcultural problem is already constituted by the fact that a universal and Catholic1 church was founded under particular historical circumstances. Indeed, in the New Testament period itself, at the very origins of the church, when it was decided against the advice of the Judaizers not only to preach to the Gentiles but also to exempt them from Mosaic rituals, the transcultural problem was clearly and distinctly displayed, and, moreover, a magnificent example was given of a solution to the same problem. (Fs)

83c Still, if we are to proceed more systematically, we have to develop further the distinction already made between what is prior in itself and what is prior for us. What is prior in itself remains the same, but it may be called a 'systematic prior,'2 a 'theological prior,' or a 'dogmatic prior.' And what we called 'prior for us' should be subdivided into a 'scriptural prior,' a 'patristic prior,' and a 'contemporary prior,' to signify respectively what was prior, better known, more obvious to an ancient Semitic or Palestinian mentality, or to the faithful of the patristic period, or to the faithful of this or that place, time, or culture. (Fs)
85a Furthermore, we can distinguish a transcultural movement, a theological movement, and a dogmatic movement. A transcultural movement is a movement from a 'scriptural prior' to a 'patristic prior,' or from either of these to a 'contemporary prior.' A theological movement is a movement from a 'scriptural or patristic prior' to 'a systematic prior.' And a dogmatic movement occurs when a 'systematic prior' is confirmed, taught, and defined by the church's magisterium. So the entry of the Gentiles into the inheritance of the people of God was a transcultural movement. Likewise, the medieval creation of catenae, of glossae, and of collections of patristic opinions was transcultural. Transcultural movements are investigated both by missiology and by the more profound type of pastoral theology. But conceiving the divine persons as consubstantial, conceiving the incarnation of the divine Word as a union of two natures in a single person, conceiving divine graces as absolutely supernatural habits and motions, and conceiving sacraments as efficacious signs of grace were all theological movements. Finally, the dogmatic movement is illustrated by the Council of Nicea, which defined that the Son is consubstantial with the Father, by the Council of Chalcedon, which defined that Christ is a single person in two natures, and by the Council of Trent and the First Vatican Council, each of which employed a large number of theological elements both to state and to define the faith. (Fs)

85b On this basis we can say that what is set down in the scriptures is not different from the correct conclusions that theologians arrive at. Rather, the same thing is stated in each, in accord with one or another type of priority. Again, what is set down in the scriptures is not different from what is set down in ecclesial definitions. Rather, the same thing is stated in each, though in accord with one or other type of priority. Finally, the primitive Palestinian faith and Hellenistic faith and medieval faith and contemporary faith are not different faiths. Rather, the same thing is believed in all of them, even though expositions differ in accord with one or other priority. (Fs) (notabene)

85c Accordingly, comparing these movements with one another yields the conclusion that a transcultural movement terminates, say, at a Hellenistic phase or at a medieval phase or at some other contemporary phase, whereas a properly theological movement, since it terminates at what is prior in itself, does not terminate at a Hellenistic phase or at a medieval phase or at some other phase bound to particular cultural circumstances. By the same token, then, to regard the homoousion as merely Hellenistic or transubstantiation as merely medieval is to disparage the dogmatic movement. And finally, there is an enormous difference between a theological movement and a dogmatic movement, for while they may coincide conceptually, still it is one thing to offer a judgment on the private authority of a theologian and quite another to state the faith itself infallibly, under the guidance of the Spirit of God. (Fs) (notabene)

87a We still have to determine the great difference that exists between the general transcultural problem and that same problem as it is found in Catholicism. We have seen how historians pass with consummate skill and astuteness from one relative view to another relative view, without daring to ascend to what is prior in itself and absolute, because philosophers propose so many and such diverse teachings. Yet the church of God not only accomplishes such transcultural movements, but also in one and the same voice it can speak to all cultures and all times. For it does ascend to what is prior in itself and, moreover, passes an infallible judgment on its own ascent. (Fs) (notabene)

1.Kommentar (27/03/08): Interssant hier das Argument als prior in itself.

87b Finally, we must not overlook how intimately this analysis of history squares with what has already been said about the goal of theology, about the act whereby the goal is attained, and about the movement whereby we proceed to that act. For in this section we have added only one element to those considerations, namely, the ambiguity and equivocity of the category that announces what is prior, better known, more obvious with respect to us. Still, once this element is added, there immediately come to light in their main lines (i) a historical series of cultural differences, (2) the Catholic transcultural problem, (3) the importance of the dogmatic way that proceeds from what is prior for so and so to what is prior in itself, (4) the importance of the systematic way that explores in an ordered fashion what is prior in itself, and (5) how great a difference there is between transcultural movements, theological movements, and dogmatic movements. And once all this is grasped, the dogmatic way and the systematic way will be seen not only to enter into their proper concrete historical context, but also are perceived to exercise a special task within the historical process itself. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Theologie, Geschichte allgemein: Bewegung bestimmt vom Ziel her; Häresie - Dogma; Gott, Regierung: das Gute - das Böse

Kurzinhalt: But infallible definitions are certainly good, and heresies are certainly evil; and yet definitions and heresies are not just opposed to each other but also connected with each other.

Textausschnitt: 8 A Further Consideration of the Historical Movement
87c We have distinguished different movements on the basis of their different starting points and goals. Now we have to consider movement itself as it proceeds from the starting point to the goal. Since the issue concerns intellectual movement, we have first to grasp that, no matter how intelligent the people involved in such a movement may be, they cannot understand their own movement clearly and distinctly. Every movement is understood from its goal, and so those who do not understand the goal to which they are moved cannot understand the movement to this goal. Now those who are involved in an intellectual movement are being moved to knowledge as goal, and as long as they are in movement, they do not yet have the knowledge. Therefore they cannot clearly and distinctly grasp what goal they are moving toward; and if they do not so understand the goal, they do not so understand the movement toward the goal. (Fs) (notabene)

1.Kommentar (28/03/08): Das Ziel bestimmt die Bewegung ... das ist ein ganz anderer Lonergan als jener von manchen Lonergan-Experten, die kaum über eine Intentionalitäts-Analyse hinauszukommen vermögen.

89a Thus, there is nothing surprising about the fact that popes and Fathers of the church and the greatest theologians have had practically nothing to say about the development of theology and of dogma, even though they were the ones who effected the development. Some human achievements are understood before they happen, while others have first to happen before they can be understood. Every intellectual movement is of the latter kind. (Fs) (notabene)

89b Still, what happens beyond the range of every human intention is hardly beyond God's intention. The God who founded a universal church through a revelation accommodated to a particular culture has not only grasped the transcultural problem but also has prepared, inspired, and guided its solution. It will not be particularly difficult for one who attends to this divine intention to understand theological and dogmatic development from that development itself. For whatever has happened has happened under God's governance. If something good has happened, it has happened in virtue of God positively willing it; but if something evil has happened, it has happened with God simply allowing it to happen. But infallible definitions are certainly good, and heresies are certainly evil; and yet definitions and heresies are not just opposed to each other but also connected with each other. For in the realm of human intention heresy is the occasion of definitions, and definitions are the remedy for heresy, and in the realm of God's intention evil is allowed so that from the very evil there may be drawn a greater good. Thus, if individual infallible definitions are good, the whole series of definitions, that is, the very development of dogma itself, is a still greater good. If individual heresies are evil, the whole series of heresies is a still greater evil. But if evil is allowed only for the sake of a greater good, then a greater evil is allowed only for the sake of a very great good. The very great good in this case, then, is the development of dogma that proceeded under God's guiding action even before human beings gave it any thought. (Fs) (notabene)

89c That is all very general. To move to particulars, we select four examples. The first is homoousion, in which in a solemn definition the 'scriptural prior' is left behind. The second is Chalcedon's two-natures doctrine, in which in a more tacit manner the 'patristic prior' is left behind. The third is the medieval conflict between Augustinianism and Aristotelianism, from which de facto there developed the systematic shift to what is prior in itself. The fourth, finally, is the subsequent methodological uncertainty, which urges us to examine more accurately the relations between the 'scriptural prior' and the 'systematic prior.' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Theologie, Geschichte: drei Beispiele: Nizäa (Nicea) Athanasius (Beispiel göttlicher Vorsehung), homoousion; Chalcedon

Kurzinhalt: Yet how greatly the intention of divine providence exceeds human intentions is evident from the fact that even Athanasius would not have affirmed such a general principle

Textausschnitt: 91a First, then, in the Arian controversy that raged through most of the fourth century, there was one question that was primary and was posed openly, namely, 'Is the Son of God a creature?' And there was another question that was secondary and somehow remained hidden, namely, 'Can an explicit and obligatory profession of faith employ words other than those that we read in the sacred scriptures?' Now in fact, as regards this secondary question, Council of Nicea did use the word homoousion. And in fact, after the Council was accepted, there was never any doubt about using nonscriptural language in the symbols of faith. That means that in fact there was firmly established the legitimacy of a shift from the scriptural 'prior to us' to something that is prior in itself. Yet how greatly the intention of divine providence exceeds human intentions is evident from the fact that even Athanasius would not have affirmed such a general principle. When he defended the decrees of Nicea, he was not defending any dogmatic or theological method, but an exception. He thought it was quite satisfactory that every confession of faith be made in scriptural language, but he contended that homoousion was necessary to root out more effectively the Arian heresy. (Fs)

91b Thus, even after Nicea it remained possible to believe that the only licit transition is one that proceeds from a scriptural 'prior for us' to a patristic 'prior for us.' That is what Severus of Antioch thought. Since he found that the Fathers used the word 'nature' to mean a complete, concrete being, so that every nature is also a supposit, he acknowledged only one nature in Christ God and man, and so he rejected the Council of Chalcedon as Nestorian. It would seem, then, that what happened in the case of these Monophysites is not that they defected from the faith because of a christological error,1 but that they refused to comply with the church and the ecumenical council because of a methodological error. Yet the case of the Monophysites was so unclear that it could not keep others from believing that a 'scriptural prior' should never be abandoned except for a transition to a 'patristic prior.'

91c And so we have the third example: the medieval conflict between the Augustinians and the Aristotelians. John Peckham, O.F.M., Archbishop of Canterbury, described the dispute in a letter to Rome:
... and that the Holy Roman Church might please notice how the teaching of the two orders [Franciscans and Dominicans] is almost completely opposed today on every debatable question. The teaching of one of these orders rejects and often contemns the positions of saintly authors. It rests almost entirely on philosophical dogmas. Thus, the house of God becomes filled with idols and with the futility of disputed questions foretold by the apostle. Great danger lies ahead on that route for the church of future generations. Smash the pillars
and the house will fall. Nothing is more inevitable. Despise the teachings of Augustine and other authentic doctors, and in will come the prince of evil as truth collapses before falsehood.2

93a The author seems to have failed to distinguish adequately the two different operations of the mind. Asking 'What is it?' is different from asking 'Is it so?' If, in answering this second question, you do indeed cast aside the teachings of the saints and for all practical purposes depend entirely on philosophical presuppositions, no doubt you do stray from the faith. But if faith is not the issue, if the argument is entirely about questions that really are debatable, how is it possible that the house of God is being filled with idols, or that authentic teachers like Augustine are being contemned, or that the teaching of one of the orders rests almost exclusively on philosophical dogmas? The only ground for such comments seems to be that the commentator was not a sagacious witness, although he was probably no less sagacious than others of the same period. The issue in these debatable questions was not truth but understanding, and not philosophical but theological understanding. The achievement of the thirteenth century, even among the Augustinians, was the transition from what was prior for the scriptural and patristic people of faith to the theological and systematic 'prior in itself.' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: 3 Irrtümer, Synthese; Futurismus, Archaismus (Fundamentalismus); Vatikan I

Kurzinhalt: There are three ways of making the transition to the systematic without achieving a synthesis. First, ... In parallel fashion, when synthesis is lacking there are three ways of going astray on the positive side

Textausschnitt: 95c There are three ways of making the transition to the systematic without achieving a synthesis. First, the philosophical handmaid can be so dominant that theologians are occupied at great length with questions that at root are philosophical. Second, theologians can attend to both speculative and positive issues but achieve, not a joining and a synthesis, but just a juxtaposition and an aggregate. Third, system itself can be so exaggerated that positive elements become superfluous, since they can be demonstrated. The first tendency can be seen quite clearly in the decadence of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, but it also troubled later theology. The second tendency occurs when apologetic exigencies combine with philosophical domination. The third tendency appeared in nineteenth-century semirationalism, whose short life was ended by the First Vatican Council. (Fs)

95d In parallel fashion, when synthesis is lacking there are three ways of going astray on the positive side. The first is an archaism that tempts people to reject at least the later syntheses and return to a more ancient, simple, pure stage of Christianity. The second is a futurism that tempts people to bypass earlier and later syntheses alike and to accept some new and as yet unheard-of overview of everything. The third is the tendency of those whose minds are so exhausted by a plethora of weighty theories that they settle for certitude and exclude all understanding. (Fs)

95e Now the sixteenth-century Reformers and the later Pietists extolled a scriptural archaism; the followers of Baius and Jansenius wanted a patristic and Augustinian archaism; nor are theologians of our own age immune from the same tendency, who so praise biblical or patristic theology that they almost seem to prefer to omit all later theology. Next, futurism is seen in liberals and modernists, who suggest that not only Catholics and Protestants but also the Fathers of the church and the New Testament authors themselves were mistaken regarding the true nature of the Christian religion. Finally, the third error consists, not in the division of labor within positive studies, which is quite proper, nor in insisting on a solid analytic foundation for the way of synthesis, which is also quite proper, but in so highly esteeming the necessity and solidity of the positive path as to end up with a positivistic exclusion of speculation. (Fs)

97a The understanding of mysteries taught by the First Vatican Council is opposed to all of these aberrations. Because there is an understanding of mysteries, there is a strictly theological understanding. Because there is a strictly theological understanding, there are also concepts that express this understanding and principles that will be uttered in these concepts. Because there are concepts and principles that originate from a strictly theological understanding, the proper object of theology, its proper method, and its proper field of activity are vindicated. (Fs)

97b Once these points are grasped, a stable foundation is provided for resisting the domination of philosophy. On the same basis, the notion that theology is a mere aggregate, as if theology had no principles of its own and consisted only in conclusions drawn from revelation alone or from revelation and philosophy, is ruled out. And the positivistic tendency to neglect all understanding is also ruled out. (Fs)

97c Again, since this theological understanding increases age after age, there are ruled out both the archaism that regards later understanding as illegitimate and the anachronism that imagines that later understanding existed much earlier than in fact it did. (Fs)

97d Moreover, because declarations and definitions of the church are protected from error through the assistance of the Holy Spirit, the theological understanding that truly enters into these declarations and definitions will not change.1 And so the figments that we have named 'futurism' are ruled out. (Fs)

97e Finally, since theological understanding is imperfect, rationalism and semirationalism are also ruled out. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Nizäa (Nicea), Chalcedon, Vatikan I; Unterschied: Entwicklung des Dogmas - Absicht der Entwicklung; Absicht, Fügung Gottes; Notwendigkeit des Strebens nach Einsicht

Kurzinhalt: What stands out in all of this is that it is one thing to effect a development of dogma and something else to intend the same development.

Textausschnitt: 97f We have examined four examples of historical movement: (1) the homoousion of Nicea, in which the 'scriptural prior' was left behind; (2) the 'two natures' doctrine of Chalcedon, in which the 'patristic prior' was left behind; (3) the medieval conflict between Augustinians and Aristotelians, in which a move was made to a systematic 'prior in itself; and (4) the subsequent methodological uncertainty, in which we discerned a golden mean between various opposed aberrations. (Fs)

99a What stands out in all of this is that it is one thing to effect a development of dogma and something else to intend the same development. It was not the intention of the Council of Nicea to affirm a general possibility of passing from the 'scriptural prior' to the 'systematic prior.' Nor was it intention of the Council of Chalcedon to affirm a general possibility of passing from the 'patristic prior' to the 'systematic prior.' The medieval theologians, whether Augustinian or Aristotelian, did not argue whether a shift should be made to the 'systematic prior.' Nor was it a common decision of the theologians of the fourteenth and fifteenth century, the Reformers and the Catholic apologists, the Baianists and the Jansenists, the semirationalists and the traditionalists, the liberals and the modernists, that by their different opposed tendencies they would place the Catholic mean in a clearer light. Even the First Vatican Council wished not so much to ground further methodological conclusions as to condemn specific errors and to affirm Christ's saving doctrine. (Fs) (notabene)

99b Still, a development of dogma was brought about, especially in the ecumenical councils from Nicea to Vatican I. But it is one thing to intend the individual definitions, one at a time, as each of the councils undoubtedly did, and it is quite another thing to intend the entire series of definitions and declarations in which the development of dogma can be seen. To intend that entire series surpasses human powers; nevertheless, it was brought about by God's intention, will, governance, and infallible assistance. And the reason why it was brought about is not obscure: it was necessary if the Catholic and universal church of God is to be able to express God's revelation in a Catholic and universal way. (Fs) (notabene)

99c An increase in understanding, knowledge, and wisdom accompanies the development of dogma. One who understands imperfectly homoousion or transubstantiation does understand something - something more than those who may never have reflected seriously on either consubstantiality or transubstantiation. But where more is understood, obviously understanding increases. Then if conclusions are drawn from this increased understanding, knowledge increases as well. The more things there are that are understood and known, the more is progress made toward that wisdom that orders and judges all things. Indeed, since ultimate wisdom about divine matters belongs to God alone, it is not given even to the wisest theologian to pass judgment on divine matters in any absolute fashion; rather, it is necessary for theologians to submit their judgments to the one to whom God has promised infallibility on this earth. (Fs)

101a Finally, God through ministerial instruments brings about the development of dogma and the increase of understanding, knowledge, and wisdom in such a way that the goal God intends cannot fail to be attained. If there are many lovers of intelligible truth, then clearly the understanding, knowledge, and wisdom of one and all, of individuals as well as of the whole church, grows and makes great and vigorous progress. But if the love of intelligible truth grows cold, people are led astray by the false appearance of intelligibility; problems are multiplied; false solutions are urged; heresies arise; and the final result is that those who are not moved by love of the good are at least compelled by the mounting evils. Thus, whether we want intelligible truth or not, the increase that God intends and is effectively producing in inscrutable ways can never be thwarted. (Fs)

101b Thus, we return to our starting point, Aquinas. There are people today who are little moved to doctrinal disputations and speculative theology by the argument that without such disputations the student will 'acquire no knowledge or understanding, but will go away empty.' But if the abstract name of science does not convince them, perhaps the concrete reality of science can attract them. The point at issue is the understanding of mysteries that we have seen as not only gradually developing in the history of the church but also as having been used by God's intention so that revelation, adapted to a particular mentality, might receive a universal and Catholic expression. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Objekt der Theologie; in sich - in Relation zu anderen Wissenschaften

Kurzinhalt: ... since acts are known through objects and movements are known through their terms, we shall have to discuss briefly (1) the twofold aspect of theology, (2) the object as the goal of theology, (3) ...

Textausschnitt: 9 The Object of Theology

101c Now that we have considered the goal, the act by which the goal is attained, and the movement toward that act, it is time to draw all these considerations together, so that they can be grasped from the unity of a single viewpoint. Therefore, since acts are known through objects and movements are known through their terms, we shall have to discuss briefly (1) the twofold aspect of theology, (2) the object as the goal of theology, (3) the object as an immanently produced term, (4) the object as moving, (5) the process from the object as moving to the object as a term, and (6) the process from the object as a term to the object as the goal. (Fs)

101d First, then, theology can be considered either in itself or in relation to other sciences. The consideration of theology in itself regards objects and processes. But the consideration of theology in relation to other sciences calls for a distinction between what is common and what is specific. It is common to all the sciences that, while they must be distinguished from one another, they must not be separated from one another; there is only one universe to be understood, and each human being has only one intellect - an intellect that submits to every mere multiplicity only reluctantly. Moreover, it is common to many sciences that one uses another to move to its own proper perfection; this is increasingly the case as the sciences treat the concrete reality of a more perfect object. Thus, more sciences collaborate in knowing plants than in knowing minerals, more in knowing animals than in knowing plants, more in knowing human beings than in knowing other animals. Finally, there is a need that wisdom (whose role it is to judge and order everything) exercise her specific office and function, in order to determine the proper ends and adapt the proper methods of the individual sciences so that all of them may proceed more effectively to a unified and coherent understanding of the one universe. (Fs)

103a From this it is clear both that theology must make use of the other sciences, and especially the human sciences, and also that the other sciences, and again especially the human sciences, should learn from theology. For in this life every human being is infected with original sin and helped by God's supernatural grace and the magisterium of the church. In that mutual assistance (DB 1799, DS 3019, ND 135), theology performs the function of wisdom, both because theology is guided by the superior light of faith and because only theology can resolve into causes the situation of humankind1 as in fact it exists in this state of fallen and redeemed nature. And so, although theology in the exercise of its sapiential function uses and should use other sciences such as logic, methodology, and philosophy, nevertheless it is up to theology to determine the proper ends of each of these other sciences (DB 1799, DS 3019, ND 135).2 (Fs)

103b As for theology considered in itself as one particular science, it treats objects that become known by the supernatural light of faith, namely, the triune God, the incarnate Word, and other objects that pertain to the economy of salvation. Yet faith and theology differ from one another - not because they intend different objects but because they consider the same objects in different ways. What the believer believes, the theologian to some extent understands; what the believer affirms as true, the theologian intends as an intelligible truth. Just as science is not just any certain knowledge but certain knowledge of things through causes, so theology adds something to simple faith in that it proceeds from a truth that is believed to a truth that is both believed and to some extent understood. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Inneres Wort: zweifach; erste Ebene des Intellekts: Unterschied zw. Theologie u. Glaube; zweite Ebene des Intellekts: Unterschied zw. Theologie und Wissenschaft

Kurzinhalt: Thus, as regards the first operation of intellect, theology differs from faith and is more like science, but as regards the second operation of intellect, theology differs from science and relies on faith.

Textausschnitt: 105c For, just as there are two operations of intellect, two kinds of questions, and two acts of understanding, so there are two inner words, two terms immanently produced by an act of understanding.1 Now all properly human knowledge is knowledge to the extent that it is formally true; and so the second operation of intellect, in which the true is uttered, belongs to the very constitution of properly human knowledge. But as regards this operation we have to distinguish between faith and other kinds of certain knowledge. The other kinds of knowledge proceed from evidence of an object grasped by the subject, while faith proceeds from evidence of an object grasped not by the subject but by someone else whom the subject believes. And so, since theology rests on faith, it is distinct from other certain knowledge, whether prescientific or scientific. (Fs)

107a Moreover, just as in every finite being existence and essence are distinct, so too in every finite truth the formality of truth is distinct from that to which the formality of truth is added. That to which the formality of truth is added is the term of the first operation of intellect. And since in this operation there is a distinction between prescientific apprehension (in which causes are not yet known) and scientific apprehension (in which things are conceived through causes), one can distinguish on this basis both between science and other kinds of knowledge and, on the supernatural level, between theology and faith. (Fs) (notabene)

107b Thus, as regards the first operation of intellect, theology differs from faith and is more like science, but as regards the second operation of intellect, theology differs from science and relies on faith. The reason for these surprising conjunctions is that, because theology has a supernatural object, theological understanding is imperfect insofar as it never attains to evidence regarding its object. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Objekt der Theologie; das Ziel als bewegendes; nahes, fernes Ziel; Prinzipien - Wissen Gottes

Kurzinhalt: Theology does not begin from sensible data but from truths revealed by God and believed by us; and theology attains, not the kind of understanding that would suffice for discovering with certitude what is true, but ...

Textausschnitt: 107c Fourth, besides the object of intellect in the sense of its goal (being) and its object in the sense of immanent term (intelligible truth), there is also the object in the sense of whatever moves us to understand. The object that moves us to understand, the one proper to us and proportionate to us in our present state, is the intelligibility or nature that exists in corporeal matter. It follows that in this life we cannot understand or conceive God or angels except through analogies; but we do await another life in which the divine quiddity or essence will move our intellect without mediation. (Fs)

107d Thus, the object that moves us to theological understanding is, remotely, the divine essence or quiddity and, proximately, the truth that God has revealed to us about God, that God proposes to us through the church, and that we accept in faith. (Fs)

107e For this reason theology differs from the natural sciences, which begin from sensible data and proceed through understanding to the discovery of what is true. Theology does not begin from sensible data but from truths revealed by God and believed by us;1 and theology attains, not the kind of understanding that would suffice for discovering with certitude what is true, but that obscure, analogical, and imperfect understanding that throws some light on the truth already known from elsewhere, and enables us to possess it more fully. (Fs)

109a Moreover, since the object that moves us to theological understanding is revealed truth, the principles of theological science are called articles of faith. Furthermore, since it is the property of a subordinate science to receive its principles from another science, theology is likened to a subordinate science in that it begins from those principles that it receives from divine knowledge through revelation and faith. Finally, since no science as science is measured by the prescientific knowledge from which it begins, it is incorrect to measure theological science as science by the knowledge of faith from which it begins. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Ziel des Buchs; Ausgangspunkt: intellektuelle Emanation; Scholastik

Kurzinhalt: We do not begin with the relations, for understanding the relations presupposes understanding the processions. And we do not begin with the generation of the Son and the breathing forth of the Holy Spirit, for ..

Textausschnitt: 10 The Purpose of This Work

117a Our goal in this work is that imperfect, analogical, obscure, gradually developing, synthetic, and fruitful theological understanding. As understanding, it is neither true nor false, whether in itself or in its inner word or in its outer word. Of itself it does not lead to a truth that is per se known by us, or to a truth that is demonstrable from its own intrinsic principles, or to a hypothesis whose intrinsic possibility can be either clearly or distinctly grasped. Nevertheless it does relate to the formality of truth, in that it begins from something true that has been explicitly or implicitly revealed, in that it makes use of other truth, whether philosophic or historical, in that all its consequences are coherent with revealed truth, and in that it is an understanding of revealed truth itself. (Fs)

117b It proceeds to this goal, not by the dogmatic way but by the systematic. Therefore, it presupposes not only the revealed truths but also all that is deduced from the revealed truths. Our present intent is not to increase certitude about revealed truths, or to confirm deductions from revealed truths, or to refute more effectively the opponents of Catholic truth. For just as man does not live on bread alone, so knowledge does not live on certitude alone. Thus, presupposing firm certitude with regard to the faith, presupposing conclusions that have been deduced with certainty, presupposing that opponents have already been refuted, we are seeking an understanding of what is certain. (Fs)

119a We begin, then, not from what is most obvious in order to demonstrate something more obscure, but from what is most obscure in order to understand what is already certain and obvious. We do not begin from what is obscure because it is obscure, as if motivated by some strange perversity. Rather we follow the straigh-forward procedure of beginning with what is first in itself even though it is obscure. Anyone seeking understanding in an orderly way begins from what can be understood without presupposing the understanding of anything else. This is why we do not begin with the divine persons, for understanding the divine persons presupposes understanding the relations. We do not begin with the relations, for understanding the relations presupposes understanding the processions. And we do not begin with the generation of the Son and the breathing forth of the Holy Spirit, for these processions, which are specifically distinct from each other, presuppose something prior, something generic in respect to both of them. Our starting point, then, is intellectual emanation, as that which is absolutely basic in the systematic approach. The persons are considered only in chapter 4, the relations only in chapter 3, and the generation of the Son and the spiration of the Spirit only toward the end of chapter 2. But our starting point is intellectual emanation as it can be conceived of in God, before the two processions are distinguished, before the four relations are considered, before the three persons are conceived systematically. (Fs)

119b When we have understood intellectual emanation in God as well as we can, we will go on to distinguish two emanations. Once we have distinguished the two emanations, we will determine whether one is generation and the other not; once the processions have been determined, we will proceed to the relations; and after the relations have been investigated, we end with a treatment of the persons. (Fs)

119c We are seeking nothing else in this process than an ordered and pedagogically guided growth in understanding. We are seeking that special precious quality that Aristotle discerned in the 'epistemonic' or explanatory syllogism, the syllogism that 'makes us know.' While all syllogisms lead equally to conclusions that are certain, the explanatory syllogism brings forth a conclusion that is not only certain but also understood. And so, since theology is analogously a science, it uses syllogisms that are scientific in an analogous way, in order to add some imperfect understanding to a certitude that has been acquired elsewhere.1 (Fs)

121a While the process that is proper and essential to the systematic way can hardly be expressed in human words except through deductions that are also certain, still it aims, not at this certitude, but at the increase of understanding that starts by understanding one item and then gradually extends to understanding others. Thus, given some understanding of intellectual emanation in God, we move to an understanding of the emanation of the Word and the emanation of Love. Having understood what we can of these, we go on to an understanding of generation in God. And so with all other points, one step at a time, we develop our ideas until we come to as much understanding as is available on these matters. Nothing more can be intended directly in this volume, nor should it be. The argument of the volume is already complex enough, the method of dealing with issues of positive research is quite different from what we are doing here, and there is no lack of outstanding works that set forth the positive foundation in a quite complete manner. (Fs)

[...]

121c Today it appears that positive studies are being pursued not only most diligently but also with their own proper and exact methods. Since this is a fact, unless the speculative part of theology is pursued with equal diligence and with a method that is equally proper and specialized, there will arise from this inequality only difficulties, complaints, misunderstandings, crises, even aberrations. The encyclical Humani generis singled out as a regrettable source of errors the opinion that Scholasticism is out of date. If we want to demolish that opinion, I think it will help to have a brief work that illustrates the nature of theological understanding by aiming uniquely at the speculative goal, leaving out everything that might distract from that goal.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Einleitung; die göttlichen Hervorgänge (processio)

Kurzinhalt: ... first we present the problem, and then we list the principal groups of opinions, according to their roots; third, we explain what intellectual emanation is; fourth, we establish three assertions; and fifth, we solve four related questions ...

Textausschnitt: 125a Since the systematic way begins from what can be understood without presupposing the understanding of anything else, we must begin with the processions. For the processions are the basis for the relations, and in accordance with our manner of conceiving, the divine persons are conceived subsequently to conceiving the relations. (Fs)

125b Regarding the processions, first we present the problem, and then we list the principal groups of opinions, according to their roots; third, we explain what intellectual emanation is; fourth, we establish three assertions; and fifth, we solve four related questions. (Fs)

125c The first of the three assertions has to do with the psychological analogy taken generically: the divine processions are to be conceived by their likeness to intellectual emanation. The second assertion has to do with the differentiation of the generic notion: two and only two divine processions can be conceived by means of their likeness to intellectual emanation, namely, the procession of the word from the speaker, and the procession of love from the speaker and the word. The third assertion has to do with an application of the specific notion: the divine emanation of the word is properly called generation but the emanation of love is not. (Fs)

125d The related questions regard the distinction between understanding and the word, the demonstrability of the divine Word, the procession of the divine Word from the understanding of creatures, and the relationship between love and what is called 'the beloved in the lover.' (Fs)

125d In all of this, as perhaps was already stated sufficiently in the first chapter, we are aiming exclusively at the proper goal of the way of synthesis. For this reason, we will not repeat here the positive foundations that are customarily adduced from church documents, from sacred scripture, and from the Fathers and the theologians. First of all, these elements are readily available in many excellent works; second, they are effectively set forth only in their own proper order, and that order is completely contrary to the order of the way of synthesis; third, our argument is already burdened with an overabundance of complexity; and fourth, we judge it most useful to exhibit separately the proper intrinsic nature of the way of synthesis; for, although the way of synthesis is only a part of theology, it is the part that is not too highly esteemed these days. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Die göttlichen Hervorgänge (processio); Problem

Kurzinhalt: The fundamental trinitarian problem lies in the following facts: (1) the Son is both a se, from himself, and not a se, not from himself; (2) the Holy Spirit ...

Textausschnitt: The Problem

127a The fundamental trinitarian problem lies in the following facts: (1) the Son is both a se, from himself, and not a se, not from himself; (2) the Holy Spirit is both a se, from himself, and not a se, not from himself; (3) the way in which the Son is not a se, not from himself, is different from the way in which the Holy Spirit is not a se, not from himself. (Fs) (notabene)


127b Thus, God is a se, from himself. But the Son is God. Therefore, the Son is a se, from himself. Similarly, the Holy Spirit is God. Therefore the Holy Spirit is a se, from himself. (Fs)
127c Nevertheless, the Son is also not a se, not from himself. For he is the Son, the only-begotten, born of the Father, from the Father's substance, God from God, light from light, true God from true God (DB 54, DS 125, ND 7). (Fs)

127d Similarly, the Holy Spirit is also not a se, not from himself. For the Holy Spirit 'proceeds from the Father' (DB 86, DS 150, ND 305) and 'is eternally from the Father and the Son together, having his essence and his subsistent act of existence from the Father and the Son together, and proceeds eternally from both as from one principle and by a single spiration' (DB 691, DS 1300, ND 322). (Fs)

127e Finally, the way in which the Son is not a se, not from himself, is different from the way in which the Holy Spirit is not a se, not from himself. For the Son is the only-begotten (DB 54, DS 125, ND 7), but the Holy Spirit is not begotten but proceeding (DB 39, DS 75, ND 16). Therefore, the Son originates through generation, but the Holy Spirit originates through spiration (DB 691, DS 1300, ND 322). (Fs) (notabene)

127f Now, the same reality under the same aspect cannot be simultaneously affirmed and denied. Therefore, we must say that, in one way, the Son is a se, from himself, and in another way, not a se, not from himself. Similarly, we must say that the Holy Spirit is a se, from himself, in one way, and not a se, not from himself, in another way. Finally, it is necessary that the way in which the Son is not a se, not from himself, is different from the way in which the Holy Spirit is not a se, not from himself." (Fs)

129a The first step toward solving this problem is very easy. It is very easy to say that, as God, the Son is a se, from himself, but, as begotten, the Son is not a se, not from himself. It is also very easy to say that, as God, the Holy Spirit is a se, from himself, but, as spirated, the Holy Spirit is not a se, not from himself. Lastly, it is very easy to say that being begotten is different from being spirated. (Fs)

129b Nevertheless, if the entire solution consists in externally uttered words, then a sound is indeed made in the air but, as nothing is present in the mind, the sound itself is completely without meaning. And if one were to say that the generation of the Son and the spiration of the Holy Spirit are words without meaning, one would surely be a heretic. Therefore, we must go further in order to say what this remarkable emanation is according to which God is from God, and indeed not one God from another God, but the same God from the same God. Moreover, we must say what the difference is between the emanation in which the Son is generated and the other emanation in which the Holy Spirit is spirated. Finally, we must state why the first emanation is generation but the other is not. These are the questions discussed in this chapter on the divine processions. (Fs) (notabene)

129c However, it is not sufficient if we just understand something in the mind when we utter the words 'generation' and 'spiration.' If the something understood in the mind is not also found in reality, it is only a conceptual being. And if one were to say that the generation of the Son and the spiration of the Holy Spirit are merely conceptual beings, one would surely be a heretic. Therefore, we must go still further in order to say how within the absolutely simple God the Son in one way is a se, from himself, and in another way is not. This presents a great difficulty. For since the Son is God, and God is absolutely simple, and within absolute simplicity there is really no this and that, no 'one' and 'another,' it seems to follow that the same Son under the same aspect is both a se, from himself, and not a se, not from himself. The same contradiction seems to follow with respect to the Holy Spirit. Therefore we raise the issue of the divine relations, asking whether the divine relations are real and how many of them are real, whether they are really distinct from one another, whether they are really distinct from the divine essence or only conceptually distinct. These are the questions discussed in the third chapter. (Fs)

129d There remains a further step. Let us grant that generation and spiration exist not only in words but also in the mind, and not only in the mind but also in the very reality of God. Still, nothing is to be posited within the divine nature other than what is really there. The faithful confess three divine persons really distinct from one another; but the preceding outline of steps to be taken has ended with just three subsistent relations that are really distinct from one another. Therefore, in the fourth chapter we must determine whether, both ontologically and psychologically, the divine subsistent relations are persons in the true sense of the word. Once this question is solved, the fundamental trinitarian problem is solved, so that without contradiction and with some understanding the three really distinct persons in one and the same divine nature may be conceived and truly affirmed. (Fs)

131a All that we have viewed as one and in a single glance must now be considered more particularly. First, then, we must discuss the divine processions in order to state (1) how in general the emanation of God from God is to be conceived, (2) how two such emanations and only two are to be conceived, and (3) why the first emanation is generation properly so called, while the other is not. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche Hervorgänge; Irrtümer allgemein: Mangel, Übermaß (defect, excess); psychologische Analogie: richtiges Verständnis vom Intellekt (Thomas - Scotus)

Kurzinhalt: The erroneous opinions err either through excess or through defect. The semi-rationalists err through excess; ...

Textausschnitt: Opinions

131b Some opinions about the ways in which the divine processions may be understood are erroneous, others are insufficient, still others are poorly propounded; then there is the opinion of St Thomas. (Fs)

131c The erroneous opinions err either through excess or through defect. The semi-rationalists err through excess; they affirm that the mysteries of faith are demonstrable, and they strive to demonstrate them. This opinion was explicitly condemned under an anathema by Vatican I (DB 1816, DS 3041, ND 137). On the other hand, those who say that we cannot in this life have even an imperfect understanding of the mysteries of faith err by defect. This opinion could once have been understood as piety repelling heretical errors or curbing audacious speculation; but since it openly contradicts Vatican I (DB 1796, DS 3016, ND 132), it should be completely abandoned. (Fs)

131d The insufficient opinions express some truth but in such a way as to show that their proponents have only a slight understanding of the problem. Thus, it is entirely true that the good is self-diffusive; more than that, however, is required. What kind of diffusion is this? How does the first self-diffusion differ from the second? Why is there not a third, a fourth, a six-hundredth instance of self-diffusion? Again, it is entirely true that the triune God is the perfect society of love. But this gives rise to further questions; and they are not solved. (Fs)

131e By poorly propounded opinions I mean opinions of those who employ the psychological analogy, but in a way that overlooks to some extent the proper force and efficacy of the analogy. According to this approach, which we admit is closer to the truth than the previous approaches, some likeness exists between the divine processions and the finite emanations that occur in human intelligence. But human intelligence can be conceived in two ways: first, in accordance with the reality of intelligence itself, and second, in accordance with some analogy drawn from human sensibility. In the first way, the human intellect is conceived in terms of the act of understanding itself; thus St Thomas affirms that 'the human soul understands itself by its understanding, which is its proper act, perfectly demonstrating its power and its nature.'1 In the second way, the human intellect is conceived first as proceeding from external words to universal concepts, then as proceeding from the corporeal act of seeing to some simple spiritual apprehension whereby concepts become known to us; this is the approach of Scotus and the Scotists, and of many others who believe they are following St Thomas. Now, if the human intellect is conceived in accordance with the intellect's proper reality and nature, one is able to press forward to an analogical conception of the divine processions; this is the view that argues in favor of the psychological analogy.2 But if the human intellect is conceived in accordance with some remote analogy founded in sensible data and sensations, one is overlooking the real basis for discovering the likeness between the triune God and the human intellect; and if this is overlooked one may labor strenuously and dispute extensively and yet conclude to nothing clear. (Fs) (notabene)

133a Therefore, not only should the psychological analogy be employed, it must also be understood in such a way that the likeness is not sought between the sensitive part of our nature and the triune God. And if we attend even for a few moments to our own internal and properly intellectual experiences, we make three discoveries. (Fs)

133b First, 'whenever we understand, by the mere fact that we do understand, something proceeds within us, which is the conception of the thing understood, issuing from our intellective power and proceeding from its knowledge.'1 (Fs)

135a Second, 'it is of the nature of love not to proceed except from a conception of the intellect.'2 (Fs)

135b Third, 'what proceeds internally by an intellectual process does not have to be different. Indeed, the more perfectly it proceeds, the more it is one with that from which it proceeds.'3 (Fs)

135c Once we understand these three statements, the entire fundamental trinitarian problem is solved, at least virtually. The rest of what has to be said demands not the acquisition of further understanding, but only further applications of the understanding already achieved. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche Hervorgänge; Reflexion über Erfahrung: intellektuelle Emanation; Wille, Vernunft: Hervorgang, Liebe

Kurzinhalt: Indeed, this emanation is nothing other than the fact that, whenever we grasp sufficient evidence, from that very grasp of sufficient evidence, by an intellectually conscious necessity we bring forth a true judgment.

Textausschnitt: 135d There are three ways of treating intellectual emanation. The first is philosophical; we investigate everything concerning our mind, whether from a psychological or from a metaphysical perspective. The second way is historical; we strive to understand exactly what individual philosophers and theologians thought concerning our mind. The third way is theological and speculative; we seek to acquire such knowledge of our mind as will enable us to have some understanding of the divine processions. Since we have already written something about both the philosophical question1 and the historical question,2 it seems sufficient here to proceed according to the third way. (Fs)

135e We are therefore attempting something very easy. For we are attempting neither to grasp some philosophical synthesis nor to review and pass judgment on a whole series of opinions, but to go through a simple, brief process of reflection. Everyone who has truly reached the age of reason can go through this process. (Fs)

135f Thus, we all know from experience the difference between a rash judgment and a true judgment. A rash judgment is produced without sufficient evidence. A true judgment, on the other hand, is a judgment so based on the evidence one has grasped that a certain intellectual necessity makes that judgment inescapable. Now, what is lacking in a rash judgment and found in a true judgment is said to be an intellectual or intelligible emanation.3 Indeed, this emanation is nothing other than the fact that, whenever we grasp sufficient evidence, from that very grasp of sufficient evidence, by an intellectually conscious necessity we bring forth a true judgment. (Fs) (notabene)

137a Again, we all know from experience the difference between a definition repeated from memory and a definition proposed because we have grasped something through understanding. When we repeat a definition by memory, we certainly make sounds, not because we have understood anything, but rather because we have acquired some sensitive habit. However, when we produce a definition, because we want to express what we have understood, we can illustrate what we intend not only with other words but also with many different examples. As in defining, so also in illustrating with examples, everything we say is directed and, in a way, necessitated by the very act of understanding. Now, what is lacking in someone repeating things by memory but present in someone who understands and displays that understanding in a variety of ways is again what we are calling an intellectual or intelligible emanation. Indeed, this emanation is nothing other than the fact that, whenever we understand, from the very fact that we understand, by an intellectually conscious necessity we bring forth definitions as well as explications and illustrations. (Fs)

137b Finally, we all know from experience the difference between an act of will that is disordered and contrary to reason and one that is well ordered, right, obligatory, holy. For a good that is grasped by the intellect, approved by reason, and imposed upon the will obligates us in such a way that either we choose what is against the dictates of right reason and so are irrational, or we yield to the dictates of intellect and so are rational. Thus, what is lacking in a morally evil act but present in a morally good act is that spiritual and moral procession that effectively obligates the will in such a way that we not only ought to love the good, but actually do love it. This procession too is an intellectual or intelligible emanation, for it consists in the fact that a potentially rational appetite becomes actually rational because of a good grasped by the intellect. Therefore, since by its very nature the will is a rational appetite, and since this appetite cannot be actually rational unless it actually follows upon reason, we must say that 'it is of the nature of love to proceed only from a conception of the intellect.' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Relativismus, Relativist (Punkte 1-5): Postion gegen Empirismus, Mangel der Stufe der Reflexion; Beispiel: Schreibmaschine; das virtuell Unbedingte

Kurzinhalt: Fifthly, not only will the relativist make it plain that there are further questions until everything is known, but also he will explain why this is so.

Textausschnitt: 366a From Kantian we turn to relativist thought. The initial question in the present section was whether correct judgments occur. Our account of self-affirmation directly contradicts the relativist contention that correct judgments do not occur. Though the arguments for our position have been given, it will not be amiss to indicate where the relativist would disagree and why. (Fs)

366b First, relativist thought is largely devoted to a refutation of empiricism. Correctly it insists that human knowing cannot be accounted for by the level of presentations alone. There is as well the level of intelligence, of grasping and formulating intelligible unities and systematic relations. Without this second level of activities, there is indeed a given but there is no possibility of saying what is given. (Fs)

366c Secondly, just as the relativist insists on the level of intelligence against the empiricist, so we insist on the level of reflection against the relativist. Human knowing is not merely theory about the given; there are also facts: and the relativist has not and cannot establish that there are no facts, for the absence of any other fact would itself be a fact. (Fs) (notabene)

366d Thirdly, just as the empiricist could have nothing to say if, in fact, he did not utilize operations on the level of intelligence, so also the relativist does not confine himself strictly to the levels of presentations and of intelligence. He is quite familiar with the notion of the unconditioned. He regards the unconditioned as the ideal towards which human knowing tends. But he supposes that this ideal is to be reached through understanding. If the universe in its every part and aspect were thoroughly understood, there could be no further questions; everything would be conceived exactly as it ought to be;h on every possible topic a man could say just what he meant and mean just what he said. On the other hand, short of this comprehensive coherence, there can be no sure footing. There is understanding, but it is partial: it is joined with incomprehension: it is open to revision when present incomprehension yields to future understanding; and so intimately are all things related that knowledge of anything can be definitive only when everything is known. (Fs) (notabene)

367a Fourthly, the relativist is able to follow up this general view by facing concrete issues. Is this a typewriter? Probably, yes. For practical purposes, yes. Absolutely? The relativist would prefer to be clear about the precise meaning of the name 'typewriter'; he would like to be told just what is meant by the demonstrative 'this'; he would be grateful for an explanation of the meaning of the copula 'is.' Your simple question is met by three further questions: and if you answer these three, your answers will give rise to many more. If you are quick and see that you are starting on an infinite series, you may confront the relativist with a rounded system. But the relativist is also a smart fellow. He will point out that ordinary people, quite certain that this is a typewriter, know nothing of the system on which you base their knowledge. Nor is this all. For human knowledge is limited; systems have their weak points; and the relativist will pounce upon the very issues on which a defender of the system would prefer to profess ignorance. (Fs) (notabene)

367b Fifthly, not only will the relativist make it plain that there are further questions until everything is known, but also he will explain why this is so. A relation is named internal to an object when, without the relation, the object would differ radically. Thus, we have spoken of inquiry and insight. But by inquiry we have not meant some pure wonder; we have meant a wonder about something. Similarly, by insight we have not meant a pure understanding but an understanding of something. Inquiry and insight, then, are related internally to materials about which one inquires and into which one gains insight. Now, if one supposes that the whole universe is a pattern of internal relations, clearly it follows that no part and no aspect of the universe can be known in isolation from any other part or aspect; for every item is related internally to every other; and to prescind from such relations is to prescind from things as they are and to substitute in their place other, imaginary objects that simply are not. If then, one asks the relativist to explain why questions run off to infinity, he has a ready answer. The universe to be known by answering questions is a tissue of internal relations. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Insight

Titel: Insight

Stichwort: Relativismus, Relativist (Punkte 6-11); das Unbedingte: vituell - umfassend; das Konkrete: nicht-systematische Abweichung von idealen Frequenzen

Kurzinhalt: the unconditioned that is required for judgment is not the comprehensive coherence that is the ideal of understanding ... explanatory system has validity in the measure that it conforms to descriptive facts.

Textausschnitt: 367c Sixthly, if the foregoing fairly represents the relativist position, it also reveals its oversights. Questions are of two kinds. There are questions for intelligence asking what this is, what that means, why this is so, how frequently it occurs or exists. There also are questions for reflection that ask whether answers to the former type of question are correct. Next, the unconditioned that is required for judgment is not the comprehensive coherence that is the ideal of understanding, that grounds answers to all questions of the first type. On the contrary, it is a virtually unconditioned that results from the combination of a conditioned with the fulfilment of its conditions. Further, a judgment is a limited commitment: so far from resting on knowledge of the universe, it is to the effect that, no matter what the rest of the universe may prove to be, at least this is so. I may not be able to settle borderline instances in which one might dispute whether the name 'typewriter' would be appropriate. But at least I can settle definitively that this is a typewriter. I may not be able to clarify the meaning of 'is,' but it is sufficient for present purposes to know the difference between 'is' and 'is not'; and that, I know. I am not very articulate when it comes to explaining the meaning of 'this,' but if you prefer to use 'that,' it will make no difference provided we both see what we are talking about. You warn me that I have made mistakes in the past. But your warning is meaningless if I am making a further mistake in recognizing a past mistake as a mistake. And in any case, the sole present issue is whether or not I am mistaken in affirming this to be a typewriter. You explain to me that my notion of a typewriter would be very different if I understood the chemistry of the materials, the mechanics of the construction, the psychology of the typist's skill, the effect on sentence structure resulting from the use of a machine in composing, the economic and sociological repercussions of the invention, its relation to commercial and political bureaucracy, and so forth. But may I not explain to you that all these further items, however interesting and significant, are to be known through further judgments, that such further judgments, so far from shifting me from my present conviction that this is a typewriter, will only confirm me in it, that to make those further judgments would be rather difficult if, at the start, I could not be certain whether or not this is a typewriter? (Fs) (notabene)

368a Seventhly, however, the questions that are answered by a pattern of internal relations are only questions that ask for explanatory system. But besides things-themselves and prior to them in our knowing, there are things-for-us, things as described. Moreover, the existents and occurrences in which explanatory systems are verified diverge nonsystematically from the ideal frequencies that ideally would be deduced from the explanatory systems. Again, the activity of verifying involves the use of description as an intermediary between the system defined by internal relations and, on the other hand, the presentations of sense that are the fulfilling conditions. Finally, it would be a mistake to suppose that explanation is the one true knowledge; not only does its verification rest on description but also the relations of things to us are just as much objects of knowledge as are the relations of things among themselves. (Fs)

369a Eighthly, the relativist invents for himself a universe that consists merely of explanatory system because he conceives the unconditioned as the ideal of understanding, as the comprehensive coherence towards which understanding tends by asking what and why. But as we have seen, the criterion of judgment is the virtually unconditioned. Each judgment is a limited commitment. So far from pronouncing on the universe, it is content to affirm some single conditioned that has a finite number of conditions which in fact are fulfilled. No doubt, were the universe simply a vast explanatory system, knowledge of the conditions of any conditioned would be identical with knowledge of the universe. But in fact the universe is not simply explanatory system; its existents and its occurrences diverge nonsystematically from pure intelligibility; it exhibits an empirical residue of the individual, the incidental, the continuous, the merely juxtaposed, and the merely successive; it is a universe of facts, and explanatory system has validity in the measure that it conforms to descriptive facts. (Fs) (notabene)

369b Ninthly, the relativist argument from unending further questions is more impressive than conclusive. Human knowing does not begin from previous knowing but from natural spontaneities and inevitabilities. Its basic terms are not defined for it in some knowing prior to knowing; they are fixed by the dynamic structure of cognitional process itself. The relativist asks what is meant by the copula 'is' and the demonstrative 'this.' But neither he nor anyone else is given to confusing 'is' with 'is not or 'this' with 'not this'; and that basic clarity is all that is relevant to the meaning of the affirmation 'This is a typewriter.' A cognitional theorist would be called upon to explain such elementary terms; he would do so by saving that 'is' represents the yes that occurs in judgment and that is anticipated by such questions as 'Is it?' 'What is it?' Similarly, a theorist would explain 'this' as the return from the field of conception to the empirical residue in the field of presentations. But questions relevant to cognitional theory are not relevant to every instance of knowing. They are not universally relevant because, in fact, there is no operational obscurity about the meanings that cognitional theory elucidates. Again, they are not universally relevant, because such elementary meanings are fixed, in a manner that surpasses determination by definition, with the native immutability of the dynamic structures of cognitional process. (Fs)

370a Tenthly, as human knowing begins from natural spontaneity, so its initial developments are inarticulate. As it asks what and why without being given the reason for its inquiry, so also it sets off on the self-correcting process of learning without the explicit formulations that rightly would be required in an explanatory system. Single insights are partial. Spontaneously they give rise to the further questions that elicit complementary insights. Were the universe purely an explanatory system, the minor clusters of insights reached by what is called common sense would not head for a limiting position of familiarity and mastery in which evidently it is silly to doubt whether or not this is a typewriter. But in fact, the universe to be known by answering questions is not pure explanatory system. In fact, insights do head for limiting positions of familiarity and mastery. In fact, as everyone knows very well, it is silly to doubt whether or not this is a typewriter. The relativist would beg me to advert to the enormous difference in my notion of the typewriter were I to understand fully the chemistry of its materials, the mechanics of its construction, the psychology of the typist's skill, the twist given literary style by composing on a typewriter, the effect of its invention on the development of commercial and political bureaucracy, and so forth. But granted such an enrichment of my knowledge to be possible and desirable, nonetheless it is further knowledge to be obtained by further judgments; and since the enrichment is explanatory, since explanatory knowledge rests on descriptive knowledge, not only must I begin by knowing that this is a typewriter, not only must I advance by learning how similar other machines must be if they are to be named typewriters, but also I can attain valid explanation only insofar as my descriptions are exact. (Fs)

370b Eleventhly, it is quite true that I can be mistaken. But that truth presupposes that I am not making a further mistake in acknowledging a past mistake as a mistake. More generally, judgments of fact are correct or incorrect, not of necessity, but merely in fact. If this is something, still it might be nothing at all. If it is a typewriter, still it might be something else. Similarly, if I am correct in affirming it to be a typewriter, it is not a pure necessity, but merely a fact, that I am correct. To ask for the evidence that excludes the possibility of my being mistaken in affirming this to be a typewriter is to ask too much. Such evidence is not available, for if I am correct, that is merely fact. But if that evidence is not available, still less is there the evidence that will exclude the possibility of error in all judgments of fact. Errors are just as much facts as are correct judgments. But the relativist is in conflict with both categories of fact. For him nothing is simply true, for that is possible only when comprehensive coherence is reached; for him, nothing is simply wrong, for every statement involves some understanding and so some part of what he names truth. In the last analysis, just as the empiricist tries to banish intelligence, so the relativist tries to banish fact and with it what everyone else names truth.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche Hervorgänge; Emanation; Licht der Vernunft: geschaffene Teilnahme am ungeschaffenen Licht - Prinzipien (Identität, Widerspruch) - weitere Bestimmung: Materie, Form (Verstehen), Akt; Thomas

Kurzinhalt: The fundamental and utterly general light is our created participation in uncreated light, the source in us that gives rise to all our wonder, ...

Textausschnitt: 139a If we have adverted to all of this in our own internal experience, we can go on to a conception of intellectual emanation. For we are conscious in two ways: in one way, through our sensibility, we undergo rather passively what we sense and imagine, our desires and fears, our delights and sorrows, our joys and sadness; in another way, through our intellectuality, we are more active when we consciously inquire in order to understand, understand in order to utter a word, weigh evidence in order to judge, deliberate in order to choose, and exercise our will in order to act. Accordingly, in this active intellectual consciousness we can distinguish a general fundamental light and further determinations of the same light. The fundamental and utterly general light is our created participation in uncreated light, the source in us that gives rise to all our wonder, all our inquiry, all our reflection. Again, we attribute to this light those most general principles that contain no determination drawn from experience; for example, the principles of identity, noncontradiction, and sufficient reason, or the precept that good must be done and evil must be avoided. Still, what is consciously and intellectually operative in us not only consists in this general light, but is further determined by our own conscious acts. Sensible data determine us after the manner of matter; acts of understanding determine us after the manner of form; grasping evidence, judging, and deliberating further determine us after the manner of second act as intellectually, rationally, and morally conscious and as consciously active and functioning. (Fs)

139b Bearing all this in mind, let us listen once more to St Thomas: 'Whenever we understand, by the mere fact that we do understand, something proceeds within us, which is the conception of the thing understood, issuing from our intellective power and proceeding from its knowledge.'1 Accordingly, when we understand and by the very fact that we understand, from our intellective power, which is the general light of intellectual consciousness, and from the knowledge contained in the act of understanding that adds a determination to the general light, there proceeds within our intellectual consciousness a conception or definition of the reality understood. Similarly, when we grasp that the evidence is sufficient, by the very fact that we grasp it, and from the exigency of intellectual light as determined through that grasp, there proceeds within our intellectual consciousness either a true affirmation or a true negative assertion. Similarly again, when we judge some good as obligatory, by the very fact that we so judge, through our intellectuality, our rationality, we spirate an act of will. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Definition: intellektuelle Emanation; Wortklärung: Akt, real, natürlich, bewusst; intellektuelles Bewusstsein

Kurzinhalt: Intellectual emanation, then, is the conscious origin of a real, natural, and conscious act from a real, natural, and conscious act, both within intellectual consciousness and ...

Textausschnitt: 141a
Intellectual emanation, then, is the conscious origin of a real, natural, and conscious act from a real, natural, and conscious act, both within intellectual consciousness and also by virtue of intellectual consciousness itself as determined by the prior act. (Fs)

141b Act: not defined through genus and species, but clarified by a familiar proportion, namely, act: form : potency :: seeing: eyesight: eye :: hearing something: the faculty of hearing : the ear :: understanding something : the intelligible species : the possible intellect :: willing : willingness : will :: existence : substantial form : prime matter. (Fs)

real: that to which, each in its own way, the act of existence belongs. (Fs)

141c natural: the real is divided into the natural (for example, a horse in itself) and the intentional (for example, a horse as intended). Hence, there are two aspects to psychological acts; for the same psychological act is intentional insofar as it refers to some other, and natural insofar as it is considered in itself. (Fs)

141d conscious: present to the subject. In every sensitive and intellectual act, whether apprehensive or appetitive, there are three things that occur simultaneously: (1) the object is intended; (2) the intending subject himself is rendered present to himself; (3) the act of the subject is rendered present to the subject. Distinguish sharply between the presence of the subject to himself and the presence of the object to the subject: the object is present as that which is intended, the act is present as that by which the object is intended, the subject is present as that which intends. In a similar way, distinguish this presence of the subject through consciousness and the presence of the same subject through reflection or introspection: reflection or introspection renders the subject present as an object, as that which is intended; but this could not be were not the subject already present to himself through consciousness, as subject, as that which intends. (Fs)

141e within consciousness: within a reality in accordance with a psychological, not a metaphysical, consideration. What metaphysically is an accident inhering in a substance or an act received in a potency is psychologically a conscious event within the field of consciousness. Note, however, that the distinction of a psychological consideration from a metaphysical consideration in no way implies that 'conscious' adds something beyond 'being'; for 'being' is not a genus, and what is thought of as above, outside, beyond 'being' is nothing. 'Conscious,' therefore, refers to being at a certain degree of perfection. (Fs)

141f intellectual consciousness: constituted by acts both of intellect and of will while prescinding from sensitive acts. Certainly, in one human being there is just one consciousness; still, that one consciousness is not simply homogeneous but diversified in accordance with the diverse nature of the acts. (Fs)

143a conscious origin: within consciousness act originates from act: a real, natural, conscious act from a real, natural, conscious act. Thus, if one sees a large fierce-looking dog without a leash, one spontaneously feels fear. Just as seeing is a real, natural, conscious act, so too is fearing. And these two acts are not unrelated: the dog is feared because it is seen. (Fs)

143b by virtue of consciousness itself: whenever a conscious act originates from a conscious act, consciousness itself mediates between the two, so that (1) the conscious subject as conscious is the principle-which of the procession; (2) the conscious act as conscious is the principle-by-which of the procession; (3) the procession itself has an intrinsic modality that is lacking in an unconscious procession such as a chemical procession; (4) the act that in some way proceeds consciously is because of and in accord with the act from which it proceeds. Therefore, the phenomenalism of consciousness that would deny causality, or the mode of causality proper to consciousness, is excluded. (Fs; ??? letzter Satz)

143c by virtue of intellectual consciousness: when act consciously originates from act, sensitive consciousness mediates in one way and intellectual consciousness in another. A sensitive act originates from another sensitive act according to a particular law of nature. But an intellectual act originates from another intellectual act in accord with the conscious, transcendental exigencies of intellect itself, which are not bound to any particular nature but are ordered to all that is intelligible, all that is true, all that is being, all that is good. (Fs)

143d as determined by the prior act: there are two ways in which an act originates within intellectual consciousness and by virtue of intellectual consciousness. In the first and more spontaneous way, an act originates as if from some potency; thus we proceed from speculative or practical or existential questions to acts of understanding. In another, more autonomous way, a subsequent act originates from a prior act and is proportionate to the prior act; thus, we define because we understand and in accordance with what we understand; again, we judge because we grasp evidence as sufficient and in accordance with the evidence we have grasped; finally, we choose because we judge and in accordance with what we judge to be useful or proper or fitting or obligatory.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: These 1: Verständnis der göttlichen Hervorgänge analog zur intellektuellen Emanation; Terminologie: processio operati usw.

Kurzinhalt: The divine processions, which are processions according to the mode of a processio operati, are understood in some measure on the basis of a likeness to intellectual emanation ...

Textausschnitt: 145a
ASSERTION 1
The divine processions, which are processions according to the mode of a processio operati, are understood in some measure on the basis of a likeness to intellectual emanation; and there does not seem to be another analogy for forming a systematic conception of a divine procession.
Terminology
procession: the origin of one from another.
process, emanation: the same as procession.
proceeding, originated: that which has an origin.
principle, originating: that from which something has an origin.
mode of procession: procession considered concretely; that which this or that procession adds beyond the abstract definition 'origin of one from another.'
determination of mode: the mode is determined in order to distinguish one procession from another.
external determination: the determination of the principle and of that which proceeds.

147a
internal determination: the determination of the origin itself as violent or natural, as unconscious or conscious, as spontaneous or autonomous, and so forth.1 (Fs)
metaphysical determination: the determination uses the common notions that are worked out in general metaphysics, notions such as the same and the other, potency and act, the absolute and the relative, and so forth. (Fs)
natural determination: the mode is determined as proper to some generic or specific or individual nature, for example, physical, chemical, biological, sensitive, intellectual, or divine nature. (Fs)
analogical determination: the mode of an unknown nature is determined on the basis of a likeness to a known nature. (Fs)
external procession, into another: the origin of one reality from another. Here the determination of mode is external and metaphysical. Making, creating, and animal generation are illustrations. (Fs)
internal procession, in the same: both the principle and that which proceeds are in the same [...]2 Again, the determination of mode is external and metaphysical. However, 'in the same' can be understood in three ways, namely, in the same subsistent, within the same consciousness, in the same faculty or potency.3 (Fs)

149a
procession of an operation: an internal procession in which the principle and that which proceeds are related as potency and act. Again, the determination of mode is external and metaphysical. The procession of an operation is illustrated by the act of seeing taking its origin from both the power of sight and the eye, the act of understanding taking its origin from both the possible intellect and the intelligible species, the act of will taking its origin from both the will and from a habit received in the will.1 (Fs)
processio operati: an internal procession in which the principle is related to that which proceeds as act to act. Again, the determination of mode is metaphysical and external. A processio operati is illustrated by the act of desiring taking its origin from the act of seeing, by the act of defining taking its origin from the act of understanding, by the act of judging taking its origin from the act of grasping sufficient evidence, by the act of choosing taking its origin from a practical judgment.2 (Fs) (notabene)
procession according to the mode of a processio operati: an internal procession in which the originating act and the originated act are really distinct, not however on the basis of absolute existence but on the basis of relative existence. Again, the determination of mode is external and metaphysical. This definition has been worked out in order to state clearly a divine mystery. (Fs)

151a
divine procession: the origin of God from God. Here, the determination of mode is external yet natural. A divine procession is illustrated by the generation of the Son from the Father and also by the procession of the Holy Spirit from both the Father and the Son. (Fs)
intellectual emanation: the conscious origin of a real, natural, and conscious act from a real, natural, and conscious act, both within the same intellectual consciousness and also by virtue of that intellectual consciousness itself as it is determined by the originating act. Here, the determination of mode is internal and natural. We have already indicated above the kind of mode this is. (Fs)
on the basis of the likeness: the analogical determination of the internal mode of a divine procession on the basis of the internal mode that we experience in an intellectual emanation. (Fs)
understanding: an interior and strictly spiritual act that occurs more rarely and with greater difficulty in the slow-witted and more often and with greater ease in the sharp-witted. (Fs)
in some measure: mediately, imperfectly, analogically. What is understood perfectly is comprehended immediately through its essence. (Fs)
conception: the interior expression of what is intended by inquiry (heuristic conception) or of what is grasped by an act of understanding (conception in the proper sense). (Fs)
systematic conception: a conception that expresses an understanding that is virtually sufficient for resolving all the questions of a treatise. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche intellektuelle Emanation: Hypothese, Ableitung, Deduktion

Kurzinhalt: Now we want to conceive clearly and distinctly what a divine intellectual emanation would be like ... first, that the infinite act is an originating act ...

Textausschnitt: 163a The meaning of intellectual emanation has already been discussed above. Now we want to conceive clearly and distinctly what a divine intellectual emanation would be like. And we are proposing this conception as a supposition or a hypothesis. (Fs)

163b Moreover, since intellectual emanation exists by virtue of intellectual consciousness itself as determined by some act, we have to suppose that there is consciousness in God, and indeed intellectual consciousness. We also have to suppose that this intellectual consciousness is determined by an act, and that this act can only be the infinite act. Finally, we have to suppose that this consciousness, thus determined, is dynamic, that is, that it has a conscious exigence for an emanation. (Fs)

163c From these suppositions it follows, first, that the infinite act is an originating act. In God there cannot be any real distinction between infinite act and divine consciousness; and since they are not really distinct, they cannot be conceived as really determining and as really determined. Therefore, the motive on account of which and in accord with which there is an exigence for the emanation is known by the infinite act. And through this knowledge and conscious exigence, the infinite act is constituted as an originating act. (Fs)

163d Second, it follows that an originated act really and truly comes forth within divine consciousness. One cannot suppose that an infinite act is inconsistent with itself, that it has a conscious exigence for an emanation and yet there is no emanation, or that it has an exigence for an emanation within consciousness and yet there is no emanation within consciousness. Thus, if an originating act is posited, then necessarily, by that very fact, a true and real emanation is also posited. And if there is a true and real emanation, then there is also that which emanates, that is to say, there is also an originated act. (Fs)

163e Third, it follows that the originated act is infinite. For the originated act is not nothing, and therefore it is either finite or infinite. Now, it cannot be finite, for everything finite is also created, and everything created originates through external procession; but an act within consciousness and originated by virtue of consciousness is originated internally. Moreover, everything finite is contingent; but what is originated because of the exigencies of divine consciousness is originated by necessity. It remains, then, that the originated act is infinite. (Fs)

163f Fourth, it follows that God originates from God. Whatever is infinite is God. But the originating act is infinite; the originated act is infinite; the originated act truly and really comes forth from the originating act. Thus, on the supposition of divine intellectual emanation, God originates from God. (Fs)

163g Fifth, it follows that the originating act and the originated act are not really distinct with respect to absolute existence. For the originating act and the originated act are infinite. But there is only one infinite act; therefore, with respect to absolute existence there cannot be a real distinction between the originating act and the originated act. (Fs)

165a Sixth, it follows that the originating act and the originated act are really distinct with respect to relative existence. Opposed relations of originating and originated necessarily follow upon the supposition of real emanation that we have made. And it makes no difference to this that the same act is originating and originated. For we are not discussing a causal emanation, which would cease to be if cause and effect were not two really distinct absolutes. We are discussing an intellectual emanation, according to which to love the good is right because loving proceeds from the good truly affirmed, and affirming the good is true because affirming proceeds from a grasp of evidence. And it cannot be demonstrated by reason that this truth and this rightness are to be excluded because the act of grasping evidence, of affirming, of loving is infinite, and there is only one infinite act. (Fs)

165b Thus, if divine intellectual emanation is supposed, all that pertains to divine procession and all that we have already proved from the truths of faith under the heading 'procession according to the mode of a processio operati' follows. (Fs)

165c Now, if there is a deduction, there is also some understanding; and this understanding is not annulled simply by the fact that a premise is only a supposition or a hypothesis. Thus, if divine intellectual emanation is supposed, there results some understanding of the faith. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Konklusion: Hervorgang - keine andere Analogie als jene der intellektuellen Emanation; Weisen der Hervorgangs: bewusst u. autonom; bewusst u. spontan; unbewusst u. spontan

Kurzinhalt: ... whether there is any other likeness or analogy from which the mode of divine procession can be understood ...

Textausschnitt: 10 Conclusion.

179b The question, then, was whether divine procession is after the manner of intellectual emanation. Initially we responded that we can indeed acquire some understanding of the mystery in this life through such a likeness. So a second question arose, namely, whether there is any other likeness or analogy from which the mode of divine procession can be understood by us differently but either equally well or better. (Fs)

179c We have responded to this question through a series of disjunctions. (Fs)

Knowledge of the divine is either immediate or mediate, imperfect, and analogical. But in this life our knowledge of the divine is not immediate. (Fs)

Analogical knowledge can be either implicit, unthematic, and rhetorical, or explicit, thematic, and systematic. But a theological analogy should be explicit, thematic, and systematic. (Fs)

179d A systematic analogy is based either on common notions and principles elaborated in general metaphysics, or in some determinate created nature such as the physical, the chemical, the biological, the sensitive, the intellectual. But common notions do not suffice for a systematic trinitarian analogy. (Fs)

179e An analogy according to the likeness of nature is selected either from material nature or from a strictly spiritual nature. But God is completely immaterial; so the likeness is to be found only in a strictly spiritual nature. (Fs)

179f The modes of proceeding in a strictly spiritual nature that are known to us in this life are either
(1) conscious and autonomous, such as the intellectual emanation of a word from understanding and the intellectual emanation of a choice from the word, or
(2) conscious but spontaneous, such as the procession of an act of understanding from questions, or
(3) unconscious and spontaneous, such as the origin of a conscious act from a potency, from a disposition, from a habit, which in themselves are unconscious. But God is pure act, and so unconscious origin from a potency, a disposition, or a habit is excluded. And God does not ask questions, raise doubts, or deliberate, so conscious but spontaneous procession is excluded. Therefore, there remains no likeness of nature to the mode of divine procession except the intellectual emanation through which a conscious act originates from a conscious act according to a conscious and autonomous mode. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Argument zu These 2; Schlussfolgerung: nur 2 Hervorgänge aus Gott

Kurzinhalt: First, we argue that in the deity two processions can be conceived on the basis of the likeness of intellectual emanation.

Textausschnitt: Argument

187b First, we argue that in the deity two processions can be conceived on the basis of the likeness of intellectual emanation. (Fs)

God is being by essence and the very act of understanding, truth by essence and the very act of affirming, good by essence and the very act of loving. For it is impossible that the highest being lack the perfection of intelligence, that the highest truth lack truth in the formal sense (which is the act of affirming), that the highest good lack the goodness of love itself.1 (Fs; Fußnote)

Fußnote:
[In Insight (p. 681), Lonergan speaks of God not as the highest being, the highest truth, and the highest good, but as the primary being, the primary truth, and the primary good. Bearing this in mind provides a useful control for understanding accurately his use of 'highest' here.]


187c Now, every act of affirming known to us is true to the extent that it emanates from one who understands; and every spiritual love known to us is right and holy to the extent that it proceeds from a true affirmation of a good. (Fs)

187d Therefore, if any intellectual emanations can be conceived in God, surely the emanation of the word from the speaker and the emanation of love from both of these can be conceived in God. (Fs)

187e If these two intellectual emanations are posited in God, they are not reducible to one emanation only. For 'to emanate from the word' and 'not to emanate from the word' stand to each other in contradictory opposition. But it is of the nature of love to emanate from the word. And it is of the nature of the word not to be from itself but to emanate from the one understanding and speaking. Now, certainly, one cannot posit contradiction in God; so the emanation of the word and the emanation of love cannot be posited in God in such a manner that there results one emanation only. Therefore, there are two divine processions that can be conceived through the likeness of intellectual emanation. (Fs)

189a Next, we argue that only two processions in God can be conceived through the likeness of intellectual emanation. (Fs)

For in God there can be conceived only one act of understanding, only one word, only one love. (Fs)

But there is only one emanation of one love; there is only one emanation of one word; and the divine act of understanding cannot intellectually emanate from some other principle. (Fs)

Therefore, in terms of the likeness to intellectual emanation, one can conceive only two processions in God. (Fs)

189b The major premise is certain both by reason of the act and by reason of the object: by reason of the act, since in God, who is absolutely simple, there is only one act; by reason of the object, because the infinite act of understanding attains the totality of being, the infinite act of affirming attains the totality of truth, the infinite act of love attains the totality of the good.2 (Fs)

189c The minor premise is evident inasmuch as it asserts that in a single eternal and immutable act there is one emanation of one word and one emanation of one love. In us, however, in some measure there is an intellectual emanation of the act of understanding, to the extent that when we are intellectually conscious we inquire, investigate, and reason, so that we may come to an act of understanding. But this is not the case with God, since God is not reduced from the potency to the act of understanding. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: These 3; Zeugung: nur zutreffend für das Wort; Definition: Zeugung (Aristoteles)

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 3; Generation in the strict sense of the term is implied by the divine emanation of the Word, but not by the divine emanation of Love.

Textausschnitt: ASSERTION 3

Generation in the strict sense of the term is implied by the divine emanation of the Word, but not by the divine emanation of Love.
Meaning of the Assertion

189e We have determined the manner in which divine procession can be conceived and the number and kinds of processions that are conceived in this manner. We now ask whether generation in the strict sense of the term applies formally either to the emanation of the Word or to the emanation of Love. And our response is to affirm the first and deny the second. In this way, a further congruence between the psychological analogy and what we know by faith comes to light. (Fs)

Theological Note

191a It is of divine and catholic faith that the Son is begotten and the Holy Spirit is not begotten (DB 39, DS 75, ND 16). It is of divine and catholic faith that the same one is both Son and Word, entirely so [DB 288, DS 548]. It is the opinion of St Thomas that 'In the name "Word" the same property is implied as in the name "Son."'1 This is also the opinion of those theologians who follow St Augustine,2 and their opinion, when occasion arose, received the approval of Pius VI (DB 1597, DS 2698). (Fs)

Division of the Argument

191b The argument hinges upon three points, namely, from the formality of generation in the strict sense of the term, from the manner of conceiving the divine nature, and from the difference between the emanation of the word and the emanation of love. With these points as premises, it is easy to conclude that the divine emanation of the Word includes the formality of generation in the strict sense of the term, but that the divine emanation of Love does not. (Fs)

The Formality of Generation

191c For Aristotle, 'generation' in the wide sense denotes the origin of a material substance; this is the way the term is used in various places throughout his work On Generation and Corruption. (Fs)

Taken strictly, generation is usually defined as the origin of something alive from a conjoined living principle, with a resulting likeness in nature.

191d Accordingly, the following are not instances of generation in the strict sense of the term:
(1) the origin of something that is not alive (for example, the origin of water from hydrogen and oxygen);
(2) the origin of something alive from a principle that is not living (for example, so-called spontaneous generation);
(3) the origin of something alive from a living principle, but not from a conjoined living principle (for example, the creation of living beings);
(4) the origin of something alive from a conjoined but dissimilar living principle (for example, the origin of hair from the scalp);
(5) the origin of something alive from a conjoined and similar living principle, but a living principle whose similarity to the originated is not in a likeness in nature (for example, the origin of Eve from Adam through a rib, for it does not pertain to the nature of a rib taken from a man that a woman comes to be from it). (Fs)

191a Thus, we can conclude that there is generation in the strict sense of the term if and only if each and every element included in the definition is applicable. And in the present discussion we must pay special attention to the fifth element of the definition, namely, 'with a resulting likeness in nature'; for although it is necessary that what emanates be similar in nature to that from which it emanates, this is not sufficient. To have the formality of generation in the strict sense, this likeness in nature must result by virtue of the emanation itself. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Unterschied: Emanation des Wortes - der Liebe; Intellekt - Wille

Kurzinhalt: The Emanation of the Word Differs from the Emanation of Love

Textausschnitt: The Emanation of the Word Differs from the Emanation of Love

199a Since generation results in likeness of nature, after having considered the nature of God, it remains for us to compare the emanation of a word and the emanation of love. (Fs)

199b In this comparison we must distinguish
(1) a thing itself,
(2) the understanding of it,
(3) the word concerning it, and
(4) the love for it.
For intellectual consciousness is related to something in such a way that, first, it understands it, next, from that understanding it utters a true word concerning it, third, from that understanding and word it spirates a love for it, and fourth, by virtue of that very love it is borne toward what is loved. (Fs)

199c Now, there is a true word concerning something to the extent that a perfect likeness of it is formed within the intellect. So this emanation, by which the word comes forth, results in the formation of a likeness of the thing. (Fs)

199d On the other hand, there is love for something to the extent that the one loving is inclined, borne, impelled toward what is loved, and is united with and adheres to it. So this emanation, by which loves comes forth, involves the constitution of an inclination, an impulse, an adhesion. (Fs)

199e Indeed, to some extent these two emanations are opposed to each other. Since the object of intellect is truth, and since truth is found within the intellect, the intellect is so engrossed in the formation within itself of a true likeness of something that those who devote themselves to the sciences seem rather cold and aloof, since they are not much inclined, attracted, or given to things themselves for their own sake. But since the object of will is the good, and since the good exists not within the will but externally and in things themselves, the one loving is so absorbed with what is loved that those who cultivate the affections more than the sciences are said to be blind. (Fs)

201a But if the intellect avoids blindness, and the will aloofness, then a perfect circle of consciousness is complete.1 For one begins from some thing itself in order to grasp it intellectually; once it is so grasped, it is represented by a true word; and once it is so represented, it is loved with a love that returns one to the thing as it is in itself. (Fs) (notabene) (notabene)

201b This makes clear the difference between the emanation of the word and the emanation of love. For truth and falsity are in the mind; but good and evil are in things. Therefore, because the intellect tends toward an interior truth, the intrinsic formality of the emanation of a word tends to the formation within of a true likeness of a thing. But because the will tends toward an exterior good, the intrinsic formality of the emanation of love is the actuation of an inclination toward the object loved.2 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Argument: Emanation des Wortes - der Liebe; der Geist erfüllt nicht die Bedingung der Zeugung (Ähnlichkeit); Beispiel: Rippe, Eva

Kurzinhalt: For the emanation of love does not lead to the formation of a likeness of a thing but to constituting an impulse toward or adhesion to the thing itself for its own sake.

Textausschnitt: Argument

201c If in an emanation everything pertaining to the formality of generation is verified, then that emanation is generation in the proper sense. (Fs)

But everything pertaining to the formality of generation is verified in the divine emanation of the Word, but not in the divine emanation of Love. (Fs)

Therefore, the divine emanation of the Word is generation in the proper sense, but the divine emanation of Love is not. (Fs)
The major premise is evident, and the minor is proved part by part. (Fs)
The divine emanation of the Word is an origin, for every emanation is an origin. (Fs)

The divine emanation of the Word is an origin of one living, for God is living and the divine Word is God. (Fs)

The divine emanation of the Word is the origin of one living from a living principle, for God is living, and the principle of the Word or the Speaker is God. (Fs)

The divine emanation of the Word is the origin of one living from a conjoined living principle, for what are within the same consciousness as the principle and term of an emanation are conjoined. (Fs)

201d The divine emanation of the Word is the origin of one living from a conjoined living principle resulting in a likeness, for by reason of the emanation itself of the Word, the Word proceeds as forming a true likeness. (Fs)

203a The divine emanation of the Word is the origin of one living from a conjoined living principle with a resulting likeness in nature, for God's intentional act of existence is the same as God's natural act of existence; so, although all other true words are likenesses only with respect to an intentional act of existence, the Word of God, from the very fact that it is likeness in intentional act of existence, necessarily also is likeness in natural act of existence. (Fs)

203b The divine emanation of Love, on the other hand, even though it is the origin of one living from a conjoined living principle, even though through this emanation God originates in accordance with God's natural act of existence, nevertheless one element of generation in the proper sense is lacking, and that a necessary one. For the emanation of love does not lead to the formation of a likeness of a thing but to constituting an impulse toward or adhesion to the thing itself for its own sake. Therefore, although there does originate from this emanation something that is similar in nature, just as Eve was similar in nature to Adam, nevertheless the formal intelligibility of this emanation does not lead to the constitution of likeness, just as the rib taken from Adam's side proceeded to the formation of Eve not on account of the intrinsic formality pertaining to the rib, but from the supervening power of God. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Emanation; Unterschied: Akt des Verstehens - inneres Wort; erste, zweite Tätigkeit des Verstandes - die entsprechenden Objekte; intellectus agens, possibilis, phantasma; Beispiele; Hylophormismus

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 1: Is our act of understanding different from our [inner] word? ... in relation to our intellect one distinguishes the object that is the goal of intellect (being), the object that is the term of the second operation of intellect (the true) ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 1
Is our act of understanding different from our [inner] word?1

203c Since an act takes its species from its object, if one discovers different specific objects, one must distinguish different acts.2 (Fs)

203d Now, in relation to our intellect one distinguishes the object that is the goal of intellect (being), the object that is the term of the second operation of intellect (the true), the object that moves the intellect toward its second operation (sufficient evidence), the object that is the term of the first operation of intellect (a definition, a hypothesis), and the object that moves the intellect toward its first operation (the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter). (Fs) (notabene)

203e Furthermore, being and the true are convertible; whatever are convertible are not different in species; so being is also attained by the same act by which the true is attained. For this reason, the true is said to be the medium in which being is known. (Fs)

203f But the true is one thing, and sufficient evidence is another; so the act by which evidence is grasped as sufficient is different from the act by which the true is affirmed and the false is denied. It is quite clear that these two acts are connected to each other by an intellectual emanation, for we are able to affirm the true because we have grasped evidence as sufficient.1 Therefore, as regards the second operation of intellect, by which we respond to the question, Is it? one must distinguish very carefully between the act of understanding by which the sufficiency of evidence is grasped and the act of affirming the true, which is a word uttered within. (Fs)

205a With respect to the first operation of intellect,2 the object that moves, which is external, is the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter. First, corporeal and individual matter is made known through the senses. Second, from the agent intellect a wondering arises that asks, 'What is it?' or 'Why is it so?' Third, a phantasm is formed in which the intelligible that is to be grasped in sensible data becomes more clearly manifest in the sensible data themselves. Fourth, the possible intellect, directed to the phantasm, grasps in the phantasm an intelligible, a quiddity, or another cause. Fifth, the possible intellect, since it now actually understands the quiddity of a reality, or another cause, utters a simple inner word, which is the definition of the reality through its quiddity or through another cause. (Fs) (notabene)

205b Now the intelligible that is grasped in sensible data is the same as the intelligible that is uttered in the definition. Nevertheless, the object when grasped is different from the object when defined. For when it is grasped, corporeal matter becomes known separately through the senses, but the quiddity or nature or cause becomes known separately through the intellect. However, when it is defined, what became known earlier through distinct acts are now brought together into one; for in the definition common corporeal matter is posited, but not individual corporeal matter; and the quiddity, nature, or cause are not themselves defined, but rather the reality is defined in accordance with its quiddity, nature, or cause. Therefore, because the objects are different, the acts must be different. (Fs) (notabene)

205c Lest one be deterred by this terminology, we add these examples. (Fs)

What is an eclipse? An eclipse is the darkening brought about on a heavenly body by the interposition of another heavenly body. That is a quidditative definition, for it states what an eclipse is. How, then, does it differ from any other kind of definition? It differs in that not only does it set forth sensible similarities, but it also assigns a cause or reason why. For the cause of an eclipse is the interposition of another heavenly body: that cause is grasped in the sensible data themselves, or at least in the phantasm, by an act of understanding, before an eclipse can be defined through its cause. (Fs)

207a What is a circle? A circle is the locus of points lying on the same plane surface and equally distant from a center. That is another quidditative definition. For it does not state that the circle is a perfectly round plane figure; rather, it assigns the cause why the circle necessarily is perfectly round. Moreover, this necessary consequence itself must be grasped in the phantasm by an act of understanding before there can be an intellectual emanation of the definition of the circle.1 (Fs)

207b What is a human being? A rational animal. That again is a quidditative definition, because it assigns the cause. For what becomes known through the senses is a certain kind of organic body. A form is understood in this body: the soul that is both sensitive and rational. Because the form is a sensitive soul, the reality is an animal. Because the form is a rational soul, the reality is a rational animal. (Fs)

207c Once these things have been grasped, the gnoseological foundation of hylomorphism comes to light: because we conceive realities by means of sensation and understanding, it is necessary that they be composed of matter and form. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Notwendigkeit des Wortes in uns; Beweis: Wort in Gott?; falsches Verständnis von Sein (Objekt - Subjekt): Plato, Scotus, Rosmini, Satre; intellectus in actu ...;

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 2: Can the existence of a Word in God be demonstrated by the natural light of reason? ... we must consider by what necessity there is a word in us, so that we can determine whether ...

Textausschnitt: 207d As to the fact, the answer is obvious from the condemnation of the semirationalists by the Vatican Council (DB 1816, DS 3041, ND 137). Still, in order to add some understanding to our certitude, we must consider by what necessity there is a word in us, so that we can determine whether there is any necessity for a word in God that we can know naturally.1 (Fs)

207e A first reason, then, that a word is necessary in us is to enable us to proceed from a grasp of a cause or quiddity to a conception of a thing. For we are moved to an act of understanding by the causes or quiddities of things; but these causes or quiddities are not the things themselves, but parts or relations of the things; so the first reason that a word is necessary in us is so that from having grasped a quiddity, we may proceed to a thing as quidditatively defined. (Fs)

209a A second reason is to enable us to proceed from definitions and from a grasp of evidence to things as existing. This does not occur unless from a grasp of evidence there proceeds a true affirmation in which, as in a medium, being is known.1 (Fs)

209b A third reason is to enable us to cultivate the sciences. For if universal words were not being produced we would never be able to know the whole visible universe; rather, we would be confined to experienced or imagined particulars. Again, if exactly defined words were not being produced, we would be tossed about by the flow of images after the manner of the mythic mentality, since it would never be clearly and distinctly determined what we were talking about. (Fs)

209c A fourth and final reason is to enable us to proceed beyond the limits of the visible universe by means of analogies and the way of eminence. One could never so proceed unless interior words were being formed both for defining and for judging. (Fs)

209d These four reasons for the necessity of a word have this common source, that the object that moves us to the act of understanding is different from the object toward which we tend as toward a goal. For the object that moves our intellect in this life is the quiddity of a material thing; but the goal toward which intellect tends is the totality of being. Because we begin from a quiddity, the word is required, first, so that the thing may be defined through its quiddity; second, so that we may judge whether what we have defined exists; third, so that we may be directed away from sensibly perceived particulars toward the entirety of the visible universe; and fourth, so that we may be able to reach beyond the material world to God. (Fs)

209e Now the necessity of the word in God cannot be of this kind. For the divine intellect is not moved by something else, nor does it tend toward something else as toward a goal, but being infinite in perfection, it exists eternally, perfectly comprehending itself and perfectly understanding and knowing everything else in itself. (Fs)

209f The arguments which are sometimes presented as demonstrating the existence of a divine Word are easily answered. (Fs)
Thus, one can object that an understanding that is not expressed in words is not clear and distinct; but divine knowledge is perfectly clear and distinct; therefore, divine knowledge is not without expression through a word. (Fs)

209g Response: I concede that an understanding through many acts is not clear and distinct without words; I deny that an understanding through one infinite act is not clear and distinct without words. And I contradistinguish the minor. (Fs)

211a The distinction is explained in the following manner. Of itself, the word can add no clarity and no distinctness above understanding, since the word is merely the expression of what becomes known through the act of understanding. In an incidental manner, however, words are necessary for clarity and distinctness when there are many diverse and imperfect acts of understanding; and so if there were no words in us, we should hardly be able to know what we have already grasped and what remains to be investigated. (Fs) (notabene)

211b Objection: The duality of subject and object is intrinsic to the very idea of knowledge. Therefore, if the divine subject were not to utter a word, he would not be able to know himself. But God knows himself. Therefore, he utters a word. (Fs)
Response: The principle presupposed is simply false and has no basis other than imagining a person looking and the object looked at. (Fs)

211c Because of this presupposed principle, the Platonists postulated simple, subsistent, eternal Ideas in a first order, and on the second level the gods who contemplated the Ideas. Because of the same principle, Scotus posited his formal distinction a parte rei, as will be clear below. Because of the same principle, Anton Günther and Antonio Rosmini thought they had discovered a demonstration of the divine Word. Because of the same principle, Jean-Paul Sartre distinguishes between en soi and pour soi in such a way that he impugns as contradictory a God who is real, who is conscious of himself, and who is simple. Because of the same principle, consciousness is conceived as perception of oneself, a view that leads to insoluble difficulties regarding the consciousness of Christ.1 (Fs) (notabene)

211d Aristotelian and Thomist principles are entirely opposed to this supposed principle. For the intelligible in act is the intelligent in act.2 The intelligent and the understood are the same in those things that are without matter. Accordingly, the only reason why the intellect and the intelligible object are not the same is that both are in potency.3 (Fs)

213a Objection: Finally, dynamic intellectual consciousness is so perfect that it must be posited in God, who is infinite in perfection. (Fs)

Response: If this statement is considered in itself, I concede. If it is considered in relation to us, I deny it. For the procession of the Word in God is utterly necessary and utterly perfect. But in what we know naturally concerning God there is no demonstration that dynamic intellectual consciousness is a pure perfection, and so it cannot be demonstrated that it must be posited in God. We do not attain a perfect understanding even from what we believe by faith; indeed, the reality of the emanation and the consubstantiality of the one emanating seem so to conflict with each other that we can hardly consider the two of them simultaneously. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Schöpfung (Möglichkeit, possibilia) unter dem Gesichtspunk des Seins, der Möglichkeit, der aktuellen Existenz; Bedingung für die Emanation des Wortes

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 3: Does the Word proceed from the understanding of creatures? ... it follows that the divine Word proceeds from the understanding of creatures in such a manner that creatures are truly and eternally being uttered as dependent upon the Word ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 3
Does the Word proceed from the understanding of creatures?

213b The answer seems to be no, for the divine Word is necessary and eternal, while creatures are contingent and temporal. (Fs)
On the other hand, there is the doctrine of St Thomas that in one act God understands himself and creatures, and that in a single Word God utters himself and creatures. Again, as divine understanding in regard to self is knowledge of that self but in regard to creatures is both divine knowledge of them and productive of them, so the divine Word is expressive of God and also both expressive and productive of creatures.1 (Fs)

213c However, for the solution to the foregoing difficulty, one must observe that not all theologians understand the psychological analogy in the same manner. Those who conceive the word as proceeding from the object as the act of seeing proceeds from colors can hardly admit that the divine Word proceeds from creatures. On the other hand, those who, considering the issue somewhat more profoundly, conceive the word as proceeding from knowledge of an object labor under a lesser difficulty, since the object is not the cause all by itself, but is a concurrent cause. But those who arrive at the formality of intellectual consciousness have no difficulty at all; this, however, needs to be carefully considered. (Fs) (notabene)

213d The proper principle of intellectual emanation is not the object but the subject. This is obvious in God, since God is the first principle of all things. But it is also evident to some extent in us, since an intellectual emanation can occur only inasmuch as a subject is intellectually conscious in act. (Fs)

215a Again, the necessity of an intellectual emanation arises not from the object but from the conscious intellectuality of the subject. Because intellectual consciousness owes it to itself to express to itself its own understanding, and to express it truly, it follows that what is being understood ought to be expressed truly. Because intellectual consciousness owes it to itself to bestow its own love rightly, it follows that what is judged as truly good ought also to be loved. And if perchance understanding is deficient or judgment erroneous, an unknown obligation does not prevail in such a way that one is duty-bound to act against one's conscience; rather, a known obligation prevails, so that one is duty-bound to judge in accordance with the evidence one has and to choose in accordance with one's judgment. (Fs)

215b But perhaps it will be objected that we are exaggerating this autonomy of consciousness. There are two answers to this. First, since divine autonomy is absolute, it cannot be exaggerated; and since we are endeavoring to understand this autonomy, the objector seems to stray beyond this subject of inquiry to other matters. Second, the autonomy of human consciousness is indeed subordinate, not to every object whatsoever, but to the infinite subject in whose image it has been made and whom it is bound to imitate. (Fs)

215c Moreover, we must consider further that different objects enter differently both into the act of understanding, from which the word emanates, and into the act of understanding and the word, from which love emanates. For the primary object of divine understanding, the divine being itself, is one thing, and secondary objects are another. The latter are related to the primary object by a threefold gradation: possibles considered under the formality of being are related to the divine essence in one way, possibles considered under the formality of the possible are related to the divine essence in another way, and finally all actual realities, whether past, present, or future, are related to the divine essence in yet another way.1 (Fs)

215d Considered under the formality of being, possibles are nothing but the divine active power itself which is able to produce them. And according to this, God understands and utters the possibles inasmuch as he understands and utters his power, which is entirely the same as his essence or his act of understanding. (Fs)

215e Considered under the formality of the possible, possibles are in God understanding and uttering, after the manner of an implicit conceptual being. I say 'after the manner of a conceptual being' because the entire reality of the possibles is the divine active power. I say 'after the manner of an implicit conceptual being' because God does not utter as many distinct words as there are distinct possibles. (Fs)

217a Third, and finally, all actual realities, past, present, and future, are among the secondary objects of divine understanding. Indeed, all these actual realities, precisely as actual, God knows immediately in understanding them, utters in the Word, and loves in proceeding Love. And if another world were to exist, other realities as actual would be known immediately and spoken and loved, not as if God were able to be now this and now that, not as if the divine intellectual emanations were able to be now this and now that, but because the knowledge and affirmation and love of actual realities adds only a conceptual relation to the infinite act of understanding, affirming, and loving. (Fs) (notabene)

217b Accordingly, the emanation of the divine Word is surely dependent upon divine intellectual consciousness and upon the infinite act of understanding. Because this consciousness and this act of understanding are not only identical with each other but also the same as the divine act of existence, the divine essence, and the divine power, the divine emanation of the Word is also dependent upon the divine essence and upon the divine power. Furthermore, because divine understanding includes possibles as possibles after the manner of an implicit conceptual being, the divine emanation of the Word also owes it to itself to utter as well possibles as possibles after the manner of implicit conceptual beings. Moreover, because divine understanding, with a conceptual relation accompanying that infinite act, understands all actual realities as they are, the emanation of the divine Word also owes it to itself that all actual realities be uttered with the accompanying conceptual relation, and the divine emanation of Love, with the accompanying conceptual relation, owes it to itself that all actual realities be loved through proceeding Love. Finally, because divine understanding grasps with perfect clarity that the divine Word and divine Love are not dependent upon the conceptual relation, because divine understanding grasps with perfect clarity that all actual realities and possibles are utterly dependent upon divine understanding, upon the divine Word, and upon divine Love, it follows that the divine Word proceeds from the understanding of creatures in such a manner that creatures are truly and eternally being uttered as dependent upon the Word, and the divine Love proceeds from the understanding and affirmation of creatures in such a manner that creatures are rightly and eternally loved in dependence upon this Love. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Geliebte im Liebenden (amantum in amante): konstituiert durch Liebe oder gemacht; Hervorgang im Akt des Wollens analog zu jenem im Akt des Verstehens?

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 4; Is the 'beloved in the lover' constituted by love or produced by love?; we are asking whether it is really the same as love, the act of loving, or whether perhaps it is really distinct from love and proceeds from love.

Textausschnitt: [...]

219b Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 3 c: '... in God there is procession only according to action that does not tend toward something extrinsic but remains within the agent itself. But such action in an intellectual nature is that of the intellect and that of the will. The procession of the word is considered in connection with the action of the intellect. However, another procession is found in us in connection with the operation of the will, namely, the procession of love, whereby the beloved is in the one who loves, just as the reality spoken or understood is in the one who understands through the conception of the word. Hence, in addition to the procession of the Word, another procession is to be posited in God, namely, the procession of Love.' (Fs)

219c Summa theologiae, 1, q. 37, a. 1 c: 'Just as from the fact that someone understands something, there comes forth in the one who understands some intellectual conception of the reality understood, which is called the word; so from the fact that someone loves something, there comes forth in the affection of the lover some impression, so to speak, of the reality loved, whereby the beloved is said to be in the one who loves, just as what is understood is in the one who understands. So it is that, when one understands and loves oneself, one is in oneself not only by an entitative identity, but also as what is understood is in the one who understands, and as the beloved is in the one who loves.' (Fs)

221a Regarding that reality which is named 'the beloved in the lover' we are asking whether it is really the same as love, the act of loving, or whether perhaps it is really distinct from love and proceeds from love. If you say the former is the case, then 'the beloved in the lover' is constituted by love; if you say the latter is the case, then 'the beloved in the lover' is produced by love. (Fs) (notabene)

221b In favor of the former opinion is the first passage cited above: according to that passage, the beloved is said to be in the one who loves in accordance with the procession of love, just as the thing spoken or understood is in the one who understands it through the conception of the word. For 'the reality spoken or understood' is constituted in the one who understands through the word itself; in like manner, therefore, the 'beloved' is constituted in the lover through proceeding love itself. (Fs)


221c In favor of the latter opinion is the second passage cited above: there, from the fact that someone understands, there issues forth in the one understanding a conception of the thing understood, and similarly from the fact that someone loves, there issues forth in the affection of the lover a kind of impression of the thing loved. For the word is produced by the act of understanding, and so, in like manner, 'the beloved in the lover' is produced by the act of loving. (Fs)

221d The importance of this question is that corresponding to these opposed opinions there are opposed theoretical systems. Some take the trinitarian analogy from determining that there are two processions in us, one within intellect and the other within will; so that, just as the act of understanding produces the word in the first procession, so the act of love produces the 'beloved in the lover' in the second; John of St Thomas1 and Thomists generally have been of this opinion. But we take the trinitarian analogy from the fact that we experience in ourselves two processions, the first of which is within intellect, while the second is from intellect toward will. In the first procession, we judge because and according as we grasp the sufficiency of evidence. And in the second, we choose because and according as we judge. (Fs) (notabene)

221e Thus, we do not follow the opinion of Thomists in this matter, both because it prescinds from our internal experience in its conception of the psychological trinitarian analogy, and because it prescinds from our internal experience in its interpretation of the texts of St Thomas on psychological reality. However, we postpone this general question to appendices 1 and 2, and for now we ask only whether in the writings of St Thomas 'the beloved in the lover' is constituted or produced by the act of loving. (Fs)

223a We answer by citing texts in which (1) 'the beloved' is present 'in the lover' because love is present and not because something is produced by the act of love, (2) the analogy is explicitly posited in the fact that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Word just as love proceeds in us from our mental word, (3) the Holy Spirit is called proceeding Love, and (4) a procession after the manner of a thing operated is excluded from the will. (Fs)

223b Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 19, ¶4, §3560: [...]
227b Summa theologiae, [...]

229b Our response is that a hypothesis concerning development is superfluous when one attends to St Thomas's explicit doctrine. St Thomas taught explicitly
(1) that the second procession is the procession of love from the word;
(2) that the Holy Spirit is both 'the beloved in the lover' and proceeding Love;
(3) that the only procession in the will is the procession after the manner of an operation; and
(4) that the beloved is in the lover inasmuch as the beloved is being loved. (Fs) (notabene)
229c This internally consistent doctrine would have evolved to the extreme if in some later stage it could be proved beyond doubt
(1) that the second procession is not the procession of love from the word, but 'of the beloved in the lover' from love,
(2) that the Holy Spirit is 'the beloved in the lover' but is not proceeding Love,
(3) that there is a procession in the will after the manner of a reality that is the term of the operation,
(4) that the beloved is in the lover, not because the beloved is being loved, but because something really distinct proceeds from this love, which is named 'the beloved in the lover.' (Fs)

229d However, such extreme development is so far from having been proved beyond doubt that the only texts adduced in its favor are those in which perhaps implicitly there can be found, not the fullness ofjohn of St Thomas's thought on the point, but only certain elements of it. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vier Hervorgänge, vier Relationen; Argument: Vaterschaft, Sohnschaft, passive, aktive Hauchung; Gegenargument; Vaterschaft - aktive Hauchung: reale oder begriffliche Unterscheidung; Schöpfung: begriffliche Unterscheidung

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 4; Is the 'beloved in the lover'; we conclude from the real divine processions that there are four real relations in God, namely, paternity ...

Textausschnitt: Argument

235b
1 From the real procession of the Word, there follows a real relation of the word to the principle that speaks the word; and since this procession is generation in the proper sense, this real relation of the word to its principle is filiation. (Fs)

2 From the real procession of love, there follows a real relation of love to the principle that spirates love; and since this procession is not generation in the proper sense, this real relation is not filiation, and can fittingly be termed passive spiration. (Fs)

3 The intellectually conscious procession of the word is from the grasp of the intelligibility of whatever is to be uttered; moreover, from this grasp of intelligibility there emerges in the intellect that grasps it an intellectual necessity to speak the word. Since this necessity to speak the word really exists in the intellect, it is a real relation to the word to be spoken, and, once this word is uttered, a real relation to the word spoken. Finally, since in God to speak the word is to generate the Son, the real relation to the eternally spoken Word, the eternally generated Son, is the real relation of paternity. (Fs)

237a
4 The intellectually conscious procession of love is from the grasp and affirmation of the goodness of whatever is to be loved; moreover, from this grasp and affirmation of goodness there emerges in the one who grasps and affirms it an intellectual or moral necessity to spirate love; since this necessity really exists in the one who has grasped and affirmed goodness, it is a real relation to the love that is to be spirated and, once this love has arisen, a real relation to the love spirated; finally, this real relation of the spirator to what is spirated is fittingly termed active spiration. (Fs)

5 Once these matters are grasped, we conclude from the real divine processions that there are four real relations in God, namely, paternity, filiation, active spiration, and passive spiration. (Fs)

237b It might be objected1 that the relations of paternity and active spiration seem to be not real but only conceptual. For what holds for the principle that is God the Creator holds equally for the principle that is God the Father or God the Spirator. But active creation is only a conceptual relation. Therefore paternity and active spiration are likewise only conceptual relations. (Fs)

237c In reply we say that these two cases are not the same, since a principle and what originates from it are related in various ways. There is a principle that is inferior to the originated, such as an instrument that has an effect beyond its own proper perfection. There is another principle that is equal to the originated, as when the principle is really ordered to the originated and the originated in turn is really ordered to its principle; father and son are an example of this. Finally, there is a third case in which the principle is superior to the originated, as when the principle is the end of the originated. This sort of principle is not really ordered to what it originates, for an end does not exist because of that whose end it is. (Fs) (notabene)

237d Now God the creator is both principle and end of all things (DB 1785, DS 3004, ND 113), and therefore active creation is a conceptual relation only. But God the Father is not related to God the Son as creator to creature or as the end to that whose end it is. And so the two cases are not the same. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: minor real distinction: Erfahren - Einsehen - Urteilen; Potenz - Form - Akt; kontradiktorische Prädikate können nicht ein und demselben zugeschrieben werden

Kurzinhalt: Form is neither potency nor act. Form is neither of the other two, because form is intelligible in itself. Neither act nor potency is intelligible in itself, if we are talking about finite act. But one and the same cannot have contradictory predicates ...

Textausschnitt: 1. 4 Unity and Distinction

17/9 We have put in more familiar terms what I was saying yesterday. Metaphysics is the integral heuristic structure of proportionate being. We are saying the same thing again. What is this heuristic structure? It is the use of a set of analogies, where the analogies have a fundamental determination from cognitional process. The use of cognitional process as the fundamental instance is justified by the relation between knowing and known. Why can we say that all proportionate being will stand within those analogies? It is because proportionate being is what we can know by experience, understanding, and judgment. (206; Fs)

Kommentar (07/08/08): Analog dazu: Lonergans Kategorien der Geschicht: Fortschritt, Süne, Gnade (Analytic Concept of History).

18/9 We have, then, three types of act, three levels of cognitional activity: the experiential, the intellectual, the rational. As act, these three levels also have content, and the content contained in the act is the content that is known. There is a content corresponding to experience, a content corresponding to understanding, and a content corresponding to judgment. Understanding presupposes and complements experience; judgment presupposes and complements understanding and experience. Consequently, since there are those relations between the acts, there will be relations of a similar sort between the contents. What we experience is what we inquire into; what we inquire into is what we understand; what we understand is what we conceive; what we conceive is what we reflec on; what we reflect on is what we grasp as virtually unconditioned; what we grasp as virtually unconditioned is what we affirm. That what is the content. There is a unity, then. It is always the same object that is being approached through experience, understanding, and judgment. (206f; Fs)

19/9 While there is a unity, there is also a distinction. The component that you know through experiencing is not the same as the component that you know through understanding. Understanding is not just another experiential element; it is a unification that supervenes upon experiential elements, and it stands in a different order. The affirmation of judgment, the 'is,' is a third component that closes the unity. Consequently, just as one knowing involves three components, so one known will involve three components; and one can establish, by setting up definitions of distinctions,1 that, of those three components, one really is not the other; they are really distinct. It is a minor real distinction, because it occurs within one and the same being; nonetheless, it is a real distinction. (207; Fs)

20/9 Form is what in itself is intelligible; it is the component in the known that is known precisely inasmuch as one is understanding. The experienced in itself is not an intelligible, but it is what can be understood; it is related to the intelligible, it is intelligible in the other. Act in itself has a certain intelligibility, but it is an incomplete intelligibility; it corresponds to the virtually unconditioned. Insofar as it is unconditioned, an absolute, it involves some type of intelligibility; but that intelligibility is a dependent intelligibility. It is a virtually unconditioned, an unconditioned that happens to have its conditions fulfilled; it is contingent. It has a reference to the other, and it must have that reference if it is to be fully understood.d (207; Fs) (notabene)

21/9 Now P and Q are really distinct if P is, Q is, and P is not Q. There is form, there is potency, there is act; but the three are as components in one being, and no one is the other two. Form is neither potency nor act. Form is neither of the other two, because form is intelligible in itself. Neither act nor potency is intelligible in itself, if we are talking about finite act. But one and the same cannot have contradictory predicates; one and the same cannot be both intelligible in itself and not intelligible in itself. If there are contradictory predicates, both of which are to be affirmed , then there have to be different subjects. Therefore, form is not potency, form is not act. That is a distinction that is true; therefore, it is a real distinction, it regards reality. (207; Fs) (notabene)

22/9 Again, while both potency and act are intelligible in the other, still it is a different other in which they are intelligible. Potency is intelligible in form; act is intelligible ultimately only in a formally unconditioned act an act that is not simply the virtually unconditioned, but a formally unconditioned that has no conditions at all. What is intelligible only in the formally unconditioned act is not the same as what is intelligible in form. (207f; Fs)

23/9 We may take another angle on this. One can ask, 'Are these three simply posited as real? Are they components of reality, or are they components of reality as known?' We spoke of all three in terms of their intelligibility and that would suggest that they are components of reality as known. However, if we go back to our definition of being - being is the object of the verb 'to know' - we note that it has an intrinsic relation to knowing. Being has to be intrinsically intelligible; otherwise understanding and understanding correctly could not be knowledge of being. (208; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: metaphysische Analyse; Beispiel: Inkarnation: id quod est; id quo est; intelligere: Scotus - Thomas;

Kurzinhalt: ... there is (fortunately, from my viewpoint) a passage in which St Thomas says that the compound of form and matter is just id quo est. If 'form and matter' is just id quo, then to have the id quod one has to add existence, and we have a third component.

Textausschnitt: 1..5 An Illustration of Metaphysical Analysis

24/9 Enough has been said to indicate that this procedure from a cognitional analysis to metaphysics can be a very expeditious way of arriving with great precision and rapidity at the conclusions that are found in traditional Aristotelian and Thomist metaphysics. Moreover, without a precise cognitional analysis, certain traditional metaphysical questions are very difficult to handle.1 (208; Fs)

25/9 Let us consider our human understanding. Suppose it is true that 'so and so' - Socrates, say - understands something.e If we have Socrates, we have a human central form, and we have prime matter and existence. If Socrates understands, he has to be able to understand; to be able to understand, he has to have a potency by which he is able to understand. If he actually understands, there have to be acts of understanding; and as these acts of understanding are not merely acts of understanding, but acts of understanding this kind of thing, there is needed a formal limitation, a species impressa or an acquired habit, a set of impressed species. (208; Fs)

26/9 Again, we can say that Socrates, the man in question, not merely has the capacity to understand, but on a certain range of topics he does not have to stop and think before he gives the answers. This is not true of everybody. Every man has the capacity to understand, the intellect possibilis. However, this man has the capacity to answer any question in a whole range without stopping to think. As it was defined by Avicenna, habitus est quo quis utitur quando voluerit;2 a habit is what you use whenever you please. One does not have to work up steam to be able to do it. A man who has just the capacity to understand, without any developed intellectual habit, has to learn before he will be able to handle questions in the manner of the man who has learned. That is the element of conjugate form. Thus Aristotle distinguishes between considering and merely having the habit of science. When one considers, one is actually understanding; there is a third element. (208f; Fs)

27/9 Besides the potency to understand, there is also an active principle. We have spoken of wonder, intellectual alertness, and that is the intellectus agens;3 to account for the occurrence of events in the intellect as a potency, you must have an agent intellect that is relevant to the flow of sensations, perceptions, and images. Moreover, when you understand, you are able to define; when you understand, you are able to formulate at least a hypothesis. That is an act that proceeds from the act of understanding by intellectual consciousness. (209; Fs)

28/9 Further, the intellectus agens, when it arrives at a hypothesis or formulation, a verbum interius, is not yet satisfied; it has there simply the ground for going from essence to being by raising the question of existence. When the question of existence is raised one has rational reflection, which heads toward another act, the reflective insight in which you grasp the virtually unconditioned. There can be a habit relevant to that grasp. Some people can make judgments more quickly than others; a man familiar with a particular field is able not merely to put forward hypotheses and possible answers, but he is able to say, 'That's what it is.' He has a habit of wisdom; with regard to practical matters, it is a habit of prudence. That reflective grasp of the understanding expresses itself in the verbum complexum. (209; Fs)

29/9 This analysis, in metaphysical terms, is found in the writings of St Tomas. However, you find an entirely different metaphysical setup in Scotus, who explicitly denied insight into phantasm. But in the commentators, as far as I can see, what you find is Scotist psychology forced upon this Thomist metaphysical setup, and it does not make much sense. It leads to all sorts of disputed questions. The question whether the verbum interius, the formulation, is really distinct from the intelligere, the insight, is debated rather futilely if there is no clear idea of what an act of understanding is. The tendency of a number of commentators is to conceive the intelligere as the activity from the species impressa putting forth the formulation. When the formulation is put forth, intellect takes a look at it and knows the universal. There is no act of understanding; only the activity of producing a concept is acknowledged. As far as I can tell, that seems to be the theory of John of St Thomas. (209f; Fs) (notabene)

30/9 We have given a general sketch of metaphysics and metaphysical analysis on the basis of cognitional analysis. We have a basis, then, from which to deal with metaphysical issues. Three may be considered here.4 (210; Fs)

31/9 First, there is the relation between being and essence. Is existence a third component over and above matter and form? Is being all three? Is the id quod est the compound of all three, a triple compound? Or is the id quod est the form and matter, and does it exercise the act of existence? It's a nice question. (210; Fs)
32/9 Aristotle does not advert to the act of existence; but in St Thomas, we have a series of relevant texts. In the Commentary on the Sentences, the Summa contra Gentiles, and the pars prima of the Summa theologiae, id quod est is the compound of form and matter in material things, and simply the form in angels and God. On the other hand, in the tertiapars,5 q. 17, a. 2, ad 4m, there is (fortunately, from my viewpoint) a passage in which St Thomas says that the compound of form and matter is just id quo est. If 'form and matter' is just id quo, then to have the id quod one has to add existence, and we have a third component. (210; Fs)

33/9 This question is fundamental in the theory of the incarnation, because one and the same is both God and man. If there is a man, we have matter and form; if matter and form give us an id quod, in the man Jesus Christ we have one id quod, and in the second person of the Blessed Trinity we have another; consequently, we do not have one and the same that is both God and man. That is why, in this passage, matter and form are just id quo. Because of this difficulty, in Cajetan the substance, id quod est, is matter and form, but subsistence requires the addition of a mode. A mode must be added for it to be capable of existence, and that mode is missing in the case of the incarnation. (210f; Fs)

34/9 Insofar as you are proceeding from cognitional analysis, you have a means of handling such questions systematically. Your concepts may be of essence - 'humanity' or 'this humanity' - and as such they have only a remote relation to being. If your concept is 'man,' you are seeing the implication of existence in essence; your concept of being involves not only the conception of the essence, the compound of matter and form, but also the intention of existence, the question of existence. Being as what, as a concept, an object of thought, is matter, form, and existence, where matter and form give you 'humanity,' and the question of existence, about to be raised, supplies the other component. If you do not have a precise cognitional analysis, this question is very difficult to handle. (211; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: Kanon der Metaphysik: Konkretheit, erklärender Gesichtspunkt (explanatory viewpoint); Rückkehr zur Analyse des Verstehensprozesses

Kurzinhalt: the first canon is concreteness: deal with the concrete ... The second canon is the explanatory viewpoint ... Potency, form, and act are not in any immediate correspondence with words, with grammar

Textausschnitt: 1.6 Canons of Metaphysical Analysis1
41/9 When I presented the manuscript of Insight to the publishers, it was first given to a reader who was an English Dominican2 -just who he was I've not yet learnt - and the question my publisher put to me was, 'How can you teach this?' Apparently, the report was, 'This isn't what you find in the other books.' This question has probably occurred to those engaged in teaching. One may feel that this seems so different from anything that is in the books that it could not possibly be taught. The preceding discussion, however, illustrates the possibility. (212; Fs)
42/9 In other words, you need not work through the general scheme completely every time. I make use of this material continually in my theology classes in dealing with the speculative side of problems that arise, and I do so in terms of the fundamental analogies. Aristotle knew about insight; he did not know all forms of all things and from that knowledge conclude to his hylomorphism; he knew about understanding. It was not possible for him to formulate it as we can formulate it today, but he had a marvelous formulation for it, considering the opportunities of language, and so on. If you have a clear idea of what insight is, it is not hard to become convinced that Aristotle knew about it, and that that relation between insight and data is a key to the relation between potency and form, matter and form.3 Again, it was insofar as St Thomas grasped the significance of the judgment of existence that he complemented the Augustinian emphasis on truth with the metaphysical component of existence, and set up the relation between essence and existence. The analogies, as I have worked them out in terms of cognitional theory from self-appropriation, also played their role, I believe, in the historical development of scholastic thought. By using the analogies concretely, one can give exactly the same doctrine in any particular case. (212f; Fs)
43/9 Moreover, with regard to the method, there is a whole chapter, Metaphysics as Science, that works out a number of rather detailed questions. I draw attention particularly to this point, because it is of fundamental importance: one applies metaphysical analysis, first of all, concretely.4 Thomist doctrine is not set up in Euclidean fashion. St Thomas proceeds by answering a series of questions, and the marvelous thing about his procedure is not so much the answers as the series of questions. One can set up principles to be able to answer the questions, but the surprising thing is where those questions came from, the build-up they involve, and the mastery of detail. It is a consideration of concrete questions; metaphysical analysis is applied to the concrete. (213; Fs)
44/9 When we have a truth, we know something. If we wish to go on to the metaphysics of that truth, we want, not an abstract truth, but a concrete truth. We want, for example, 'This man understands,' not 'Man understands.' Because what exists is concrete, the first canon is concreteness: deal with the concrete. We may answer general questions in metaphysical analysis, but the way to approach them always is by an analysis of a concrete instance, because it is the concrete instance that exists. It is Socrates who understands; it is not understanding, not cognitional process. Cognitional process is not a being; it is a component; it is something that happens in a being. Deal with the concrete. (213f; Fs)
45/9 The second canon is the explanatory viewpoint. It is more difficult, but it is also very fundamental. I believe that all sorts of difficulties, obscurities and insoluble problems are caused insofar as metaphysical analysis is attempted from truths that are merely descriptive. Truths cast in the form of Aristotle's predicaments, where you have descriptive knowledge that does not imply any great understanding but only a minimum of understanding, where you have an understanding of things as they are related to us or an understanding of words, are not a sufficient basis for metaphysical analysis. Even if your knowledge on a question is only descriptive, you have to cast it in explanatory form. When your knowledge is descriptive, it merely anticipates the understanding we are talking about, and you have to transpose, as it were, the descriptive knowing into an intention of explanatory knowing in order to enable the analogies to function properly. The analogies are insight into data, and judgment upon formulation. If your formulation is such that it does not involve any real insight into the thing, then you have to introduce the hypothetical insight, the objective of your heuristic structure, to be able to handle it in terms of the analogy. If you seek a metaphysical analysis that will cover absolutely everything, you get confusion and insoluble disputes. (214; Fs)
46/9 Thirdly, metaphysical analysis is not grammatical analysis; it is not logical analysis. Someone once said to me, remarking on the Thomist synthesis, that it is 'a marvelous synthesis of human psychology, a marvelous synthesis of reality, a marvelous synthesis of grammar.' You can get bogged down in words. You may get concerned with the metaphysical significance of a word; but when questions get onto that level, they become hopeless. You must go behind the words to the experiences, the understanding, the rational judgment, to the analysis of the cognitional process at its root. Potency, form, and act are not in any immediate correspondence with words, with grammar. There are elements in grammar that are closely connected; you can emphasize the 'is,' but it is not 'is' as a word that is metaphysically significant: you can have 'is' merely in the expression of an object of thought or in a question. What counts is the rational act of judgment. Again, what counts is not words but the insight. Unless you reduce your truths to the experience, understanding, and judgment on which their expression rests, you are going to encounter difficulties in metaphysical analysis. (214f; Fs)

47/9 There are, then, three points. The first is concreteness, because being is concrete. The second is the explanatory viewpoint. Suppose we have the descriptive expression, 'He is five feet tall.' Now what are the conjugate potencies, forms, and acts in that? I do not think you can handle the question. You have to conceive the measurement, 'five feet tall,' in terms of an understanding of man, and you can see that it shades off into a datum that is not going to be integrated in any explanatory system; it is just going to be a matter of statistical frequency. The third point is that we are concerned with cognitional acts, not talk. The applications of the canons may be complicated, but if you take those directives you can perform metaphysical analysis in terms of central and conjugate potency, form, and act, and explanatory genera and species, and the analysis will be satisfactory; and I think you will also find - although it is a matter of experience - that the root of a large number of disputed questions is simply a violation of those canons. (215; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Understanding and Being

Titel: Understanding and Being

Stichwort: metaphysische Analyse; Beispiel: Beziehung von Substanz zu Akzidenz; zentrale, konjugate Form; Bewusstsein

Kurzinhalt: What is the relation of substance and accident?

Textausschnitt:
35/9 Let us take a second question. What is the relation of substance and accident? I understand by my intelligence. My intelligence is an id quo; it is conjugate or accidental potency. What is it that understands? What is the 'I'? In our analysis of Socrates, we had prime matter, substantial form, substantial act, accidental potencies, accidental forms or habits, and some accidental acts. Is the 'I' that understands the being, the id quod est, the whole, or is it just some id quo?'6 If you think simply in terms of the predicaments, which occur in the Corpus Aristotelicum as an introductory statement and, I believe, as a purely descriptive stage of the science of metaphysics before the question of causes is raised at all, it is almost inevitable that you will answer that the being is just this id quo. You have substance, man, and quality, intelligence, and you have potency, form, and act accounting for the man, and potency, form, and act accounting for the intelligence. On this view, the man, the being, is just the substance, and qualities are added on; they come to the substance. (211; Fs)

36/9 On the other hand, on the analysis of central and conjugate forms that can be worked out from cognitional analysis, what we have is data that we consider in either of two ways: insofar as they are individual, we grasp in these data a central form; insofar as they are of a kind, we reach conjugate forms. It is understanding the same data from different viewpoints that leads to the two types of form. The central form is the comprehensive unity in the whole; consequently, the man is one by his central form, which is the principle of unity in the whole. On this second view it is much easier to understand why a change in the accidents is a change in the man. (211f; Fs)

40/9 Thirdly, there are questions of consciousness. Who is conscious? In virtue of sense and imagination we have an empirical consciousness; by understanding we have an intellectual consciousness; by reflection we have a rational consciousness; and when we go on to will, we have rational self-consciousness. But who is conscious? If 'this' is the man, if it is true that the man is conscious, then it has to be this substance that is conscious. How is it conscious? It is conscious by really distinct accidents. If you say that the man is the whole which is one by the substance, then you can say the man is conscious.

That is a general sketch of metaphysical analysis on the basis of cogni-tional analysis.6 (212; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Bestimmung: Subjekt; Bewusstsein: conscientia-experientia - conscientia-perceptio

Kurzinhalt: ... what precisely is the difference between the two positions, between consciousness conceived as an experience and consciousness conceived as the perception of an object?

Textausschnitt: 2 The Notion of the Subject

162b The notion of the subject is difficult, recent, and primitive. (Fs)

It is difficult. St Thomas once remarked that everyone knows he has a soul, yet even great philosophers go wrong on the nature of the soul. The same is true of the subject. Everyone knows he is a subject, and so everyone is interested in the consciousness of Christ. Not everyone knows the nature of the subject, and so there is a variety of opinions. (Fs)

162c The notion is also recent. If one wishes to find out what a soul is, one has only to read St Thomas. If one wishes to find out what a subject is, it is not enough to read ancient or medieval writers. They did not treat the matter explicitly. They did not work out systematically the notion of the subject. They did not integrate this systematic notion with the rest of their philosophic and psychological doctrine.1 (Fs; Fußnote!)

163a In the third place, the notion is primitive. It cannot be reached merely by combining other, better known concepts. It can be reached only by directing one's attention to the facts and to understanding them correctly. Nor is this enough. A difficult, recent, and primitive notion is not theologically useful until it has been transposed into the classical categories of scholastic thought;e and obviously such a transposition supposes some research into the exact meaning and the latent potentialities of classical writers such as St Thomas. (Fs)
163b Needless to say, I did not attempt all this in a set of notes for theological students. I had explored Thomist intellectual theory in a series of articles published in Theological Studies.2 I had explored the complex speculative issues in a book, Insight.3 In my De constitutione Christi I was simply making available in Latin and for my students the conclusions I had reached in other studies. (Fs)

163c My procedure was to present two opposed notions of consciousness: the first I named conscientia-experientia, and I employed it as the basis of my view of the consciousness of Christ; the second I named conscientia-perceptio, and I employed it to account for the opinions of those with whom I happened to disagree. Since the former met dogmatic requirements and the latter, I believed, did not, there seemed to me no need to leave the properly theological level of thought and to enter into philosophic and psychological questions. (Fs)

163d Still, what precisely is the difference between the two positions, between consciousness conceived as an experiencef and consciousness conceived as the perception of an object? In my booklet I set forth these differences at length (130-34), but for present purposes it will be sufficient, perhaps, to select the fourth difference (ad) out of six, namely, that if consciousness is conceived as an experience there is a psychological subject, while if consciousness is conceived as the perception of an object there is no psychological subject. To establish this point I shall begin by indicating one manner in which the notion of conscientia-perceptio may arise; I shall next point out the defect in this notion; thirdly, I shall indicate the essentially opposed character of conscientia-experientia; and finally I shall turn to Fr Perego's objections. (Fs)

164a Consider, then, the two propositions, John knows his dog, John knows himself. In both, the subject is John. In the first, the object is John's dog. In the second, the object is John himself. It follows that knowing is of two kinds: there is direct knowing in which the object is not the subject; there is reflexive knowing in which the object is the subject. Name reflexive knowing consciousness. Define the subject as the object of consciousness. Then it cannot be disputed, it seems, that consciousness is a reflexive knowing, for in consciousness the knower himself is known; and it cannot be disputed, it seems, that the subject is the object of consciousness, for whatever is known is an object. Nothing, it seems, could be simpler or clearer or more evident. (Fs)

164b Still, it may be well to attend to a difficulty that could be raised. A cognitive act exercises no constitutive effect upon its object;8 it simply reveals what the object already is; it exercises no transforming power over the object in its proper reality, but simply and solely manifests what that proper reality is. Accordingly, if consciousness is knowledge of an object, it can have no constitutive effect upon its object; it can only reveal its object as it was in its proper reality prior to the occurrence of the cognitive act or function named consciousness. (Fs)

164c Thus, to illustrate this aspect of conscientia-perceptio, if without consciousness John is simply a prime substance (such as this man or this horse) then by consciousness John is merely revealed to himself as a prime substance. Again, if without consciousness John has no other psychological unity beyond the unity found in the objects of his knowledge, then by consciousness John is merely manifested as having no psychological unity beyond the unity found in the objects of his knowledge. Again, if without consciousness John cannot possibly be the conscious subject of physical pain, then by consciousness John is merely manifested as being incapable of suffering. Similarly, if without consciousness John cannot be the consciously intelligent or the consciously rational or the consciously free or the consciously responsible principle of his own intelligent, rational, free, or responsible acts, then by consciousness as knowledge of an object John merely knows himself as neither consciously intelligent, nor consciously rational, nor consciously free, nor consciously responsible.h (Fs)

165a My difficulty, then, with the simple, clear, and evident view, which I named conscientia-perceptio, is that it is simpliste. It takes account of the fact that by consciousness the subject is known by the subject. It overlooks the fact that consciousness is not merely cognitive but also constitutive. It overlooks as well the subtler fact that consciousness is cognitive, not of what exists without consciousness, but of what is constituted by consciousness. For consciousness does not reveal a prime substance; it reveals a psychological subject that subsequently may be subsumed, and subsumed correctly, under the category of prime substance. Similarly, consciousness does not reveal the psychological unity that is known in the field of objects; it constitutes and reveals the basic psychological unity of the subject as subject. In like manner, consciousness not merely reveals us as suffering but also makes us capable of suffering; and similarly it pertains to the constitution of the consciously intelligent subject of intelligent acts, the consciously rational subject of rational acts, the consciously free subject of free acts, and the consciously responsible subject of responsible acts. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Subjekt; Bewusstsein: conscientia-experientia; unumquodque cognoscitur secundum quod est actu;

Kurzinhalt: On this view the subject in act and his act are constituted and, as well, they are known simultaneously and concomitantly with the knowledge of objects; for the sensibile actu is the sensus actu, and the intelligibile actu is the intellectus actu.

Textausschnitt: 165b How, then, can one account for this constitutive function of consciousness? One cannot reject the principle that knowing simply reveals its object; one cannot suppose that knowing exercises a constitutive effect upon its object. It is true that the mode of the knowing may and does differ from the mode of the reality known. But it is fantastic to suggest that knowing an object changes the mode of reality in the object. (Fs) (notabene)

165c The alternative, I suggest, is to deny that consciousness is a matter of knowing an object; the alternative is to deny that only objects are known; the alternative is to reject the tacit assumption that unumquodque cognoscitur secundem quod est obiectum, and to put in its place the familiar axiom that unumquodque cognoscitur secundum quod est actu. On the basis of this axiom, one can assert that whenever there is a sensibile actu or an intelligibile actu, an object is known; and whenever there is a sensus actu or an intellectus actu, the subject and his act are known. On this view the subject in act and his act are constituted and, as well, they are known simultaneously and concomitantly with the knowledge of objects; for the sensibile actu is the sensus actu, and the intelligibile actu is the intellectus actu. Again, on this view the object is known as id quod intenditur, the subject is known as is qui intendit, and the act is known both as the intendere of the subject and the intendi that regards the object.14 (Fs) (notabene)

footnote 14:
14 Consciousness, accordingly, is not to be confused with reflexive activity. The ordinary operations of intellect are attending, inquiring, understanding, conceiving, doubting, weighing the evidence, judging. Their objects may be either the self or other things. In the former case they are named reflexive; in the latter, direct. This difference is not formal but material; in both cases the formal objects are ens, quidditas, verum. Now by both direct and reflexive operations the subject in act is constituted and known, not as object, but as subject; this constitutive knowing and being known is consciousness. Hence, in direct activity the subject is known once, and as subject; but in reflexive activity the subject is known twice, as subject by consciousness, and as object by the reflexive activity. Finally, there is a functional relation between consciousness and reflexive activity: just as the data for direct activity are supplied by sense, so the data for reflexive activity are supplied by consciousness. Hence, just as I think of 'this' by a backward reference to sense,1 so I think of T by a backward reference to the conscious subject; in both cases one is thinking of the particular; and we think of particulars, not because we understand particularity, but because our inquiry and understanding suppose and regard data. Similarly, just as our judgments about material things involve a verification of concepts in the data of sense, so our judgments about our feelings, our minds, our wills involve a verification of concepts in the data of consciousness. It was this parallelism in function that led me to speak of conscientia-experientia.

166a On this position, which for other reasons I named conscientia-experientia, the constitutive as well as the cognitive aspects of consciousness are satisfied. For cognitive acts certainly constitute a prime substance as actually knowing sensible and intelligible objects; on the view I favor, they also constitute the prime substance as consciously sentient, consciously intelligent, consciously the one principle of many acts, consciously rational when one act supplies the known reason that motivates another act, consciously free when one act is the principle of other alternative acts, consciously responsible when the consciously free subject knows by other acts the consequences of his free choices.1 (Fs)

166b Such, then, is one difference between conscientia-perceptio and conscientia-experientia. It remains that we listen to Fr Perego's objections. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: intelligere; Verstehen: formales Objekt, Formalobjekt (Sein) - materiales Objekt (Materialobjekt; proper object); Paradox des endlichen Intellekts

Kurzinhalt: Besides the proper object of human intellect, there is its formal object. The proper object pertains to human intellect as human, as specifically different from other types of intellect. The formal object pertains to human intellect as intellect, ...

Textausschnitt: 176a Ninthly, a hypothetical reader may interpose that he too finds quite odd my meaning when I employ such terms as intelligere, quidditas, quid sit, quidditative, and even ens. (Fs)

176b Reply: The act that occurs when the teacher teaches and the learner learns is from the teacher and in the learner; it is named understanding, intelligere. It occurs frequently in the intelligent and rarely in the slow-witted. When it has occurred, one finds things clear; when it has not, one finds things obscure; thus one and the same mathematical theorem can be a masterpiece of elegance to one man and an insoluble puzzle to another. Further, once a man has understood, he no longer needs the teacher; he can operate on his own; he can repeat similar and cognate acts of understanding with ease, promptitude, and pleasure; he has an acquired habit. (Fs) (notabene)

176c The object of the act of understanding is the intelligible; the intelligible is expressed in concepts, but its basic occurrence is prior to the occurrence of the concept. When one finds things obscure, one cannot conceive them, define them, think them; they are for one, unless one is modest, inconceivable, indefinite, unthinkable. Hence, before one can conceive, one must understand; and, of course, unless one is rash, before one can judge, one must both understand and conceive. (Fs)

176d The intelligible, grasped by human understanding, is known in the sensible, in what is imagined; it is the ground of universal concepts; nonetheless, it is related intrinsically to the concrete. Such intelligible-in-the-sensible is the proper object of human intellect; it is proper in two senses: first, in the sense that man in this life understands no intelligible whatever except as a derivative of that proper object, and secondly, in the sense that no pure spirit has as its proper object, its basic source of all intelligibility, the intelligible-in-the-sensible. (Fs)

176e Besides the proper object of human intellect, there is its formal object. The proper object pertains to human intellect as human, as specifically different from other types of intellect. The formal object pertains to human intellect as intellect, as having something in common with every type of intellect. This formal object of intellect is being, where being means everything. The fact that being, everything, is the formal object of human intellect cannot be demonstrated by showing that man does understand everything. But it is clear from the fact that man wants to understand everything about everything, that to answer any number of questions is only to invite more questions, that man's intellect does not come to a complacent stop until it understands everything about everything. Again, the same point can be made negatively. If the formal object of human intellect were not being, then it would be some genus; and if it were a genus, then intellect would be completely confined to that genus, as sight is to color, and hearing is to sound; but human intellect is not completely confined to any genus; it can raise questions about absolutely everything that exists or even could exist, and so it cannot be completely confined to some single genus. (Fs)

177a Now human intellect is not the only intellect. Each different type of intellect has its own proper object. But there can be only one intellect in which the proper object is also the formal object. For when the proper object is also the formal object of an intellect, then its natural act of understanding is infinite; it understands in act itself and, as well, everything else that does exist or could exist; such unrestricted understanding must be God, the principle and end of all actual being and, as well, the ground of all possible being. (Fs)

177b There results the well-known paradox of finite intellect. Because its formal object is being, it is orientated towards infinite understanding; and without this orientation, it would not be an intellect. Because it is finite, it cannot be infinite understanding; for that would be a contradiction in terms; and so its proper object must differ from its formal object. Further, it cannot be said that finite understanding, while it is not infinite, nonetheless has an exigence for the infinite. If one says 'exigence,' one means necessity or one means nothing; but so far from being necessary, it is impossible for the finite either to be or to become the infinite; what necessarily is infinite, already is infinite; and what is not infinite cannot become infinite, for the infinite cannot become. Nor does the revealed mystery of the vision of God change things in the least, for not even the beatific vision of Christ is an act of understanding everything about everything;1 and so not even in Christ is the alleged exigence fulfilled. (Fs)

177c If the meaning of the foregoing has been understood,1 it is not difficult to learn the words. One has only to read St Thomas and understand what is said. An intellect completely in act with respect to being is God.2 The proper object of our intellects is 'quidditas sive natura in materia corporali existens'.3 God is not a material substance, and so we do not know quid sit Deus.4 God is being, and since we do not know quid sit Deus, we do not know quid sit ens; in both cases our knowledge is analogical.5 We naturally desire to know quid sit Deus; actually knowing it, however, is perfect beatitude, natural to God alone, beyond the natural capacity and the natural will of any possible creature.6 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Titel: Collection: Papers bei B. Lonergan

Stichwort: Christus: Bewusstsein -> quid sit homo - quid sit Deus (visio beatifica)

Kurzinhalt: By consciousness we are aware of ourselves but we do not understand our natures; because we know ourselves only sub ratione experti, we wonder what we are; and that wonder gives place to knowledge ...

Textausschnitt: 178a Tenthly, to return from the hypothetical reader to Fr Perego, he advances that there is an obscurity in my view of the relationship between Christ's human consciousness and Christ's beatific vision.1 (Fs)

178b Reply: I grant that the relationship is quite obscure if one is unfamiliar with the meaning of the question, quid sit, and also with the admiration that is the origin of all science and all philosophy. Otherwise, the relationship is plain as a pikestaff. By consciousness we are aware of ourselves but we do not understand our natures; because we know ourselves only sub ratione experti, we wonder what we are; and that wonder gives place to knowledge when we understand quid sit homo. But Christ as man was similar to us in all things save sin. He was aware of himself by consciousness, yet by that consciousness he did not know quid sit; moreover, since he had two natures, he had a twofold wonder, quid sit homo and quid sit Deus; the answer to the second was the beatific vision. (Fs) (notabene)

179a Let us end this section on the notion of the subject. My contention was that consciousness is not only cognitive but also constitutive of the subject. My contention was that an adequate account of consciousness is had by making more explicit the familiar Aristotelian-Thomist doctrine of the identity in act of subject and object.50 Perhaps the reader will agree with me when I say (1) that Fr Perego does not seem to know what consciousness is and (2) that his many objections are just solvMlia argumenta. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Prämisse: Glaube als Grundlage jeder Kooperation; kultureller Wandel (Krise);

Kurzinhalt: ... in times of great social and cultural change, beliefs too are changing and, because they are only beliefs, because they are not personally acquired knowledge, such change leaves believers at a loss

Textausschnitt: 89f I have been characterizing belief. I have said it is a necessary condition if man's coming to know is to be a group enterprise, if it is to be increased and accelerated by a division of labor. I also have said that belief accounts for a major portion in the knowledge both of the man of common sense and of the individual scientist. I have submitted that the difference between science and common sense lies not in the proportion of belief but in the control of belief. (Fs)

90a I have now to draw closer to my topic and I do so by noting that in times of little social or cultural change, beliefs are stable and little open to question, but in times of great social and cultural change, beliefs too are changing and, because they are only beliefs, because they are not personally acquired knowledge, such change leaves believers at a loss. They are disorientated. They do not know which way to turn. They feel that all they have taken for granted is menaced. They may be tempted to unbelief as a liberation or, again, they may dread it as destructive of truly human living. (Fs) (notabene)

90b Such is a major premiss, and I have only to add a minor to conclude to the contemporary issue, the contemporary disease with regard to belief. The minor is that ours is a time of great social and cultural change and, further, that this is being experienced more particularly by Catholics. (Fs)

90c First, then, ours is a time of great social change. The relation of man to nature has been transformed by the discoveries of natural science, the flood of inventions, the know-how of technicians, die enterprise of industrialists, businessmen, financiers. Earlier ways of living have been disrupted by urbanism, increasing longevity, a population explosion, built-in obsolescence, mobility, detached and functional relations between persons, universal, prolonged and continuing education, instantaneous information, increasing leisure and travel, perpetually available entertainment. There is a distinctive meaning conveyed by the phrase "modern living." It connotes a varying set of more or less established innovations in the family and in manners, in society and in education, in the state and in the law, in the economy and in technology, in the Churches and the sects. The older one is, the more lively one's memory, the more easily will one recall the many manners in which our way of living has changed in the course of the present century. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Kultur; Metastrukur (superculture); Unterschied: klassische - moderne Kultur (normativ - empirisch); Zeit der Verwirrung

Kurzinhalt: A basic difference, then, lies in the mere size of the superstructure ... We as a group are immeasurably richer but as individuals we have immeasurably more that we can know only by believing.

Textausschnitt: 91a But besides a way of living, the social, there is also the cultural, and by the "cultural" I would denote the meaning we find in our present way of life, the value we place upon it, or, again, the things we find meaningless, stupid, wicked, horrid, atrocious, disastrous. (Fs)
91b In its immediacy the cultural is the meaning already present in the dream before it is interpreted, the meaning in a work of art before it is articulated by the critic, the endless shades of meaning in everyday speech, the intersubjective meanings of smile and frown, tone and gesture, evasion and silence, the passionate meanings of love and hatred, of high achievement and wrathful destruction. (Fs)

91c But besides the meaning and value immediately intuited, felt, spoken, acted out, there is to any advanced culture a superstructure. To art and literature there are added criticism. To artisans and craftsmen there are added inventors and technicians. To common sense there is added science. To the proverbs of wise men there are added the reflections of philosophers. Industry and commerce are complicated by economics, togetherness by sociology, the state by political theory, the law by jurisprudence, man's body by medicine and his mind by psychiatry, schools by educational theories, and religions by theologies. Besides the meanings and values immanent in everyday living there is an enormous process in which meanings are elaborated and values are discerned in a far more reflective, deliberate, critical fashion. (Fs)

91d I have been presenting a notion of culture and, if I am to characterize contemporary cultural change, I must briefly compare modern culture with its classicist predecessor. (Fs)

91e A basic difference, then, lies in the mere size of the superstructure. Our age is an age of specialization for other reasons, of course, but also out of sheer necessity. Modern mathematics, modern physics, modern chemistry are just too vast for any of them to be mastered entirely by a single mind. What holds of them, also holds to a greater or less extent in other fields. Today the renaissance ideal of the uomo universale, master of every art and science, would be a mere figment of the imagination. But in the classicist period the modern sciences were in their infancy, and there existed a liberal education that enabled anyone so inclined to assimilate the substance of the cultural superstructure and to follow intelligently and critically the work of pioneers. We as a group are immeasurably richer but as individuals we have immeasurably more that we can know only by believing. (Fs) (notabene)

92a Again, classicist culture contrasted itself with barbarism. It was culture with a capital "C." Others might participate in it to a greater or less extent and, in the measure they did so, they ceased to be barbarians. In other words culture was conceived normatively. It was a matter of good manners and good taste, of grace and style, of virtue and character, of models and ideals, of eternal verities and inviolable laws. (Fs)

92b But the modern notion of culture is not normative but empirical. Culture is a general notion. It denotes something found in every people, for in every people there is some apprehension of meaning and value in their way of life. So it is that modern culture is the culture that knows about other cultures, that relates them to one another genetically, that knows all of them to be man-made. Far more open than classicist culture, far better informed, far more discerning, it lacks the convictions of its predecessor, its clear-cut norms, its elemental strength. (Fs)

92c Classicist culture was stable. It took its stand on what ought to be, and what ought to be is not to be refuted by what is. It legislated with its eye on the substance of things, on the unchanging essence of human living and, while it never doubted either that circumstances alter cases or that circumstances change, still it also was quite sure that essences did not change, that change affected only the accidental details that were of no great account. So its philosophy was perennial philosophy, its classics were immortal works of art, its religion and ethics enshrined the wisdom of the ages, its laws and its tribunals the prudence of mankind. (Fs)

93a Classicist culture, by conceiving itself normatively and universally, also had to think of itself as the one and only culture for all time. But modern culture is culture on the move. It is historicist. Because human cultures are man-made, they can be changed by man. They not only can but also should be changed. Modern man is not concerned simply to perpetuate the wisdom of his ancestors. For him the past is just the springboard to the future and the future, if it is to be good, will improve on all that is good in the past and it will liquidate all that is evil. (Fs)

93b The classicist was aware that men individually are responsible for the lives they lead. Modern man is aware that men collectively are responsible for the world in which they lead them. (Fs)

93c So a contemporary humanism is dynamic. It holds forth not an ideal of fixity but a programme of change. It was or is the automatic progress of the liberal, the dialectical materialism of the Marxist, the identification of cosmogenesis and christogenesis by Pierre Teilhard de Chardin. Ours is a time that criticizes and debunks the past, that preaches an ideology, that looks forward to an Utopia. (Fs)

93d It also is a time of confusion, for there are many voices, many of them shrill, and most of them contradictory. (Fs)

93e Such a time of confusion, as I have said, calls beliefs into question and, because they are just beliefs, because they are not personally generated knowledge, answers are hard to come by. So to confusion there are easily added disorientation, disillusionment, crisis, surrender, unbelief. But, as I also said, from the present situation Catholics are suffering more keenly than others, not indeed because their plight is worse, but because up to Vatican II they were sheltered against the modern world and since Vatican II they have been exposed more and more to the chill winds of modernity. Let me briefly explain why this is so. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Moderne Kultur - Kirche, Theologie; moderne Wissenschaft - Frage nach Gott -> Lonergan: Einsicht

Kurzinhalt: But only belatedly has it come to acknowledge that the world of the classicist no longer exists and that the only world in which it can function is the modern world ... Since the beginning of the eighteenth century Christianity has been under attack.

Textausschnitt: 93f Always in the past it had been the Catholic tradition to penetrate and to christianize the social fabric and the culture of the age. So it entered into the Hellenistic world of the patristic period. So it was one of the principal architects of medieval society and medieval thought. So too it was almost scandalously involved in the Renaissance. But only belatedly has it come to acknowledge that the world of the classicist no longer exists and that the only world in which it can function is the modern world. (Fs)

94a To a great extent this failure is to be explained by the fact that modern developments were covered over with a larger amount of wickedness. Since the beginning of the eighteenth century Christianity has been under attack. Agnostic and atheistic philosophies have been developed and propagated. The development of the natural and of the human sciences was such that they appeared and often were said to support such movements. The emergence of the modern languages with their new literary forms was not easily acclaimed when they contributed so little to devotion and so much, it seemed, to worldliness and irreligion. The new industry spawned slums, the new politics revolutions, the new discoveries unbelief. One may lament it but one can hardly be surprised that at the beginning of this century, when churchmen were greeted with a heresy that logically entailed all possible heresies, they named the new monster modernism. (Fs) (notabene)

94b If their opposition to wickedness made churchmen unsympathetic to modern ways, their classicism blocked their vision. They were unaware that modern science involved quite a different notion of science from that entertained by Aristotle. When they praised science and affirmed the Church's support for science, what they meant to praise and support was true and certain knowledge of things through their causes. (Fs)

94c But modern science is not true and certain; it is just probable. It is not fully knowledge; it is hypothesis, theory, system, the best available opinion. It regards not things but data, phenomena. While it still speaks of causes, what it means is not end, agent, matter, form, but correlation. (Fs)

95a Further, this new notion of science introduced radically new problems in philosophy. In Aristotelian physics one ascended from the earth to the heavens and beyond the heavens to the first mover. There was no logical break between knowledge of this world and knowledge of ultimate causes. (Fs)
95b But modern science is specialized. It is knowledge of this world and only of this world. It proceeds from data and to data it adds only verifiable hypotheses. But God is not a datum of human experience for, in this life, we do not know God face to face. Again, between this world and God there is no relationship that can be verified, for verification can occur only between data, only with regard to objects that lie within this world and so can present us with data. (Fs)

95c Now no one will be surprised that modern science, precisely because it is methodically geared to knowledge of this world, cannot yield knowledge of God. But we come to the catch when we ask the further questions. How do we know about God? What do we mean by God? Anything else we know or talk about is known or meant through experience, understanding, and judgment, where judgment rests on some type of verification. Knowledge of God, then, is a singular case. It is not immediate knowledge: there are no data on the divine itself. It is not verifiable knowledge: there are no verifiable hypotheses or principles without data. What kind of knowledge, then, is it?

95d Now I believe that question can be answered and I attempted to do so in a book, Insight. But I wish to draw your attention to the nature of the question. It is not a question that could be asked about knowledge at any time or place; on the contrary it is a question that arises only after modern science has been developed. So, if one wishes to meet that question, one will not talk metaphysics and, muchless, will one talk medieval metaphysics. But the classicist did not advert to the real novelty of modern science, and so he could not conclude to the real novelty in modern philosophic problems and, particularly, in the problems concerning God. (Fs)

96a There was a further blind spot. I have already noted that the classicist conceives culture not empirically but normatively and that this approach leads him to exaggerate the stability and the universality of his culture. Now this exaggeration had the gravest consequences for theology, for it precluded any proper sense of history and, indeed, it did so precisely when historical studies of religion and theology were undergoing their greatest development. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Moderne Wissenschaft: Abwesenheit Gottes; endgültiger Bruch: Forderung der Verifikation von Daten (Newton; anders bei: Anselm, Thomas, Descartes)

Kurzinhalt: Still Descartes did not attempt to separate philosophy and science; on the contrary, ... Such a separation was effected materially when Newton did for mechanics what Euclid had done for geometry. It was effected formally by the rule that, ...

Textausschnitt: 107a I have been attempting to characterize the reflexive, objectifying superstructure in modern culture, and I may now draw closer to my topic and observe that the modern notion of science tends to replace theology, which treats of God and all other things in their relation to God, with religious studies, which treat of man in his supposed dealings with God or gods or goddesses. (Fs)

107b For a modern science is an empirical science. Whether it studies nature or man, whether it is orientated by behaviorism or by the Geisteswissenschaften, it begins from data, it discerns intelligible unities and relationships within data, and it is subject to the check of verification, to the correction and revision to be effected by confrontation with further relevant data. Now such procedures cannot lead one beyond this world. The divine is not a datum to be observed by sense or to be uncovered by introspection. Nor will any intelligible unity or relationship verifiable within such data lead us totally beyond such data to God. Precisely because modern science is specialized knowledge of man and of nature, it cannot include knowledge of God. God is neither man nor nature. It would only be the idolatry of identifying God with man or with nature if one attempted to know God through the methods of modern science. (Fs)

107c Religion, however, is very human. So we have histories of religion, phenomenologies of religion, psychologies of religion, sociologies of religion, philosophies of religion and, to unite these many parts into a whole, the science of religion. These disciplines cannot, of course, escape the radical dilemma confronting modern science. In the measure that they follow the model provided by natural science, they tend towards a reductionism that empties human living and especially human religion of all serious content. In the measure that they insist on their specific difference from the natural sciences, they risk losing their autonomy and becoming the captive of some fashion or fad in philosophy. But whichever way they tend, at least this much is certain: they cannot make scientific statements about God. As long as they remain within the boundaries specified by the methods of a modern science, they cannot get beyond describing and explaining the multiplicity and the variety of human religious attitudes. (Fs)

108a God, then, is absent from modern science. Even the modern science of religion, though it bears witness to the divine, speaks not of God but of man. This, of course, is simply the inevitable result of specialization, of distinguishing different fields of investigation, of working out appropriate methods in each field, and of excluding conflicts of methodical precepts by pursuing different subjects separately. In the writings of St. Anselm there is no systematic distinction between theology and philosophy, and so his ontological argument is not what later would be desired, a strictly philosophic argument. In the writings of St. Thomas philosophy and theology are distinguished, but the distinction does not lead to a separation; so his celebrated five ways occur within a theological Summa. With Descartes occurs the effort to provide philosophy with its proper and independent foundations, and so not only to distinguish but also separate philosophy and theology. Still Descartes did not attempt to separate philosophy and science; on the contrary, he attempted to prove the conservation of momentum by appealing to the immutability of God. Such a separation was effected materially when Newton did for mechanics what Euclid had done for geometry. It was effected formally by the rule that, if a hypothesis is not verifiable, it is not scientific. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Moderne Wissenschaft (Kultur) - Theologie; Krise der Theologie (5 Gründe; Lonergans persönliche Meinung); Dogma: Schwierigkeit der Begründung

Kurzinhalt: ... one would expect it to enable modern theology to speak of God all the more fully and effectively ... But a new integration ... is not yet plainly in sight

Textausschnitt: 108b But if increasing specialization prevents modern science from speaking of God, one would expect it to enable modern theology to speak of God all the more fully and effectively. However, while I hope and labor that this will be so, I have to grant that it is not yet achieved. Contemporary theology and especially contemporary Catholic theology are in a feverish ferment. An old theology is being recognized as obsolete. There is a scattering of new theological fragments. But a new integration-and by this I mean, not another integration of the old type, but a new type of integration-is not yet plainly in sight. Let me describe the situation briefly under five headings. (Fs)

109a First, the modern science or discipline of religious studies has undercut the assumptions and antiquated the methods of a theology structured by Melchior Cano's De locis theologicis. Such a theology was classicist in its assumptions. Truth is eternal. Principles are immutable. Change is accidental. But religious studies deal meticulously with endless matters of detail. They find that the expressions of truth and the enunciations of principles are neither eternal nor immutable. They concentrate on the historical process in which these changes occur. They bring to light whole ranges of interesting facts and quite new types of problems. In brief, religious studies have stripped the old theology of its very sources in Scripture, in patristic writings, in medieval and subsequent religious writers. They have done so by subjecting the sources to a fuller and more penetrating scrutiny than had been attempted by earlier methods. (Fs)

109b Secondly, there is the new demythologization of Scripture. The old demythologization took place at the end of the second century. It consisted in rejecting the Bible's anthropomorphic conception of God. It may be summed up in Clement of Alexandria's statement: "Even though it is written, one must not so much think of the Father of all as having a shape, as moving, as standing or seated or in a place, as having a right hand or a left."1 Now to this old philosophic critique of biblical statement there has been added a literary and historical critique that puts radical questions about the composition of the gospels, about the infancy narratives, the miracle stories, the sayings attributed to Jesus, the accounts of his resurrection, the origins of Pauline and Joannine theologoumena. (Fs)

109c Thirdly, there is the thrust of modern philosophy. Theologians not only repeat the past but also speak to people of today. The old theology was content, for the most part, to operate with technical concepts derived from Greek and medieval thought. But the concreteness of modern science has imposed a similar concreteness on much modern philosophy. Historicism, phenomenology, personalism, existentialism belong to a climate utterly different from that of the per se subject with his necessary principles or processes and his claims to demonstration. Moreover, this movement of philosophy towards concreteness and especially to the concreteness of human living has brought to light a host of notions, approaches, procedures, that are proving very fertile and illuminating in theology. (Fs)

110a Fourthly, there is the collapse of Thomism. In the thirties it seemed still in the ascendant. After the war it seemed for a while to be holding its ground. Since Vatican II it seems to have vanished. Aquinas still is a great and venerated figure in the history of Catholic thought. But Aquinas no longer is thought of or appealed to as an arbiter in contemporary Catholic thought. Nor is the sudden change really surprising. For the assumption on which Thomism rested was typically classicist. It supposed the existence of a single perennial philosophy that might need to be adapted in this or that accidental detail but in substance remained the repository of human wisdom, a permanent oracle, and, like Thucydides' history, a possession for all time. In fact, there are a perennial materialism and a perennial idealism as well as a perennial realism. They all shift and change from one age to the next, for the questions they once treated become obsolete and the methods they employed are superseded. (Fs) (notabene)

110b Fifthly, there is a notable softening, if not weakening, of the dogmatic component once so prominent in Catholic theology. Nor can this be described as simply the correction of a former exaggeration, the advent of charity, ecumenism, dialogue, in place of less pleasant attitudes. The new philosophies are not capable of grounding objective statements about what really is so. (Fs)

111a Further it is not only dogmas that are at stake, for it is not only dogmas that lie outside the range of a modern science. Not only every statement about God but also every statement about scientific method, about hermeneutics, about historiography, supposes a reflective procedure quite distinct from the direct procedures sanctioned by the success of modern science. (Fs)
111b To conclude, Catholic theology at present is at a critical juncture. If I may express a personal view, I should say that the contemporary task of assimilating the fruits both of religious studies and of the new philosophies, of handling the problems of demythologization and of the possibility of objective religious statement, imposes on theology the task of recasting its notion of theological method in the most thoroughgoing and profound fashion. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Moderne Kultur: Abwesenheit Gottes im Alltagsleben; Metastruktur: Simplifizierung; Pierre Teilhard; Dialektik; Ablehnung des Modernismus - unkritische Annahme moderner Positionen;
aggiomamento

Kurzinhalt: ... there is the reinterpretation of man in his world. This reinterpretation primarily occurs in the cultural superstructure ... But it is not confined to the superstructure. It is popularized, schematized, simplified

Textausschnitt: 111c I have been speaking, not of the whole of modern culture, not of its most vital part, but of its superstructure. I have said that God is absent from modern science precisely because such science systematically and exclusively is directed to knowledge of this world. Further I have said that Catholic theology is going through an unsettling period of transition in which older procedures are being repudiated and newer ones yield only incomplete and fragmentary benefits. But I have yet to ask whether God is absent not from the superstructure of modern culture but from the everyday, familiar domain of feeling, insight, judgment, decision. (Fs)

111d On this more concrete level modern culture involves a reinterpretation of man and his world, a transformation of the ordering of society and of the control over nature, and a new sense of power and of responsibility. All three have a bearing on the absence of God in modern culture. (Fs)

112a First, there is the reinterpretation of man in his world. This reinterpretation primarily occurs in the cultural superstructure, in the natural and the human sciences, in philosophy, history, and theology. But it is not confined to the superstructure. It is popularized, schematized, simplified. It is transposed from technical statement through simile and metaphor, image and narrative, catch-phrase and slogan, to what can be understood without too much effort and is judged to be, for practical purposes, sufficiently accurate. (Fs) (notabene)

112b Now it is quite conceivable that in a process of great cultural change all parts of the superstructure should keep in step and the popularizations of the several parts should be coherent. Such, however, has not been the transition from classicist to modern culture. For, in the first place, the classicist believed that he could escape history, that he could encapsulate culture in the universal, the normative, the ideal, the immutable, that, while times would change, still the changes necessarily would be minor, accidental, of no serious significance. In the second place, the classicist judged modern science in the light of the Aristotelian notion of science and by that standard found it wanting, for modern science does not proceed from self-evident, necessary principles and it does not demonstrate conclusions from such principles. In the third place, classicist churchmen found that the natural sciences frequently were presented in a reductionist version that was materialistic and, if not atheistic, at least agnostic, while the historical sciences were the locus of continuous attacks on traditional views of the Church in its origins and throughout its development. In brief, so far were churchmen from acknowledging the distinctive character of modern culture that they regarded it as an aberration that had to be resisted and overcome. When they were confronted with a heresy, which they considered to be the sum and substance of all heresy, they named it modernism. So far were they from seeking to enrich modern culture with a religious interpretation that they had only mistrust for a Pierre Teilhard de Chardin. (Fs) (notabene)

113b Besides its reinterpretation of man in his world, modern culture transforms man's control over nature and in consequence involves a reordering of society. The new scene is one of technology, automation, built-in obsolescence, a population explosion, increasing longevity, urbanism, mobility, detached and functional relations between persons, universal, prolonged, and continuing education, increasing leisure and travel, instantaneous information, and perpetually available entertainment. In this ever changing scene God, when not totally absent, appears an intruder. To mention him, if not meaningless, seems to be irrelevant. The greatest of financial powers, the power to increase gross national income by taxing and spending for worthy purposes, is restricted to non-religious ends, so that pluralism is given lip-service while secularism is the religion-or, perhaps, the anti-religion-by law established. At the same time, a rigorously codified religious organization finds itself ever less capable of moving with ever fluid situations, [...]

115a Now this concern with the future of humanity is a concern for humanity in this world; so it has been thought to be purely secular. Such a conclusion is, I believe, mistaken. It is true that concern for the future is incompatible with a blind traditionalism, but a blind traditionalism is not the essence of religion. It is true that concern for the future will work itself out by human means, by drawing on human experience, human intelligence, human judgment, human decision, but again this is quite compatible with a profoundly religious attitude. It was St. Ignatius Loyola who gave the advice: act as though results depended exclusively on you, but await the results as though they depended entirely on God. What is false is that human concern for the future can generate a better future on the basis of individual and group egoism. For to know what is truly good and to effect it calls for a self-transcendence that seeks to benefit not self at the cost of the group, not the group at the cost of mankind, not present mankind at the cost of mankind's future. Concern for the future, if it is not just high-sounding hypocrisy, supposes rare moral attainment. It calls for what Christians name heroic charity. In the measure that Christians practise and radiate heroic charity they need not fear they will be superfluous either in the task of discerning man's true good in this life or in the task of bringing it about. (Fs)

116a I have been speaking of the absence of God in modern culture. I have dwelt at length on the many ways in which he is absent both in the superstructure and on the day-to-day level of that culture. But every absence is also a potential presence, not indeed in the sense that the past is to be restored, but in the sense that our creativity has to discover the future and our determination has to realize it. Nor is God's presence only potential. Evidently, almost palpably, it is actual. Pope John spoke to the whole world. Vatican II stirred it profoundly. For the Spirit of God is moving the hearts of many and, in Paul Tillich's phrase, ultimate concern has grasped them. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Dogmatische Konstitution Dei Filius: Schwierigkeit der Annahme (7 Gründe)

Kurzinhalt: Difficulties with this doctrine are widespread today and they are not confined to those outside the church. A first question would be about the relevance of the doctrine.

Textausschnitt: 119b Difficulties with this doctrine are widespread today and they are not confined to those outside the church. A first question would be about the relevance of the doctrine. It springs from what seems to be an excessive objectivism, an objectivism that just leaves subjects out of account. It tells what can be done by the natural light of human reason, but it does not commit itself either to saying that the possibility ever was realized or to predicting that it ever would be realized. A contemporary would want to know what there is about this possibility that makes any difference to human life or human society. (Fs)

119c Secondly, the context of the doctrine is the distinction between faith and reason, grace and nature, supernatural and natural. This distinction has a long history in Catholic theology, but that history is complex, abstruse, difficult, Scholastic. A contemporary is quite ready to speak with the Bible and the Fathers about God's grace and man's sinfulness. But he will ask whether things must be complicated with the notion of human nature or the natural light of human reason. (Fs)

119d Thirdly, what the doctrine means is that there exists, at least in principle, some valid and certain argument accessible to the human mind that concludes with an affirmation of God's existence. But any such procedure would treat God as an object. Now for very many today God is not and cannot be an object. Consequently, they would repudiate any attempt to prove God's existence. (Fs) (notabene)

119e Fourthly, there are those that would admit the possibility of establishing the existence of a merely metaphysical object, an ens a se, but they would argue with Max Scheler that God is a person, and that no person can be known as an object but only inter-subjectively through co-operation and, so to speak, co-performance (Mitvollzug).1 (Fs)

120a Fifthly, there are all those very religious persons to whom philosophy means little or nothing. They know about God in a very real way and they know that this knowledge is something quite different from the logical business of premisses and conclusions. With Pascal they will distinguish between the Dieu des philosophes and le Dieu d'Abraham, d'Isaac, et de Jacob. So by a simpler route they reach much the same conclusion as the phenomenologist, Max Scheler. The god concluded from premises is not the God Christians worship. (Fs)

120b Sixthly, in our day the obvious instance of valid knowledge is science. Science is empirical. It proceeds from data and it develops by returning again and again to the data. Moreover, it never adds to data any intelligibility, any unity or relationship, that is not verifiable in the data. Now there are no data on the divine. God is not among the data of sense and he is not among the data of human consciousness. God, then, is not a possible object of modern science. (Fs)

120c Further, there is no verifiable principle by which we might conclude from this world to God's existence. For a principle is verifiable only if there are data on both the terms related by the principle. There are no data on God, and so there are not the data for a principle relating this world to God. Hence, to affirm natural knowledge of God in the contemporary context is to lay oneself open to the question, By what unverifiable principle do you propose to conclude from this world to God's existence?

120d One might answer, By an analytic principle. But then one has to meet the distinction between analytic propositions and analytic principles.2 Analytic propositions are to be achieved by merely verbal definitions. Analytic principles are analytic propositions whose terms in their defined sense have been verified. With this distinction one once more is met by the demand for verifiability. (Fs)

121a Seventhly, ontological and moral judgments pertain to quite different domains. In other words "ought" cannot occur in a conclusion, when "ought" does not occur in the premisses. To state that God is good in the moral sense presupposes moral judgments. Such moral judgments proceed not from an abstract ontology but from a morally good person.3 Now the God of religion is the good God, and his goodness is mysteriously in contrast with the evils and suffering of this world. To acknowledge God as good is not just a conclusion; it is to adopt a whole Weltanschauung; it is to make an existential decision. So once more we come to the conclusion that draws a distinction between the God of the philosophers and the God of religion. (Fs) (notabene)

121b Such, very summarily, are difficulties perhaps commonly felt about the doctrine of natural knowledge of God. I propose to discuss them, not in the order in which I raised them, but in the order that will best serve to clarify the issues. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Konstitution Dei Filius: Objekt (verschiedene Bedeutungen: Kant, Fichte, Lonergan)

Kurzinhalt: So much for a first meaning of the word "object." There is, however, a second quite different meaning. On this view, objects are what are intended in questioning and what become better known as our answers to questions ...

Textausschnitt: 121c First, then let us consider two meanings of the word "object." On the one hand, there is the etymological meaning of the word, which was systematized by Kant, and remains in various subsequent philosophies that have not broken loose from Kant's basic influence. On the other hand, there is the meaning implicit in all discourse: an object is what is intended in questioning and becomes known by answering questions. (Fs)

121d The Greek word for object, to antikeimenon, means what lies opposite. The Latin, obiectum, whence are derived our word "object," the French, objet, the Italian, oggetto, means what is put or set or lies before or opposite. The German, Gegenstand, means what stands opposite. In all cases, then, "object" connotes something sensible, localized, locally related presumably to a spectator or sensitive subject. (Fs)

122a In full accord with the etymological meaning of "object" is one of the key sentences in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. It occurs at the very beginning of the Transcendental Aesthetic, and it asserts that the one way in which our cognitional activities are related to objects immediately is by Anschauung, by intuition. Since for Kant our only intuitions are sensitive, it follows that the categories of the understanding and the ideals of reason of themselves are empty; they refer to objects only mediately, only inasmuch as they are applied to the objects intuited by sense. Accordingly, our cognitional activity is restricted to a world of possible experience and that a world not of metaphysical realities but of sensible phenomena.1 (Fs) (notabene)

122b Substantially the same position recurs in logical atomism, logical positivism, logical empiricism.2 Inasmuch as there is an insistence on the significance of the logical, discourse is admitted. But this admission is restricted by the affirmation of an atomism, positivism, or empiricism, for the only discourse considered meaningful is discourse that can be reduced to, or be verified in, or at least be falsifiable by sensible objects. (Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (25.09.08): Cf. Ockhams Verständnis von Intuition

122c However, the nineteenth and twentieth centuries have witnessed a series of attempts to get beyond Kant and, in one way or another, these attempts have consisted in an insistence on the subject to offset and compensate for Kant's excessive attention to sensible objects. This was already apparent in the absolute idealisms of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. It took a more personal form with Kierkegaard's emphasis on the contingently existing subject and with the emphasis on will in Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. The phenomenological studies of intersubjectivity by Edmund Husserl and Max Scheler and the various forms of existentialism have set up against die objectivist world of impersonal science a not-to-be-objectified inner world of subjects striving for authenticity. (Fs)

123a Now it is clear that God is not and cannot be an object in the etymological sense, in the Kantian sense, in the sense acceptable to a logical atomism, positivism, or empiricism. Moreover, as long as such a notion of object prevails, phenomenology and existentialism may allow us some access to God as a subject to whom we are subjectively orientated. (Our hearts are restless till they rest in thee), but any procedure that regards God as an object will remain excluded. (Fs) (notabene)

123b So much for a first meaning of the word "object." There is, however, a second quite different meaning. On this view, objects are what are intended in questioning and what become better known as our answers to questions become fuller and more accurate. (Fs) (notabene)

123c Objects are what are intended in questioning. What is this intending? It is neither ignorance nor knowledge but die dynamic intermediary between ignorance and knowledge. It is the conscious movement away from ignorance and towards knowledge. When we question, we do not know the answer yet, but already we want the answer. Not only do we want the answer but also we are aiming at what is to be known through the answer. Such, then, is intending and, essentially, it is dynamic. It promotes us from mere experiencing to understanding by asking what and why and how. It promotes us from understanding to truth by asking whether this or that is really so. It promotes us from truth to value by asking whether this or that is truly good or only apparendy good. As answers accumulate, as they correct, complete, qualify one another, knowledge advances. But answers only give rise to still further questions. Objects are never completely, exhaustively known, for our intending always goes beyond present achievement. The greatest achievement, so far from drying up the source of questioning, of intending, only provides a broader base whence ever more questions arise. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Konstitution Dei Filius: Objekt - Gegenstand der Intention (Sein); Verifikation: direkte u. indirekte; Prinzip (2 Bedeutungen)

Kurzinhalt: ... are there principles that do not need to be verified? Here I would distinguish two meanings of the word "principle."

Textausschnitt: 124a Intending then is comprehensive. Though human achievement is limited, still the root dynamism is unrestricted. We would know everything about everything, the whole universe in all its multiplicity and concreteness, omnia, to pan, and, in that concrete and comprehensive sense, being. To that object our cognitional operations are related immediately, not by sensitive intuition, but by questioning. (Fs) (notabene)

124b Now if God cannot be an object in the etymological or Kantian or equivalent meanings of the word "object" it would be only a fallacy to conclude that he cannot be an object in the quite different meaning just indicated. Moreover, it has always been in the context, at least implicit, of this meaning that the question of God and arguments for God's existence have been presented. Nor is this meaning of the word "object" limited to philosophers and theologians. On the contrary, every serious scientist that ever existed was concerned with the advancement of science, with coming to know more than at present is known, with the object to which we dynamically are orientated by our questions but which we only partially know. (Fs)

124c Secondly, let us consider the nature of the unverifiable principle by which we proceed from knowledge of this world to knowledge of God. Four points need to be touched upon, namely, What is verification? What principles need to be verified? Are there principles that do not need to be verified? Will these principles take us beyond this world to knowledge of God?

124d First, what is verification? Vulgarly, verification seems to be conceived as a matter of taking a look, of making an observation. In fact, while verification includes observations, it includes not one but indefinitely many, and it includes them within a very elaborate context. That context divides into two parts, direct and indirect verification. Direct verification is a matter of working out the logical presuppositions and implications of a very carefully formulated hypothesis, devising experiments that will yield data that conform or do not conform with the implications of the hypothesis and, when hypotheses conflict, devising crucial experiments that will resolve the conflict. Indirect verification is more massive and, ultimately, more significant. All hypotheses, theories, systems of a science are linked together proximately or remotely in logical interdependence. So, for instance, the law of falling bodies was verified directly by Galileo, but it also has been verified indirectly every time in the last four centuries that that law was among the presuppositions of a successful experiment or a successful application. Similarly, any other law of principle wins an ever securer position by the far-flung and almost continuous process of indirect verification whether in laboratories or in the applications of science to industry. Nonetheless, not even the cumulative evidence assembled by the all but countless observations of direct and prolonged indirect verification suffice to exempt a scientific hypothesis from liability to revision. Unlike the everyday statements of common sense, such as "I now am here speaking to you," they do not meet the requirements for a certain judgment set by the natural light of human reason. They are merely probable, and everyone enjoying the use of the natural light of human reason knows that they are merely probable. (Fs)

125a Incidentally, may I remark that I should like to see greater attention paid by certain types of analytic philosophy to the notable gaps between an observation and a process of verification and, on the other hand, true and certain knowledge. (Fs)

125b Secondly, what needs to be verified? What is the need for verification? It is a need disclosed to us by what Vatican I referred to as the natural light of human reason, by what I should name our power to ask and answer questions. The first type of question, the question for intelligence, asks what or why or how. The question is put with respect to data, but the answer that is sought goes beyond the data; it is not just some other datum but something quite different from data, namely, a possibly relevant intelligible unity or relationship. Such possibly relevant intelligible unities or relationships are grasped by insights and expressed in hypothetical statements. From the nature of the case there arises, then, the further question, Is the possibly relevant unity or relationship the one that is actually relevant to this case or to this type of case? Common sense meets such questions by what I called in my book Insight the self-correcting process of learning. Natural science meets them by the process of direct and indirect verification. (Fs)

126a Thirdly, are there principles that do not need to be verified? Here I would distinguish two meanings of the word "principle." Commonly it is understood as a logically first proposition, an ultimate premiss. More generally, principle has been defined as what is first in any ordered set, primum in aliquo ordine. In this more general sense, an originating power is a principle, and, specifically, our power to ask and answer questions is such an originating power and so a principle. Now obviously this principle, which is the human mind itself, does not need verification for its validation. It is only by the actual use of our minds that any inquiry and any process of verification can be carried out. Hence, every appeal to verification as a source of validation presupposes a prior and more fundamental appeal to the human mind as a source of validation. (Fs) (notabene)

126b However, besides the mind itself, besides our originating power to ask and answer questions, there is the objectification of this power in concepts and principles. Besides the notion of being, which is the intending behind all our questions, there is also the concept of being, which is an objectification of the notion. Besides the native procedures of the mind in asking and answering questions, there is the objectification of these procedures in such principles as identity, contradiction, sufficient reason and, more fully, in logics and methods. Now these objectifications are historically conditioned. They can be incomplete or erroneous, and they can be corrected, revised, developed. Consequently, they have to be scrutinized, checked, verified. But the process of verification appeals, not to the data of sense, but to the data of consciousness, not to any data whatever of consciousness but to the data on the process of asking and answering questions. (Fs)
127a Fourthly, do these principles suffice to take us beyond the visible universe to knowledge of God? The answer to that question depends on the answer to our prior question about knowledge and its object. On Kantian and positivist views our knowledge is confined to a world of experience. On some subjectivist views, while we cannot know God as an object, still we can enter into some subject-to-subject relation with him in religious experience. But if human knowing consists in asking and answering questions, if ever further questions arise, if the further questions are given honest answers then, as I have argued elsewhere at some length, we can and do arrive at knowledge of God.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Selbsttranszendenz (self-transcendence; Selbst-Transzenden): drei Stufen (intellektuelle, moralische, religiöse)

Kurzinhalt: ... the fact remains that the intellectual, the moral, and the religious are three successive stages in a single achievement, the achievement of self-transcendence;

Textausschnitt: 127b If I have said something to clarify the ambiguities of the term "object," and the process, verification, let me now draw attention to the continuity of the intellectual with the moral and the religious, of the mind with the heart. (Fs)

127c Our conscious and intentional operations occur on four interlocked levels. There is a level of experiencing, a level of understanding and conception, a level of reflection and judgment, a level of deliberation and decision. We are moved, promoted from one level to the next by questions; from experiencing to understanding by questions for intelligence; from understanding to judging by questions for reflection; from judging to deciding by questions for deliberation. So the many operations are linked together both on the side of the subject and on the side of the object. On the side of the subject there is the one mind putting the many questions in pursuit of a single goal. On the side of the object there is the gradual cumulation and conjoining of partial elements into a single whole. So insight grasps the intelligibility of what sense perceives. Conception unites what separately sense perceives and intelligence grasps. Judgment pronounces on the truth of the conceiving and on the reality of the conceived. Decision acknowledges the value of actuating potentialities grasped by intelligence and judged to be real. So the transcendentals, the intelligible, the true, the real, the good, apply to absolutely every object for the very good reason that they are grounded in the successive stages in our dealing with objects. But they are one in their root as well as in their application. For the intending subject intends, first of all, the good but to achieve it must know the real; to know the real he must know what is true; to know what is true he must grasp what is intelligible; and to grasp what is intelligible he must attend to the data of sense and to the data of consciousness. (Fs)

128a Now this unity of the human spirit, this continuity in its operations, this cumulative character in their results, seem very little understood by those that endeavor to separate and compartmentalize and isolate the intellectual, the moral, and the religious. They may, of course, be excused inasmuch as the good work they happen to have read is mostly critical while the constructive work they happen to have come across is mostly sloppy. But the fact remains that the intellectual, the moral, and the religious are three successive stages in a single achievement, the achievement of self-transcendence; and so attempts to separate and isolate the intellectual, the moral, and the religious are just so many efforts to distort or to entirely block authentic human development. (Fs)

128b What is the intellectual but an intentional self-transcendence? It is coming to know, not what appears, not what is imagined, not what is thought, not what seems to me to be so, but what is so. To know what is so is to get beyond the subject, to transcend the subject, to reach what would be even if this particular subject happened not to exist. (Fs)

128c Still the self-transcendence of knowledge is merely intentional. With the moral a further step is taken, for by the moral we come to know and to do what is truly good. That is a real self-transcendence, a moving beyond all merely personal satisfactions and interests and tastes and preferences and becoming a principle of benevolence and beneficence, becoming capable of genuine loving. (Fs) (notabene)

129a What, finally, is religion but complete self-transcendence? It is the love of God poured forth in our hearts by the Holy Spirit that is given to us (Rom. 5:5). It is the love in Christ Jesus St. Paul described when he wrote: "For I am convinced that there is nothing in death or life, in the realm of spirits or superhuman powers, in the world as it is or the world as it shall be, in the forces of the universe, in heights or depths-nothing in all creation that can separate us from the love of God in Christ Jesus our Lord" (Rom. 8:38f.). That love is not this or that act of loving but a radical being-in-love, a first principle of all one's thoughts and words and deeds and omissions, a principle that keeps us out of sin, that moves us to prayer and to penance, that can become the ever so quiet yet passionate center of all our living. It is, whatever its degree, a being-in-love that is without conditions or qualifications or reserves, and so it is other-worldly, a being-in-love that occurs within this world but heads beyond it, for no finite object or person can be the object of unqualified, unconditional loving. Such unconditional being-in-love actuates to the full the dynamic potentiality of the human spirit with its unrestricted reach and, as a full actuation, it is fulfilment, deep-set peace, the peace the world cannot give, abiding joy, the joy that remains despite humiliation and failure and privation and pain. (Fs) (notabene)

129a This complete being-in-love, the gift of God's grace, is the reason of the heart that reason does not know. It is a religious experience by which we enter into a subject-to-subject relation with God. It is the eye of faith that discerns God's hand in nature and his message in revelation. It is the efficacious reality that brings men to God despite their lack of learning or their learned errors. It is in this life the crown of human development, grace perfecting nature, the entry of God into the life of man so that man comes to love his neighbor as himself.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Konstitution Dei Filius: Position Lonergans; Unterschied: Gott der Philosophen - Abrahams? quaestio iuris - facti

Kurzinhalt: It is the view that man's spirit, his mind and his heart, is an active power, an eros, for self-transcendence; consequently, the subject is related intrinsically and indeed, constitutively to the object towards which it transcends itself; finally, ...

Textausschnitt: 130a I have been contending, then, that the intellectual, the moral, and the religious are quite distinct but not at all disparate. They are three distinct phases in die unfolding of the human spirit, of that eros for self-transcendence that goes beyond itself intentionally in knowledge, effectively in morality, totally in religion. With the affirmation of this continuity our efforts at basic clarification come to an end, and we turn to meeting explicitly some of the questions that were raised initially but so far have not been treated. (Fs)

130b First, however, let us note very briefly our position. It is not the naive realist, Kantian, positivist view of the object. It is not the mixed view that leaves science to naive realists, Kantians, and positivists to add for humanist or religious reasons an insistence on the subjectivity of the subject. It is the view that man's spirit, his mind and his heart, is an active power, an eros, for self-transcendence; consequently, the subject is related intrinsically and indeed, constitutively to the object towards which it transcends itself; finally, knowledge, morality, and religion are the three distinct phases in which such self-transcendence is realized. (Fs) (notabene)

130c Next, it was asked what is the relevance of the doctrine of natural knowledge of God, what difference does it make to human living and human society. Obviously, I cannot attempt to treat this question in any but a very summary fashion. There are those today for whom any thought about, any mention of, either theism or atheism is just meaningless, for whom all religion at best is just a comforting illusion. Such opinions involve a profound ignorance of man's real nature, and such ignorance cannot but have a gravely distorting effect on the conduct of human affairs. The doctrine of natural knowledge of God means that God lies within the horizon of man's knowing and doing, that religion represents a fundamental dimension in human living. (Fs) (notabene)

131a Thirdly, it was urged that we have to drop the words, "nature," "natural," that we should be content to speak with Scripture and the Fathers of God's grace and man's sinfulness. Now I have no doubt that such words as "nature" and "natural," no less than object and verification, can be abused. But I also have no doubt that if we are not only going to speak about God's grace and man's sinfulness but also we are going to say what precisely we mean by such speaking, then we are going to have to find some third term over and above grace and sin.1 (Fs)

131b Fourthly, can a person be an object? A person cannot be an object if "object" is taken in a naive realist, Kantian, or positivist sense. But if "object" means that towards which self-transcending heads, obviously persons are objects: we know them and we love them. (Fs) (notabene)

131c But, it will be urged, according to Max Scheler, we know other persons only intersubjectively. I would grant that such a conclusion follows from Scheler's cognitional theory but, at the same time, I would point out that, just as we pass from consciousness of the self as subject to an objectification of the self in conception and judging, so too we pass from intersubjectivity to the objectification of intersubjectivity. Not only do we (two subjects in a subject-to-subject relation) speak and act. We speak about ourselves; we act on one another; and inasmuch as we are spoken of or acted on, we are not just subjects, not subjects as subjects, but subjects as objects. (Fs) (notabene)

131d Fifthly, is not philosophy totally different from religion, and is not the God of the philosophers totally different from the God of Abraham, Isaac, Jacob?

131e On my analysis philosophy and religion are quite distinct but they are not totally different; they are two of the three phases of that single thrust by which the human spirit moves towards self-transcendence. What gives rise to the appearance of total difference, I should say, is a failure to distinguish between undifferentiated and differentiated consciousness. Undifferentiated consciousness is global; it is at once intellectual, moral, and religious; it does not sort out different types of issues, specialize now in one type and later in another, seek the integration of separate, specialized developments. Differentiated consciousness results precisely from this process of distinguishing, specializing and, eventually, integrating. As intellectual, it becomes technical. As moral, it concentrates on moral development. As religious, it heads towards mysticism. Now while differentiated consciousness understands undifferentiated, undifferentiated consciousness finds differentiated incomprehensible, totally different; not only does it find the technical aspects of science and philosophy simply alien to its religious piety; it also finds asceticism and mysticism equally or more alien. (Fs)

132a There remains the further question: Is not the God of the philosophers totally different from the God of Abraham, Isaac and Jacob?

132b I am quite ready to grant that there are many mistaken philosophies and many mistaken notions of God. I am also ready to grant that undifferentiated consciousness has very little grasp of any philosophic notion of God, and so would find it impossible to equate the God of its piety with the God of philosophic discourse. Again, I should insist that moral and religious development vastly enrich our relations to God and our apprehension of him; in this respect I am greatly in agreement with Max Scheler and Dietrich von Hildebrand. But I should deny that our intellectual apprehension of any real object, least of all, of God is ever complete, closed, excluding further development. I should deny that the developments from moral and religious experience in any way fail to harmonize with intellectual apprehension. I should urge that just as the intellectual, the moral, and the religious are three phases in the single thrust to self-transcendence, so too moral and religious development only reveal more fully the God that can be known by the natural light of human reason. (Fs)

133a Sixthly, natural knowledge of God is not attained without moral judgments and existential decisions. These do not occur without God's grace. Therefore, the natural light of human reason does not suffice for man's so-called natural knowledge of God. (Fs)

133b I mention this objection, not because it is to the point, but because the point is often missed. One misinterprets Vatican I if one fancies it is speaking, not about a quaestio iuris, but about a quaestio facti. The quaestio iuris is (1) whether there exists a valid argument for God's existence and (2) whether the apprehension of that argument is an actus supernaturalis quoad substantiam. Natural knowledge of God is denied if one holds that there is no valid argument or if one holds that apprehending the argument is an intrinsically supernatural act. Natural knowledge of God is affirmed if one holds that there is a valid argument and if one holds that apprehending the argument is intrinsically natural. One goes beyond the quaestio iuris to the quaestio facti, when one turns from conditions of possibility to conditions of actual occurrence. Such conditions are always very numerous. In the present instance men must exist. They must be healthy and enjoy considerable leisure. They must have attained a sufficient differentiation of consciousness to think philosophically. They must have succeeded in avoiding all of the pitfalls in which so many great philosophers have become entrapped. They must resist their personal evil tendencies and not be seduced by the bad example of others. Such are just a few very general conditions of someone actually grasping a valid argument for God's existence. An adequate account would include every entity that conditioned the actual occurrence. Now Vatican I was not speaking of a quaestio facti but of a quaestio iuris, not of conditions of actuality but of conditions of possibility. I do not think that in this life people arrive at natural knowledge of God without God's grace, but what I do not doubt is that the knowledge they so attain is natural. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Theologie bedarf der Philosophie: primärer, sekundärer Aspekt; 3 Grundfragen: erkenntnistheoretisch, epistemologisch, metaphysisch

Kurzinhalt: The primary need is for the theologian to know what he is doing when he is doing theology. To reach such knowledge three prior questions must be answered. First is the question of cognitional theory: What am I doing ...

Textausschnitt: 136a A second major influence has been philosophic. Catholic theology has been wedded to Aristotle. The beginnings of that wedding were auspicious enough. For medieval theology was doing two things when partly it accepted and partly it reinterpreted the Aristotelian corpus. On the one hand, it was providing itself with a conceptual system that would make it possible for it to work out coherent answers to its endless quaestiones. At the same time, it was christianizing the Greek and Arabic culture that was pouring into Western Europe and threatening to engulf its faith. But what once was achievement, at a later date proved to be an obstacle to vitality and development. Aristotelian thought is unacquainted not merely with the content but also with the nature of modern science. It is not equipped to distinguish and to relate to one another the natural sciences, the human sciences, philosophy, and theology. It is unable to provide the foundations for their proper functioning and collaboration. Its conceptual system in part is to be revised and in part to be replaced by notions drawn from modern philosophy and science. So it is that contemporary theologians are drawing upon personalist, phenomenological, existential, historical, and transcendental types of philosophic thought to find the conceptual tools needed for their own thinking and writing. The results are often eclectic rather than systematic and deeply based, and here I feel there is a real danger in an age when modernist subjectivism and relativism are becoming increasingly common. (Fs)


137a Contemporary Catholic theology, then, not only is open to philosophic influence but profoundly needs philosophy. Here I must distinguish between primary and secondary aspects of that need. The theologian will want to be acquainted with Stoicism in reading Tertullian, with middle Platonism in reading Origen, with Neoplatonism in reading Augustine, with Aristotle, Avicenna, and Averroes in reading Aquinas, with Aquinas in reading subsequent theologians. But this need is secondary. It is a matter of acquiring the necessary background for particular tasks of interpretation. Again, it is through a study of the philosophers that the theologian will be introduced to philosophic questions, that he will reach answers relevant to his primary need, that he will learn to think and speak on the level of his age and culture. But again this is secondary. It is concerned with the pedagogy of meeting the primary need. It does not define the primary need itself. The primary need is for the theologian to know what he is doing when he is doing theology. To reach such knowledge three prior questions must be answered. First is the question of cognitional theory: What am I doing when I am knowing? Second is the question of epistemology: Why is doing that knowing? Third is the question of metaphysics: What do I know when I do it? To these three questions the theologian needs full, precise, and well-grounded answers. If he has those answers, his essential needs are met. If he does not reach those answers, then he will not know what he is doing, not merely when he reads philosophers but also when he does theology, when he is interpreting a text, when he is ascertaining a historical fact, when he is reconstructing a situation or mentality, when he moves beyond reason to faith, when he determines what is and what is not a matter of faith, when he seeks an understanding of the mysteries of faith, and when he concerns himself with the problem of communicating the faith to all men of all classes and of all cultures. Briefly, theologians have minds and use them, and they had best know what they are doing when they use them. Again, to put the matter historically, to follow Aquinas today is not to repeat Aquinas today, but to do for the twentieth century what Aquinas did for the thirteenth. As Aquinas baptized key elements in Greek and Arabic culture, so the contemporary Catholic philosopher and/or theologian has to effect a baptism of key elements in modern culture. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Theologie: Relevanz für andere Wissenschaften; Newman, Universität; Humanwissenschaften; "wertfreie" Wissenschaft

Kurzinhalt: ... I should like to indicate a possible relevance of theology to a basic problem of the human sciences. For the human sciences may be and often are pursued simply on the analogy of the natural sciences

Textausschnitt: 141a So much for my first topic. I have indicated five major areas in which theology has been profoundly influenced or is about to be profoundly influenced by other disciplines: history, philosophy, religious studies, method, and communications. This list, of course, is not exclusive. I have selected them simply on the basis of their enormous contribution to theology or theology's pressing need of them. I now turn to my second topic: What has theology to offer? What relevance does it possess for the concerns of other disciplines? What aid can it bring towards a solution of their problems?

141b These are large and difficult questions and, perhaps, I cannot do better than go back to the basic theorem in Newman's Idea of a University. It contains two parts, one positive, the other negative. Positively, Newman advanced that human knowing was a whole with its parts organically related, and this accords with the contemporary phenomenological notion of horizon, that one's perceptions are functions of one's outlook, that one's meaning is a function of a context and that context of still broader contexts.1 On the negative side, Newman asked what would happen if a significant part of knowledge were omitted, overlooked, ignored, not just by some individual but by the cultural community, and he contended that there would be three consequences. First, people in general would be ignorant of that area. Second, the rounded whole of human knowing would be mutilated. Third, the remaining parts would endeavor to round off the whole once more despite the omission of a part and, as a result, they would suffer distortion from their effort to perform a function for which they were not designed. Such was Newman's theorem.2 In fact, theology has for some time been dropped from most university curricula. So one well may ask whether Newman's inferences have been confirmed in fact, whether there is a widespread ignorance of specifically theological areas, and whether this has resulted in a mutilation and distortion of human knowledge generally. A fair and adequate answer to these questions would have many presuppositions and would involve a very delicately nuanced survey. I cannot here expound the former nor have I been able to undertake the latter. So I must be content with having brought the matter to your attention. (Fs)

142a But it is within this context that I should like to indicate a possible relevance of theology to a basic problem of the human sciences. For the human sciences may be and often are pursued simply on the analogy of the natural sciences. When this is done rigorously, when it is contended that a scientific explanation of human behavior is reached if the same behavior can be had in a robot,1 then everything specifically human disappears from the science. The human sciences become exact by ceasing to treat of man as he is. On the other hand, when human scientists reject such reductionism, and many do,2 not only does the exactitude of the natural sciences vanish but also the human sciences risk becoming captives of some philosophy. For what the reductionist omits are the meaning and value that inform human living and acting. But meaning and value are notions that can be clarified only by painstakingly making one's way through the jungle of the philosophies. (Fs) (notabene)

143a Now the suggestion I wish to make is that theology, and in particular a theology that has carefully and accurately worked out its method, could provide the human sciences with hints or even models for tackling the type of problem I have mentioned. For theology has long worked in conjunction with philosophy. At the present time, Catholic theology is disengaging itself from Aristotle and deriving new categories from personalist, phenomenological, existential, historicist, and transcendental types of philosophic thought. It will possess a certain expertise in using the philosophies without committing itself to more of them than it intends. It is much at home with questions concerning meaning from its study of developing doctrines and its problems of demythologization. Finally, not even the natural sciences can prescind from the question of value, for the very pursuit of science is the pursuit of a value, and the contention that science should be value-free, wertfrei, if taken literally,1 implies that science should be worthless. Theology has long been aware of conflicting judgments of value, even with radical conflicts, and a successful method of theology will have a technique for dealing competently, respectfully, and honestly with this issue. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: In-Liebe-Sein als ein erstes Prinzip; Augustinus: unruhiges Herz

Kurzinhalt: That dynamic state, while it has its causes, conditions, occasions, none the less once it occurs and as long as it lasts, is a first principle in one's living. ... it removes the temptation of all that is shallow hollow, empty,

Textausschnitt: 145a Now there is a profound difference between particular acts of loving and the dynamic state to which we refer when we speak of falling in love and of being in love. That dynamic state, while it has its causes, conditions, occasions, none the less once it occurs and as long as it lasts, is a first principle in one's living. It is the origin and source that prompts and colors all one's thoughts and feelings, all one's hopes and fears, all one's joys and sorrows. Moreover, such being-in-love is of three kinds. There is being-in-love with the domestic community, with one's mate and one's children. There is being-in-love with the civil community, eagerly making one's contribution to its needs and promoting its betterment. There is being-in-love with God. Of this love St. Paul spoke when he wrote to the Romans: "The love of God is poured forth in our hearts by the Spirit of God who has been given to us" (Rom. 5: 5). To it he referred when he asked: "Then what can separate us from the love of Christ? Can affliction or hardship? Can persecution, hunger, nakedness, peril, or the sword?" And his answer was: "For I am convinced that there is nothing in death or life, in the realm of spirits or superhuman powers, in the world as it is or the world as it shall be, in the forces of the universe, in heights or depths-nothing in all creation that can separate us from the love of God in Christ Jesus our Lord" (Rom. 8:35, 38, 39). (Fs)

145b All authentic being-in-love is a total self-surrender. But the love of God is not restricted to particular areas of human living. It is the foundation of love of one's neighbor. It is the grace that keeps one ever faithful and devoted to one's mate. But it is also something in itself, something personal, intimate, and profoundly attuned to the deepest yearnings of the human heart. It constitutes a basic fulfilment of man's being. Because it is such a fulfilment, it is the source of a great peace, the peace that the world cannot give. It is a wellspring of joy that can endure despite the sorrow of failure, humiliation, privation, pain, desertion. Because it is such, a fulfilment, it removes the temptation of all that is shallow hollow, empty, and degrading without handing man over to the fanaticism that arises when man's capacity for God is misdirected to finite goals. (Fs)

[...]

146c Long ago St. Augustine exclaimed that God had made us for himself and that our hearts are restless till they rest in him. What that restlessness is, we see all about us in the mountainous discontents, hatreds, and terrors of the twentieth century. But what it is to rest in God is not easily known or readily understood. Though God's grace is given to all, still the experience of resting in God ordinarily needs a religious tradition for it to be encouraged, fostered, interpreted, guided, developed. Though grace bestows both good will and good performance, still one shrinks and draws back from the performance of denying oneself daily and taking up one's cross and following Christ. For the fulfilment that is the love of God is not the fulfilment of any appetite or desire or wish or dream impulse, but the fulfilment of getting beyond one's appetites and desires and wishes and impulses, the fulfilment of self-transcendence, the fulfilment of human authenticity, the fulfilment that overflows into a love of one's neighbor as oneself. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Religion - Kirche; Lonergan über Rahner: theologische Anthropologie; Zusammenfassung: Theologie - Wissenschaften

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 147a I have been speaking to you of religion at its best. But an organized religion, a church, is not a conventicle of saints. It is like a net cast into the sea that catches all sorts of fish. If the same ultimate goal and ideal is proposed to all, there also must be proposed the successive stages in a development towards reaching the goal. So it is that, as generation follows generation, there is always a gap between the ideal and the real, between religion as it strives to be and religion as it is in fact. But apart from cases of self-deception or insincerity, this gap or contrast does not imply that religion is phony, that religious people say one thing and do another. The very being of man is not static but dynamic; it never is a state of achieved perfection; it always is at best a striving. The striving of the religious man is to give himself to God in something nearer the way in which God has given himself to us. Such a goal is always distant, but it is not inhuman, for it corresponds to the dynamic structure of man's being, to the restlessness that is ours till we rest in God. (Fs) (notabene)

147b I have been arguing that, because religion pertains to an authentic humanism, theology has a contribution to make to the humanities. But one can go further and argue with Karl Rahner that the dogmatic theology of the past has to become a theological anthropology.1 By this is meant that all theological questions and answers have to be matched by the transcendental questions and answers that reveal in the human subject the conditions of the possibility of the theological answers. Explicitly Father Rahner excludes a modernist interpretation of his view, namely, that theological doctrines are to be taken as statements about merely human reality. His position is that man is for God, that religion is intrinsic to an authentic humanism, that in theology theocentrism and anthropocentrism coincide. On this basis he desires all theological statements to be matched by statements of their meaning in human terms. His purpose is not to water down theological truth but to bring it to life, not to impose an alien method but to exclude the risk of mythology and to introduce into theological thinking the challenge of rigorous controls. (Fs) (notabene)

148a I must not give the impression, however, that such a theological anthropology already exists. Father Rahner has not, to my knowledge, done more than sketch how one might go about constructing it. But the mere fact that the proposal has been made reveals how closely a future theology may be related to the human sciences and to the humanities. (Fs)

148b Let me conclude with a brief summary. I pointed to five areas in which theology has been learning or has to learn from other disciplines: history, philosophy, religious studies, methodology, and communications. Then I recalled Newman's theorem that the omission of a significant discipline from the university curriculum left a blind spot, the mutilation of an organic whole, and a distortion of the disciplines that remained and endeavored to meet real human needs. While I was not in a position to discern whether this theorem is borne out by facts, I did suggest that a theology with a properly developed method would be of some use to human scientists who, on the one hand, wished to avoid all reductionism without, on the other hand, becoming captives of some philosophic fad. Further, I added that religion was part of an authentic humanism, and so that theological reflection on religion was pertinent to the human sciences and the humanities. Finally, I referred to a paper of Father Karl Rahner's with which I am in substantial agreement, to indicate just how closely related to human studies a future theology may prove to be. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Friedrich Heiler: 7 Gemeinsamkeiten aller Hauptreligionen

Kurzinhalt: ... Friedrich Heiler had occasion to list seven principal areas of unity to be discerned, not only in Christian churches and congregations, but in all the religions of mankind:

Textausschnitt: 149a In a collective work on the history of religions published by the Divinity School of the University of Chicago almost a decade ago, the noted German scholar Friedrich Heiler had occasion to list seven principal areas of unity to be discerned, not only in Christian churches and congregations, but in all the religions of mankind: in Judaism, in Islam, in Zoroastrian Mazdaism, in Hinduism, Buddhism, Taoism.1 I should like to begin this paper with a brief summary of Prof. Heiler's account. For it will draw attention away from what is outward and towards what is inner and vital in religion. It will reassure us that the Christian churches and congregations, despite their many differences, have in common something that is very profound and very dynamic, that promises Christianity a future, that constitutes a basis for serious dialogue not only among Christians but among the representatives of all the world religions. It is true, of course, that Prof. Heiler's list omits what is distinctive of Christianity, but I feel sure that that omission is something that each of us will be more than ready to remedy. (Fs)

149b First, then, Prof. Heiler listed "the reality of the transcendent, the holy, the divine, the Other." Distinct from all things transient there is acknowledged "true being," the "reality of all realities," "the one without a counterpart," "the eternal truth." What is meant is what we name God. While God may be conceived rationally as the ground of the universe, and personally as the "Thou" we interiorly address, still these movements of the human mind and heart are held to be inadequate to reveal what God is. (Fs)

150a Secondly, the divine, while transcendent, is also immanent in human hearts. St. Paul has it that our bodies are temples of the Holy Spirit. The Koran, that God is nearer than our very pulse. St. Augustine, that he is more inward than one's innermost being. The mysticism of ancient India, that man is one with Brahma. (Fs)

150b Thirdly, this reality, transcendent and immanent, is for man the highest good, the highest truth, righteousness, goodness, beauty. There is nothing in the world of nature or spirit to compare with this Ultimate and Supreme; and so that highest good is the final goal of all the longing and striving of the world religions. (Fs)

150c Fourthly, the reality of the divine is ultimate love. Mercy and grace are the attributes of Yahweh in the experience of the prophets of Israel. God in the gospel is outgoing and forgiving love. Goodness and all-encompassing care makeup the characteristic of the Tao of Laotse. The great heart of compassion is the inmost essence of the divine in Mahayana Buddhism. (Fs)

150d Fifthly, the way of man to God is universally the way of sacrifice. The path of salvation everywhere begins with sorrowful renunciation, resignation, the via purgatiua, ethical self-discipline, asceticism. The path to God finds its continuation in meditation, contemplation, prayer. All pious men pray, partly in words, partly without words, partly in complete solitude, partly in the community of the faithful. And the great saints of all high religions "pray without ceasing," as Paul says. Their whole life is, as Origen said, "one single, great continuing prayer." As they advance they seek not earthly good but God himself and God's rule on earth. (Fs)

150e Sixthly, the high religions teach not only the way to God but always and at the same time the way to the neighbor as well. All preach brotherly love, a love on which there are no limitations, a love that is to be extended even to enemies, a love that has its origin and source not in man himself but in God operating on man, a love that, as it comes from God, also returns to him, for in loving our neighbor we are loving God. (Fs)

151a Finally, while religious experience is as manifold and various as the human condition itself, still the superior way to God is love. It is love of God that leads the high religions to conceive bliss, the highest blessedness, now as the vision of God, now as some other union with him, now as some dissolving into him. (Fs)

151b I have been giving a brief summary of what Prof. Heiler set forth in some eleven pages. I have been doing so because such a summary seemed to me the best way of indicating realistically, though incompletely, what is meant by religion. I now propose to pursue that topic further by raising two questions. First, what is the function of religion in human living? Secondly, how may a Christian account for the great similarity in the diverse high religions without denying the uniqueness of Christianity?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Religion, Christentum: Funktion im menschlichen Leben; Selbsttranszendenz - Authentizität

Kurzinhalt: ... What is the function of religion in human life? By now, perhaps, the answer will be plain enough ... . I have argued that man exists authentically in the measure that he succeeds in self-transcendence, and I have found that self-transcendence ...

Textausschnitt: 152a Now I have described these four levels of man's intentional consciousness, because I wish to draw a conclusion, namely, that authentic human living consists in self-transcendence. Already on the level of experience we are going beyond ourselves in apprehending and in responding to persons and things about us. But while animals live in a habitat, man lives in a universe. He does so because he asks endless questions, because he draws on the experience and memories of his contemporaries and their predecessors, because he cannot live humanly without forming some view concerning the facts and the possibilities of human existence. With the third level of judgment there emerges a still more radical element in self-transcendence. For the judgment may be, not a simple report on what I feel, or imagine, or think, or am inclined to say, but a quite confident statement of what is or is not so. Indeed, the true statement (concerning objects) intends to state what would be so even if the subject making the statement did not exist. But self-transcendence has a still further dimension. For so far we have considered a self-transcendence that is only cognitional. Beyond it there is a self-transcendence that is real. When he pronounces a project to be worthwhile, a man moves beyond consideration of all merely personal satisfactions and interests, tastes and preferences. He is acknowledging objective values and taking the first step towards authentic human existence. That authenticity is realized when judgments of value are followed by decision and action, when knowing what truly is good leads to doing what truly is good. (Fs)

[...]

153c God's gift of his love to us is the crowning point of our self-transcendence. St. Ausustine wrote: "Thou hast made us for thyself, O Lord, and our hearts are restless till they rest in thee." But that resting in God is something, not that we achieve, but that we receive, accept, ratify. It comes quietly, secretly, unobtrusively. We know about it when we notice its fruits in our lives. It is the profoundest fulfilment of the human spirit. Because it is fulfilment, it gives us peace, the peace that the world cannot give. Because it is fulfilment, it gives us joy, a joy that can endure despite the sorrows of failure, humiliation, privation, pain, betrayal, desertion. Because it is fulfilment, its absence is revealed, now in the trivialization of human life in debauchery, now in the fanaticism with which limited goals are pursued violently and recklessly, now in the despair that condemns man and his world as absurd. (Fs)

[...]

154b I have been endeavoring to meet the question, What is the function of religion in human life? By now, perhaps, the answer will be plain enough. To live intelligently, reasonably, responsibly, an adult has to form some view of the universe, of man's place in the universe, of his role along with other men. He may do so by appealing to myth, or to science, or to philosophy, or to religion. He may do so explicitly, consciously, deliberately, or he may do so implicitly, inadvertently, without deliberation. He may confront what he beholds, or try to escape in debauchery and drugs, or rage fanatically against it, or collapse in existential despair. Such is the human condition and such the human problem. A mythic solution will do only for the immature. A scientific solution is impossible, for science methodically and systematically refuses to consider the issue. A philosophic solution is out-of-date, for philosophy has become existential; it is concerned with man in his concrete existing; and there the issue is authenticity. I have argued that man exists authentically in the measure that he succeeds in self-transcendence, and I have found that self-transcendence has both its fulfilment and its enduring ground in holiness, in God's gift of his love to us. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Christentum - andere Religionen; Gnade an alle (1. Brief an Timotheus); Christentum: keine eigentümliche Ethik (Lady Margaret)

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 155a I began by asking two questions. I have said something about the significance of religion in human living, and now I must turn very briefly to the relationship between Christianity and the other world religions. Now I have been quoting St. Paul and St. Augustine and speaking in Christian terms, but I have not been doing so in any exclusive manner, for it is not Christian doctrine that the gift of God's love is restricted to Christians. The First Epistle to Timothy tells us that it is God's will that all men should find salvation and come to knowledge of the truth (1 Tim. 2:4). From this many theologians have concluded that, since grace is necessary to salvation, grace sufficient for salvation is given to all men. That this grace does include the great grace, the gift of God's love, may be inferred, I think, from Prof. Heiler's account of the seven areas common to all the high religions. (Fs)

155b For these seven areas are just what one would expect to result from God's gift of his love. That love itself is the seventh common area. It involves love of one's neighbor, which is the sixth. It involves loving attention to God, which is prayer, and self-transcendence, which is self-denial; prayer and self-denial are the fifth common area. Further, love of God is not love of this world or of any part of it, and so it is love of a transcendent being; yet God's love is in us, more intimate than our innermost being, and so God is immanent in human hearts; the transcendence and immanence of God were the first two common areas. Finally, God's gift of his love is fulfilment of our massive thrust to self-transcendence. But we transcend ourselves by seeking the intelligible, the true, the real, the good, love. What fulfils that seeking, the God in whom we rest, must be the summit of intelligibility, truth, reality, goodness, love; and so we conclude to the third and fourth areas. It would seem that the seven areas listed by Prof. Heiler from the viewpoint of a history of religions, may be described from a Christian viewpoint as seven effects of God's gift of his love. (Fs) (notabene)

156a To come now to what is distinctive of Christianity, let me quote the Lady Margaret Professor of Divinity in the University of Cambridge, C. F. D. Moule. In a recent series of lectures he stated: "At no point within the New Testament is there any evidence that the Christians stood for an original philosophy of life or an original ethic. Their sole function is to bear witness to what they claim as an event-the raising of Jesus from among the dead."1 What distinguishes the Christian, then, is not God's grace, which he shares with others, but the mediation of God's grace through Jesus Christ our Lord. (Fs)

156b In the Christian, accordingly, God's gift of his love is a love that is in Christ Jesus. From this fact flow the social, historical, doctrinal aspects of Christianity. For the gift of God's love, however intimate and personal, is not so private as to be solitary. It is given to many through Christ Jesus that they may be one in him. They need one another to come to understand the gift that has been given them, to think out what it implies and involves, to support one another in their effort to live Christian lives. (Fs)

157a Normally, the gift of God's love is not a sudden transformation of character or personality. It is like the seed planted in ground that needs to be tilled, like the sprout that needs sunlight and rain and protection from choking weeds, devouring insects, and roving animals. As Charlie Brown needs all the friends he can get, so Christians need all the help they can get. Great saints are rare, and even they call themselves vessels of clay. The need of teaching and preaching, of rituals and common worship, is the need to be members of one another, to share with one another what is deepest in ourselves, to be recalled from our waywardness, to be encouraged in our good intentions. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Philosophie: Beitrag für eine Theologie; transzendentale Methode: Erkenntnistheorie, Epistomologie, Metaphysik

Kurzinhalt: ... What does one know when one does it? When the foregoing questions are answered with philosophic generality, one is already in possession of a transcendental method, ... The foregoing is, in my opinion, the core contribution a philosophy can make ...

Textausschnitt: The Contribution of Philosophy to the Establishment of New Thought-Forms

202b One can turn on the television set and adjust it without ever having attempted to penetrate the mysteries of electronics. But if one wishes to design a new and better type of television set, the more one knows of electronics and the more fertile one is in invention, the greater the likelihood one will succeed. Similarly, one can learn the techniques of this or that branch or division of theology by repeating the performance of others revealed in their lectures, their seminars, their articles, and their books. But it is one thing to juxtapose the various techniques of the many branches. It is quite another to see how each set can be rearranged, expanded, curtailed, transformed, so that all will lock together in a single, ongoing, cumulative process. Most of all, it is in preparing that transforming and unifying view that philosophy can make a contribution to contemporary theology. (Fs)

203a For a method guides cognitional performance. Because the performance is cognitional, there are needed full and precise answers to three basic questions. There is the question of cognitional theory: What precisely is one doing when one is knowing? There is the question of epistemology: Why is doing that knowing? There is the question of metaphysics? What does one know when one does it? When the foregoing questions are answered with philosophic generality, one is already in possession of a transcendental method, that is, of a method that is as yet not specified by any particular field or subject but, by suitable additions and adaptations, can be specified to any field or subject of human inquiry. (Fs) (notabene)

203b The foregoing is, in my opinion, the core contribution a philosophy can make to contemporary theological need. But it also can make further contributions that help theology explicate its proper adaptations of transcendental method. Let me briefly indicate the nature of such further contributions. (Fs)

203c First, in terms of cognitional theory, epistemology, and metaphysics, there has to be worked out a foundational account both of hermeneutics and of critical history. The techniques exist and are practised. But there is needed an adequate analysis followed by an epistemological critique of the different interpretations given the techniques by naive realists, by empiricists, by positivists, by idealists, by phenomenologists, by critical realists. Without the analysis and the epistemological critique, any attempt to get beyond the "Jesus of history" to the "Christ of faith" risks being blocked by usually unacknowledged philosophic assumptions. (Fs)

203d Secondly, let me note that the metaphysics I would envisage would not be a philosophic first. It would be a conclusion derived from epistemology and cognitional theory, and these in turn would be formulations of one's personal experience of one's own cognitional operations. In this fashion philosophy and the root of theological method would come out of the personal experience of the thinker and it would evoke the personal experience of those to whom he speaks or for whom he writes. (Fs)

204a Thirdly, cognitional theory, epistemology, and metaphysics are needed but they are not enough. They have to be subsumed under the higher operations that integrate knowing with feeling and consist in deliberating, evaluating, deciding, acting. It is on this level that people move from unauthenticity to authenticity; it is on this level that they decide to believe; it is at the root of this level that God's love floods their hearts through the gift of the Holy Spirit (Rom. 5: 5). As before, so here too the account is not to presuppose a metaphysical framework of potencies, habits, acts, objects but basically it is to proceed from personal experience and move towards an analysis of the structures of our conscious and intentional operations. More than anywhere it is essential here to be able to speak from the heart to the heart without introducing elements that, however true in themselves, have the disadvantage of not being given in experience. (Fs)

204b Fourthly, there exist religious studies. There are the history of religions, the phenomenology of religion, the psychology of religion, the sociology of religion, and underpinning them all and, as well, overarching them there is the philosophy of religion. Philosophy of religion reveals how basic thinking relates itself to the various branches of religious studies. Thereby it offers theology an analogous model of the way it can relate itself to religious studies, how it can profit from them, and how it can teach its own students what they will need to understand if the new secretariats, established by Vatican II, for ecumenism, for non-Christian religions, and for unbelievers, are to have competent staffs and to be properly understood, supported, and promoted by the Church and the hierarchy. (Fs)

204c Fifthly, there is the history of philosophy. If one is to read Tertullian, one had best know Stoicism. If one is to read Origen, one has to be acquainted with Middle Platonism. If one is to read Augustine, one has to know his Platonici. Similarly, down the ages, theology has drawn upon the philosophers, because it has to speak both of the man that grace converts and of the world in which he lives. The historical theologian, then, has to know the philosophers relevant to his field of study; he has to be able to discern how much of the philosophers' thought the Christian writer really grasped and how much was only loosely assimilated. Finally, he must also be a critical philosopher, both capable of spotting what is misleading or inadequate in this or that philosophy, and able to reveal how philosophic defect led to theological defect. By such criticism historical theology can yield a dialectic. By revealing the philosophic sources of aberrations, it can account for differences in patristic and in theological thought. By discerning the manner in which aberrations have been overcome, it can sketch the genesis of a distinctive Catholic philosophy. For neither Plato nor Aristotle, neither Stoics nor Gnostics, anticipated the notions implied by Nicea, by Ephesus, by Chalcedon. (Fs)

205a Sixthly, just as transcendental method can be adapted and extended into theology, into religious studies, into historical theology, so too it can be adapted and extended into sociocultural studies. Meanings, values, modes of group action have developed and diversified down the ages. There is no lack of detailed studies. There is no lack of the expertise that, through the self-correcting process of common-sense learning, comes to understand alien cultures. Besides detailed studies there exist such overall views as Bruno Snell's The Discovery of Mind and Ernst Cassirer's Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. (Fs)

205b But something more is wanted. It is not supplied either by Aquinas' interpretation of Scripture in Aristotelian terms or by Bultmann's interpretation of the New Testament in terms of the early Heidegger. Rather what is wanted is a coming together of the fruits of historical expertise and, on the other hand, of models derived from the data of consciousness, from the different types of its differentiation and specialization, from the various structures that result from differentiation and specialization. From the interaction of detailed research, overall views, and the construction of models there would gradually emerge a phylogenetic set of schemata that would provide socio-cultural expertise with a first approximation to the notions it has to express and, on the other hand, would provide students both with an initial access to alien cultures and with an overall view of the stages and variations of human meanings, values, structures. (Fs)

206a To this academic utility there must be added its practical utility. The Gospel is to be preached to all nations, to every class of men in every culture. As long as classicist culture was accepted, it could be thought that there existed but a single culture and that the Gospel could be preached substantially through that culture, even though accidentally certain adaptations had to be made to reach the uncultured. Now that classicist culture is a thing of the past, we can no longer suppose that classicist assumptions could succeed in preaching the Gospel to all nations. We have to learn to express the Gospel message so that it can be grasped by the members of every class within each of the cultures of the world. A philosophy of culture can make a great contribution towards the fulfilment of that task. (Fs)

206b There is, then, a certain type of philosophy that in many ways is very relevant to Catholic theology in its current crisis. For the current crisis is a shift in horizon. The earlier horizon was a basic outlook in terms of logic and of eternal truths, with the consequence that serious change of context was assumed to be impossible and so its possibility was not investigated. The current horizon is a basic outlook in terms of method and developing doctrines. The application of hermeneutics and critical history has brought to light notable changes of context and, with them, those continuities and contrasts that we refer to as doctrinal developments. In place of eternal truths, we now have differing apprehensions of the object of faith, where the differences rise from the changing contexts within which the apprehensions occur. (Fs)

207a A philosophy very relevant to this shift of horizon, of basic outlook, is one that centers on three questions: (1) What am I doing when I am knowing? (2) Why is doing that knowing? and (3) What do I know when I do it? With answers to those questions ascertained, one reaches the method of theology by asking and answering the specific question: What are we doing when we do theology?

207b The same type of philosophy also makes possible an analysis and a much needed critique both of hermeneutics and of critical history. It underpins a philosophy of action-a philosophy of deliberation, evaluation, decision, deed. It opens out upon a philosophy of religion, a dialectical history of theology, a philosophy of culture and of communications. In all these areas it blazes trails for theology to follow, enlarge, enrich. (Fs)

SUMMARY COMMENTS

1. Transcendental method is transcendental both in the Scholastic sense (it is not confined to any particular genus or category of inquiry) and in the Kantian sense (it is the condition of the possibility, that is, the necessary but not sufficient condition of any categorial method). (Fs)

2. Those that still cling to eternal truths may object that my position is relativist. They may argue a posteriori: hermeneutics and critical history did lead to the historicism of Ernst Troeltsch, which was just a thorough-going relativism. They may argue a priori: a truth that is not eternal is relative to some particular place and time. (Fs)

To the a posteriori argument: recall that I accept hermeneutics and critical method but not without a soundly based analysis and an epistemological critique. Troeltsch's relativism springs from a philosophic inadequacy. (Fs)

To the a priori argument: note that truths that are not eternal are relative, not to a place and time, but to the context of a place and time; but such contexts are related to one another; history includes the study of such relations; in the light of history it becomes possible to transpose from one context to another; by such transpositions one reaches a truth that extends over places and times. (Fs)

3. While the paper sets forth problems in contemporary theology, it can make no attempt to solve them on the theological level. That is a task for a separate book. Our concern is limited to the contribution that philosophy might make to the solution of theological problems. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan über: Verhältnis seiner Methode zu seinen frühen Werken (De Verbo Incarnato, De Deo Trino)

Kurzinhalt: I was developing there also what I consider something permanently valid, namely this type of interpretation that is concerned with things that the thinkers themselves didn't think about.

Textausschnitt: The Classic Treatises

211d Questions were raised as to the relation of Fr. Lonergan's Latin treatises De Verbo Incarnato and De Deo Trino to this method. (Fs)

"Well-those things are practical chores, that you have to do if you're teaching a class of 650 people. They're not going to get it on the wing out of lectures. One of the techniques of getting them to come to the lectures and get something out of them is to provide them with a thick book so that they'll be glad to have some map as to what's important in it and what you can skip. It belongs to a period in which the situation I was in was hopelessly antiquated, but had not yet been demolished-it has since been demolished. But to be a professor in dogmatic theology was to be a specialist in the Old Testament-not just in the Pentateuch or something like that-the Old Testament, the New, the Apostolic Fathers, the Greek Fathers, the ante-Nicene, Greek and Latin, the post-Nicene, the medieval Scholastics, the Renaissance period, the Reformation, contemporary philosophy and so on. There's no one who is a specialist in all that; but that was the sort of thing you had to handle. And you did what you could-(as Damon Runyon's characters put it: 'How are you doing?' 'I'm doing what I can.'). (Fs)

212a "It was a matter of doing that-and also of introducing what I could. For example my analysis of the ante-Nicene period on trinitarian doctrine: I was developing there also what I consider something permanently valid, namely this type of interpretation that is concerned with things that the thinkers themselves didn't think about. Tertullian has a stoic background, Origen has a middle Platonist background, Athanasius' account of Nicea is something totally new that you can't reduce to anything Platonic, Aristotelian, Gnostic, or Stoic and so on; a new situation is created. It's second-level thinking, the sort of thing that is possible within a Hellenistic culture. But that comparison of all three, revealing their different backgrounds-the different ways in which they conceived the Son to be divine, totally different ways-is an understanding of the process from the New Testament to Nicea. That, I think, is something valid. There are chunks in those books that I think are permanently valid. But having to write the book at all was totally invalid-yet necessary concretely. (Fs)

212b "Doing method fundamentally is distinguishing different tasks, and thereby eliminating totalitarian ambitions. Systematic theologians for a couple of centuries thought they were the only ones who were theologians, then, positive theologians thought they were the only ones. This other stuff was all out. (Fs)

213a "What I want is eight different tasks distinguished. It isn't that one can't do all eight. One extraordinary person may very well do all eight-but he's doing eight different things, not just one and the same thing over and over again. That's a fundamental concern for method, eliminating totalitarian ambitions. On the other hand, it's making tasks not intolerably difficult. If you're trying to do one thing, and people are asking you why aren't you doing the other seven, and you're constantly explaining, you never get anywhere. And that's the way things were. My De Deo Trino comes in two parts. In the first part I manage to separate what I call systematics from doctrines. In the second I manage to separate what I call systematics and doctrine on the one hand and on the other positive studies, positive research, historical research. Well, I've moved on from those three to eight entirely different tasks."

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan über sein Werk Einsicht (Insight)

Kurzinhalt: But it is not theory in exactly the same way physics is. Its basic elements-mass, temperature, electromagnetic field-are not within the field of experience ... But the fundamental terms and relations in cognitional theory are given in consciousness.

Textausschnitt: Insight

213b Questions were put regarding the book Insight, whether it was a way or a theory, and how the exercise of self-appropriation to which it invites one generates horizons. (Fs)

213c "Now with regard to the business of Insight, Insight happened this way: my original intention was method in theology. Insight was an exploration of methods in other fields, prior to trying to do method in theology. I got word in 1952 that I was to go to the Gregorian and teach in 1953, so I cut down my original ambition to do method in theology and put this book together. It's both a way and something like a theory. Fundamentally it's a way. It's asking people to discover in themselves what they are. And as Fr. Heelan put it, 'There's something liberating about that.' The word Lonerganian has come up in recent days. In a sense there's no such thing. Because what I'm asking people is to discover themselves and be themselves. They can arrive at conclusions different from mine on the basis of what they find in themselves. And in that sense it is a way. (Fs)

214a "But that self-appropriation can be objectified. It's a heightening of consciousness-as one moves from attention to intelligence, to reasonableness, to responsibility, to religious experience. Those modalities of consciousness, the a priori that they constitute, that can be objectified. Not in the sense of subject-object-in here now, out there now-but in the sense that objectivity is the fruit of authentic subjectivity. That self-appropriation can be objectified and its objectification is theory. (Fs)

214b "But it is not theory in exactly the same way physics is. Its basic elements-mass, temperature, electromagnetic field-are not within the field of experience. They are, all of them, constructs. Temperature is not what feels hot or cold. You put your hand on something metal, on something wood and one feels warmer than the other. They're both the same temperature-they're in the same room for a sufficient length of time. These fundamental concepts in physics are not data of experience. (Fs)

214c "But the fundamental terms and relations in cognitional theory are given in consciousness. The relations are the dynamisms of consciousness and the terms are the operations that are related through the dynamisms. So it is theory-but in a sense as totally different from theory (in physics) as Eddington's two tables. On one you can put your hands, rest your weight; you find it solid, brown, it weighs so much. The other consists mostly of empty space, and where the space isn't empty you have a wavicle; but what it's doing is very hard to say. (Fs)

214d "The exercise of self-appropriation gives you the structure that generates horizons. And because you have the structure that's generating horizon, because that structure is heuristic, you're anticipating. If the intelligible, being, the good-what you mean by those terms-is what is correlative to the desire to understand, to be reasonable, to be responsible; then, in yourself, you have the subjective pole of an objective field. You have also, in intelligent reasonable responsibility, norms, built-in norms, that are yourself. They are not propositions about yourself; but yourself, in your spiritual reality, to guide you in working out what that objective horizon is, the objective pole of the horizon. It's normative, it's potential. Not absolute, in the sense that you have it all tucked away. But you have the machinery for going at it, and you know what happens when you do."

215a To the objection that the structure is invariant and therefore not open, Lonergan replied:

"Well, it can happen that any particular person does get caught in some sort of cul-de-sac and that's his misfortune. (Fs)

"But how do you get him out of it?
"By asking further questions. (Fs)

215b "And the thing I'm talking about is dynamic and it is precisely the dynamic of asking further questions. And while there are restricted topics, on which you can say, 'Well, I don't think there are any further relevant questions with regard to that' (as in the chapter on judgment I talked about the man who leaves his beautiful, neat, perfect home in the morning to go to work, comes back in the evening and finds the windows broken, water on the floor and smoke in the air-and he doesn't say 'There was a fire.' That could be all faked, but he says 'Something happened.' He might ask 'Where's my wife?' and that would be a further question on a different topic. Still, with regard to the statement 'Something happened' there are no further relevant questions)."

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Symbol: Lonergan - Ricoeur; Gefühl; Wert: transzendentale Notion; Gewissen - Werturteil; Aristoteles, der tugendhafte Mensch

Kurzinhalt: The symbol for me is the 'affect-laden image.' It's evoked by an affect, or the image evokes the affect. They're linked. It's the means of internal communication between psyche and mind and heart.

Textausschnitt: Regarding Symbols and Ricoeur on Symbolism:

220c "Well, I can't match Ricoeur on symbolism. The symbol for me is the 'affect-laden image.' It's evoked by an affect, or the image evokes the affect. They're linked. It's the means of internal communication between psyche and mind and heart. Where mind is experience, understanding, judgment; and heart is what's beyond this on the level of feeling and 'is this worthwhile?'-judgment of value, decision. Without feelings this experience, understanding, judgment is paper-thin. The whole mass and momentum of living is in feeling. (Fs)

221a "Feelings: there's a whole series of categories on them-to go into them would take too long. You get them in Scheler, and then von Hildebrand, in his Christian Ethics, distinguishing different kinds-different meanings of the word 'feeling,' different types. But there are feelings that are apprehensions of value in a strict sense. There are vital values. Then social values- the vital values of the group. Then cultural values-'not in bread alone does man live.' There's the personal realization, incorporation of values, religious values, the personal appropriation of values, the development of one's feelings, the education of feeling. This is all on the level of the apprehension of values. (Fs)

221b "Beyond that there's the transcendental notion of values, in the question for deliberation-'Is this worthwhile? or are we wasting our time?' It stops you-and in the judgment of value in answer to that question. This demands not only these feelings-if you just have these feelings, well, you have a moral idealism that usually does more harm than good-you have to have also an apprehension of human reality, and possibility, and what probably will happen from different courses of action. (Fs)

221c "For your judgment of values, for the objectivity of a judgment of value, the criterion is the good conscience of the virtuous man. You're not sure of your moral judgments unless you're sure you're a virtuous man! It's very Aristotelian, incidentally. Aristotle made ethics empirical by postulating the existence of virtuous men. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Geheimnis, Mysterium: Lonergan - Rahner

Kurzinhalt: But mystery remains. When you talk, you're not aiming at communicating a mystery. Buy you don't dispel it either. Rahner emphasizes mystery a lot. I have a few clear things to say.

Textausschnitt: 229b Lonergan, unlike Rahner, lays emphasis in his writings on clarity rather than mystery. (Fs)

"But mystery remains. When you talk, you're not aiming at communicating a mystery. Buy you don't dispel it either. Rahner emphasizes mystery a lot. I have a few clear things to say. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Liebe als Prinzip; Kriterium wahrer Liebe

Kurzinhalt: If one is deceiving oneself one is not in love. One is mistaking something for love. Love is something that proves itself.

Textausschnitt: 229c Should one not critically ground religion?

"I put the question the other night. A person was demanding that I critically ground this religion and he was talking to Professor So and So and I went up to him and, said 'Would you require Professor So and So to critically ground the love he has for his wife and children?' Being in love is a fact, and it's what you are, it's existential. And your living flows from it. It's the first principle, as long as it lasts. It has its causes and its occasions and its conditions and all the rest of it. But while it's there it's the first principle and it's the source of all one's desires and fears, all the good one can see, and so on. And critically grounding knowledge isn't finding the ground for knowledge. It's already there. Being critical means eliminating the ordinary nonsense, the systematically misleading images and so on; the mythical account. (Fs)

229d "Every scientific or philosophic breakthrough is the elimination of some myth in the pejorative sense; the flat earth, right on. But if you are in love it doesn't need any justification. It's the justification beyond anything else. Just as you don't explain God, God is the ultimate explanation."

230a Might one not then be deceived?

"One can be deceiving himself. If one is deceiving oneself one is not in love. One is mistaking something for love. Love is something that proves itself. 'By their fruits you shall know them,' and 'in fear and trembling work out your salvation' and all the rest of it. Love isn't cocksure, either. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Zweideutigkeit: Realismus; Welt des Kindes, des Erwachsenen; naiver Realismus -> Empirimus -> kritischer Idealismus (Hume, Kant Hegel, Piaget)

Kurzinhalt: Such is naive realism. Its offspring is empiricism. For the empiricist takes naive realism seriously and so proceeds to empty the world mediated by meaning of everything that is not given to immediate experience.

Textausschnitt: THE ORIGINS OF CHRISTIAN REALISM1

239a My approach to the question of the origins of Christian realism is determined by three topics. Elsewhere I have treated these topics separately. But it is my hope that you will be interested in having them brought together in a single focus. (Fs)

239b The first topic is the notion of critical realism, i.e., the attempt to get beyond the empiricism of Hume, the critical idealism of Kant, the absolute idealism of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, and the subsequent varieties of subjectivism. The second topic is how did it happen that the Christian Church became involved in such issues. To this the common answer since the pronouncements of Harnack has been the influence of Hellenistic thought. Such an answer, as I have argued in the first volume of my De Deo Trino,2 is quite inadequate. The third topic has to do with contemporary Roman Catholic Christology. Some years ago, Fathers Hulsbosch, Schillebeeckx, and Schoonenberg discussed or proposed revisions of Christological doctrine.3 Father Piet Schoonenberg in 1969 published a book on the topic; a German translation was published in the same year; and in 1971 there appeared an English translation under the title, The Christ.4 (Fs)

239c Apparently contrary to Father Schoonenberg's views, the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith on February 21, 1972 reaffirmed the doctrines of the Councils of Nicea and Chalcedon. The materials then of this third topic come from Dutch and Roman theology. But the question I propose to treat is the relation of this Dutch-Roman conflict to the views I set forth in my Père Marquette lecture on Doctrinal Pluralism.5 (Fs)

I. The Ambiguity of Realism

240a Many no doubt will feel it quite ridiculous for a theologian to confront head-on a philosophic issue. While at the back of their minds there may linger some old and mistaken notions of sciences defined by their formal objects and consequently completely disparate, more probably in the foreground will be the conviction that philosophic issues are tremendously profound and difficult. (Fs)

240b Let me begin then by assuring you that in proposing to speak of the ambiguity of realism I have not the slightest intention of touching on anything either profound or difficult. For in my opinion the ambiguity of realism arises from the very simple and evident fact that infants do not speak while most adults do speak. From this simple and evident fact it follows that infants, because they do not speak, do not live in a world mediated by language. Their world is a world of immediacy, of sights and sounds, of tastes and smells, of touching and feeling, of joys and sorrows. But as infants learn to speak, they gradually move into a far larger world. It includes the past and the future as well as the present, the possible and the probable as well as the actual, rights and duties as well as facts. It is a world enriched by travellers' tales, by stories and legends, by literature, philosophy, science, by religion, theology, history. (Fs)

240c Now the criteria of reality in the infant's world of immediacy are given in immediate experience. They are simply the occurrence of seeing or hearing, tasting or smelling, touching or feeling, enjoying or suffering. But the criteria of reality in the world mediated by meaning are far more complex. They include immediate experience but they also go beyond it. To the criteria of immediate experience they add the criteria of relevant understanding, of accurate formulation of correct judgment or prudent belief. (Fs)

241a For the world mediated by meaning is not just given. Over and above what is given there is the universe that is intended by questions, that is organized by intelligence, that is described by language, that is enriched by tradition. It is an enormous world far beyond the comprehension of the nursery. But it also is an insecure world, for besides fact there is fiction, besides truth there is error, besides science there is myth, besides honesty there is deceit. (Fs)

241b Now such ambiguity and insecurity do not bother the average man but they do trouble philosophers. For philosophers ask strange questions. What am I doing when I am knowing? Why is doing that knowing? What do I know when I do it? Having put to themselves the questions of cognitional theory, of epistemology, and of metaphysics, they are apt to go into a deep huddle with themselves, to overlook the number of years they spent learning to speak, to disregard the differences between the infant's world of immediacy and the adult's world mediated by meaning, to reach back to their infancy, and to come up with the infantile solution that the real is what is given in immediate experience. Knowing, they will claim, is a matter of taking a good look; objectivity is a matter of seeing what is there to be seen; reality is whatever is given in immediate experience. (Fs)

241c Such is naive realism. Its offspring is empiricism. For the empiricist takes naive realism seriously and so proceeds to empty the world mediated by meaning of everything that is not given to immediate experience. In turn empiricism begets critical idealism. It awakens Kant from his dogmatic slumbers by revealing to him that the one and only immediate apprehension we have of objects is by sensible intuition. It follows that the categories of understanding of themselves are empty, that they can refer to objects only insofar as they are applied to the data of sense. It further follows that the ideals of reason are doubly mediated, for they can be referred to objects only insofar as they guide the use of the categories of understanding when the categories themselves are applied to the data of sense. (Fs) (notabene)

242a There results Kant's critical idealism. Because we have access only to objects sensibly presented, we are confined to a merely phenomenal world. "Things themselves" become a merely limiting concept, a Grenzbegriff by which we designate what we cannot know. Knowledge of the soul, of morality, of God, arises only as conclusions from the postulates of practical reason. (Fs)

242b In reaction to Kant's critical idealism, there were propounded the absolute idealisms of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. It was their aim to restore speculative reason to its ancient eminence though in a new idealist context. But while they enriched philosophy enormously, their basic project has not prospered. In a variety of ways the primacy of practical reason has been reaffirmed. Schopenhauer wrote on Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung. Kierkegaard took his stand on faith. Newman toasted conscience. Nietzsche praised the will to power. Dilthey wanted a Lebensphilosophie. Blondel insisted on a philosophy of action. Laberthonnière criticized Plato and Aristotle for reducing life to the contemplation of abstractions. Paul Ricoeur has not yet finished his three-volume philosophy of the will. And in similar directions move pragmatists, personalists, and many existentialists. (Fs)

242c I too hold for the primacy of conscience, for the primacy of the questions that lead to deliberation, evaluation, decision. Still, responsible answers to those questions presuppose sound judgments of fact, of possibility, and of probability. But such sound judgments, in turn, presuppose that we have escaped the clutches of naive realism, empiricism, critical and absolute idealism, that we have succeeded in formulating a critical realism. The key to such a formulation is basically simple. It is the distinction already drawn between the infant's world of immediacy and the adult's world mediated by meaning. In the infant's world of immediacy the only objects to which we are related immediately are the objects of sensible intuition. But in the adult's world mediated by meaning the objects to which we are related immediately are the objects intended by our questioning and known by correct answering. In more traditional language, the objects intended are beings: what is to be known by intending Quid sit and An sit and by finding correct answers. (Fs)

243a I have been stressing a contrast between a world of immediacy and a world mediated by meaning. But I now must add certain further features that will round out the picture and, perhaps, forestall objections. The recurrent difficulty in cognitional theory and in psychology generally arises from a failure to distinguish between our actual performance and our abbreviated objectification of that performance. Both the world of immediacy and the world mediated by meaning are abbreviated objectifications. They are not full accounts of what actually occurs. But they are fair approximations to the accounts that people are prone to give of their own performance. Inasmuch as they are fair approximations to what people think they do, they also are fair approximations to the confusions in which cognitional theory becomes involved. (Fs)

243b Infancy, as studied and described by Jean Piaget, is a time of enormous operational development. It is a time in which we learn to use our limbs and senses and to coordinate different uses in all their possible combinations. It is the time in which we discover what is other than ourselves and learn to respond with appropriate affects. It is the time in which we learn to speak and so learn to move beyond the immediate to the world mediated by meaning. All this is true, but it would be untrue to suppose that the infant is a strict empiricist. His activity may be predominantly on the sensitive level but there is no reason to suppose that intelligent activity is to be excluded. (Fs)

244a Again, the entry into the world mediated by meaning does not exclude immediate consciousness of the operations by which that entry is effected. On the contrary, it is only by the objectification of such conscious operations, of our acts of understanding and formulating, of reflecting, weighing the evidence, and judging, of deliberating, evaluating, deciding, that we can reach any real apprehension of the mediation that meaning effects, of the broad and the fine structures of the world that meaning mediates. (Fs)



____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Christentum - Realität: Tertullian (alle Wirklichkeit ist körperlich); Materialismus der Stoa

Kurzinhalt: ... while his thinking is largely a matter of simile and metaphor, nonetheless there is to his expression an undertow of Stoic materialism.

Textausschnitt: 244b Insofar as Christianity is a reality, it is involved in the problems of realism. But this involvement is twofold. There is a remote involvement in which the problems of realism have not yet appeared. There is a proximate involvement in which the problems of realism gradually manifest themselves and meet with an implicit solution. Finally, there is the explicit involvement which arises when people discuss whether or not there is a Christian philosophy. Let us consider in turn the first two of these. (Fs)
244c First, then, there is the remote involvement inasmuch as Christianity is mediated by meaning. It is mediated by meaning in its communicative function inasmuch as it is preached. It is mediated by meaning in its cognitive function inasmuch as it is believed. It is mediated by meaning in its constitutive function inasmuch as it is a way of life that is lived. It is mediated by meaning in its effective function inasmuch as its precepts are put into practice. (Fs)

244d However, the ambiguity of realism is not absent from Christianity. For the Christian world is not exclusively a world mediated by meaning. It includes as well a world of immediacy. For there is the new man in Christ Jesus, and the new man is primarily, not the product of the preacher, not the fruit of one's own free choice, but the effect of God's grace. Moreover, though the matter has been disputed in various ways, in my opinion at least God's gift of his grace occurs not unconsciously but consciously. It is not confined to some metaphysical realm so that experiencing it would be impossible. It can come as a thunderclap as when, in the prophet Ezekiel's words, God plucks out man's heart of stone and replaces it with a heart of flesh. But more commonly it comes so quietly and gently that it is conscious indeed but not adverted to, not inquired into, not understood, not identified and named, not verified and affirmed. For, as you know, consciousness is one thing and knowledge is another. (Fs)

245a So much for the remote involvement of Christianity in the problems of realism. This involvement arises inasmuch as Christianity is a reality. It arises in two manners because, in part, Christianity is a reality in the world of immediacy, and in part, it is a reality in the world mediated by meaning. (Fs)

245b The proximate involvement of Christianity in the problems of realism arose in the developments effected in Christological thought in the third, fourth, and fifth centuries. We shall take these samples of Christian thought and find them to represent three views on the nature of reality. Tertullian we shall find to represent the influence of Stoic materialism; Origen to represent a variant of Platonist idealism; Athanasius to represent the thrust to realism implicit in the fact that, in part, Christianity is in the world mediated by meaning. (Fs)

245c Tertullian was concerned to refute an otherwise unknown Praxeas who maintained that God the Father was identical with God the Son and consequently that it was God the Father who was crucified on Calvary. Against this view Tertullian recites a creed very similar to our Apostles' Creed. He insists that God the Son is both real and really distinct from God the Father. Inevitably such a contention has its philosophic underpinnings, for it presupposes some notion of reality and some notion of what is really distinct. And so while Tertullian's intention is apologetic, while his main concern is to defend the faith, while his arguments are from Scripture, while his thinking is largely a matter of simile and metaphor, nonetheless there is to his expression an undertow of Stoic materialism. (Fs)

246a Ernest Evans, in his invaluable introduction, edition, translation, and commentary on Tertullian's Treatise against Praxeas,1 remarks that it was a Stoic fancy that all reality was corporeal. Cicero maintains that Zeno held every cause and every effect to be a body. Other authorities concluded that truth, knowledge, understanding, and mind were bodies because they produced effects. So it is that Tertullian approved the Stoic view that the arts were corporeal and, since the soul was nourished by the arts, the soul too must be corporeal (De Anima, 6). He would grant that corporeal and incorporeal constituted a logical disjunction (Adv. Hermog., 35), but he would also claim that what is incorporeal also is non-existent (De Carne Christi, II; De Res. Carnis, ii, 53; De Anima, 7).2 If one were to urge that invisible spirits are real and exist, he would answer that spirits are invisible to us but nonetheless they have their own bodies and shapes by which they are visible to God alone (Adv. Prax., 7). (Fs) (notabene)

246b It is within this horizon that the peculiarities of Tertullian's Christology have to be understood. He was aware that the Greek word logos meant both the rational principle within man and, as well, the language that man speaks. He maintained that God the Father always had within himself his rational principle, his wisdom. But when the Father at the moment of creation uttered his wisdom with the command, "Let there be light," then his wisdom by being uttered became a Son. Tertullian considered the objection that an utterance is just voice and sound and smitten air intelligible in the hearing, and for the rest an empty something void and incorporeal. But Tertullian denied that anything void and empty could come forth from God, least of all the Word through whom were made all things, since nothing can be made through something void and empty (Adv. Prax., 7). (Fs)

247a Further, Tertullian was careful to distinguish his position from that of the Gnostics, such as Valentine, who spoke of emissions from the pleroma. The Valentinian emission, he claimed, was separated from its source. In contrast, the Word is always in the Father, as he says "I am in the Father" On 14: 11); and always with God, as it is written, "And the Word was with God" (Jn 1: 1); and never separate from the Father or other than the Father, because "I and the Father are one" (Jn 10:30). To the comment that, if there are Father and Son, then there is not just one but two, Tertullian's reply is to distinguish root and shoot, spring and stream, the sun and its beam. He points out that root and shoot are two things but conjoined, and the spring and the river are two manifestations but undivided, that the sun and its beam are two aspects, but they cohere. Whatever proceeds from something must be another beside that from which it proceeds, but is it not for that reason separate from it (Adv. Prax., 8). (Fs) (notabene)

247b While he insisted that the Son was distinct from the Father and that the Holy Spirit was distinct from both Father and Son, Tertullian also insisted that there was only one God, only one substance. His justification was that there are three not in quality but in sequence, not in substance but in aspect, not in power but in manifestation, yet of one substance and one quality and one power (Adv. Prax., 2). (Fs)

247c Although Tertullian found very happy formulae for expressing Christian beliefs, still he did not draw one conclusion that later was drawn. If the Father is God and the Son is God, then all that is true of the Father must also be true of the Son, except that the Son is not the Father. For Tertullian there were things true of the Father but not of the Son. He could write, "There was a time when there was neither sin to make God a judge nor a Son to make God a Father" (Adv. Hermog, 31). Again, he wrote, "The Father is the whole substance, while the Son is an outflow and assignment of the whole, as he Himself professes, 'Because my Father is greater than I'" (Adv. Prax., 9; Jn. [14:28]). Again, he distinguished the Father as giving the order to create and the Son executing it (Adv. Prax., 12). In a later theology such expressions were regarded as subordinating the Son to the Father; for, if the Son is God, he has all the divine attributes and, if he has not all the divine attributes, then he is not God. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Christentum - Realität: Origines (Immaterialität von Vater und Sohn); Partizipation

Kurzinhalt: But the basic contrast lies in differing notions of reality. For Tertullian the real had to be bodily; ... But for Origen the real was idea, as in middle Platonism.

Textausschnitt: 248a While Origen also was later regarded as subordinationist, his thought unfolds in an entirely different climate of opinion. Where Tertullian considered the incorporeal to be nonexistent, Origen strongly and insistently affirmed the strict immateriality of both the Father and the Son.1 While Tertullian could admit the divine wisdom to be eternal, he held that the Son came into existence only at the creation of the world. In contrast, Origen held the Son to be no less eternal than the Father.2 Tertullian thought of the generation of the Son as of a bodily substance proceeding from the bodily substance of the Father but in no way separated from it. Origen rejected any account of the Son's generation that appealed to the analogy of human or animal generation or to some mythic extrusion from the godhead.3 For Origen the Son is the image of the Father; he proceeds from the Father spiritually as a choice from the mind: again, whatever the Father does, he also does (John 5:19).4 (Fs)

248b But the basic contrast lies in differing notions of reality. For Tertullian the real had to be bodily; it was what elsewhere I have named the already-out-there-now of extroverted animal consciousness. But for Origen the real was idea, as in middle Platonism. Moreover, because the Father and the Son were distinct, theirs had to be the reality of distinct ideas. The Father was divinity itself, but the Son was divine only by participation.5 The Father was goodness itself, but the Son was good only by participation.6 On the other hand, the Son was light itself, wisdom itself; truth itself, life itself, and justice itself, but the Father was the source of all of these and in himself something far better, far more profound, far more mysterious.7 (Fs)

249a The distinction between Father and Son is sharp and subordinationist. Their unity is what today would be called moral. We worship, he wrote, the Father of truth and the Son that is truth. They are two realities in respect of hypostasis, but a single one by consent, concord, and identity of will. So he who sees the Son, who is the effulgence of God's splendor and the stamp of God's very being, also will see the Father in him who is the image of God.1 It is an image in which participation reaches its supreme perfection for it consists in the Son's eternal contemplation of the Father and his constant acceptance of the Father's will.2 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Christentum - Realität: Tertullian, Origines, Athanasius -> 3. Möglichkeit; ens per verum innotescit

Kurzinhalt: But there is a third possibility, in which one's apprehension of reality is in the world mediated by meaning, where the meanings in question are affirmations and negations, that is, answers to questions for reflection.

Textausschnitt: 249b Let us now briefly revert to our discussion of the ambiguity of realism. There we distinguished two different meanings of the immediate object of our knowledge. There was the object in the world of immediacy and the object in the world mediated by meaning. The first is immediately experienced in the data of sense or of consciousness. The second is immediately intended in the questions we raise but mediately known in the correct answers we reach. We now must add that the questions we raise are of different kinds. There are questions for intelligence that ask, What? Why? How? There are questions for reflection that ask whether or not this or that really is so. There are questions for deliberation that ask whether or not this or that course of action is truly good. (Fs)

250a Now it would seem that Tertullian's Christology and, specifically, his identification of the incorporeal with the non-existent, are connected with an apprehension of reality in terms of the world of immediacy. Again, it would seem that Origen's Christology pertains to the world mediated by meaning, where the meanings in question are ideas, that is, answers to questions for intelligence. But there is a third possibility, in which one's apprehension of reality is in the world mediated by meaning, where the meanings in question are affirmations and negations, that is, answers to questions for reflection. It is this third view that finds expression in the Scholastic tag, ens per verum innotescit, reality becomes known through knowing what is true. It is this third view that we find in Christian preaching and teaching and more generally, in Christianity as a reality mediated by meaning. Finally, it is this third view that is implicit in conciliar pronouncements and particularly in the canons to the effect, if anyone says so and so, then let him be anathema. What is said is all-important to a group whose reality, in part, is mediated by meaning. (Fs) (notabene)

250b The origins, then, of Christian realism are twofold. Their root lies in Christian preaching and teaching and in local, regional, and ecumenical gatherings that sought to control preaching and teaching. But that root remained implicit for a long time. Tertullian wrote against Praxeas because he considered Praxeas' teaching to be mistaken and pernicious. Origen rejected Stoic materialism and opted for Platonism because that enabled him to treat of things of the spirit. But it was the Council of Nicea and the ensuing controversies that provoked from Athanasius, along with his other clarifications, the fundamental little rule that all that is said of the Father also is to be said of the Son except that the Son is Son and not Father.1 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Schoonenberg, Chalzedon (Chalcedon): Bedeutung: Person, Hypostase, Sohn; 3 Bedeutungen: "eins", Einheit; Möglichkeitsbedingunen der Inkarnation; dogmatischer Pluralismus - "ewige" Wahrheit

Kurzinhalt: To return, then, to Fr. Schoonenberg, it is true that Chalcedon does not speak of the actual personal pre-existence of the Logos or the Son. But ...

Textausschnitt: 257c To return, then, to Fr. Schoonenberg, it is true that Chalcedon does not speak of the actual personal pre-existence of the Logos or the Son. But it also is true that it speaks of the Son, our Lord Jesus Christ, perfect in divinity and the same perfect in humanity, before all ages begotten from the Father in his divinity, and in these last days the same for our sakes and our salvation born of the Virgin Mary, the Mother of God, according to his humanity. (Fs)

258a There remains the systematic issue. Just what was meant by "person or hypostasis" in the context of Chalcedon? To put the question equivalently but differently, How are we to understand these terms as they occur in the Chalcedonian decree without intruding into them the many and varied associations they have since acquired? As long as Scholastic theology was alive, answers were available. But today in many parts of the world Scholasticism has withered and vanished. Can anything be done to meet the current needs for clarification?

258b A first step in this direction I have already suggested. It is to overcome the ambiguity of realism. As long as the world of immediacy and the world mediated by meaning are not clearly distinguished, as long as the criteria to be used with respect to these two worlds are not clearly distinguished, confusion will be endless and attempts at clarification will largely be unsuccessful. (Fs)

258c A second step would be to distinguish three meanings of the word, "one." The first of these meanings is associated with experiential activity; it is "one more"; it is the numerical "one" in the sense that one is more than zero, two is more than one, three is more than two, and so on indefinitely. The second meaning of "one" is associated with understanding. Understanding grasps the functional unity of the parts of a machine, the functional and organic unity of a living thing, the developmental unity of a person's life. The third meaning of "one" is associated with judgment: it is "one" in the sense of identity. To affirm implies negations. Jones is all that Jones is, but he is not somebody else or all that somebody else is. He is himself and just himself. (Fs) (notabene)

258d A third step would be to state the conditions of the possibility of the Incarnation. A first condition would be that the Father, Son, and Spirit be identities in the positive sense: each is himself. A second condition would be that they be identities in the restrictive sense with regard to one another: The Father is not the Son; the Father not the Spirit; the Son is not the Spirit. A third condition would be that the Son need not be an identity in the restrictive sense with regard to some rational creature: the Son can become a man. A fourth condition is that a man may have his identity not in himself but in another. To affirm the possibility of the Incarnation is to affirm that these conditions can have been fulfilled. To affirm the Incarnation as a fact is to say that these conditions have been fulfilled. To say what the Incarnation means is to explain the conditions of its possibility. (Fs)

259a The foregoing statement is a statement of the meaning of the repeated "one and the same" in Cyril's second letter to Nestorius and in the decree of Chalcedon. There is in Christ, God and man, only one identity; that one identity is the identity of the Word; the man, Jesus, has an identity but not in himself but in the Word. Finally, the person or hypostasis of the second paragraph of the Chalcedonian decree refers back to the "one and the same" of the first paragraph. The distinction between persons and nature is added to state what is one and the same and what are not one and the same. The person is one and the same; the natures are not one and the same. While later developments put persons and natures in many further contexts, the context of Chalcedon needs no more than heuristic concepts.1 What is a person or hypostasis? It is in the Trinity what there are three of and in the Incarnation what there is one of. What is a nature? In the Trinity it is what there is one of and in the Incarnation it is what there are two of. (Fs)

259b I have still to relate the foregoing to what I said both in the Père Marquette lecture on Doctrinal Pluralism and once more in my chapter on "Doctrines" in Method in Theology.1 In both these writings I accepted the statement of the first Vatican council that what has been both revealed by God and defined by the Church is permanently valid in the sense determined by its own historical context. But similarly, in both this and other writings, I contrasted classicist assumptions to the effect that there exists de jure one fixed and immutable culture for the whole of mankind with the empirical fact that there have existed and exist several human cultures all of which are subject to development and decay. When classicist assumptions are pushed to the point of denying matters of fact, I feel I must disagree. The meaning of the term "person" at Chalcedon is not what commonly is understood by the term today, and theologians at least have to take that fact into account.2 (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Christentum - Realität: Zusammenfassung; Nizäa (Nicea) und folgende Konzilien: implizit -> Realität durch Urteil und Glaube

Kurzinhalt: ... that the reality of the world mediated by meaning was known not by experience alone, not by ideas alone or in conjunction with experience, but by true judgments and beliefs.

Textausschnitt: V. Conclusion

260a It is time to conclude. We have been discussing the origins of Christian realism. We began from an account of the ambiguity of realism with one meaning relevant to the world of immediacy and the other relevant to the world mediated by meaning. Between these extremes we intercalated the confusions of naive realists, empiricists, critical idealists, absolute idealists, and subsequent philosophies of pessimism, faith, conscience, power, life, action, will. (Fs)

260b Turning to Christianity we noted that both the world of immediacy and the world mediated by meaning were vital to it: the world of immediacy because of religious experience, because of God's love flooding our hearts through the Holy Spirit given to us (Rom. 5:5); the world mediated by meaning because divine revelation is God's own entry into man's world mediated by meaning. (Fs)

260c It remains, however, that the ambiguity of realism was not among the revealed truths. Christians had to find out for themselves that it was a mistake to assume with Tertullian that the criteria for the world of immediacy also held for the world mediated by meaning and so to conclude that what was incorporeal also was nonexistent. They had to find out for themselves that it was a mistake to assume with Origen that the meanings relevant to the world mediated by meaning were ideas, the contents of acts of understanding, and so to arrive at the conclusion that the Father was goodness itself and divinity itself while the Son was good and divine only by participation. At Nicea and in the numerous subsequent synods and decrees that kept multiplying as long as Constantius was emperor, there did emerge in some implicit fashion that the reality of the world mediated by meaning was known not by experience alone, not by ideas alone or in conjunction with experience, but by true judgments and beliefs. For that became the presupposition not only of their preaching and teaching but also of their deliberations, their decrees, and their anathemas. They wrote, explained, defended, impugned; they invented distinctions and used technical terms; they laid the foundations for the medieval endeavor in systematic thinking. In brief, they employed the criteria relevant to the world mediated by meaning, but they did not thematize the fact they were doing so. (Fs) (notabene)

261a Such, I conceive, were the origins of Christian realism. Implicit from the beginning in preaching and teaching, through mistakes and the correction of mistakes the implication gradually took shape in modes of procedure ever more elaborate and ever more refined in a long series of crises, debates, deliberations, decisions. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan über sein Werk Einsicht (Insight Revisited)

Kurzinhalt: The first eight chapters of Insight are a series of five-finger exercises inviting the reader to discover in himself and for himself just what happens when he understands. My aim is ...

Textausschnitt: 268b I worked at Insight from 1949 to 1953. During the first three years my intention was an exploration of methods generally in preparation for a study of the method of theology. But in 1952 it became clear that I was due to start teaching at the Gregorian University in Rome in 1953, so I changed my plan and decided to round off what I had done and publish it under the title, Insight, A Study of Human Understanding. (Fs)

268c The problem tackled in the book was complex indeed. At its root was a question of psychological fact. Human intellect does not intuit essences. It grasps in simplifying images intelligible possibilities that may prove relevant to an understanding of the data. However, naive realists cannot remain naive realists and at the same time acknowledge the psychological facts. For them knowing is a matter of taking a good look; objectivity is a matter of seeing just what is there to be seen. For them my account of human understanding would appear to present intelligence as merely subjective and so imply an empiricism and, if they managed to get beyond empiricism, they would find themselves mere idealists. Accordingly, besides convincing people of the precise manner in which human understanding operates and develops, I also had to persuade them to drop intuitionist assumptions and come to understand the discursive character of human knowledge. Besides the world of immediacy alone known to the infant, there is also the world mediated by meaning into which the infant gradually moves. The former is Kant's world in which our only intuitions are sensitive. The latter is the world of a critical realism in which the objects are intended when we ask questions and are known when the questions are answered correctly. (Fs)

269a The first eight chapters of Insight are a series of five-finger exercises inviting the reader to discover in himself and for himself just what happens when he understands. My aim is to help people experience themselves understanding, advert to the experience, distinguish it from other experiences, name and identify it, and recognize it when it recurs. My aim, I surmise, is parallel to Carl Rogers' aim of inducing his clients to advert to the feelings that they experience but do not advert to, distinguish, name, identify, recognize. (Fs) (notabene)

269b The first chapter draws on instances of insight in mathematics. I began there because it is in mathematics that the content and context of an insight are more clearly and precisely defined. Again, it is in mathematics that one has the clearest proof of the existence of preconceptual operations on the intellectual level. Apart from its mistaken assumption of uniqueness, Euclidean geometry is not mistaken. But this does not mean that it is rigorous. Euclidean proofs frequently rest on valid but unacknowledged insights.1 Contemporary mathematicians employ highly formalized methods to avoid the use of insights that are not explicitly formulated, for what is not explicitly formulated is not subject to control. (Fs)

270a Chapters two to five draw on physics for their illustrations. Here insights are well enough defined, but they are much more in a context of ongoing process. Again, while mathematical formulations rest on insights, and while the insights rest on diagrams and other symbols, still this process can remain implicit, with explicit attention concentrated on rigorously logical formulation and proof. In contrast, in the natural sciences, besides the logical operations of description, the formulation of hypotheses, the deduction of assumptions and implications, there also occur such nonlogical operations as observation, discovery, the planning and execution of experiments, the presence or absence of verification and, in the latter case, the modification of the hypothesis or the substitution of another hypothesis. So the second chapter is devoted to ongoing structures of discovery, the third to the canons of empirical method, the fourth to the complementarity of classical and statistical heuristic structures, and the fifth to a clarification of the meaning of special relativity. (Fs)

270b Chapters six and seven are concerned with the operations of common-sense intelligence. While this is the universal manifestation of intelligence, it also is the most difficult to objectify clearly and distinctly. Common sense is more at home in doing than in speaking, and its speaking is apt to be terse and elliptical, or else metaphorical if not fanciful. It is a development of intelligence that is prior to that achieved in system, science, logic, and so it is prior to the systematic mode of differentiated consciousness. Common sense does not argue from principles but attends to proverbs, i.e., to brief bits of advice that are worth attending to when the occasion arises. It does not define terms but, along with the analysts, knows when terms are used appropriately. It is a specialization of intelligence in the realm of the particular and the concrete and, while it always remains a necessary specialization, still it is open to as many revisions and qualifications as there develop other specializations which take over areas that common sense once assigned to its own omnicompetence. (Fs)

271a Chapter six touches on the bias of the dynamic unconscious; here I wish to take advantage of the present opportunity to draw attention to two works that I found very enlightening and, in some measure, to confirm the surmises I expressed in Insight. Herbert Fingarette in The Self in Transformation2 conceived neurosis as cumulatively misinterpreted experience. Both the experience and the misinterpretation are conscious though not adverted to, identified, named, distinguished from other experience and interpretations. What is properly unconscious and, as well, the goal of the psyche's profound striving is the correct interpretation of the misinterpreted experience. Eugene Gendlin in "A Theory of Personality Change"3 set himself the task of saying just what was meant by personality change and just how psychotherapy brings it about. I found it a most helpful study. (Fs) (notabene)

271b It was about 1937-38 that I became interested in a theoretical analysis of history. I worked out an analysis on the model of a threefold approximation. Newton's planetary theory had a first approximation in the first law of motion: bodies move in a straight line with constant velocity unless some force intervenes. There was a second approximation when the addition of the law of gravity between the sun and the planet yielded an elliptical orbit for the planet. A third approximation was reached when the influence of the gravity of the planets on one another is taken into account to reveal the perturbed ellipses in which the planets actually move. The point to this model is, of course, that in the intellectual construction of reality it is not any of the earlier stages of the construction but only the final product that actually exists. Planets do not move in straight lines nor in properly elliptical orbits; but these conceptions are needed to arrive at the perturbed ellipses in which they actually do move. (Fs)

272a In my rather theological analysis of human history, my first approximation was the assumption that men always do what is intelligent and reasonable, and its implication was an ever increasing progress. The second approximation was the radical inverse insight that men can be biased, and so unintelligent and unreasonable in their choices and decisions. The third approximation was the redemptive process resulting from God's gift of his grace to individuals and from the manifestation of his love in Christ Jesus. The whole idea was presented in chapter twenty of Insight. The sundry forms of bias were presented in chapters six and seven on common sense. The notion of moral impotence, which I had studied in some detail when working on Aquinas' notion of gratia operans in my dissertation, was worked out in chapter eighteen on the possibility of ethics. (Fs)

272b The first seven chapters of Insight deal with human intelligence insofar as it unifies data by setting up intelligible correlations. The eighth chapter moves on to a quite different type of insight, in which one grasps a concrete unity-identity-whole. This I referred to as a "thing," and I contrasted it with the already-out-there-now-real of extroverted animality, which I referred to as "body." Both of these, of course, are to be contrasted with Aristotle's substance, which is the first of a series of predicaments and arises, not from a study of human intelligence, but from an analysis that basically is grammatical. It arises, I mean, not in an account of the genesis of the mediation of a world through meaning, but in a study of the meanings so generated. Finally, when Aristotle's notion of substance is taken over by a naive realist, it acquires the meaning of what is underneath the already-out-there-now-real.1 (Fs)

273a Chapters nine, ten, and eleven have to do with judgment. Chapter nine endeavors to say what we mean by judgment. Chapter ten investigates the immediate ground of judgment and finds it in a grasp of the virtually unconditioned, a view that was preceded in my thinking by some acquaintance with Newman's illative sense. It differs from the naive realist and empiricist opinion, which thinks of verification simply as a matter of attending to data and not as a matter of finding data that fit in with a hypothesis. It further differs, of course, from the old notion that judging can be a matter of comparing concepts and discovering that one entails another. Such entailment we considered to yield no more than analytic propositions. To reach analytic principles the compared concepts in their defined sense have to be verified in experience. (Fs)

273b Chapter eleven asks whether any true judgments occur and it attempts to meet the issue by asking whether I am a knower. The "I" is the unity-identity-whole given in consciousness; a "knower" is one who performs the operations investigated in the previous ten chapters; the reader is asked to find out for himself and in himself whether it is virtually unconditioned that he is a knower. The alternative to an affirmative answer, as presented in Method in Theology, is the admission that one is a nonresponsible, nonreasonable, nonintelligent somnambulist.2 (Fs)

273c Not only are the "I" and its cognitional operations to be affirmed, but also the pattern in which they occur is acknowledged as invariant, not of course in the sense that further methodical developments are impossible, nor in the sense that fuller and more adequate knowledge of the pattern is unattainable, but in the sense that any attempt to revise the patterns as now known would involve the very operations that the pattern prescribes. (Fs)
273d Chapter twelve attempts an account of the notion of being. It distinguishes notion, idea, concept, and knowledge of being. Knowledge of being occurs in true judgments. Concepts of being are objectifications of the notion of being. The idea of being is the content of the act of understanding that understands everything about everything. The notion of being is our ability and drive to ask questions for intelligence (What? Why? How? What for? How often?) and for reflection (Is that so? Are you certain?). That ability and drive is prior to all acts of understanding and also to all concepts and judgments. As there is no limit to the questions we can ask, the notion of being is unrestricted. Accordingly, it is not categorial but transcendental. (Fs)

274a A point not made in Insight I have since learnt from Fr. Coreth. It regards spheres of being. Real being is known when the fulfilling conditions are data of sense or of consciousness. Restricted spheres of being are known when the fulfilling conditions are not data but some lesser requirement: the merely logical is what satisfies criteria of clarity, coherence, and rigor; the mathematical is any freely chosen set of suitable postulates with their conclusions rigorously drawn; the hypothetical is an instance of the logical that has some likelihood of being relevant to an understanding of the data of sense or of consciousness. Finally, there is transcendent being, and to this topic we return in chapter nineteen. (Fs) (notabene)

274b Chapter thirteen raises the key question of objectivity. It is a key question because insights are not intuitions. They are not of themselves knowledge of what really is so. Of themselves they merely grasp what may be relevant to what one is imagining and, if one's imagining is sufficiently accurate, to an understanding of what is so. Now if the intuitionist view of insight is mistaken, some other meaning has to be found for object, objective, objectivity. Hence, I distinguished a principal notion and three partial notions. The principal notion is that A and B are objects if it is true that (1) A is, (2) B is, and (3) A is not B. Further, if it is true that A is the subject and that B is not the subject, then there occurs an instance of the subject-object relation. The three partial notions of objectivity were referred to as the experiential, the normative, and the absolute. Absolute objectivity is reached with the grasp of a virtually unconditioned. Experiential objectivity is provided by the data as given. Normative objectivity arises when the exigences of one's intelligence and of one's reasonableness are met. If the virtually unconditioned is represented by the syllogism, If X, then Y; but X; therefore Y, then the major becomes known through normative objectivity, the minor becomes known through experiential objectivity, and the virtually unconditioned becomes known when the conclusion is drawn. (Fs)

275a With chapter thirteen the book could end. The first eight chapters explore human understanding. The next five reveal how correct understanding can be discerned and incorrect rejected. However, I felt that if I went no further, my work would be regarded as just psychological theory incapable of grounding a metaphysics. Unfortunately that type of argument could be repeated. A metaphysics could be possible and yet an ethics impossible. An ethics could be possible and yet arguments for God's existence impossible. In that fashion seven more chapters and an epilogue came to be written. Some of the points made then I still like; others have been superseded in the light of further reading, conversing, reflecting. (Fs)

275b I have not been moved to change my mind about the first three chapters on metaphysics, i.e., on chapters fourteen, fifteen, sixteen. But in chapter seventeen my usage of the word "myth" is out of line with current usage. My contrast of mystery and myth was between symbolic expressions of positions and of counter-positions. It was perhaps justifiable in the context of Insight, but it is not going to be understood outside of it, so another mode of expression is desirable. Further, the account of mystery has to be filled out with what chapter four of Method in Theology says about religious experience. (Fs)

275c Similarly, the third section of chapter seventeen on truth of interpretation has been given a more concrete expression in chapters seven to eleven of Method. A systematic account of the problems of interpretation there yield place in the later work to an orderly set of directions on what is to be done towards moving to the attainment of universal viewpoint. In this connection I might mention a doctoral dissertation presented at Fordham by Terry J. Tekippe on The Universal Viewpoint and the Relationship of Philosophy and Theology in the Works of Bernard Lonergan. It illustrates very well an intermediate position between what I had worked out in Insight and, on the other hand, the views presented in Method in Theology. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan über den Unterschied: Einsicht (Insight) - Methode der Theologie

Kurzinhalt: In Insight the good was the intelligent and reasonable. In Method the good is a distinct notion. It is intended in questions for deliberation: Is this worthwhile?

Textausschnitt: 276a A principal source of the difference between these two works is that I was transferred from Toronto to the Gregorian University in Rome in the summer of 1953. For the first ten years I was there I lectured in alternate years on the Incarnate Word and on the Trinity to both second and third year theologians. They were about six hundred and fifty strong and between them, not individually but distributively, they seemed to read everything. It was quite a challenge. I had learnt honesty from my teachers of philosophy at Heythrop College. I had had an introduction to modern science from Joseph's Introduction to Logic and from the mathematics tutor at Heythrop, Fr. Charles O'Hara. I had become something of an existentialist from my study of Newman's A Grammar of Assent. I had become a Thomist through the influence of Marshal mediated to me by Stefanos Stefanu and through Bernard Leaning's lectures on the unicum esse in Christo. In a practical way I had become familiar with historical work both in my doctoral dissertation on gratia operans and in my later study of verbum in Aquinas. Insight was the fruit of all this. It enabled me to achieve in myself what since has been called Die anthropologische Wende.1 Without the explicit formulations that later were possible, metaphysics had ceased for me to be what Fr. Coreth named the Gesamt- und Grundwissenschaft. The empirical sciences were allowed to work out their basic terms and relations apart from any consideration of metaphysics. The basic inquiry was cognitional theory and, while I still spoke in terms of a faculty psychology, in reality I had moved out of its influence and was conducting an intentionality analysis. (Fs) (notabene)

277a The new challenge came from the Geisteswissenschaften, from the problems of hermeneutics and critical history, from the need of integrating nineteenth-century achievement in this field with the teachings of Catholic religion and Catholic theology. It was a long struggle that can be documented from my Latin and English writing during this period and from the doctoral courses I conducted De intellectu et methodo, De systemate et historia, and eventually De methodo theologiae. The eventual outcome has been the book, Method in Theology. (Fs)

277b In Insight the good was the intelligent and reasonable. In Method the good is a distinct notion. It is intended in questions for deliberation: Is this worthwhile? Is it truly or only apparently good? It is aspired to in the intentional response of feeling to values. It is known in judgments of value made by a virtuous or authentic person with a good conscience. It is brought about by deciding and living up to one's decisions. Just as intelligence sublates sense, just as reasonableness sublates intelligence, so deliberation sublates and thereby unifies knowing and feeling. (Fs)

277c Again, in Insight the treatment of God's existence and nature, while developed along the lines of the book, nonetheless failed to provide the explicit context towards which the book was moving. In Method the question of God is considered more important than the precise manner in which an answer is formulated, and our basic awareness of God comes to us not through our arguments or choices but primarily through God's gift of his love. It is argued that natural and systematic theology should be fused in the manner of Aquinas' Contra Gentiles and Summa theologiae. (Fs)

277d Finally, what is perhaps novel in Insight, is taken for granted in Method. The starting point is not facts but data. Development is a gradual accumulation of insights that complement, qualify, correct one another. Formulation sets the development within its cultural context. Marshalling and weighing the evidence reveals judgment to be possible, probable, and at times certain. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Authentizität - Selbsttranszendenz

Kurzinhalt: ... human authenticity is a matter of following the built-in law of the human spirit ... in the measure we fulfil these conditions of being human persons, we also achieve self-transcendence both in the field of knowledge and in the field of action ...

Textausschnitt: 1. Authenticity

165b First, then, authenticity. For I wish to begin from what is simply human and, indeed, from a contemporary apprehension of what it is to be human. There is the older, highly logical, and so abstract, static, and minimal apprehension of being human. It holds that being human is something independent of the merely accidental, and so one is pronounced human whether or not one is awake or asleep, a genius or a moron, a saint or a sinner, young or old, sober or drunk, well or ill, sane or crazy. In contrast with the static, minimal, logical approach, there is the contemporary, concrete, dynamic, maximal view that endeavors to envisage the range of human potentiality and to distinguish authentic from unauthentic realization of that potentiality. On this approach, being human is ambivalent: one can be human authentically, genuinely, and one can be human unauthentically. Moreover, besides ambivalence, there also is dialectic: authenticity never is some pure, serene, secure possession; it is always precarious, ever a withdrawal from unauthenticity, ever in danger of slipping back into unauthenticity. (Fs) (notabene)

166a On this view, then, the basic question is, What is authentic or genuine realization of human potentiality? In a word, my answer is that authentic realization is a self-transcending realization. So I must attempt to describe what I mean by self-transcending. I shall illustrate five different instances and conclude that the last four of the five form an ordered unity. (Fs)

166b In dreamless sleep, we are still alive. We are operating in accord with the laws of physics, chemistry, and biology. It may be said that we are ourselves but not that we are reaching beyond ourselves and, much less, that we are rising above ourselves. But when we begin to dream, consciousness emerges. However helpless, however lacking in initiative, the dreamer is an intending subject. What is intended, commonly is obscure, fragmentary, symbolic. In so-called dreams of the night the source of the dream is one's somatic state, say, the state of one's digestion. But in dreams of the morning the dreamer is anticipating his waking state; he is recollecting his world; he is beginning to adopt a stance within that world. In the dream of the morning, then, the dreamer has got beyond himself; he is concerned with what is distinct from himself; he is anticipating his self-transcendence. (Fs)

166c An enormously richer self-transcendence emerges when one awakes. There is the endless variety of things to be seen, sounds to be heard, odors to be sniffed, tastes to be palated, shapes and textures to be touched. We feel pleasure and pain, desire and fear, joy and sorrow, and in such feelings there seem to reside the mass and momentum of our lives. We move about in various manners, assume now this and now that posture and position, and by the fleeting movements of our facial muscles, communicate to others the quiet pulse or sudden surge of our feelings. (Fs)

166d Still, sensations, feelings, movements are confined to the narrow strip of space-time occupied by immediate experience. But beyond that there is a vastly larger world. Nor is anyone content with immediate experience. Imagination wants to fill out and round off the picture. Language makes questions possible, and intelligence makes them fascinating. So we ask why and what and what for and how. Our answers construct, serialize, extrapolate, generalize. Memory and tradition and belief put at our disposal the tales of travellers, the stories of clans or nations, the exploits of heroes, the treasures of literature, the discoveries of science, the reflections of philosophers, and the meditations of holy men. Each of us has his own little world of immediacy, but all such worlds are just minute strips within a far larger world, a world constructed by imagination and intelligence, mediated by words and meaning, and based largely upon belief. (Fs)

167a If the larger world is one and the same, still there are as many different constructions of it as there are stages in human development and differences in human cultures. But such diversity only serves to bring to light a still further dimension of self-transcendence. Beyond questions for intelligence-such as what and why and how and what for-there are the questions for reflection that ask, Is that so or is it not so? Is that certain or is it only probable? Unlike questions for intelligence, these can be answered by a simple "Yes" or "No." How we can give such answers, is beside my present purpose; but what such answers mean, is very much to it. For when we say that this or that really and truly is so, we do not mean that this is what appears, or what we imagine, or what we would like, or what we think, or what seems to be so, or what we would be inclined to say. No doubt, we frequently have to be content with such lesser statements. But the point I would make is that the greater statement is not reducible to the lesser. When we seriously affirm that something really and truly is so, we are making the claim that we have got beyond ourselves in some absolute fashion, somehow have got hold of something that is independent of ourselves, somehow have reached beyond, transcended ourselves. (Fs)
168a I have been endeavoring to clarify the notion of self-transcendence by contrasting, first, dreamless sleep with the beginnings of consciousness in the dream, secondly, the dreaming with the waking subject, thirdly, the world of immediate experience and the enormously vaster real world in which we live our lives, fourthly that larger world as constructed by intelligence with the same larger world as known to have been constructed as it really is. (Fs)

168b There remains a still further dimension of self-transcendence. Our illustrations, so far, have mainly regarded knowledge. There remains action. Beyond questions for intelligence-what? why? how? what for?-there are questions for reflection-is that so? But beyond both there are questions for deliberation. Beyond the pleasures we enjoy and the pains we dread, there are the values to which we may respond with the whole of our being. On the topmost level of human consciousness the subject deliberates, evaluates, decides, controls, acts. At once he is practical and existential: practical inasmuch as he is concerned with concrete courses of action; existential inasmuch as control includes self-control, and the possibility of self-control involves responsibility for the effects of his actions on others and, more basically, on himself. The topmost level of human consciousness is conscience. (Fs)

168c However, man's self-control can proceed from quite different grounds. It can tend to be mere selfishness. Then the process of deliberation, evaluation, decision, is limited to determining what is most to one's advantage, what best serves one's interests, what on the whole yields a maximum of pleasure and a minimum of pain. At the opposite pole it can tend to be concerned solely with values: with the vital values of health and strength; with the social values enshrined in family and custom, society and education, the state and the law, the economy and technology, the church or sect; with the cultural values of religion and art, language and literature, science, philosophy, history, theology; with the achieved personal value of one dedicated to realizing values in himself and promoting their realization in others. (Fs)

169a In the measure that one's living, one's aims, one's achievements are a response to values, in that measure self-transcendence is effected in the field of action. One has got beyond mere selfishness. One has become a principle of benevolence and beneficence. One has become capable of genuine collaboration and of true love. In the measure that self-transcendence in the field of action characterizes the members of a society, in that measure their world not only is constructed by imagination and intelligence, mediated by words and meaning, based by and large on belief; it also is a world motivated and regulated not by self-seeking but by values, not by what is only apparently good but by what truly is good. (Fs) (notabene)

169b Now if we compare the last four of our modes of self-transcendence, we find that they form an interlocking unity. Experiencing is presupposed and complemented by inquiry and understanding. Experiencing and understanding are presupposed and complemented by reflecting and judging. Experiencing, understanding, and judging, are presupposed and complemented by deliberating and deciding. The four modes are interdependent, and each later level sublates those that precede in the sense that it goes beyond them, introduces something entirely new, makes that new element a new basis of operation; but so far from crowding or interfering with its predecessors, it preserves them, perfects them, and extends their relevance and significance. Inquiry sharpens our powers of observation, understanding enormously extends the field of data one can master, reflection and judgment force inquiry to attend to ever further data and force understanding to revise its previous achievements, deliberation turns attention from what is to what can be, to what probably would be and above all, to what really is worthwhile. (Fs)

169c To conclude, human authenticity is a matter of following the built-in law of the human spirit. Because we can experience, we should attend. Because we can understand, we should inquire. Because we can reach the truth, we should reflect and check. Because we can realize values in ourselves and promote them in others, we should deliberate. In the measure that we follow these precepts, in the measure we fulfil these conditions of being human persons, we also achieve self-transcendence both in the field of knowledge and in the field of action. (Fs)

170a Now you may have been wondering why I have spent so much time on so remote a topic as authenticity. I have had three reasons for doing so. First, I wished to get out of the abstract and static context dictated by logical clarity, coherence, and rigor and into the concrete, open, and ongoing context dictated by attention, inquiry, reflection, and deliberation. Secondly, I wished to get out of the context of a faculty psychology with its consequent alternatives of voluntarism, intellectualism, sentimentalism, and sensism, none of which has any serious, viable meaning, and into the context of intentionality analysis that distinguishes and relates the manifold of human conscious operations and reveals that together they head man towards self-trauscendence. Thirdly, I wished to have a base, a starting-point, a springboard, in people as they are and as they can discover themselves to be; for without such a base, talk about the Spirit, the Word, the apostolate, the Jesuit priesthood is all in the air; it sounds abstract, irrelevant, without substance. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Bewusstsein; Liebe Gottes (Geist): Datum der Erfahrung, aber nicht des Wissens; Rudolf Otto; Ignatius, Rahner: Tröstung ohne Grund

Kurzinhalt: Because that dynamic state is conscious without being known, it is an experience of mystery. Because the dynamic state is being in love, the mystery is not merely attractive but fascinating:

Textausschnitt: 2. The Spirit

170b I have said that human authenticity is a matter of achieving self-transcendence. I have said that such achievement is always precarious, always a withdrawal from unauthenticity, always in danger of slipping back into unauthenticity. This is not a cheerful picture, and you may ask whether ordinary human beings ever seriously and perseveringly transcend themselves. (Fs)

170c I think they do so when they fall in love. Then their being becomes being-in-love. Such being-in-love has its antecedents, its causes, its conditions, its occasions. But once it has occurred and as long as it lasts, it takes over. It becomes the first principle. From it flow one's desires and fears, one's joys and sorrows, one's discernment of values, one's vision of possibilities, one's decisions and deeds. (Fs)

171a Being-in-love is of different kinds. There is the love of intimacy, of husband and wife, of parents and children. There is the love of one's fellowmen with its fruit in the achievement of human welfare. There is the love of God with one's whole heart and whole soul, with all one's mind and all one's strength (Mk. 12: 30). It is God's love flooding our hearts through the Holy Spirit given to us (Rom. 5:5). In it was grounded the conviction of St. Paul that "... there is nothing in death or life, in the realm of spirits or superhuman powers, in the world as it is or the world as it shall be, in the forces of the universe-nothing in all creation that can separate us from the love of God in Christ Jesus our Lord" (Rom. 8:38-39). ... (Fs)

171b Being in love with God, as experienced, is being in love in an unrestricted fashion. All love is self-surrender, but being in love with God is being in love without limits or qualifications or conditions or reservations. It is with one's whole heart and whole soul and all one's mind and all one's strength. Just as a total openness to all questioning is our capacity for self-transcendence, so too an unrestricted being in love is the proper fulfilment of that capacity. (Fs) (notabene)

171c Because that love is the proper fulfilment of our capacity, fulfilment brings a deep-set joy that can remain despite humiliation, privation, pain, betrayal, desertion. Again, that fulfilment brings a radical peace, the peace that the world cannot give. That fulfilment bears fruit in acts of love for one's neighbor, a love that strives mightily to bring about the kingdom of God on this earth. On the other hand, the absence of that fulfilment opens the way to the trivialization of human life in the pursuit of fun, to the harshness of human life that results from the ruthless exercise of power, to despair about human welfare springing up from the conviction that the universe is absurd. (Fs)

172a The fulfilment that is being in love with God is not the product of our knowledge and choice. It is God's gift. Like all being in love, as distinct from particular acts of loving, it is a first principle. So far from resulting from our knowledge and choice, it dismantles and abolishes the horizon within which our knowing and choosing went on, and it sets up a new horizon within which the love of God transvalues our values and the eyes of that love transform our knowing. (Fs)

172b Though not the product of our knowing and choosing, it is not unconscious. On the contrary, it is a conscious, dynamic state, manifesting itself in what St. Paul named the harvest of the Spirit: love, joy, peace, kindness, goodness, fidelity, gentleness, and self-control (Gal. 5:22). (Fs) (notabene)

172c To say that this dynamic state is conscious is not to say that it is known. What is conscious, indeed, is experienced. But human knowing is not just experiencing. Human knowing includes experiencing but adds to it attention, scrutiny, inquiry, insight, conception, naming, reflecting, checking, judging. The whole problem of cognitional theory is to effect the transition from operations as experienced to operations as known. A great part of psychiatry is helping people to make the transition from conscious feelings to known feelings. In like manner the gift of God's love ordinarily is not objectified in knowledge, but remains within subjectivity as a dynamic vector, a mysterious undertow, a fateful call to a dreaded holiness. (Fs)

172d Because that dynamic state is conscious without being known, it is an experience of mystery. Because the dynamic state is being in love, the mystery is not merely attractive but fascinating: to it one belongs, by it one is possessed. Because it is an unrestricted, unmeasured being in love, the mystery is out of this world; it is otherworldly; it evokes awe. Because it is a love so different from the selfish self it transcends, it evokes fear and terror. Of itself, then, and apart from any particular religious context in which it is interpreted, the experience of the gift of God's love is an experience of the holy, of Rudolph Otto's mysterium tremendum et fascinans. Again, it is what Paul Tillich named a being grasped by ultimate concern. Again, it corresponds to Ignatius of Loyola's consolation without a cause, as interpreted by Karl Rahner, namely, an experience with a content but without an apprehended object. (Fs)

173a I have distinguished different levels of consciousness, and now I must add that the gift of God's love is on the topmost level. It is not the sensitive type of consciousness that emerged with sensing, feeling, moving. It is not the intellectual type that is added when we inquire, understand, think. It is not the rational type that emerges when we reflect, weigh the evidence, judge. It is the type of consciousness that also is conscience, that deliberates, evaluates, decides, controls, acts. But it is this type of consciousness at its root, as brought to fulfilment, as having undergone conversion, as possessing a basis that may be broadened and deepened and heightened and enriched but not superseded, as ever more ready to deliberate and evaluate and decide and act with the easy freedom of those that do all good because they are in love. The gift of God's love takes over the ground and root of the fourth and highest level of man's waking consciousness. It takes over the peak of the soul, the apex animae. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Priester, priest: zweifache Bedeutung des Wortes; allgemeines Priestertum; Bischof, Diakon

Kurzinhalt: From this twofold use of the word, priest, there can arise some confusion. The priesthood of all the faithful means, not that all the faithful are elders, presbúteroi, but that all are hiereis, concerned with to hierón, the sacred.

Textausschnitt: 180b A few notes are in order. The Greek word for elder is presbúteros. From it are derived the English, priest, the French, prêtre, the German, Priester, the Italian, prete. But while the New Testament thinks of the elder chiefly as leading and teaching, later thought gives more prominence to the priest's role as dispenser of the sacraments. (Fs)

180c Again, while the English word, priest, is derived from the Greek, presbúteros, it also is used to translate the Greek, hiereis, and the Latin, sacerdos. Later on these terms were used to refer to members of the Christian clergy, but in the New Testament they refer to Jewish and pagan priests, or to Christ, or to all the faithful. (Fs)

180d From this twofold use of the word, priest, there can arise some confusion. The priesthood of all the faithful means, not that all the faithful are elders, presbúteroi, but that all are hiereis, concerned with to hierón, the sacred. (Fs)

180e Finally, the tasks performed by the elders elsewhere, were performed by untitled laborers at Thessalonika. To the Thessalonians Paul wrote: "We beg you, brothers, to acknowledge those who are working so hard among you, and in the Lord's fellowship are your leaders and counsellors. Hold them in the highest possible esteem and affection for the work they do" (i Thes. 5:12). But though the letter to the Romans does allude to the one that presides (Rom. 12:8), and First Corinthians speaks of gifts of guidance (1 Cor. 12:28), the silence about local leaders in much of St. Paul's writing suggests a gradual development. (Fs)

181a There remain bishops and deacons. In two passages it would seem that these terms denote, not simply "overseer" and "helper," but ranks or orders in the church. The letter to the Philippians salutes all the faithful there with the bishops and the deacons (Phil. 1:1). The first letter to Timothy lists the qualities to be required first of bishops (1 Tim. 3:1-7) and then of deacons (1 Tim. 3:8-13). The term "deacon" occurs elsewhere frequently enough, but it seems to mean simply a helper. The term "bishop" occurs on three other occasions: once it is applied to Christ (1 Pt. 2:25); twice it is applied to persons who in the context have already been referred to as elders (Acts 20:17, 28; Ti. 1:5-9). It seems to be doubtful that those named bishops in the New Testament were bishops in the later sense: first, they are not assigned functions distinct from those of elders; secondly, there hardly could be successors to the apostles when the apostles were still around. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Second Collection

Titel: A Second Collection

Stichwort: Lonergan -> 3 Kennzeichen unserer Zeit: Modernität, Säkularismus, Selbstzerstörung (Zerstörung des Glaubens, reduktionistische Sicht des Menschen, Diktat der Erfolgreichen)

Kurzinhalt: A third feature of contemporary society is the consequence of secularism ...
A second distortion occurs in man's apprehension of man ... A third distortion is in the realm of technique. Applied science and consequent inventions ...

Textausschnitt: 6. The Jesuit Today

183a A principal function of the Society of Jesus, in its original conception, was to meet crises. There is a crises of the first magnitude today. For a principal duty of priests is to lead and teach the people of God. But all leadership and all teaching occurs within social structures and through cultural channels. In the measure that one insists on leading and teaching within structures that no longer function and through channels that no longer exist, in that very measure leadership and teaching cease to exist. The sheep are without shepherds: they are disoriented, bewildered, lost. Indeed, what is true of the sheep, can also be true of the shepherds as well: they too can be disoriented, bewildered, lost. (Fs) (notabene)

183b Perhaps the best I can attempt will be to outline three fundamental features of our time: modernity, secularism, and self-destructiveness. (Fs)
183c By modernity I do not mean just anything that exists or functions today. I mean the basic developments out of which has come the modern world. Of these the first is empirical science. It is something quite different from the notion of science set forth in Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. Not only is it a new notion but also it admits application, and its application has resulted in industrialization, urbanization, automation, a population explosion, mass media, instantaneous world news, rapid transportation, guided missiles, and thermonuclear bombs. (Fs)

183d Next, despite the Renaissance ideal of speaking Latin, writing Greek, and reading Hebrew, there developed the modern languages and literatures. In the nineteenth century new conceptions and procedures were introduced into philology, hermeneutics, and history by a phalanx of investigators following the lead of Friedrich Wolf, Friedrich Schleiermacher, August Boeckh, and Leopold von Ranke. The classicist, normative notion of culture was replaced by an empirical notion: a culture came to denote the set of meanings and values inherent in a way of life. Human studies, Geisteswissenschaften, set about investigating, understanding, depicting the cultures of mankind. All were found to be man-made, contingent, subject to development, propagation, alteration, decay. All were found to have their good points and their weaknesses and, when to knowledge of them was added respect for them, there resulted pluralism. The new methods, applied to Hebrew and Christian religion, made it plain that one had to dilute conciliar statements about quod tenet atque semper tenuit sancta mater ecclesia. Not only was development a fact that had to be acknowledged, not only were previous theological positions to be reversed, but the whole conception and method of theology has had to be overhauled. (Fs)

184a The natural sciences and the new human studies have had their repercussions on philosophy. Positivism would drop philosophy and make sociology the queen of the sciences. Kantians offer a foundation for science, absolute idealists set forth a super-science, Kierkegaard, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, Blondel, American pragmatists, and European existentialists turn to decision and action. The Catholic decision, promulgated by Leo XIII in Aeterni Patris, was "Back to Aquinas " While this movement flourished in the early part of this century, in the last decade it has completely collapsed, first, because historical studies of the medieval period made any accurate statement of Thomist thought enormously complicated and permanently open to revision and, secondly, because the infiltration of the new types of human studies into theology necessitated a far more sophisticated type of philosophy than the medieval world could furnish. However, as yet there is no generally accepted up-to-date philosophy and, until there is, we can only expect a theological pluralism far more radical than the old-style pluralism of Thomists, Scotists, Suarezians, and so on. Such pluralism is the first item on the agenda of the recently formed International Theological Commission. (Fs)

184b The problems that Catholics finally are facing have long existed. In his book, The Moden Schism, Martin Marty has them splitting the West into a religious minority and a secularist majority between the years 1840 and 1870. Further, he distinguished three types of secularists. In continental Europe secularists considered religion an evil and aimed at extirpating it. In Great Britain they considered it a private affair of no importance. In the United States religious leaders themselves tended to adapt religion to the secularizing trends of the times. But where religion is persecuted or ridiculed or watered down, there is unbelief, and unbelief is contagious. When everyone believes except the village atheist, doubting is almost impossible. When few believe, doubting is spontaneous, and believing is difficult. (Fs)

185a A third feature of contemporary society is the consequence of secularism. It was Newman's theorem in The Idea of a University that to suppress a part of human knowledge has three effects: first, it results in ignorance of that part; secondly, it mutilates what of itself is an organic whole; thirdly, it causes distortion in the remainder in which man endeavors to compensate for the part that has been suppressed. On this showing, one is to expect that secularism not only leads to ignorance of religion but also mutilates knowledge as a whole and brings about distortion in what remains. Consider a few instances of such distortion. (Fs)

185a Human knowledge results from a vast collaboration of many peoples over uncounted millennia. The necessary condition of that collaboration is belief. What any of us knows, only slightly results from personal experience, personal discovery, personally conducted verification; for the most part it results from believing. But the eighteenth-century Enlightenment was not content to attack religious belief. It prided itself on its philosophers. It set up a rationalist individualism that asked people to prove their assumptions or else regard them as arbitrary. In effect it was out to destroy not only the religious tradition but all tradition. Such rationalist individualism in the twentieth century seems to have infected our educationalists. Students are encouraged to find things out for themselves, to develop originality, to be creative, to criticize, but it does not seem that they are instructed in the enormous role of belief in the acquisition and the expansion of knowledge. Many do not seem to be aware that what they know of science is not immanently generated but for the most part simply belief. (Fs) (notabene)

186a A second distortion occurs in man's apprehension of man. Positivists, naturalists, behaviorists insist that human sciences have to be conducted on the same lines as the natural sciences. But the resultant apprehension of man, if not mechanistic, is theriomorphic. Nor is this view of man as a machine or as an animal confined to some rarefied academic realm. It is applied. The applications reach out into all departments of thought and into all walks of life. They have the common feature of omitting advertence to human dignity and respect for human morality. (Fs)

186b A third distortion is in the realm of technique. Applied science and consequent inventions have given us our vast industrial, commercial, financial, adminstrative, educational, military complex. Technicians are the people with the task of figuring out the most efficient use of currently available hardware. The more successful they are, the greater is the domain that they organize, and the less the domain under the control of old-style decision-makers, of managers, directors, mayors, governors, presidents. Again, the more brilliant they are, the less is it possible to explain to the uninitiated why things are done the way in which they are done. Finally, the more thorough the application of the principle of efficiency, the more must men adapt themselves to its dictates in all their labor hours and in all the goods and services they purchase from the technological establishment. Yet we must bear in mind that anything less than the most efficient procedures threatens the survival of the mass of mankind. (Fs)

186c If I am correct in assuming that the Jesuits of the twentieth century, like those of the sixteenth, exist to meet crises, they have to accept the gains of modernity in natural science, in philosophy, in theology, while working out strategies for dealing with secularist views on religion and with concomitant distortions in man's notion of human knowledge, in his apprehension of human reality, in his organization of human affairs. How such strategies are to be worked out is, of course, an enormous question, and I must be content to offer no more than the briefest suggestions. First, any such strategy is not a conclusion from premisses but a creative project emerging from a thorough understanding of a situation and a grasp of just what can be done about it. Secondly, it is not some static project set forth once and for all but, on the contrary, it is an ongoing project constantly revised in the light of the feedback from its implementation. Thirdly, it is not some single, ongoing project but a set of them, constantly reported to some central clearinghouse with the twofold function (i) of drawing attention to conflicts between separate parts and (2) of keeping all parts informed both of what has been achieved elsewhere and what has been tried and found wanting. Finally, all such projects must be in Christ Jesus, the work of those who take up their cross daily, who live by the Spirit in the Word, who consecrate themselves to loving, who banish all tendencies to hatred, reviling, destroying. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion vom Bewusstsein; was ist ein Erkennender?; bewusster Akt - Erkenntnisakt

Kurzinhalt: ... deshalb haben wir den Erkennenden nicht so definiert, daß wir sagten, er erkenne etwas, sondern daß wir nur sagten, er vollziehe gewisse Arten von Akten ... daß es ein Innewerden gibt, das den Erkenntnisakten immanent ist.

Textausschnitt: 1. Die Notion vom Bewußtsein

374b Erstens soll das Bewußtsein nicht verstanden werden als eine Art innere Schau. Die Leute stellen sich unter Erkennen einen Menschen vor, der auf etwas hinschaut, und dann weiter unter Bewußtsein, daß sie selbst in sich selbst hineinschauen. Und sie geben sich solchen Ansichten der Phantasie nicht nur hin, sondern sie werden sie auch durch Argumente zu rechtfertigen suchen. Erkennen, werden sie sagen, heißt etwas erkennen; es bedeutet, mit einem Objekt konfrontiert zu werden; es ist die merkwürdige, mysteriöse, auf nichts anderes zurückführbare Präsenz eines Dinges zu einem anderen. Obwohl daher das Erkennen auch nicht ausschließlich eine Sache des Sehens mit den Augen ist, ist es doch radikal eben diese Art von Ding. Es ist ein Schauen, Intuieren, Betrachten. Welche Wörter man auch immer wählen mag, Bewußtsein ist ein Erkennen und damit eine Art innere Schau. (Fs)

374c Während nun das Bewußtsein ein Faktor in der Erkenntnis ist, und während das Erkennen eine Aktivität ist, mit welcher sich ein Objektivitätsproblem verbindet, ist es doch eine Sache, diese Aktivität darzulegen, und eine ganz andere, das Objektivitätsproblem in Angriff zu nehmen. Für den Augenblick beschäftigt uns nur eine Darlegung der Aktivität, und deshalb haben wir den Erkennenden nicht so definiert, daß wir sagten, er erkenne etwas, sondern daß wir nur sagten, er vollziehe gewisse Arten von Akten. Ähnlich fragten wir auch nicht, ob der Erkennende sich selbst erkenne; wir fragen nur, ob er den Akt der Selbstbejahung vollziehen könne. Während also einige meiner Leser über die bemerkenswerte Gabe verfügen mögen, in sich selbst hineinzublicken und die Dinge klar und deutlich anzuschauen, werden wir unsere Sache nicht auf ihrem Erfolg aufbauen. Denn es kann sehr wohl andere Leser geben, die wie der Schreibende selbst finden, daß das Hineinschauen in sich selbst nicht viel hergebe. (Fs)

374d Zweitens, mit Bewußtsein wollen wir sagen, daß es ein Innewerden gibt, das den Erkenntnisakten immanent ist. Wir haben schon zwischen Akt und Inhalt unterschieden, zum Beispiel zwischen Sehen und Farben, Hören und Schall, Sich-Vorstellen und Bild, Einsehen und Idee. Das Bewußtsein zu behaupten bedeutet zu behaupten, daß der Erkenntnisprozeß nicht lediglich eine Reihenfolge von Inhalten ist, sondern auch ein Aufeinanderfolgen von Akten. Es bedeutet zu behaupten, daß diese Akte von solchen unbewußten Akten radikal verschieden sind, wie etwa der Stoffwechsel in unseren Zellen, der Unterhalt unserer Organe, die vielfältigen biologischen Prozesse, die wir durch das Studium der zeitgenössischen Medizinwissenschaft kennen lernen. Beide Arten von Akten kommen vor; aber die biologischen [321] Akte kommen außerhalb des Bewußtseins vor und die kognitiven innerhalb des Bewußtseins. Sehen ist nicht bloß eine Reaktion auf den Stimulus von Farbe und Gestalt; es ist eine Reaktion, welche im Innewerden von Farbe und Gestalt besteht. Hören ist nicht allein eine Reaktion auf den Stimulus von Schall; es ist eine Reaktion, die im Innewerden von Schall besteht. So wie sich die Farbe vom Schall unterscheidet, so unterscheidet sich das Sehen vom Hören. Sehen und Hören haben aber eine gemeinsame Eigenschaft, insofern bei beiden Vorkommnissen nicht nur ein Inhalt, sondern auch ein bewußter Akt vorhanden ist. (Fs)

375a Unter dem bewußten Akt ist nicht ein absichtlicher Akt gemeint; wir sind uns von Akten bewußt, ohne darüber zu debattieren, ob wir sie vollziehen wollen. Unter dem bewußten Akt ist auch nicht ein Akt gemeint, auf den man aufmerksam ist; das Bewußtsein kann erhöht werden, indem man die Aufmerksamkeit vom Inhalt zum Akt verschiebt; aber das Bewußtsein konstituiert sich nicht durch dieses Verschieben der Aufmerksamkeit; denn es ist eine Qualität, die in Akten einer gewissen Art immanent ist, und ohne es wären die Akte so unbewußt, wie es das Wachsen des eigenen Bartes ist. Unter dem bewußten Akt ist nicht gemeint, daß der Akt irgendwie zur Inspektion isoliert wird, und auch nicht, daß man seine Funktion im Erkenntnisprozeß erfaßt, und auch nicht, daß man ihm einen Namen geben kann, und auch nicht, daß man ihn von anderen Akten unterscheiden kann, und auch nicht, daß man sich seines Eintretens sicher ist. (Fs)

375b Bedeutet dann also "bewußter Akt" nichts anderes als "Erkenntnisakt"? Hier muß eine Unterscheidung vorgenommen worden. Erstens glaube ich nicht, daß nur Erkenntnisakte bewußt sind. Zweitens gibt es Leute, die "Sehen" als "Innewerden einer Farbe" definieren würden und dann gleich folgern, daß man beim Sehen der Farbe inne war, aber sonst nichts, daß ein "Innewerden von Farbe" vorkomme, aber daß ein gleichzeitiges "Innewerden vom Innewerden" eine reine Fiktion sei. Dies wird den Tatsachen, wie ich meine, nicht gerecht. Wenn Sehen ein Innewerden von nichts als Farbe ist und Hören ein Innewerden von nichts als Schall, warum werden dann beide "Innewerden" genannt? Geschieht es, weil Farbe und Schall irgendwie ähnlich sind? Oder sind Farbe und Schall zwar disparat, aber hinsichtlich beider gibt es Akte, die ähnlich sind? Und wenn der zweite Fall gilt, welches ist dann die Ähnlichkeit? Besteht sie darin, daß beide Akte vorkommen, so wie der Stoffwechsel vorkommt? Oder besteht sie darin, daß beide Akte bewußt sind? Man mag seine Schwierigkeiten mit dem Ausdruck "Innewerden vom Innewerden" haben, speziell dann, wenn man sich das Innewerden als ein Sehen vorstellt und es widersinnig findet, von einem "Hinsehen auf ein Sehen" zu sprechen. Man kann aber nicht bestreiten, daß es im Erkenntnisakt, so wie er vorkommt, einen Faktor oder ein Element oder eine Komponente gibt über und jenseits seines Inhalts, und daß es dieser Faktor ist, der die Erkenntnisakte von den unbewußten Vorkommnissen unterscheidet. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Bewusstsein: empirisch, intelligent, rational; Intelligenz - Intelligibilität, Vernünftigkeit - Begründetheit

Kurzinhalt: Unter Bewußtsein wird ein Innesein (Gewahrwerden) verstanden, das den Erkenntnisakten immanent ist. Diese Akte aber sind von verschiedenen Arten, und so unterscheidet sich auch das Innewerden ... je nach den Akten

Textausschnitt: 2. Empirisches, intelligentes und rationales Bewußtsein b [322]

376a Unter Bewußtsein wird ein Innesein (Gewahrwerden) verstanden, das den Erkenntnisakten immanent ist. Diese Akte aber sind von verschiedenen Arten, und so unterscheidet sich auch das Innewerden in seiner Art je nach den Akten. Es gibt ein empirisches Bewußtsein, das für das Empfinden, Wahrnehmen, Vorstellen charakteristisch ist. Wie der Inhalt dieser Akte nun präsentiert oder repräsentiert wird, so ist das in diesen Akten immanente Innewerden die reine Gegebenheit der Akte. Aber es gibt auch ein intelligentes Bewußtsein, das für das Untersuchen, Einsehen und Formulieren charakteristisch ist. Auf dieser Ebene strebt der Erkenntnisprozeß nicht nur nach dem Intelligiblen und erreicht es, sondern er erweist in diesem Tun seine eigene Intelligenz; er handelt intelligent. Das Innesein ist präsent; aber es ist das Innesein der Intelligenz; dessen, was nach Verstehen strebt; dessen, was durch das Verstehen befriedigt wird; dessen, was das Verstandene formuliert, nicht wie ein Schüler, der eine Definition auswendig wiederholt, sondern wie einer, der definiert, weil er versteht, warum diese Definition die Sache trifft. Schließlich, auf der dritten Ebene von Reflexion, Erfassen des Unbedingten und Urteil gibt es das rationale Bewußtsein. Es ist das zutage Treten und das wirksame Handeln eines einzigen Gesetzes von höchster Allgemeinheit, das Gesetz vom zureichenden Grund, wobei der zureichende Grund das Unbedingte ist. Es entsteht als eine Forderung nach dem Unbedingten und als eine Weigerung, auf der Basis weniger befriedigender Gründe vorbehaltlos zuzustimmen. Es schreitet zum Erfassen des Unbedingten weiter. Es endet in dem rationalen Zwang, mit dem das Erfassen des Unbedingten nach Zustimmung verlangt. (Fs)

377a Das empirische Bewußtsein braucht vielleicht keinen weiteren Kommentar; denn wir verwendeten es, um den Unterschied zwischen bewußten und unbewußten Akten zu erläutern. Das intelligente und das rationale Bewußtsein ihrerseits können durch eine Kontrastierung Klärung finden. Auf verschiedene Weisen betrachten sowohl der Common Sense als auch die positive Wissenschaft die materielle Welt als intelligiblen Mustern unterworfen und durch irgendein Kausalitätsgesetz geregelt. Beschränken wir die Aufmerksamkeit auf das, was der Mensch am besten kennt, nämlich seine Artefakte, so läßt sich in diesen ein intelligibler Plan ausmachen, und ihre Existenz hat ihren Grund in der Produktionsarbeit. Ehe der Plan aber in den Dingen verwirklicht wird, wurde er von der Intelligenz erfunden; ehe die Reihenfolge der Produktionshandlungen eingeleitet wurde, wurde sie wegen eines hinreichenden oder scheinbar hinreichenden Grundes als der Mühe wert bejaht. Im Ding gibt es den intelligiblen Plan; aber im Erfinder gab es nicht nur die Intelligibilität auf der Objektseite, sondern auch das intelligente Bewußtsein auf der Subjektseite. Im Ding gibt es die Begründetheit, welche darin besteht, daß seine Existenz durch eine Reihenfolge von Handlungen erklärt wird; im Unternehmer aber gab es nicht nur die Begründetheit seines Urteils in den Gründen, welche zu [323] ihm führten, sondern auch das rationale Bewußtsein, welches nach Gründen verlangte, um zu einem Urteil zu kommen. (Fs)

377b Intelligenz und Intelligibilität sind die Vorder- und Rückseite der zweiten Erkenntnisebene: Die Intelligenz sucht nach intelligiblen Mustern in den Vorstellungen der Erfahrung bzw. der Einbildungskraft; sie erfaßt solche Muster in ihren Augenblicken des Einsehens; sie nützt dieses Erfassen in ihren Formulierungen und weiteren Handlungen, die ebenfalls durch Einsichten geleitet werden. Auf ähnliche Weise sind Vernünftigkeit und Begründetheit die Vorder- und Rückseite der dritten Erkenntnisebene. Die Vernünftigkeit ist Reflexion, insofern sie nach der Begründetheit der Gedankenobjekte sucht; die Vernünftigkeit entdeckt die Begründetheit in ihrem reflektierenden Erfassen des Unbedingten; die Vernünftigkeit nützt die Begründetheit, wenn sie Objekte bejaht, weil sie begründet sind. In den Artefakten des Menschen kommen die rückseitigen Elemente der Intelligibilität und Begründetheit vor, aber nicht die vorderseitigen der Intelligenz und Vernünftigkeit. Die vorderseitigen Elemente gehören zum Erkenntnisprozeß auf seiner zweiten und dritten Ebene; sie gehören nicht zu den auf diesen Ebenen hervortretenden Inhalten, zur Idee oder zum Begriff, zum Unbedingten oder zum Bejahten; im Gegenteil, sie charakterisieren die Akte, mit welchen diese Inhalte gekoppelt sind, und sind somit spezifische Differenzierungen des Innewerdens des Bewußtseins. Eine klare und deutliche Auffassung offenbart nicht nur die Intelligibilität des Objektes, sondern manifestiert auch die Intelligenz des Subjektes. Exaktes und ausgewogenes Urteilen bejaht die Dinge nicht nur so, wie sie sind, sondern bezeugt auch die Vorherrschaft der Vernünftigkeit im Subjekt. (Fs)

378a Es mag nun noch immer gefragt werden: Bin ich mir wirklich der Intelligenz und Vernünftigkeit bewußt? Die Frage ist, wie ich meine, irreführend. Sie legt nahe, daß es einen Typ des Erkennens gibt, in welchem Intelligenz und Vernünftigkeit sich der Inspektion zur Verfügung stellen. Was aber behauptet wird, ist nicht, daß man die Intelligenz durch Introspektion aufdecken kann, so wie man mit dem Finger auf Calcutta auf einer Karte zeigen kann. Die Behauptung ist, daß man bewußte Zustände und bewußte Akte hat, die intelligent und vernünftig sind. Intelligentes und rationales Bewußtsein bezeichnen Charakteristika des Erkenntnisprozesses und die Charakteristika, die sie bezeichnen, gehören nicht zu den Inhalten, sondern zu der Vorgehensweise. Es widerstrebt mir, Astrologie und Astronomie, Alchimie und Chemie, Legende und Geschichte, Hypothese und Tatsache auf exakt denselben Sockel zu stellen. Ich bin nicht zufrieden mit Theorien, wie brillant kohärent auch immer, sondern ich bestehe darauf, weiter zu fragen: Sind sie wahr? Was ist dieses Widerstreben, dieses Unbefriedigtsein, diese Hartnäckigkeit? Sie [324] sind nur eben so viele Variationen der fundamentaleren Ausdrucksweise, daß ich rational bewußt bin; daß ich einen hinreichenden Grund verlange; daß ich ihn im Unbedingten finde; daß ich vorbehaltlos nur diesem meine Zustimmung gebe; daß solches Fordern, Finden, sich-Festlegen nicht wie das Wachsen meines Haares, sondern innerhalb des Feldes des Bewußt- oder Inneseins stattfindet. (Fs)

378b Wenn ich auch manchmal in ein Lotosland flüchten kann, in welchem reine Vorstellungen der Sinne und der Einbildungskraft nebeneinander stehen oder aufeinander folgen, ist dies doch nicht mein Normalzustand. Die Humesche Welt der bloßen Eindrücke kommt auf mich zu als ein Puzzlespiel, das noch zusammenzusetzen ist. Ich will verstehen, intelligible Einheiten und Beziehungen erfassen, wissen, was los ist und wo ich stehe. Lobpreisung des wissenschaftlichen Geistes, der forscht, meistert, kontrolliert, bleibt nicht ohne Echo, ohne einen tiefen Widerhall in mir; denn auf meine bescheidenere Weise forsche und erfasse auch ich, sehe ich, was zu tun ist, und daß es richtig getan wird. Was anderes aber sind diese als Variationen der grundlegenderen Ausdrucksweise, daß ich mir intelligent bewußt bin, daß das für die Erkenntnisakte auf der zweiten Ebene charakteristische Innewerden ein aktives Beitragen ist zur Intelligibilität seiner Produkte? Wenn ich die Geschichte von Archimedes höre und wenn ich den Bericht einer mystischen Erfahrung lese, gibt es da einen markanten Unterschied. Was ein Mystiker erfährt, weiß ich nicht. Aber, wenn ich selbst auch nie mich einer so bemerkenswerten Einsicht erfreute, wie das Archimedes tat, weiß ich doch, was es bedeutet, den springenden Punkt zu verpassen und den springenden Punkt zu erfassen, keinen Anhaltspunkt zu haben und dann zu kapieren, die Dinge in einem neuen Licht zu sehen, zu erfassen, wie sie zusammenhängen, zur Erkenntnis des Grundes, der Erklärung, der Ursache zu gelangen. Nachdem Archimedes "Ich hab's!" geschrien hatte, mag er verlegen gewesen sein, wenn er gefragt worden wäre, ob er sich einer Einsicht bewußt sei. Es kann aber kein Zweifel darüber bestehen, daß er sich eines Erkenntniszuwachses bewußt war, eines Zuwachses, nach dem er sehr stark verlangt hatte. Suchte er nach der Gunst des Königs? Wollte er seinen Ruf steigern? Vielleicht; aber auf einer tieferen und spontaneren Ebene wollte er wissen, wie etwas angepackt werden mußte; er wollte ein Problem lösen; er wollte verstehen; sein Bewußtsein war auf der zweiten Ebene, wo es das Intelligible sucht und Teileinsichten mit weiteren Fragen verfolgt, bis es zur letzten krönenden Einsicht gelangt, die dem Fragen ein Ende setzt und das intelligente Bewußtsein befriedigt. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Tatsachenurteil: Möglichkeit (Möglichkeitsbedingung)

Kurzinhalt: Die erste Bedingung für jegliches mögliches Tatsachenurteil ist also das Erfassen (1) eines Bedingten, (2) einer Verbindung zwischen dem Bedingten und seinen Bedingungen und ...

Textausschnitt: 9. Selbstbejahung in der Möglichkeit der Tatsachenurteile [336-39]

392b Dieselbe Konklusion kann erreicht werden, indem man die Apriori-Bedingungen für die Möglichkeit jeglichen Tatsachenurteils ausarbeitet. Denn jedes solches Urteil kann durch ein "Ja" oder "Nein" in Antwort auf eine Frage "Ist es so?" dargestellt werden. Die Antwort wird rational sein, das heißt, sie wird auf einem erkannten hinreichenden Grund basieren. Die Antwort wird zudem absolut sein; "Ja" schließt "Nein" völlig aus; und "Nein" schließt "Ja" völlig aus. Folglich, weil der erkannte hinreichende Grund für eine absolute Antwort selbst absolut und erkannt zu sein hat, müssen das "Ja" oder das "Nein" auf einem Erfassen des Unbedingten beruhen. Das Tatsachenurteil besagt nun nicht, daß etwas so sein muß oder nicht anders sein könnte; es behauptet nur, daß etwas so ist; das Unbedingte, welches es begründet, wird dehalb nicht formell, sondern bloß virtuell unbedingt sein. Die erste Bedingung für jegliches mögliches Tatsachenurteil ist also das Erfassen
(1) eines Bedingten,
(2) einer Verbindung zwischen dem Bedingten und seinen Bedingungen und
(3) der Erfüllung der Bedingungen. (Fs)
[337] Es ist ein solches Erfassen, das den Übergang von der Frage "Ist es so?" zu einer rationalen, absoluten Antwort bewirkt. (Fs)

393a Aber diese zweite Anforderung setzt eine dritte voraus. Es muß ein Feld der erfüllenden Bedingungen geben. Genauer, weil die Bedingungen gleichzeitig sind mit dem, was sie bedingen, muß es ein vorhergehendes Feld geben, welches das enthält, was zu erfüllenden Bedingungen werden kann. Für sich selbst genommen, werden sie weder bedingend noch bedingt sein; sie werden einfach gegeben sein. (Fs)

393b Schließlich ist die Möglichkeit konkret. Logiker mögen sagen, daß ein "Berg von Gold" möglich sei, wenn in der Annahme eines solchen Berges kein Widerspruch enthalten ist. Tatsächlich ist aber ein Berg von Gold nur möglich, wenn die Mittel vorhanden sind, genug Gold für einen ganzen Berg zu erwerben, es an einen einzigen Ort zu bringen, es in der Form eines Berges aufzuhäufen, und es dort solange zu behalten, daß der Goldberg während eines minimalen Zeitintervalles tatsächlich existiert. Ähnlich wird jedes mögliche Tatsachenurteil ein konkretes Urteil sein. Die Bedingungen für seine Möglichkeit schließen die Bedingungen mit [338] ein, seine verschiedenen Komponenten zusammenzubringen. Es muß dann also eine konkrete Einheit-Identität-Totalität1 geben, welche das Gegebene erfährt, das über das Gegebene eine Untersuchung anstellt, um die freie Entwicklung systematischer Einheiten und Relationen hervorzubringen, das über solche Entwicklungen reflektiert und nach dem virtuell Unbedingten als seinem Grund verlangt, um mit "Ja" oder "Nein" zu antworten. Es ist diese konkrete Einheit, die fragt, "Ist es so?" Es ist diese konkrete Einheit, die die freie Entwicklung initiiert, indem sie über das Gegebene fragt: "Was ist das?", "Warum ist es?", "Wie oft existiert es oder kommt es vor?" Es ist diese konkrete Einheit, die das Bedingte als Bedingtes erfaßt und formuliert und die sich auf das Gegebene beruft, um das virtuell Unbedingte zu erfassen und es rational und absolut zu bejahen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Kontrast, Unterschied (Transzendentale Deduktion): Lonergan - Kant

Kurzinhalt: Ein zweiter Unterschied liegt in der Unterscheidung zwischen Ding-für-uns und Ding-selbst ... Ein dritter Unterschied bezieht sich auf die allgemeinen und notwendigen Urteile ...

Textausschnitt: 10. Kontrast mit der Analyse Kants [339-42]

395a Wir haben etwas vollzogen, das ähnlich ist demjenigen, was ein Kantianer eine transzendentale Deduktion nennen würde. Man wird uns deshalb die Frage stellen, warum unsere Deduktion Resultate ergibt, die von denen Kants verschieden sind. (Fs)

395b Ein erster Unterschied ist, daß Kant nach den Apriori-Bedingungen der Möglichkeit von Erfahrung im Sinne der Erkenntnis eines Objektes fragte. Wir haben zwei Fragen unterschieden; es gibt das Problem der Objektivität, und von diesem haben wir sorgfältig abgesehen, und zwar nicht nur im vorliegenden Abschnitt, sondern ebenso in allen anderen früheren Abschnitten; es gibt da auch das vorhergehende Problem zu bestimmen, was für Handlungen im Erkennen beteiligt sind, und auf dieses vorhergehende Problem haben wir bis jetzt unsere Bemühungen beschränkt. Wir haben deshalb nicht nach den Bedingungen für die Erkenntnis eines Objektes, sondern nach den Bedingungen dafür, daß ein Tatsachenurteil stattfinden kann, gefragt. Wir haben nach den Bedingungen eines absoluten und rationalen "Ja" oder "Nein" gefragt einfach als Akt betrachtet. Wir haben nicht gefragt, unter welchen Bedingungen es eine Tatsache geben könnte, welche dem "Ja" entsprechen würde. Wir haben nicht einmal gefragt, welche Bedeutung eine solche Entsprechung haben könnte. (Fs)

395c Ein zweiter Unterschied liegt in der Unterscheidung zwischen Ding-für-uns und Ding-selbst. Kant unterschied diese als Phänomenon und Noumenon. Was er damit gemeint hat, ist umstritten; aber es ist doch wenigstens klar, daß diese Unterscheidung zu seiner Formulierung einer Theorie der Objektivität gehört. Außerdem scheint es mir ziemlich wahrscheinlich, daß der historische Ursprung für die Kantsche Unterscheidung in der Renaissance-Unterscheidung von primären und sekundären Qualitäten zu suchen ist, wobei die ersteren zu den wirklichen und objektiven Dingen selbst gehörten, während die letzteren zu der Art und Weise gehörten, wie das Subjekt die Dinge erfaßt. Auf jeden Fall ist unsere Unterscheidung weder die Renaissance-Unterscheidung noch die Kants. Sie ist einfach eine Unterscheidung zwischen Beschreibung und Erklärung, zwischen der Art von kognitiven Aktivitäten, welche die Inhalte festlegen, indem sie angeben, wem sie ähnlich sind, und andererseits der Art, welche die Inhalte festlegen, indem sie ihre erfahrungsmäßig bestätigten Relationen angeben. Ein Ding ist eine konkrete Einheit-Identität-Totalität, welche in den Daten als individuellen erfaßt wird. Beschreiben Sie es, und es ist ein Ding-für-uns. Erklären Sie es, und es ist ein Ding-selbst. Ist es wirklich? Ist es objektiv? Ist es mehr als bloß die immanente Bestimmung des Erkenntnisaktes? Dies sind alles recht vernünftige Fragen. Bis jetzt aber antworten wir weder mit "Ja" noch mit "Nein". Für den Augenblick ist unsere Antwort einfach, daß Objektivität [340] ein hochkomplexes Problem ist und daß wir es erst befriedigend behandeln werden, wenn wir beginnen zu bestimmen, was genau der Erkenntnisprozeß ist. Zweifellos gibt es Einwände, die gegen ein solches Vorgehen erhoben werden können; aber auch die Einwände werden befriedigend behandelt, erst nachdem die vorhergehenden Fragen beantwortet sind. (Fs)

396a Ein dritter Unterschied bezieht sich auf die allgemeinen und notwendigen Urteile. Sie stehen im Vordergrund der Kantschen Kritik, die sich hauptsächlich damit befaßte, Humes empirischen Atomismus zu überwinden. In unserer Analyse spielen sie aber nur eine sekundäre Rolle. Ein allgemeines und notwendiges Urteil kann bloß die Bejahung einer analytischen Aussage sein, und solche analytische Aussagen können bloß abstrakte Möglichkeiten sein, ohne Relevanz für den zentralen Kontext von Urteilen, den wir Erkenntnis nennen. Wir legen den Nachdruck auf das Tatsachenurteil, das selbst ein Erkenntniszuwachs ist, und zugleich zum Übergang von der analytischen Aussage zum analytischen Prinzip beiträgt, das heißt, zu dem allgemeinen und notwendigen Urteil, dessen Termini und Relationen existen-tiell sind in dem Sinne, daß sie in Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen. (Fs)

396b Ein vierter Unterschied bezieht sich auf den unmittelbaren Grund des Urteils. Kant formulierte diesen Grund, indem er seinen Kategorienschematismus vorbrachte. Die Kategorie des Wirklichen wird richtig eingesetzt, wenn die leere Form der Zeit erfüllt wird. Die Kategorie der Substanz kommt richtig zur Anwendung, wenn die Beharrlichkeit des Realen in der Zeit festzustellen ist. Nun wird aber Kants Schematismus nicht als eine seiner glücklichsten Erfindungen betrachtet. Jedenfalls haben wir erwiesen, daß die Begriffe durch ihre Entstehung selbst mit den Daten verbunden sind. Die Untersuchung bezieht sich auf Sinnesdaten oder auf Bewußtseinsdaten. Die Einsicht ist Einsicht in die Daten der Untersuchung. Begriffe und Theorien sind die Produkte der Einsicht und müssen im Vergleich zu den Daten überprüft werden. Außerdem, und dies ist der wesentliche Unterschied, offenbart der Prozeß der Überprüfung im menschlichen Erkennen eine dritte, verschiedene und konstitutive Ebene, die über Erfahrung und Verstehen hinausgeht, und die selbst-authentisierend und entscheidend ist. Sie ist selbst-authentisierend: Die rationale Reflexion verlangt und das reflektierende Verstehen erfaßt ein virtuell Unbedingtes; und wenn dieses Erfassen einmal stattgefunden hat, kann man nicht zugleich vernünftig sein und sich des Urteils enthalten. Ferner, die dritte Ebene ist allein entscheidend: Bis ich urteile, denke ich bloß; wenn ich einmal urteile, dann erkenne ich. Wie die Einsicht das bestimme Gedankenobjekt aus dem nebelhaften Erfahrungsobjekt zieht, so wählt das Urteil die Gedankenobjekte aus, die Erkenntnisobjekte sind. Wie schließlich in den Kapiteln XII und XIII klar werden wird, bedeutet Erkennen das Sein Erkennen, und das Sein Erkennen schließt das Erkennen von Objekten und Subjekten mit ein. (Fs)

397a Weil nun die dritte Ebene selbst-authentisierend ist, können die Vernunft und [341] ihr Ideal, das Unbedingte, nicht in der zweifelhaften und rein überwachenden Rolle verbleiben, die ihnen Kant zugewiesen hat. Weil es konstitutiv und allein entscheidend ist, ist das rationale Urteil das einzige Kriterium in unserer Erkenntnis; und dies schließt die Spuren von Empirismus aus, die so oft dem Kantschen Denken angelastet wurden. Unser Unbedingtes ist aber nur virtuell; es ist bloß das, was in der Tat so ist; und die universelle Relevanz der Tatsache in diesem Sinne (siehe S. 331) korrigiert den vorkantischen Rationalismus und schließt zugleich den nachkantischen Idealismus aus. Schließlich wird unser Realismus, wenn auch nicht intuitiv, doch unmittelbar sein: Die Erkenntnisanalyse wird benötigt, nicht um das Sein zu erkennen, sondern um die Erkenntnis zu erkennen. (Fs)

397b Ein fünfter Unterschied hat mit dem Bewußtsein zu tun. Kant anerkannte einen inneren Sinn, welcher ungefähr dem entspricht, was wir empirisches Bewußtsein nannten, nämlich das Innesein, das den Akten des Empfindens, Wahrnehmens, in der Einbildungskraft Vorstellens, Wünschens, Fürchtens und ähnlichen immanent ist. Außer der Anerkennung eines inneren Sinnes leitete Kant eine ursprüngliche synthetische Einheit der Apperzeption als die Apriori-Bedingung des alle Erkenntnisakte begleitenden "Ich denke" ab oder postulierte sie. Andererseits hat die Kantsche Theorie keinen Platz für ein Bewußtsein der Prinzipien, die die Kategorien hervorbringen. Die Kategorien können abgeleitet werden aus den Urteilen, in denen sie vorkommen; aber es ist unmöglich, hinter die Kategorien auf deren Quelle zurückzugehen. Es ist gerade dieser Aspekt des Kantschen Denkens, der den Kategorien ihren Mangel an Flexibilität und ihre irreduzible Mysteriosität verleiht. Es ist derselbe Aspekt, der Fichte und Hegel die Gelegenheit verschaffte, in das unbesetzte Gebiet des intelligenten und rationalen Bewußtseins einzumarschieren. Die dynamischen Zustände, die Untersuchen und Reflektieren genannt wurden, kommen tatsächlich vor. Die Untersuchung bringt alles Verstehen hervor, und das Verstehen bringt alle Begriffe und Systeme hervor. Die Reflexion bringt alles reflektierende Erfassen des Unbedingten hervor, und dieses Erfassen bringt alle Urteile hervor. Wenn der Kantianer die Betrachtung der Untersuchung und der Reflexion verbietet, dann setzt er sich dem Vorwurf des Obskurantismus aus. Wenn er eine solche Betrachtung zuläßt, wenn er die intellektuelle Neugier und den kritischen Geist lobt, dann ist er auf dem Weg, die Prinzipien anzuerkennen, die sowohl die Kategorien, die Kant bekannt waren, als auch die Kategorien, die Kant nicht bekannt waren, hervorbringen. (Fs)

398a Die obige Liste erklärt den Unterschied zwischen Kants Konklusion und meiner eigenen. Es sind Unterschiede in dem Problem, das betrachtet wird; in dem [342] Gesichtspunkt, unter dem es betrachtet wird; in der Methode, wie es gelöst wird. Noch grundlegender gibt es Unterschiede in bezug auf Tatsachen; denn unsere Selbstbejahung ist, wie wir betont haben und, man möge uns verzeihen, es zu wiederholen, primär und letztlich ein Tatsachenurteil. Der orthodoxe Kantianer würde unseren Standpunkt als reinen Psychologismus bezeichnen, als ein sich auf das Empirische Berufen, das nicht mehr ergeben kann denn eine provisorische Wahrscheinlichkeit. Unsere Entgegnung ist allerdings recht einfach. Ohne Tatsachenurteile kann man nicht über rein analytische Aussagen hinausgehen. Ferner, wenn die Selbstbejahung auch nicht mehr ist als ein Urteil über eine reine Tatsache, ist sie doch ein privilegiertes Urteil. Selbst-Verneinung ist inkohärent. Man hat nur zu untersuchen und zu reflektieren, um sich in den Spontaneitäten und Unausweichlichkeiten gefangen vorzufinden, welche die Evidenz für die Selbstbejahung liefern. Man hat nur ein einziges Tatsachenurteil zu fällen, was immer sein Inhalt sein mag, um sich in eine notwendige Selbstbejahung zu verwickeln. Schließlich unterscheidet sich die Erkenntnistheorie von anderen Theorien; denn andere Theorien erreichen die Erklärung nur, indem sie sich in das bloß Angenommene wagen; die Erkenntnistheorie dagegen erreicht die Erklärung ohne ein solches Wagen; und weil sie kein rein hypothetisches Element enthält, ist sie einer radikalen Revision nicht unterworfen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Kontrast, Unterschied: Lonergan - Relativismus; Position des Relativisten (1-5); Beispiel Schreibmaschine; Universum als Netz von Relationen

Kurzinhalt: ... genauso wie der Relativist auf der Ebene der Intelligenz gegen den Empiristen beharrt, beharren wir auf der Ebene der Reflexion gegen den Relativisten ... der Relativist hat nicht bewiesen und kann nicht beweisen, daß es keine Tatsachen gibt; ...

Textausschnitt: 11. Kontrast mit der relativistischen Analyse [342-47]

398b Von Kant wenden wir uns nun dem relativistischen Denken zu. Die Ausgangsfrage im vorliegenden Abschnitt war, ob korrekte Urteile vorkommen. Unsere Darstellung der Selbstbejahung widerspricht direkt der relativistischen Behauptung, daß korrekte Urteile nicht vorkommen. Wenn auch die Argumente für unsere Position schon gegeben worden sind, wird es nicht fehl am Platze sein, wenn wir angeben, wo der Relativist nicht übereinstimmen würde und warum. (Fs)

398c Erstens, das relativistische Denken widmet sich zu einem großen Teil der Widerlegung des Empirismus. Es betont ganz richtig, daß das menschliche Erkennen nicht allein durch die Ebene der Vorstellungen erklärt werden kann. Es gibt auch die Ebene der Intelligenz, des Erfassens und Formulierens von intelligiblen Einheiten und systematischen Relationen. Ohne diese zweite Ebene gibt es zwar ein Gegebenes, aber keine Möglichkeit zu sagen, was gegeben ist. (Fs)

399a Zweitens, genauso wie der Relativist auf der Ebene der Intelligenz gegen den Empiristen beharrt, beharren wir auf der Ebene der Reflexion gegen den Relativisten. Menschliches Erkennen ist nicht rein Theorie über das Gegebene; es gibt auch Tatsachen; und der Relativist hat nicht bewiesen und kann nicht beweisen, daß es keine Tatsachen gibt; denn die Abwesenheit aller anderen Tatsachen wäre ja selbst eine Tatsache. (Fs) (notabene)

399b Drittens, genau so wie der Empirist nichts zu sagen hätte, wenn er nicht Handlungen auf der Intelligenzebene nutzte, so beschränkt sich auch der Relativist nicht strikte auf die Ebenen der Vorstellungen und der Intelligenz. Er ist mit der Notion [343] des Unbedingten durchaus vertraut. Er betrachtet das Unbedingte als das Ideal, auf das hin alles menschliche Erkennen tendiert. Aber er unterstellt, daß dieses Ideal durch das Verstehen zu erreichen ist. Wäre das Universum in all seinen Teilen und Aspekten vollständig verstanden, dann könnte es keine weiteren Fragen mehr geben; alles wäre genau begriffen, wie es sein sollte; über jedes Thema könnte der Mensch sagen, was er gerade gedacht, und denken, was er gerade gesagt hat. Solange wir andererseits diese umfassende Kohärenz nicht erreicht haben, kann es keine sichere Basis geben. Es gibt Verstehen, aber es ist partiell; es ist mit Nicht-Verstehen gekoppelt; es ist der Revision offen, sobald das gegenwärtige Nicht-Verstehen dem künftigen Verstehen weicht; und so innig sind alle Dinge verbunden, daß die Erkenntnis von irgendetwas nur definitiv sein kann, wenn alles erkannt wird. (Fs)

399c Viertens, der Relativist ist imstande, auf diese allgemeine Sicht eine Auseinandersetzung mit konkreten Problemen folgen zu lassen. Ist dies eine Schreibmaschine? Wahrscheinlich, ja. Zu praktischen Zwecken, ja. Absolut? Der Relativist würde es vorziehen, die präzise Bedeutung der Bezeichnung Schreibmaschine zu klären; er möchte gerne wissen, was denn genau mit dem Demonstrativum dies gemeint ist; er wäre dankbar für eine Erklärung der Bedeutung der Kopula ist. Der ursprünglich simplen Frage wird mit drei weiteren Fragen begegnet; und wenn diese drei beantwortet werden, dann werden diese Antworten noch mehr Fragen aufkommen lassen. Ist einer schnell und bemerkt, daß er mit einer unendlichen Reihe beginnt, dann mag er dem Relativisten mit einem abgerundeten System entgegentreten. Aber auch der Relativist ist ein kluger Kerl. Er wird daraufhinweisen, daß normale Menschen, die sich ziemlich sicher sind, daß das hier eine Schreibmaschine ist, nichts vom System wissen, auf das sein Gesprächspartner ihre Erkenntnis gründet. Und das ist noch nicht alles. Denn die menschliche Erkenntnis ist begrenzt; Systeme haben ihre schwachen Punkte; und der Relativist wird sich eben auf jene Probleme stürzen, in bezug auf die ein Verteidiger des Systems lieber seine Ignoranz eingestehen würde. (Fs)

400a Fünftens, der Relativist wird nicht nur klarmachen, daß es weitere Fragen gibt, bis alles erkannt ist, sondern er wird auch erklären, warum das so ist. Eine Relation wird eine innere in bezug auf ein Objekt genannt, wenn das Objekt ohne diese Relation radikal verschieden wäre. Wir haben in diesem Sinne von Untersuchung und Einsicht gesprochen. Unter der Untersuchung haben wir aber nicht irgendein reines Staunen verstanden; wir meinten ein Staunen über etwas. Ähnlich meinten wir mit der Einsicht nicht irgendein reines Verstehen, sondern ein Verstehen von etwas. Untersuchung und Einsicht sind deshalb inner hinsichtlich der Materialien, über die man eine Untersuchung anstellt und in die man Einsichten gewinnt. Wenn man nun annimmt, daß das ganze Universum ein Muster solcher inneren Relationen [344] ist, dann folgt daraus evidentermaßen, daß kein Teil und kein Aspekt des Universums isoliert von jeglichem anderen Teil oder Aspekt verstanden werden kann. Denn jedes Ding ist innerlich auf jedes andere bezogen; und von solchen Relationen abzusehen bedeutet, von den Dingen abzusehen, so wie sie sind, und an ihre Stelle imaginäre Objekte zu stellen, die einfach nicht existieren. Wenn man also den Relativisten fragt, warum die Fragen ins Unendliche davonlaufen, hat er eine Antwort parat: Das Universum, das zu erkennen ist, indem man Fragen beantwortet, ist ein Netz innerer Relationen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Kontrast, Unterschied: Lonergan - Relativismus; Argumente (6-) gegen die Position des Relativisten

Kurzinhalt: In der Tat ist aber das Universum nicht einfach ein Erklärungssystem; seine existierenden Dinge und seine Vorkommnisse divergieren nichtsystematisch von der reinen Intelligibilität ...

Textausschnitt: 400b Sechstens, wenn das Obige einigermaßen die relativistische Position wiedergibt, so zeigt es auch, wo ihre Versehen liegen. Die Fragen sind von zwei Arten. Es gibt Fragen nach Einsicht, die fragen, was das ist, was das bedeutet, warum das so ist, mit welcher Häufigkeit es vorkommt oder existiert. Es gibt auch Fragen nach Reflexion, die fragen, ob die Antworten auf die Fragen des ersten Typs korrekt sind. Ferner, das für ein Urteil benötigte Unbedingte ist nicht die umfassende Kohärenz, die das Ideal des Verstehens ist, die die Antworten auf alle Fragen des ersten Typs begründet. Im Gegenteil, es ist ein virtuell Unbedingtes, das aus der Kombination eines Bedingten mit der Erfüllung seiner Bedingungen resultiert. Weiter, ein Urteil ist ein begrenztes Engagement; weit davon entfernt, auf einer Erkenntnis des Universums zu beruhen, besagt es, daß, als was immer das Übrige des Universums sich herausstellen wird, dies zumindest so ist. Ich mag nicht in der Lage sein, Grenzfälle zu entscheiden, in denen man darüber streiten kann, ob das Wort Schreibmaschine passend verwendet würde. Aber ich kann doch wenigstens eindeutig entscheiden, daß dies hier eine Schreibmaschine ist. Ich mag nicht in der Lage sein, die Bedeutung von ist zu klären; aber es ist für unsere gegenwärtigen Zwecke völlig genug, den Unterschied zwischen ist und ist nicht zu kennen, und den kenne ich. (Fs)

401a Ich bin nicht sehr deutlich, wenn es darum geht, die Bedeutung von dies zu erklären; aber wenn jemand es vorziehen sollte, jenes zu sagen, dann wird das keinen Unterschied machen, vorausgesetzt wir sehen beide das, worüber wir sprechen. Man wird mich warnen, daß ich in der Vergangenheit Fehler begangen habe. Aber diese Warnung ist sinnlos, wenn ich einen weiteren Fehler begehe, indem ich einen vergangenen Fehler als Fehler anerkenne. Und jedenfalls ist unser einziges Problem jetzt, ob ich einen Fehler begehe oder nicht, wenn ich behaupte, dies hier sei eine Schreibmaschine. Nun wird man mir sagen, daß meine Notion der Schreibmaschine ganz anders wäre, wenn ich die Chemie der Materialien verstünde, die Mechanik der Konstruktion, die Psychologie der Fertigkeit des Maschinenschreibens, die Wirkung, die die Verwendung der Maschine beim Schreiben auf die Satzstruktur hat, die wirtschaftlichen und soziologischen Auswirkungen ihrer Erfindung, ihre Beziehung zur kommerziellen und politischen Bürokratie und so weiter. Aber könnte ich dann nicht erklären, daß all diese weiteren Dinge, wie interessant und bedeutsam auch immer sie sein mögen, nur durch weitere Urteile zu erkennen sind; [345] daß solche weiteren Urteile, weit davon entfernt, mich von meiner gegenwärtigen Überzeugung abzubringen, daß dies eine Schreibmaschine ist, mich nur in ihr bestätigen werden; daß es ziemlich schwierig wäre, diese weiteren Urteile zu fällen, wenn ich mir zu Beginn nicht sicher sein könnte, ob dies nun eine Schreibmaschine ist oder nicht? (Fs)
401b Siebtens, wie auch immer, sind die Fragen, die durch ein Muster innerer Relationen eine Antwort finden, nur Fragen, die nach einem Erklärungssystem verlangen. Aber neben den Dingen-selbst und vor ihnen gibt es in unserem Erkennen die Dinge-für-uns, die Dinge als beschriebene. Außerdem divergieren die existierenden Dinge und Vorkommnisse, in denen die Erklärungssysteme verifiziert werden, nichtsystematisch von den idealen Häufigkeiten, die idealerweise aus den Erklärungssystemen abgeleitet werden könnten. Ferner schließt die Tätigkeit des Verifizierens den Gebrauch der Beschreibung als Mittlerin zwischen dem durch innere Relationen definierten System einerseits und den Vorstellungen der Sinne andererseits ein, welche die Erfüllungsbedingungen sind. Schließlich wäre es falsch, wollte man annehmen, daß die Erklärung die einzige wahre Erkenntnis sei; nicht nur beruht ihre Verifikation auf Beschreibung, sondern auch die Relationen der Dinge zu uns sind ebenso sehr Erkenntnisobjekte, wie es die Relationen der Dinge untereinander sind. (Fs)

401c Achtens, der Relativist erfindet sich ein Universum, das lediglich aus einem Erklärungssystem besteht, weil er sich das Unbedingte als das Ideal des Verstandes denkt, als die umfassende Kohärenz, auf die hin das Verstehen strebt, wenn es "Was?" und "Wie?" fragt. Wie wir aber gesehen haben, ist das Kriterium für das Urteil das virtuell Unbedingte. Jedes Urteil ist ein begrenztes Engagement. Weit davon entfernt, sich über das Universum zu äußern, begnügt es sich damit, ein einzelnes Bedingtes zu bejahen, das eine begrenzte Zahl von Bedingungen hat, die tatsächlich erfüllt sind. Zweifellos, wäre das Universum einfach ein riesiges Erklärungssystem, wäre die Erkenntnis der Bedingungen eines Bedingten identisch mit der Erkenntnis des Universums. In der Tat ist aber das Universum nicht einfach ein Erklärungssystem; seine existierenden Dinge und seine Vorkommnisse divergieren nichtsystematisch von der reinen Intelligibilität; es weist ein empirisches Residuum des Individuellen, des Zufälligen, des Kontinuierlichen, des bloß Nebeneinanderliegenden und des bloß aufeinander Folgenden auf; es ist ein Universum von Fakten, und das Erklärungssystem hat Gültigkeit in dem Maße, in dem es mit den deskriptiven Fakten konform ist. (Fs)

402a Neuntens, das relativistische Argument von den unendlichen weiteren Fragen her ist eher eindrucksvoll als schlüssig. Das menschliche Erkennen geht nicht von einem früherem Erkennen, sondern von natürlichen Spontaneitäten und Unausweichlichkeiten aus. Seine Basistermini sind für es in einem Erkennen definiert, das dem [346] Erkennen vorausgeht; sie werden durch die dynamische Struktur des Erkenntnisprozesses selbst festgelegt. Der Relativist fragt, was mit der Kopula ist, und was mit dem Demonstrativum dies gemeint ist. Aber weder er noch sonst jemand verwechselt ist mit ist nicht, oder dies mit nicht dies; und diese Grundklarheit ist alles, was für die Bedeutung der Behauptung relevant ist: Dies ist eine Schreibmaschine. Ein Erkenntnistheoretiker würde aufgefordert werden, derartige elementare Termini zu erklären; er würde das tun, indem er sagen würde, daß das ist das Ja darstellt, das im Urteil vorkommt, und daß es durch Fragen wie "Ist es?", "Was ist es?" vorweggenommen wird. Ähnlich würde ein Theoretiker dies als die Rückkehr vom Feld der Begriffe zum empirischen Residuum im Feld der Vorstellungen erklären. Aber die Fragen, die für die Erkenntnistheorie relevant sind, sind nicht relevant für jeden Fall des Erkennens. Sie sind deshalb nicht universell relevant, weil es tatsächlich keine operationeile Unklarheit gibt in bezug auf die Bedeutungen, welche die Erkenntnistheorie erhellt. Ferner, sie sind nicht universell relevant, weil solche elementaren Bedeutungen auf eine Weise festgelegt sind, welche die Bestimmung durch Definition übersteigt, nämlich mit der ursprünglichen Unveränderlichkeit der dynamischen Struktur des Erkenntnisprozesses. (Fs)

402b Zehntens, wie das menschliche Erkennen mit einer natürlichen Spontaneität beginnt, so sind auch seine anfänglichen Entwicklungen unartikuliert. Wie es fragt, warum und wie, ohne daß ihm ein Grund für sein Untersuchen angegeben würde, so läßt es sich auch auf den sich selbst korrigierenden Lernprozeß ein, ohne die expliziten Formulierungen, die in einem Erklärungssystem mit Recht verlangt würden. Einzelne Einsichten sind partiell. Spontan fuhren sie zu den weiteren Fragen, welche komplementäre Einsichten hervorbringen. Wäre das Universum ausschließlich ein Erklärungssystem, dann bewegten sich die kleineren Anhäufungen von Einsichten, die erreicht werden von dem, was Common Sense genannt wird, nicht auf eine Grenzposition der Vertrautheit und Meisterung zu, wo es offensichtlich unsinnig ist zu zweifeln, ob dies eine Schreibmaschine ist oder nicht. In der Tat aber ist das Universum, das erkannt wird, indem wir Fragen beantworten, nicht ein reines Erklärungssystem. In der Tat bewegen sich Einsichten auf die Grenzpositionen der Vertrautheit und Meisterung zu. In der Tat ist es unsinnig zu zweifeln, und jedermann weiß das, ob dies eine Schreibmaschine ist oder nicht. Der Relativist würde mich bitten, meine Aufmerksamkeit darauf zu richten, welch enormen Unterschied in meiner Notion der Schreibmaschine es machen würde, wenn ich die Chemie ihrer Materialien, die Mechanik ihrer Konstruktion, die Psychologie der Tippfertigkeit, den Einfluß auf den literarischen Stil, der durch das Schreiben auf der Maschine entsteht, die Wirkung ihrer Entdeckung auf die kommerzielle und politische Bürokratie und so weiter völlig verstünde. Zugegeben, eine solche Bereicherung meines Wissens wäre möglich und wünschenswert, handelte es sich doch um eine weitere Erkenntnis, die durch weitere Urteile zu gewinnen ist. Und weil die Bereicherung erklärend ist, weil erklärende Erkenntnis auf beschreibender [347] Erkenntnis beruht, muß ich nicht nur damit beginnen zu erkennen, daß dies hier eine Schreibmaschine ist, muß ich nicht nur damit fortfahren zu lernen, wie ähnlich andere Maschinen dieser hier sein müssen, wenn sie auch Schreibmaschinen genannt werden sollen, sondern ich kann auch eine gültige Erklärung nur erreichen, insofern meine Beschreibungen exakt sind. (Fs)

403a Elftens, es ist völlig wahr, daß ich mich täuschen kann. Aber diese Wahrheit setzt voraus, daß ich mich nicht weiter täusche, indem ich einen Fehler der Vergangenheit als Fehler anerkenne. Allgemeiner gesagt: Tatsachenurteile sind korrekt oder inkorrekt, nicht aus Notwendigkeit, sondern einfach in der Tat. Wenn dies hier etwas ist, könnte es doch auch nichts sein. Wenn dies eine Schreibmaschine ist, könnte es doch auch etwas anderes sein. Ähnlich ist es, wenn ich korrekt bejahe, daß dies eine Schreibmaschine ist, nicht eine reine Notwendigkeit, sondern es ist einfach eine Tatsache, daß ich korrekt bin. Verlangen nach der Evidenz, die die Möglichkeit selbst ausschließt, daß ich mich täusche, wenn ich behaupte, dies hier sei eine Schreibmaschine, heißt, zuviel verlangen. Eine solche Evidenz ist nicht verfügbar; denn wenn meine Behauptung korrekt ist, ist das bloß eine Tatsache. Wenn diese Evidenz aber nicht zu Gebote steht, ist noch viel weniger die Evidenz vorhanden, welche in allen Tatsachenurteilen die Möglichkeit des Irrtums ausschließen wird. Irrtümer sind ebensosehr Fakten, wie es die korrekten Urteile sind. Aber der Relativist steht im Konflikt mit beiden Kategorien von Tatsachen. Für ihn ist nichts einfach wahr, weil das nur möglich ist, wenn eine umfassende Kohärenz erreicht wird; für ihn ist nichts einfach falsch, weil jede Aussage ein gewisses Verstehen miteinschließt, und deshalb einen Teil dessen, was er Wahrheit nennt. Letzten Endes, wie der Empirist versucht, die Intelligenz zu verbannen, so versucht der Relativist die Tatsache zu verbannen, und mit ihr das, was alle anderen Wahrheit nennen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion des Seins; Definition (zweiter Ordnung): Sein

Kurzinhalt: Sein ist das Zielobjekt des reinen Wissenstrebens ... diese Definition ist entfernter, weil sie festlegt, nicht was unter Sein gemeint ist, sondern wie das Gemeinte zu bestimmen ist.

Textausschnitt: 1. Eine Definition [348-50]

405b Sein ist das Zielobjekt des reinen Wissenstrebens. (Fs)

Mit dem Wissenstreben meinen wir die dynamische Ausrichtung, die sich in Fragen nach Einsicht und nach Reflexion manifestiert. Es ist nicht die sprachliche Äußerung von Fragen. Es ist nicht die begriffliche Formulierung von Fragen. Es ist nicht eine Einsicht oder ein Gedanke. Es ist nicht ein reflektierendes Erfassen oder Urteilen. Es ist der vorausgehende und umfassende Trieb, der den Erkenntnisprozeß von der Sinneserfahrung und der Vorstellung in der Einbildungskraft zum Verstehen führt, vom Verstehen zum Urteil, vom Urteil zum vollständigen Kontext korrekter Urteile, den wir Erkenntnis nennen. Das Wissensstreben ist deshalb einfach der untersuchende und kritische Geist des Menschen. Indem es ihn dazu bewegt, verstehen zu suchen, hält es ihn davon ab, sich mit dem bloßen Fluß der äußeren und inneren Erfahrung zufriedenzugeben. Indem es ein adäquates Verstehen verlangt, bindet es den Menschen in den sich selbst korrigierenden Lernprozeß ein, in welchem weitere Fragen zu komplementären Einsichten führen. Indem es den Menschen dazu bringt zu reflektieren, das Unbedingte zu suchen, uneingeschränkte Zustimmung allein dem Unbedingten zu geben, hält es ihn davon ab, sich mit Hörensagen und Legenden, mit unverifizierten Hypothesen und ungeprüften Theorien zufriedenzugeben. Indem es schließlich noch weitere Fragen nach Einsicht und Reflexion aufwirft, schließt es selbstgefällige Trägheit aus; denn wenn die Fragen ohne Antwort bleiben, kann der Mensch nicht selbstzufrieden sein; und wenn Antworten gesucht werden, ist der Mensch nicht träge. (Fs)

405c Weil es von anderen Arten von Streben radikal verschieden ist, haben wir dieses Streben "rein" genannt. Es kann nicht durch die irreführende Analogie zu anderen Arten von Streben erkannt werden, sondern indem man dem intelligenten und rationalen Bewußtsein die Zügel schießen läßt. Es ist zwar ungreifbar, aber doch mächtig. Es reißt den Menschen aus der soliden Routine von Wahrnehmungen und Begehren, Instinkt und Gewohnheit, Tun und Erleben heraus. Es läßt ihn von [349] Problemen fasziniert sein. Es verpflichtet ihn zur Suche nach Lösungen. Es macht ihn zurückhaltend gegenüber dem, was nicht erwiesen ist. Es erzwingt Zustimmung zu dem Unbedingten. Es ist die kühle Klugheit des Common Sense, die Interesselosigkeit der Wissenschaft, die Unvoreingenommenheit der Philosophie. Es ist das Absorbiertsein in eine Untersuchung, die Freude der Entdeckung, die Gewißheit des Urteils, die Bescheidenheit der begrenzten Erkenntnis. Es ist die unnachgiebige Heiterkeit, die bedächtige Entschiedenheit, der ruhige Schwung, mit dem in der Entstehung von Wahrheit Frage treffend auf Frage folgt. (Fs)
406a Dieses reine Streben hat ein Zielobjekt. Es ist ein Streben nach Erkenntnis. Als bloßes Streben ist es auf Befriedigung durch Akte des Erkennens ausgerichtet, auf Befriedigung durch Akte des Verstehens, des vollständigen Verstehens, des korrekten Verstehens. Als reines Streben aber, als kühles, interesseloses und unparteiisches ist es nicht auf Erkenntnisakte und die Befriedigung, die sie dem Subjekt geben, ausgerichtet, sondern auf Erkenntnisinhalte, auf das, was erkannt werden soll. Die Befriedigung eines falschen Verstehens kann der Befriedigung eines korrekten Verstehens gleichkommen, vorausgesetzt, man weiß nicht, daß man sich täuscht. Das reine Streben aber verschmäht das erstere und schätzt das letztere hoch; es schätzt es als vom ersteren Verschiedenes; es schätzt es, nicht weil es zu einer Befriedigung fuhrt, sondern weil sein Inhalt korrekt ist. (Fs)

406b Das Zielobjekt des reinen Strebens ist der Inhalt des Aktes eher als der Akt selbst. Das Streben ist selbst aber noch nicht ein Erkennen und so ist auch sein Bereich nicht derselbe wie der Bereich des Erkennens. Anfänglich ist das reine Streben in jedem Individuum eine dynamische Orientierung auf ein gänzlich Unbekanntes hin. Indem sich das Erkennen entwickelt, wird das Objekt weniger und weniger unbekannt und immer mehr bekannt. Zu jeder Zeit schließt dieses Zielobjekt alles, was erkannt ist, und alles, was zu erkennen noch übrig bleibt, mit ein; denn es ist das Ziel der immanenten Dynamik des Erkenntnisprozesses, und diese Dynamik liegt der bereits erreichten Erkenntnis zugrunde und zielt über sie hinaus mit immer weiteren Fragen. (Fs)

406c Was ist dieses Zielobjekt? Ist es begrenzt oder unbegrenzt? Ist es Eines oder Vieles? Ist es materiell oder ideal? Ist es phänomenal oder real? Ist es ein immanenter Inhalt oder ein transzendentes Objekt? Ist es ein Bereich der Erfahrung oder des Denkens oder der Essenzen oder der Existierenden? Die Antworten auf diese und alle anderen Fragen haben alle eine einzige Quelle. Sie können nicht ohne das Funktionieren des reinen Strebens erhalten werden. Sie können nicht vom reinen Streben allein erhalten werden. Sie können erhalten werden, insofern das reine Streben Erkenntnisprozesse anregt und unterhält. Wenn es z. B. wahr ist, daß A ist, daß A eines ist, und daß es nur ein A gibt, dann ist das Zielobjekt des reinen Strebens Eines. Wenn es aber wahr ist, daß A ist, daß B ist, daß A nicht B ist, dann ist das Zielobjekt Vieles. Was ist, wird man fragen, denn nun wahr? Die Tatsache, daß gefragt wird, ergibt sich aus dem reinen Streben. Um die Antwort aber zu erreichen [350], genügt das Streben allein nicht; die Antworten stammen nur aus dem Untersuchen und dem Reflektieren. (Fs) (notabene)

407a Unsere Definition war nun, daß das Sein das Zielobjekt des reinen Erkenntnisstrebens ist. Sein ist dann
(1) alles, was erkannt ist, und
(2) alles, was zu erkennen übrig bleibt. (Fs)

Ferner, weil ein vollständiger Erkenntniszuwachs nur im Urteil stattfindet, ist das Sein das, was durch die Gesamtheit wahrer Urteile erkannt werden kann. Was ist nun, kann man fragen, diese Gesamtheit1? Es ist der vollständige Satz von Antworten auf den vollständigen Satz von Fragen. Was die Antworten sind, werden wir noch sehen. Welches die Fragen sind, wird sich uns noch zeigen. Bedeutungslose oder inkohärente oder illegitime Fragen sind möglich; aber wie sie zu definieren sind, ist ein anderes Problem. Wir behaupten hier, daß es ein reines Erkenntnisstreben gibt, einen suchenden und kritischen Geist, der Fragen auf weitere Fragen folgen läßt, der auf ein Zielobjekt hinarbeitet, das wir das Sein genannt haben. (Fs)

407b Unsere Definition des Seins ist deshalb zweiter Ordnung. Andere Definitionen bestimmen, was gemeint ist. Aber diese Definition ist entfernter, weil sie festlegt, nicht was unter Sein gemeint ist, sondern wie das Gemeinte zu bestimmen ist. Sie behauptet, daß wenn jemand erkennt, er das Sein erkennt; sie behauptet, daß wenn jemand erkennen will, er das Sein erkennen will; aber sie entscheidet nicht, ob man erkennt, oder was man erkennt, ob sich der Wunsch erfüllen wird, oder was man wissen wird, wenn der Wunsch sich erfüllt. (Fs) (notabene)

407c Wenn unsere Definition aber auch zweiter Ordnung ist, ist sie doch nicht einfach unbestimmt. Denn weder das Erkenntnisstreben noch das Erkennen selbst ist unbestimmt. Insofern das Erkennen bestimmt ist, konnten wir sagen, daß das Sein das ist, was durch wahre Urteile erkannt wird. Insofern das Erkenntnisstreben je das aktuelle Erkennen überschreitet, konnten wir sagen, daß das Sein ist, was durch die Gesamtheit der wahren Urteile erkannt wird. Das Sein hat damit zumindest ein Charakteristikum: Es ist allumfassend. Außer dem Sein gibt es nichts. Ferner, das Sein ist völlig konkret und völlig universell. Es ist völlig konkret; über und jenseits des Seins jedes Dinges gibt es nichts mehr von diesem Ding. Es ist völlig universell: Außerhalb des Bereichs des Seins gibt es einfach nichts. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein: eine uneingeschränkte Notion; Möglichkeit des Unerkennbaren?

Kurzinhalt: eshalb muß der Versuch, zu zeigen, daß das Sein nicht allumfassend ist, sich selbst aufheben; denn an der Wurzel all dessen, ... steht das reine Erkenntnisstreben ...

Textausschnitt: 2. Eine uneingeschränkte Notion

408a Man mag sich wundern, wie allumfassend das Sein denn sei. Dieses Sich-Wun-dern kann sich in einer Vielfalt von Weisen ausdrücken. Aber wie immer es auch [351] formuliert wird, und ob es auch formuliert werden kann, es wird nur zeigen, wie allumfassend das Sein ist. Das Wundern ist nämlich ein Fragen. Es ist das Streben nach Erkenntnis. Was immer es entdecken oder erfinden kann, ist durch eben diese Tatsache in die Notion des Seins eingeschlossen. Deshalb muß der Versuch, zu zeigen, daß das Sein nicht allumfassend ist, sich selbst aufheben; denn an der Wurzel all dessen, was bejaht werden kann, an der Wurzel all dessen, was gedacht werden kann, steht das reine Erkenntnisstreben; und es ist dieses reine Streben, das allem Urteilen und Formulieren zugrundeliegt, das allem Fragen und allem Streben nach Fragen zugrundeliegt, das sein allumfassendes Zielobjekt definiert. (Fs)

408b Trotzdem mag es nicht fehl am Platze sein, dieses Prinzip konkret zu erläutern. Es wird gesagt, daß wir Vieles nicht wissen. Zweifellos ist unsere Ignoranz groß; aber wir wissen um diese Tatsache, indem wir Fragen aufwerfen, die wir nicht beantworten; und das Sein definiert sich nicht nur durch die Antworten, die wir geben, sondern auch durch die Fragen, die wir stellen. Es wird weiter gesagt, daß es Vieles gibt, das zu erkennen sich gar nicht lohnt. Ohne Zweifel ist das unmittelbar fruchtbringende Feld der Untersuchung eingeschränkt. Aber wir erkennen diese Tatsache, indem wir zwischen den Fragen unterscheiden, von denen wir hoffen, sie bald beantworten zu können, und denen, die wir noch nicht in den Griff bekommen können; und das Sein wird definiert nicht nur durch die Fragen, die wir zu beantworten hoffen können, sondern auch durch die Fragen, deren Beantwortung wir auf später verschieben müssen. (Fs)

408c Drittens, viele werden einwenden, daß sie gar nicht alles über alles zu wissen wünschen. Wie aber wissen sie, daß sie nicht schon alles über alles wissen? Weil so viele Fragen gestellt werden können. Warum wollen sie nicht wirksam alles über alles wissen? Weil es so mühsam ist, auch nur einige wenige Antworten zu erreichen, so daß sie nun durch die Aussicht auf ein Beantworten aller Fragen, die sie stellen könnten, ganz entmutigt sind. (Fs)

408d Der Angriff kann auch von der entgegengesetzten Seite kommen. Das Problem ist, daß die Definition des Seins zu allumfassend ist. Fragen können bedeutungslos, illusorisch, inkohärent, illegitim sein. Der Versuch sie zu beantworten, fuhrt zu keiner Erkenntnis von irgendetwas. Nun gibt es zweifellos falsche Fragen, die nirgendwohin führen. Aber falsche Fragen sind formulierte Fragen. Das Sein ist nicht als das Zielobjekt formulierter Fragen definiert worden, sondern als das Zielobjekt des reinen Erkenntnisstrebens. Wie dieses Streben allen Fragen vorausgeht und selbst nicht eine Antwort ist, so geht es auch jeder formulierten Frage voraus und ist selbst nicht eine Formulierung. Außerdem, wie das reine Streben die intelligente und rationale Basis ist, von der her wir zwischen korrekten und inkorrekten Antworten unterscheiden, so ist es auch die intelligente und rationale Basis, von der her wir zwischen gültigen und falschen Fragen unterscheiden. Kurz: Das reine [352] Streben nach Erkenntnis, dessen Zielobjekt das Sein ist, ist nicht nur die Quelle für Antworten, sondern auch für ihre Kriterien, und nicht nur die Quelle für Fragen, sondern auch für die Gründe, nach denen die ausgewählt werden. Es ist ja das intelligente Untersuchen und vernünftige Reflektieren, das sowohl die richtigen Fragen wie auch die richtigen Antworten ergibt. (Fs)

409a Es mögen noch tiefgründigere Zweifel entstehen. Man kann, wenn man will, das Sein definieren als das, was durch die Gesamtheit der wahren Urteile erkannt wird. Aber ist das Sein wirklich das? Könnte es nicht irgendetwas ganz anderes sein? Fragen kommen auf. Sie können gültig oder falsch sein. Wenn sie falsch sind, sind sie zu ignorieren. Wenn sie gültig sind, dann sind unsere Zweifel ohne Grundlage. Denn das Sein, das ganz anders sein könnte, stellt sich als eben das heraus, über das wir sprechen. Wenn wir fragen, ob es sein könnte, dann fragen wir; und das Sein, über das wir eben sprechen, ist all das, worüber wir Fragen stellen. (Fs)

409b Ferner, könnte es nicht ein Unerkennbares geben? Wenn die Frage ungültig ist, ist sie zu ignorieren. Wenn die Frage gültig ist, kann die Antwort "Ja" oder "Nein" sein. Die Antwort "Ja" wäre aber inkohärent; denn man würde dann wissen, daß es das Unerkennbare gibt; und die Antwort "Nein" würde alles erkennbar und im Bereich des Seins lassen. (Fs) (notabene)

409c Es mögen andere Fragen aufkommen, aber anstatt diese einzeln zu verfolgen, wird es sinnvoller sein, wenn wir nun zu unserem Anfangstheorem zurückkehren. Jeder Zweifel daran, daß das reine Streben uneingeschränkt ist, dient nur dazu zu beweisen, daß es uneingeschränkt ist. Fragt man, ob denn X nicht außerhalb seiner Reichweite liege, so beweist die Tatsache, daß man fragt, daß es innerhalb seiner Reichweite liegt. Und wenn die Frage andererseits sinnlos, inkohärent, illusorisch, illegitim ist, dann stellt sich X als das reine Nichts heraus, das aus einer Verirrung des Erkenntnisprozesses resultiert. (Fs) (notabene)

410a Nicht nur ist also das Urteil absolut, nicht nur beruht es auf einem Erfassen des Unbedingten, nicht nur stellt die Reflexion die Dichotomie "Ist es oder ist es nicht?" auf, sondern an der Wurzel des Erkenntnisprozesses liegt ein kühles, unvoreingenommenes, interesseloses Streben nach Erkenntnis und seine Reichweite ist unbeschränkt. Sein ist das Jedes und Alles, welches das Zielobjekt dieses Strebens ist. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein: eine spontane Notion; Unterschied: Sein - Existenz; Notion des Seins als immanente, dynamische Orientierung des Erkenntnisprozesses (sie geht über das Gedachte hinaus)

Kurzinhalt: Diese Notion muß die immanente, dynamische Orientierung des Erkenntnisprozesses sein. Sie muß das unparteiische und uneingeschränkte Streben nach Erkenntnis, insofern es im Erkenntnisprozeß operativ ist.

Textausschnitt: 3. Eine spontane Notion

410b Nachdem wir erklärt haben, was wir unter Sein verstehen, müssen wir nun fragen, was denn die Notion des Seins ist. (Fs)

Erstens muß unterschieden werden zwischen der spontan operativen Notion einerseits und den theoretischen Darstellungen ihrer Entstehung und ihres Inhaltes andererseits. Die spontan operative Notion ist invariant; sie ist allen Menschen [353] gemeinsam; sie funktioniert auf dieselbe Weise, ungeachtet der theoretischen Erklärung von ihr, die man sich zu eigen macht. Andererseits gibt es eine Fülle theoretischer Erklärungen ihres Gehaltes und ihrer Entstehung; sie variieren mit den philosophischen Kontexten, mit der Vollständigkeit der Beobachtungen eines Denkers, mit der Gründlichkeit seiner Analyse. Wir werden zuerst unsere Erklärung der spontan operativen Notion geben und dann ein paar Bemerkungen zu anderen theoretischen Erklärungen derselben anfügen. (Fs)

410c Unter Voraussetzung unserer Analyse des Erkenntnisprozesses kann leicht geschlossen werden, daß die spontan operative Notion des Seins in das reine Erkenntnisstreben zu setzen ist. Denn, erstens, die Menschen sind geneigt, darin übereinzustimmen, daß die Dinge sind, ob wir sie nun kennen oder nicht, und daß es zudem viele Dinge gibt, die nur unvollständig oder sogar gar nicht bekannt sind. Die Notion des Seins geht also über das Erkannte hinaus. Zweitens, das Sein wird im Urteil erkannt. Im Urteil bejahen oder verneinen wir, und bis wir zum Bejahen oder Verneinen bereit sind, wissen wir noch nicht, ob irgend ein X nun tatsächlich ist oder nicht. Wenn das Sein aber auch erst im Urteil erkannt wird, geht die Notion des Seins doch dem Urteil voraus. Denn vor allem Urteil kommt die Reflexion, und die Reflexion findet ihre Formulierung in der Frage "Ist es so?" Diese Frage setzt eine Notion des Seins voraus, und sie geht merkwürdigerweise vor jedem Fall unserer Erkenntnis von Sein vorher. Nicht nur geht dann also die Notion des Seins über das Erkannte hinaus, sondern sie geht auch der abschließenden Komponente des Erkennens voraus, in der das Sein tatsächlich erkannt wird. Drittens, es gibt Gedankenobjekte. Ich kann mir ein Pferd denken und ebenso einen Kentaur. Ich kann mir die beste zur Verfügung stehende wissenschaftliche Meinung über ein beliebiges Objekt denken, und ich kann mir auch alle früheren Meinungen denken, die, zu ihrer Zeit, die besten über dasselbe Objekt zur Verfügung stehenden waren. In einem bestimmten Sinne sind sie alle äquivalent; denn solange man nur denkt, erwägt und annimmt, beschäftigt man sich bloß mit dem Bedingten, und es macht keinen Unterschied, ob seine Bedingungen nun erfüllt sind oder nicht. Das Denken sieht dann also von der Existenz ab. Wenn es aber vom Existieren absieht, sieht es dann nicht vom Sein ab? Und wenn es vom Sein absieht, ist es dann nicht ein Denken über nichts? Das Problem bei diesem Argument ist, daß das Denken auch vom Nicht-Existieren absieht. Wenn ich einen Kentauren oder das Phlogiston denke, dann sehe ich von der Tatsache ab, daß sie nicht existieren; wenn also das Absehen vom Existieren ein Absehen vom Sein ist, ist Absehen vom Nicht-Existieren ein Absehen vom Nicht-Sein; und wenn das Absehen vom Sein beweist, daß ich nichts denke, dann beweist das Absehen vom Nicht-Sein, daß ich etwas denke. (Fs)

411a Nun hat diese Art Überlegung viele Denker zur Annahme geführt, daß Sein eine Sache ist und Existieren eine ganz andere, daß Pferde und Kentauren, [354] Elektronen und Phlogiston alle sind, daß aber Pferde und Elektronen existieren, während Kentauren und Phlogiston nicht existieren. Diese Konklusion wird aber den Tatsachen nicht gerecht; denn abgesehen von der sonderbaren Behauptung, daß das Nicht-Existierende ist, wird die Dynamik des Erkenntnisprozesses falsch verstanden. In einem bestimmten Sinne sieht das Denken von Existieren und Nicht-existieren ab; denn es ist nicht das Denken, sondern das Urteilen, das bestimmt, ob irgendetwas existiert oder nicht. In einem anderen Sinn aber sieht das Denken nicht ab von Existieren und Nicht-existieren; denn das Denken ist zweckgerichtet; wir denken, um unsere Begriffe in Ordnung zu bringen; wir wollen unsere Begriffe in Ordnung haben, damit wir urteilen können; weit davon entfernt, von Existieren und Nicht-Existieren abzusehen, ist das Denken zum Zweck des Bestimmens da, ob das Gedachte auch wirklich existiere oder nicht. (Fs) (notabene)

411b Es folgt, daß die Notion des Seins das bloß Gedachte übersteigt; denn wir fragen, ob das bloß Gedachte existiere oder nicht. Es folgt ebenso, daß die Notion des Seins dem Denken vorausgeht; denn täte sie das nicht, könnte das Denken nicht auf den Zweck des Urteilens ausgerichtet sein, auf das Bestimmen, ob das bloß Gedachte existiere oder nicht. Die Notion des Seins geht also der Begriffsbildung voraus und über sie hinaus; und sie geht dem Urteil voraus und über es hinaus. Diese Notion muß die immanente, dynamische Orientierung des Erkenntnisprozesses sein. Sie muß das unparteiische und uneingeschränkte Streben nach Erkenntnis, insofern es im Erkenntnisprozeß operativ ist. Nach Erkenntnis streben heißt, nach Erkenntnis des Seins streben; aber es ist bloß das Streben und noch nicht das Erkennen. Denken ist das Denken von Sein; es ist nicht das Denken von nichts; aber das Denken von Sein ist noch nicht das Erkennen von Sein. Das Urteilen ist ein vollständiger Zuwachs im Erkennen; wenn es korrekt ist, ist es ein Erkennen von Sein; aber es ist noch nicht ein Erkennen des Seins; denn dieses wird erst durch die Gesamtheit der korrekten Urteile erreicht. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein: eine spontane Notion; das Streben nach Sein ist intelligent und rational (Bsispiel: Fötusauge);

Kurzinhalt: Denn das Streben nach Erkenntnis ist nicht unbewußt, wie das Fötusauge, und nicht empirisch bewußt, wie der Hunger, und auch nicht eine Konsequenz intellektuellen Erkennens, wie es Entscheidung und Wahl sind ...

Textausschnitt: 412a Wie kann nun aber eine Orientierung oder ein Streben eine Notion genannt werden? Ein Fötusauge ist auf das Sehen hin orientiert; aber ein Fötusauge sieht nicht und hat keine Notion von Sehen; eine Notion kommt in diesem Fall nur auf, insofern das Verstehen die zukünftige Funktion in der gegenwärtigen Struktur ermittelt. Der Hunger ist auf Nahrung und Essen hin orientiert; er ist ein Streben; er liegt im Bereich der empirischen Bewußtseins; aber eine Notion kommt nur insofern auf, als die Orientierung des Hungers verstanden wird. Zweckgerichtete menschliche Tätigkeit ist auf ein Ziel oder Produkt ausgerichtet; erkenntnismäßige Elemente liefern die Regel und Führung eines solchen Handelns; aber die erkenntnismäßigen Elemente gehen dem Handeln voraus; sie werden nicht durch die Handlung selbst konstituiert, sondern durch das Planen, das dieser vorausgeht. (Fs)

412b Nun ist keines dieser Beispiele eine exakte Parallele zur Relation zwischen dem [355] Erkenntnisstreben und dem Erkenntnisprozeß. Denn das Streben nach Erkenntnis ist nicht unbewußt, wie das Fötusauge, und nicht empirisch bewußt, wie der Hunger, und auch nicht eine Konsequenz intellektuellen Erkennens, wie es Entscheidung und Wahl sind. Das Erkenntnisstreben ist intelligent und rational bewußt; es ist die untersuchende Intelligenz und die reflektierende Vernunft. Einfach als Streben ist es eine Orientierung, noch ohne irgendeinen Erkenntnisgehalt oder -notion. Trotzdem hält die Intelligenz - vergleichbar der Vorderseite einer Münze - nach dem Intelligiblen als Rückseite Ausschau. Die Vernunft, als Vorderseite, hält nach dem Begründeten als Rückseite Ausschau. Noch grundlegender ist das Ausschauhalten, das Streben, das Untersuchen-und-Reflektieren, eine Vorderseite, die intelligent und rational auf ein uneingeschränktes Zielobjekt zugeht, welches das Sein genannt wird. Wäre diese Tendenz unbewußt, dann gäbe es eine Ausrichtung auf das Sein hin, aber es gäbe kein Streben nach Erkenntnis des Seins und keine Notion des Seins. Wäre diese Tendenz empirisch bewußt, dann gäbe es eine Ausrichtung auf das Sein hin und ein gefühltes Streben nach Erkenntnis des Seins, aber es gäbe keine Notion des Seins. In der Tat aber ist die Tendenz intelligent und rational, und somit gibt es nicht nur eine Ausrichtung auf das Sein hin, nicht nur ein reines Streben nach Erkenntnis des Seins, sondern auch eine Notion des Seins. (Fs)

413a Wir wollen nun versuchen, diese Notion, diese Intention des Seins, in ihrem Wirken zu erfassen. Wir sprechen von der Abstraktion und gemeinhin verstehen wir darunter eine Ausrichtung der Aufmerksamkeit auf gewisse Aspekte des Gegebenen unter gleichzeitiger Vernachlässigung anderer Aspekte. Der Mathematiker betrachtet den Kreis als eine ebene Figur, die einer gewissen Regel gehorcht; er sieht von Größe, Farbe und Unexaktheit der Figur, die er zeichent oder sich vorstellt, ab; mehr noch sieht er von anderen und lockerer verbundenen Aspekten des Gegebenen ab. Das ist aber noch nicht alles. Er vernachlässigt alle anderen Fragen der Geometrie, alle anderen Abteilungen der Mathematik, alle anderen Gebiete der Wissenschaften, alle anderen menschlichen Beschäftigungen, auf die er zurückgreifen könnte. Er betrachtet allein den Kreis. Er abstrahiert von allem anderen. Er tut dies auf intelligente Weise; denn das Zielobjekt seines Strebens ist zwar uneingeschränkt, doch kann er sich nur auf es zubewegen, wenn er sich auf ein Element nach dem anderen konzentriert. Ferner, wie die Intelligenz abstrahiert, so sieht die Reflexion ab. Wenn ich beurteilen soll, ob dies eine Schreibmaschine ist oder nicht, muß ich von allem absehen, was für dieses Problem nicht relevant ist. Ich muß alles wissen, was relevant ist. Wäre ich ein Relativist, müßte ich das Universum kennen, um alles, was für dieses eine Urteil relevant ist, zu wissen. Auch wenn ich kein Relativist bin, auch wenn ich finde, daß viele bedingte Aussagen durch die Erfüllung einer beherrschbaren Zahl von Bedingungen virtuell unbedingt werden, ist diese Einschränkung des Relevanten doch begleitet von der Anerkennung eines Universums von Irrelevanzen. (Fs)

413b Schließlich, wie sich die Intelligenz auf das Signifikante konzentriert, um von [356] allem anderen zu abstrahieren, wie sich die Reflexion auf das Relevante konzentriert, um von allem anderen abzusehen, so kommen weitere Fragen und weitere Probleme nicht als eine Überraschung oder als ein Neubeginn auf. Das Abstrahieren und Absehen waren provisorisch; sie waren bloß Momente in einem umfassenderen Prozeß. Und dieser umfassendere Prozeß ist auch nicht bloß das Objekt einer introspektiven Analyse. Immanent in ihm und ihn bewirkend liegt ein intelligentes und rationales Bewußtsein, das uneingeschränkt ein entsprechend eingeschränktes Zielobjekt intendiert, welches das Sein genannt wird, oder das All, oder das Alles über Alles, oder das konkrete Universum. So wie die Notion des Intelligiblen im aktuellen Funktionieren der Intelligenz enthalten ist, so wie die Notion des Begründeten im aktuellen Funktionieren der Vernunft enthalten ist, so ist die Notion des Seins im uneingeschränkten Trieb der suchenden Intelligenz und der reflektierenden Vernunft enthalten. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Natur - Gott; Definition (3 Bedeutungen, Aristoteles); Name Gottes; Intellekt - Unendlichkeit; Existenz des Unendlichen; Natur als inneres Prinzip der Tätigkeit

Kurzinhalt: ... since we use the term 'nature' in two ways, and in the first way the term is not applicable to God while in the second it refers to that in God which in this life we cannot know.

Textausschnitt: The Nature of God

193b Since generation results in a likeness in nature, we have to consider the question, What is the nature of God? But this question seems somehow insoluble, since we use the term 'nature' in two ways, and in the first way the term is not applicable to God while in the second it refers to that in God which in this life we cannot know. (Fs)

193c Thus, according to Aristotle, nature is defined as the principle of motion and rest in that in which it exists first and per se and not as an accident.1 But God is absolutely simple; otherwise God would not be the first principle of all things. So there cannot be in God a real distinction between a principle of motion or of operation and the motion or operation itself. In this sense, therefore, nature cannot be posited in God. (Fs)
193d However, if 'nature' is taken in the sense of essence, then nature can be acknowledged in God, but we do not know it. For in this life we do not know what God is. Although the name 'God' is assigned to signify the divine nature, nevertheless the name itself is not derived from a known nature; so it seems that the name 'the One who is' is the most proper name of God, because this name is taken from God's act of existence and leaves unmentioned every determining form in order to signify an infinite ocean of substance.2 (Fs)

195a On the other hand, according to St Thomas God's act of understanding is God's substance,3 God's nature is God's very act of understanding,4 and intellectual creatures are in the image of God because they possess a specific likeness.5 (Fs) (notabene)

195b It seems, therefore, that one ought to respond that, if 'nature' is taken in the sense of essence, then in this life we do not know what God is because we do not understand God through a species proportionate to the divine essence.6 Still, this in no way prevents us from knowing God analogically in this life or from ordering what we know analogically in such a way that some element of what we know analogically is first after the manner of a nature or essence. In this sense, the nature of God is God's act of understanding, upon which follow God's infinity and aseity and simplicity, and whatever else there is in God but unknown to us. (Fs)

195c Indeed, infinity so belongs to the very notion of intellect that an intellect in act with respect to its total object is infinite. For since the intellect is such as to become all things, and since 'all things' admits no specific or generic limitation, the object of intellect is the totality of being.7 It follows that intellect tends toward its object in such a way that it does not rest until it beholds God in God's essence;8 that every created intellect is a passive potency;9 that every created act of understanding is distinct from the substance of the creature, distinct from its act of existence, and distinct from its operative potency;10 and that an intellect in act with respect to its total object is infinite being.11 (Fs)

195d Moreover, infinite being cannot be from another; so intellect in act with respect to its total object is from itself. (Fs) (notabene)

197a Again, the infinite excludes potency; for hat is in potency to a further perfection falls short of infinity by that very fact. (Fs)

197b Again, the intellect in act is the intelligible in act; and intellect differs from the intelligible only to the extent that both are in potency.12 But the infinite excludes potency. Therefore, understanding that is in act with respect to its total object is not distinct from the intellect that understands. Furthermore, the infinite itself as knowable or intelligible is not distinct from the act of understanding by which it is understood.13 Finally, the infinite act of understanding is true with respect to itself, not because of a likeness, as if the knowing and the known were two, but because of the absence of unlikeness.14 (Fs) (notabene)

1.Kommentar (28.05.08): Das "both" in "that both are in potency" ist irreführend. Cf. Thomas, F4_014: 'Das Sinnenfällige im Wahrgenommensein ist der Sinn im Wahrnehmen, und das Verstehbare im Verstandensein ist der Verstand im Verstehen' (Aristoteles). Denn dadurch fühlen oder erkennen wir etwas im Vollzug, wenn unser Verstand oder Sinn durch ein sinnenfälliges oder geistiges Bild im Vollzug geformt wird. Und nur insoweit unterscheiden sich Sinn und Verstand vom Sinnenfälligen und Verstehbaren, als [oder solange] sie beides nur der Möglichkeit nach sind. (9; Fs)

197c Again, the natural act of existence of the infinite is not different from its intentional act of existence. For the natural act of existence of some being is the act of existence by which it is; and its intentional act of existence is the medium by which it is known. But in the case of the infinite, the act of understanding by which the infinite is known is the same as the intelligible which is known. Therefore, the natural act of existence of the infinite is the same as its intentional act of existence.15 (Fs) (notabene)

197d Again, the infinite is absolutely simple. For a single act of understanding is simple; and an infinite act of understanding is a single act; and this single act is identical with all that the infinite knows concerning the infinite. (Fs)

197e Again, although we conceive the infinite only analogically inasmuch as we ascend from our finite act of understanding, nevertheless the infinite act of understanding comprehends itself perfectly. And it does not comprehend itself as different from its very act of understanding but as identical in every way. And so if the nature of God is conceived as an intellect in act with respect to its total object, then the infinity of God, the aseity of God, and the simplicity of God all follow, as does everything else in God that remains unknown to us. (Fs)

197f If, however, 'nature' is taken not in the sense of essence from which all else follows, but in the sense of the intrinsic principle of operation, we can conclude again that the divine nature is intellectual. For although absolutely no real distinction can be posited in God according to our natural knowledge of God, still, as we come to know God through faith and theology, we discover real personal distinctions in God that are constituted through relations of origin. Now, 'the mode of origin is not the same in all things; rather, the mode of origin of each thing is in accord with what befits its own nature: animate things being produced in one way, inanimate things in another; animals in one way and plants in another. It is evident, therefore, that the distinction of divine persons is in accord with what befits the divine nature.'16 But 'the uncreated Trinity is distinguished on the basis of the procession of the Word from the Speaker and of Love from both.'17 And so, since the origins in God are according to the emanations of intellectual consciousness, we must conclude that the divine nature is intellectual. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Kritik 1 u. 2 an Husserl: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften; Wissenschaft, Philosophie, Theologie; "wissenschaftlich": Flucht vom Menschsein (Wissenschaftler - Objekt); absolute Sicherheit - virtuell bedingte S. (Kritik an H.)

Kurzinhalt: The history of the human sciences, where the element 'scientific' has been emphasized, has been a continual flight from what is truly human to what, in man, is not properly human... we have to disagree with Husserl in his pursuit of philosophy as ...

Textausschnitt: 9 Critique of Husserl's Krisis

260b Such is Husserl's program, and we will attempt right away a few of the more obvious criticisms. In the next hour, we will go on to his key notion of phenomenology, which has of course had a far richer life than Husserl's philosophic ideal.1 (Fs)

9.1 Human Science, Philosophy, and Theology

260b First of all, then, there is a real problem set by science and especially by human science, and its only solution lies in going to a philosophy. Natural science can get along pretty well by relying simply on the pragmatic criterion of success. We produce the results, and everybody can see the results. They can keep going on that basis. But even so, they suffer from a neglect of basic research, of fundamental thinking, simply because it is difficult to see the necessity of fundamental research when your criteria ultimately are pragmatic, the results that everyone can appreciate. But human science cannot get along on that basis. Human science is involved in philosophic issues from the simple fact that the human scientist is one of his own objects. He cannot be totally detached in the science without special guidance. The history of the human sciences, where the element 'scientific' has been emphasized, has been a continual flight from what is truly human to what, in man, is not properly human. That flight has grounded a great deal of the success of the phenomenological movement. (Fs) (notabene)

261a So we can admit, in the main, Husserl's strictures on the situation of modern science. In other words, science has problems that it cannot solve, that can be solved only in terms of a philosophy. Further, not only does the problem of science raise philosophic questions. The problem of human science raises theological questions. We have today a situation that is essentially different from the medieval situation. St Thomas could produce the synthesis in a vertical line: theology, philosophy, science, where philosophy was the 'handmaid of theology,' ancilla theologiae, because in his time science was simply a department of philosophy. It was Aristotelian science and a part of Aristotelian philosophy. In subsequent periods, as long as science did not become strictly human, that mode of organization could be maintained. But at the present time, where we have empirical human sciences, where we have sciences dealing with men as they are, men under the influence of original sin, offered God's grace, and either accepting it or refusing it, there are theological issues involved in concrete human living, and consequently science, insofar as it includes human science, cannot be simply subsumed under philosophy, where philosophy prescinds entirely from theology. The problem of synthesis today is the problem of synthesis in the form of some sort of triangle, where philosophy, in our traditional sense, is related to theology and is related to science, but where science is not related simply to philosophy. A part of it, namely the human science, is in need of a direct contact with theology. (Fs)

9.2 Science, Necessity, and Certitude

261b Secondly, while we admit Husserl's problem and, moreover, point out the necessity not only of philosophy but in certain respects also of theology, we have to disagree with Husserl in his pursuit of philosophy as rigorous science in the sense in which he understood this, namely, as grounded in necessity and yielding absolute certitude. This ideal has undoubtedly its Greek and its Cartesian antecedents, but it stands in need of distinction. All human judgments rest on a virtually unconditioned, as I argued last week.2 They are true as a matter of fact. The pursuit of absolute necessity, absolute certitude, is the pursuit of more than man can have, and consequently it is doomed to failure because it is overshooting the mark. I think that is the fundamental criticism of Husserl, but obviously it needs considerable development and we cannot attempt that here. We do not automatically go along with a philosopher simply because he is out for absolute necessity and absolute certitude. God is absolutely necessary, and God has absolute certitude without any conditions whatever. But we arrive at our certitudes and our knowledge of necessity insofar as, as a matter of fact, each one of us reaches in particular cases the virtually unconditioned. Our knowledge is based on the knowledge of a contingent world, and our knowing is a contingent event. To demand the absolute and to be content with absolutely nothing else results in a skepticism. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Kritik 3 an Husserl: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften; Abschattung - Horizont; Einstellung - Welt; Commonsense, Theorie (Husserl vs. Lonergan); zwei Welten bei H. -> Heidegger

Kurzinhalt: The correlations of Abschattung and Horizont, of Einstellung and Welt, are, I believe, valuable contributions to cognitional analysis. Still, the alleged two worlds are but one set of beings considered from two standpoints. The one set of beings ...

Textausschnitt: 9.3 The Two Worlds and the Two Truths

262a The correlations of Abschattung and Horizont, of Einstellung and Welt, are, I believe, valuable contributions to cognitional analysis. Still, the alleged two worlds are but one set of beings considered from two standpoints. The one set of beings, as considered relatively to us in its relevance to human living, to the practical problems of man keeping alive and keeping the peace, is the world of common sense. The same set of beings, insofar as one seeks the universal laws of their interrelations, is the world of science. The two worlds are unified in the notion of being and distinguished by considering different relations among beings. The relations of all beings, insofar as they concern the practical problem of man's living, is the world of common sense, and the relations of beings to one another according to their natural laws is the world of science. (Fs)

262b Again, the two truths are simply the result of applying the appropriate criteria to two cases of knowledge that is sought from different standpoints. If I seek to know this one set of beings insofar as it concerns me practically, there is a set of criteria I follow, and I arrive at certain truths that way. If I seek to know what is universally and necessarily so with regard to the relations between beings objectively, then I have to proceed in a different manner, and use different criteria and more elaborate methods. And so we arrive at a distinction between the truths of common sense and the truths of science. You can see how this problem of the two worlds in Husserl moves Heidegger on to the question of Being. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Kritik 4 an Husserl: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften; Unterschied: Wissenschaft - Lebenswelt;

Kurzinhalt: And so I do not think that Husserl is accurate when he says that the sciences rest simply on popular notions. What is true is that, when you start questioning scientists, they usually are not very good at philosophy ...

Textausschnitt: 9.4 Science and the Lebenswelt

263a In the fourth place, de facto science does not rest on the evidence and procedures of commonsense living, of the Lebenswelt. There has been a failure to attempt the phenomenology of the scientist or of the phenomenologist. If there were a phenomenology of the scientist, certainly it would note that the scientist does not fit into the 'life scene,' the ideas of common sense on human living. Thales was an oddity, looking at the stars and tumbling into the well. He was not living in the Lebenswelt. Archimedes running naked through the streets shouting, 'I've got it!' was not an ordinary specimen of commonsense humanity. Newton, living absorbed in his problems for days in his room, having his meals brought to him and hardly pecking at them, was not an ordinary specimen of common sense. There is a specific pattern of consciousness, a specific pattern of experience, that characterizes the scientist at work. And so I do not think that Husserl is accurate when he says that the sciences rest simply on popular notions. What is true is that, when you start questioning scientists, they usually are not very good at philosophy, or the philosophy they have is not very good, and they will not be able to give a very good account of themselves. But as Einstein pointed out to epistemologists and theorists of science, 'Don't pay any attention to what the scientists say to you; watch what they do.'1 If you ask them what they are doing and start asking them for their opinions, all they will do is trot out some third-rate theory of knowledge. But if you watch what they do, you will be getting at the facts of scientific inquiry, and that is something quite independent of the third-rate theory of knowledge that any particular scientist may happen to hold. (Fs)

263b Now as far as I know - I have not read all of Husserl, but no one has, as a matter of fact, because a lot of it is still in this queer shorthand of his - Husserl has not done justice to that point. And as well, the subsequent concern with engaged consciousness, consciousness as orientated upon choosing, the flight from any type of intellectualist attitude as though it involved one necessarily in positivism or idealism (which are anathema to the contemporary European), has resulted in a neglect of that field due to a subsequent bias. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Kritik 5 an Husserl: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften; Normen - Intellekt (participatio creata lucis increatae)

Kurzinhalt: Fifthly, Greek, Renaissance, and subsequent normative accounts of truth, science, and method are not just artificial ideals floating on popular obscurity.

Textausschnitt: 9.5 Normativeness of Human Intelligence and Reason

264a Fifthly, Greek, Renaissance, and subsequent normative accounts of truth, science, and method are not just artificial ideals floating on popular obscurity. It is true that they are nonphilosophic, or inadequate philosophic expositions. But they really are expressions, clarifications, objectifications of the immanent normativeness of the human intellect, of our participatio creata lucis increatae. In other words, human intelligence and human reasonableness intrinsically involve norms. There are things that are intelligent and stupid, there are things that are reasonable and silly, and there is that ultimate normativeness in our intellect that comes to us from God, the lumen intellectus nostri that is a participatio creata lucis increatae. This aspect of human intelligence comes to light, not at all perfectly but to a notable extent, in Heidegger's notion of Erschlossenheit, openness, what the French call ouverture. the openness of mind, which is the orientation of mind to Being in tota sua latitudine. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Kritik 6 an Husserl: Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften; Priorität des Subjektes; Köhler (Schimpansen; Mangel an Imagination); participatio creata lucis increatae: Grund des Wissens; transzendentale Reduktion -> Sein (nicht Subjekt)

Kurzinhalt: ... we cannot follow Husserl in his demand for absolute necessity and absolute certitude. What we know is true as a matter of fact, and to demand more is ... finally, Husserl's transcendental reduction to the subject is not ultimate: ...

Textausschnitt: 9.6 Priority of the Subject

264b Finally, there is a real priority of the subject in knowledge. The human sensitive psyche is not the animal psyche. Kohler, in his experiment with the apes, discovered that even the most intelligent type of ape, the chimpanzee, does not have free images.1 If you put an element of the solution of a problem to the ape within its field of vision, the ape will solve the problem. But if you put the element such that the ape can only see one element now and another element later, he cannot form a free image, even though the problem is essentially the same. In man, the free image is fundamental. Children are continually imagining and pretending, and that is something essentially human. To educate people you have to give them a formation in language and literature; otherwise they lack imaginations, and without imaginations they do not have a sensitive tool of sufficient suppleness and range to provide a basis for intellectual activity. This is the theoretical ground of classical or humanistic education. (Fs)

264c Again our participatio creata lucis increatae is in fact the ground of questions and of all intellectual activity. (Fs)

265a Still, though the subject has this priority in knowledge, we cannot follow Husserl in his demand for absolute necessity and absolute certitude. What we know is true as a matter of fact, and to demand more is to move towards an impossible ideal that backfires into skepticism. In Husserl's epochê, as we will see in the next hour, there is involved the confusion between what Santayana calls animal faith and, on the other hand, rational judgment. (Fs)

265b And finally, Husserl's transcendental reduction to the subject is not ultimate: the ultimate reduction is of subject and object, scientific world and world of common sense, to being.2 The subject is, and if he is, then he is among the beings. (Fs)
265c So much, then, for a very rough outline of a powerful book by Husserl. I hope I have conveyed to you some idea of its sweep and radicalness, and some intimation also of the way Husserl worked all his life long in search of foundations for philosophy and science. The more obvious limitations I have indicated, but Husserl's great discovery was phenomenology, and in the next period we shall say what comes to mind regarding its nature, its significance, and its limitations.3 (Fs; E08 21.12.2008)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Phänomenologie: Definition (Daten, strukturiert durch Einsicht); Wesensschau (eidetische Struktur d. Daten; Aristoteles: Form - Materie); Phä.: nicht direkt Analyse d. Einsicht (Mangel an vereinheitlichender Synthese) -> Kluft zw. Phänomen und Begriff

Kurzinhalt: That is my own definition of it: an account, description, presentation of data structured by insight. ...On the other hand, phenomenology is not concerned with insight as such. Insight as such is something extremely elusive.

Textausschnitt: 1 The Nature of Phenomenology

266a It will be more helpful to start from the question of the nature of phenomenology. What is phenomenology? It is an account, description, presentation of data structured by insight. That is my own definition of it: an account, description, presentation of data structured by insight. (Fs) (notabene)

1.1 'Of Data'

266b It is 'of data,' of what is given, what is manifest, what appears, phenomena. It is not just of external data, external phenomena, but also of inner data. That is the basis of its opposition to experimental psychology as commonly understood, to all behaviorism, to all types of mechanism. It includes the internal among the data, the phenomena, what is manifest, what is given. But it is also not exclusively of internal data. The inner intentional act terminates at the outer datum, and the outer datum is just the term of the inner intentional act. The subject is nothing apart from the intended term, and the intended term is nothing apart from the intending subject. The synthesis of both is found in the intentional act. (Fs) (notabene)

266c Nothing is excluded from consideration. Phenomenology is not a matter of considering primitive data as opposed to derived, natural as opposed to cultural, sensitive as opposed to intellectual, cognitional as opposed to emotional or conative. It is concerned with everything that appears, everything that is given, everything that is manifest. (Fs)

1.2 Data Structured by Insight

267a However, it is of data structured by insight. In other words, it is selective. It does not offer an exhaustive description of all and any data whatever. There is a structure to it, a selection, and the selection is of the significant. It seeks basic, universal structures. Husserl spoke of the eidetic (from eidos, form), the structure in the data. He also spoke about Wesensschau, an intuition of essence. I bring in the word 'insight' because what he is talking about seems to me to be quite parallel to the distinction in Aristotle's Metaphysics in book vii, about chapter 10, between parts of the matter and parts of the form.1 With regard to a circle, for instance, the form is the necessary roundness of the circumference, resulting from the equality of all radii, where radii are multiplied to infinity. If all the radii are absolutely equal, you see that the curve has to be perfectly round. And if any one is not equal to any of the others, you see that this curve, because of the inequality of any one radius, involves a bump or a dent. That is something manifest, something presented, something that appears, and it is structured by the insight. Parts of the matter, on the other hand, are, for instance, the fact that the circle is white on black, that the drawing is in chalk, or that it is in almost a vertical plane, or that it is just this size and no bigger or smaller. But the parts of the form are the perimeter, the equal radii, and the center. You understand why the circle has to be round because of the inner ground of that roundness in the circle. Among the multiplicity of data, some are merely casual and are called parts of the matter, but there also are parts of the form: the center, the equal radii, and the circumference. That is a case of data structured by an insight. Husserl and phenomenology are concerned with considering all data without any exclusion, as structured by insight, as given a form, an eidos, from the insight. (Fs)

267b Now to present data structured by insight, Husserl does not proceed on the basis of the first bright idea that comes along. To find what really is the proper structure of the data takes effort and time; it calls for scrutiny, penetration, contrasts, and tests. It may be necessary to overcome spontaneous tendentiousness, systematic oversights, common over-simplifications, preconceptions arising from a scientific outlook or a philosophic position or any other source. In other words, we are not accounting for data structured by the first insight that comes along but for data structured by an ultimate insight that hits things off and meets the issues. (Fs)

1.3 Not Insight as Such

268a On the other hand, phenomenology is not concerned with insight as such. Insight as such is something extremely elusive. If the phenomenologist had hold of the insight itself, the act of intelligence by which you grasp the necessity of roundness when the radii are equal and the impossibility of roundness when they are unequal, he would immediately be led to unity, to a unification of insights into a science, to the movement of the sciences from lower to higher viewpoints, to the integration of the sciences, and to the integration of science and common sense in philosophy. A study of insight leads immediately to a synthetic position, as is illustrated in the book called Insight. And there is not that kind of tendency to unity in phenomenology.1 Husserl spent his life perpetually discovering new fields of possible investigations. He would investigate something and define the issue more and more closely. He would set aside other fields, and the fields of possible investigation in which data might be structured by insight kept multiplying. He kept filling in more and more pages of notes in shorthand.2 Again, there is no tendency to unity among his successors either; they do brilliant work in particular limited fields, but phenomenology does not head towards a synthesis, towards a unification. (Fs)

1.4 Data, Not Concepts

268b Finally, it is the data as structured by insight that are the objects of phenomenology, not the subsequent conceptualization or definition or theoretic statement of the data in their essential features. What you have to attend to in the circle, the data as structured by an insight, consists in these radii or other particular radii that you imagine, and similarly this circumference or another particular circumference that you imagine: not the concept of radius, of which there is only one, or the concept of center, of which there is only one. The basis on which you grasp this necessity is only in the imagined multiplicity. You need an infinity of radii to be able to get the insight: only if every possible radius is absolutely equal to every other one do you get this necessary roundness. (Fs)

269a There is a sharp distinction, then, in phenomenology between what appears as structured by proper insights and, on the other hand, the thematic treatment, the phenomenological exposition, of the data as structured by the insight. What is manifest is one thing, and on the other hand what the phenomenologist says is quite something else. Just as when you grasp this necessary roundness in the data you define the circle as the locus of coplanar points equidistant from the center, so the phenomenologist, considering what is manifest, what is given, what appears, as intelligently structured, distinguishes that sharply from his thematic treatment of the data. He is not concerned with his own statement about it; that is just his report. His report is one thing, and what he reports on is another. (Fs)

269b Consequently, there is in phenomenology a terrific emphasis on what is called the pre-predicative, that is, what is known before you conceptualize, before you formulate any theory, before you make any judgment or any statement. It is the pre-predicative manifest, what is manifest pre-predicatively, pre-theoretically, pre-judicially, what is there, what is given, that the phenomenologist is concerned with. He distinguishes that sharply from what he calls the thematic treatment, exposition, presentation, which is his writing, his report, his observations. The etymology of the word 'phenomenology' speaks of phenomena and legein: to read off the phenomena. The phenomena are what are manifest, and reading them off, legein, is what the phenomenologist does. I make my own statement in terms of insight because I think it makes the matter very clear, and I have provided a broader context for it. But they do not speak of insight, although they are sufficiently aware of the fact. (Fs)



____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Bedeutung d. Phänomenologie 1; fruchtbare Anwendung d. Methode in d. Psychologie; Husserl (Abschattung, Horizont), Maurice Merleau-Ponty

Kurzinhalt: So one part of the significance of phenomenology is that it has provided a tool that seems extremely fruitful and that appears in various types of investigations of a psychological character.

Textausschnitt: 2 The Significance of Phenomenology

2.1 Psychological Explorations

269c Secondly, we treat the significance of phenomenology. It has more or less swept the field in a variety of ways, and its first significance is that it provides a technique for the exploration and presentation of whole realms of matters of fact that are important but that have been neglected or treated superficially. In a psychology, for example, that calls itself scientific, there is a bias in favor of outer data, in favor of what can be measured, in favor of events that can be counted. Phenomenology, as contrasted with scientific psychology in that sense, opens up new vistas and possibilities in a manner that is comparable to Freud's discovery of significance in dreams, and far broader in its scope and implications. So phenomenology appears as a break with scientific tendencies in psychology. (Fs)

270a It also appears as a break with some older, more traditional psychologies. When compared to the results of phenomenological research, we find in traditional psychology as represented, for example, by William James or by the Scholastics either rough and ready statements, on the one hand, or on the other hand, when precision is attempted, a tendency to bog down in a set of indefinable 'somethings.' For example, when you start talking about consciousness, just precisely what are you talking about? How do you pin it all down? When you want to draw precise distinctions and get things accurately, there is needed a technique, and phenomenology provides such a technique. (Fs)

270b This may be illustrated by Husserl's distinction between Abschattung and Horizont, but it is found also in entirely different fields and in writers that have no philosophic connections either with Husserl or pretty well anyone else. For example, there is a very short little book written by Buytendijk, on the phenomenology of a meeting. The French translation, which is the only thing I've seen, published by Desclée in 1952, is entitled Phenomenologie de la rencontre.1 The book presents a description of just what is involved psychologically when one person meets another, what appears, what is manifest in a meeting when you really understand what it is for two people to meet. The description is brilliant, and it presents us with the human event, the meeting, in a way that otherwise one could not arrive at. Buytendijk wrote an earlier work, also published in French by Desclée in the same year, I think, or perhaps earlier: La femme, on woman's attitudes.2 Whether his earlier work on the essence and meaning of play, Wesen und Sinn des Spiels (Berlin, 1933), is of this type or not I do not know; I imagine it is but I have not seen it.3 At any rate, he is a representative of the use of phenomenology as a technique in psychological study. (Fs)

271a Again, Stephan Strasser has a recent book called Das Gemüt, which has been very highly praised in a review in The Philosophical Review, a publication from Cornell.4 It is a study of the emotions. He also has an earlier work, the French translation of which is called Le probleme de l'âme.5 It is a study of the respective objects of metaphysical psychology and empirical psychology, a study of how you go about stating just what you mean by the soul and how you investigate the soul. The approach again is phenomenological; Strasser is not a member of some particular philosophic school. (Fs)

271b Next, there is the work of Maurice Merleau-Ponty. He is a leader in the existentialist movement and a professor at the Sorbonne. In 1942 he wrote his Structure of Behavior, La structure du comportement,6 and in 1945 La phenomenologie de la perception, published in Paris by Gallimard.7 He is brilliant, in his account of perception, on the significance of one's own body in one's perceiving. He is, of course, engaged in an attack upon Sartre's sharp distinction between the pour-soi, the conscious, and the en-soi, the mere dead thing. The body is both pour-soi and en-soi at the same time, and it has to be both at the same time; you cannot account for perception without one's consciousness of one's body. In other words, the perceiving subject is spatiotemporal; we have a feeling of space and time, so to speak, in our bodies. This is what Marcel would call incarnation, the incarnate subject: not just the idealist subject or any merely observing subject, but the incarnate subject. The subject has to have a body to perceive. The body enters right into consciousness. Merleau-Ponty's treatment varies time and again, and very convincingly. He has no philosophic commitments, in the sense that he is not tied down to some particular philosophic school. His work offers very useful material, I believe. I am not at all an expert in his views, but I think that anyone interested in psychology would find Merleau-Ponty extremely stimulating and probably very helpful. Again, he presents the incarnate subject, the subject as the subject of feelings in a body, the body of the subject. You cannot have either the body or the perceiving subject as intelligible without bringing the other in; you have to have the body to understand the subject, and the subject to understand the body. What is the human body? It is the incarnation of meaning, of a principle of meaning. And of course this ties in with the old-time axiom that a person by the age of thirty is responsible for his own face. (Fs) (notabene)

272a There has been a study of Merleau-Ponty by de Waelhens in 1951 at Louvain, Une philosophie de l'ambiguité (A Philosophy of Ambiguity).8 It is a study of Merleau-Ponty's existentialism, but in it you get a good deal of his psychology. (Fs)

272b So one part of the significance of phenomenology is that it has provided a tool that seems extremely fruitful and that appears in various types of investigations of a psychological character. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Bedeutung d. Phänomenologie 2; Heidegger (Dasein, Existentialismus); Binswanger, Freud (Träume d. Nacht, d. Morgens); Bultmann (Glaube: existentielles Element im Christentum)

Kurzinhalt: [...] Heidegger's existentialism (if one may call it that) is parallel to phenomenological analysis. Not only is what Heidegger is doing a phenomenology of the existing man but the man is structured after the fashion of phenomenology itself.

Textausschnitt: 272d Just as the phenomenologist finds structured meanings in what is manifest, so for Heidegger a man is a source of meanings. He uses the term Dasein to eliminate the subject-object opposition. We might say in English that the existing subject is the origin of the meanings that correspond to the understanding of the phenomenologist in the manifest data. And just as the phenomenologist has to refrain from taking on face value the first bright ideas that come along, just as he has to scrutinize and dig and feel around and penetrate and eliminate oversights and oversimplifications, so man in his living first of all lives inauthentically, and if he begins to penetrate things a little better he may move on to authentic living. In other words, Heidegger's existentialism (if one may call it that) is parallel to phenomenological analysis. Not only is what Heidegger is doing a phenomenology of the existing man but the man is structured after the fashion of phenomenology itself. Just as the phenomenology is the meaning in data, so man is the source of meanings in a living. Just as man may be a source of meanings in a superficial manner that results in inauthentic living, so the phenomenologist may be misled by superficial ideas. And just as the phenomenologist may penetrate to the real meaning of the phenomena and read them off rightly, so the man may move from inauthentic to authentic living. In other words, there is a profound influence of phenomenology on Heidegger, not only from the viewpoint of method but also from the viewpoint of content. (Fs) (notabene)

273a Now Heidegger's existentialism was followed more or less immediately by Ludwig Binswanger's new interpretation of the dream. Freudian interpretation of the dream had been a matter of taking the dream symbols and moving up immediately to a conceptual level of interpretation; Freudian interpretation of what the dream really means is up on the conceptual level. But Binswanger considers the dreamer as the existential subject, and he interprets the dream on the level of the dream. At least that is his ideal. He has written a very short essay entitled Traum und Existenz' ('Dream and Existence'). It has been translated into French,2 and the value of that French translation is that there is also an introduction by Michel Foucault of about 125 pages pulling out all the implications and background and significance of this thirty-page essay that had been written about twenty years previously. Binswanger distinguishes between dreams of the night and dreams of the morning. It is a fairly old distinction. Dreams of the night are mainly under somatic influences. Dreams of the morning are the existential subject beginning to create his world.3 (Fs)

274a Then there is Heidegger's influence on Bultmann. 'The objective' for Bultmann is either science or myth. Christianity is not science, and therefore what is objective in Christianity has to be just myth. What the interpreter of the New Testament has to do is find the existential elements in Christianity. These existential elements are faith, and faith is Christian understanding of Being; the rest is myth. (Fs) (notabene)

274b As you know, of course, this has led to a terrific amount of discussion. There has been published by H.W. Bartsch a series of five volumes under the title of Kerygma und Mythos, Kerygma and Myth, from 1948 to 1955. There is also a supplemental volume to numbers 1 and 2, in which are collected together discussions of Bultman's interpretation of the New Testament.1 From a Catholic viewpoint, Rene Marlé of Louvain, a Jesuit, has written a book on Bultman and the interpretation of the New Testament. It was published in Paris by Aubier in 1956, in the collection of our Jesuit Fathers of Lyons, Théologie, volume 33.2 Marlé provides us with a very thorough exposition of Bultmann. (Fs)

274c So much, then, for the significance of phenomenology: it is a new approach in psychology that has yielded very rich results; there is the profound influence of Husserl's philosophy on Heidegger, and through Heidegger on others, including Sartre; there is the work of Merleau-Ponty; the influence goes into depth psychology and into scriptural interpretation. It ranges pretty well over the map. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Titel: Verbum: Word and Idea in Aquinas

Stichwort: Potentia activa (Unterschied zur Def. von Natur), passiva

Kurzinhalt: ... in the writings of Aquinas there are two distinct definitions of potentia activa. There is an Aristotelian definition, ... an Avicennist definition, ... it will be convenient to translate potentia activa, used in an Aristotelian sense, by ...

Textausschnitt: 4. Potentia Activa

190 The ambiguity we have just noted in connection with operatio and actio becomes clear and systematic when we turn to the parallel ambiguity of the term 'potentia activa.' Fr Stufler has remarked that, while early works make the forma gravitatis an active principle, later works make the same form with the same functions in the context of the same theory a passive principle.1 The shift observed by Fr Stufler is but a particular case in a far more fundamental ambiguity. For in the writings of Aquinas there are two distinct definitions of potentia activa. There is an Aristotelian definition, 'principium transmutationis in aliud inquantum aliud,' which attains a certain dominance in later works. There is what may be called, though with diffidence, an Avicennist definition, 'principium operationis' or 'principium actionis,' which is dominant in earlier works and far from disappears in later ones. Since these definitions are not equivalent, it will be convenient to translate potentia activa, used in an Aristotelian sense, by 'efficient potency,' with the corresponding potentia passiva translated by 'receptive potency'; further, it will be convenient to translate potentia activa, used in the Avicennist sense, by 'active potency,' with the corresponding potentia passiva translated by 'passive potency.' Finally, there is to be noted a 'principium effectus,' which is concomitant with Avicennist active potency, is distinguished from it, and amounts to a generalization of Aristotelian efficient potency. These distinctions have now to be verified. (121; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Exkurs: Unterschied zw.: Hervorgang (processio) des Wortes - der Liebe -> vom Standpunkt des "Empfängers" aus

Kurzinhalt: For this reason, we cannot accept without some distinction the thesis and argumentation of J. Brinktrine that 'within God there is only a virtual, not a real, distinction between generation and spiration.

Textausschnitt: Excursus

237e The processions are conceptually distinct from, but really identical with, the relations. (Fs)

The processions and relations are conceptually distinct, for to conceive the origin of one from another is not the same as to conceive the order of one to another; a father, for example, does not originate from his son, but he does have an order to his son. (Fs)
The processions and relations are really identical, for when there is a procession without any motion, the procession itself is nothing in reality except a relation; this is manifest also in creation, in which there is no motion; see Summa theologian, 1, q. 45, a. 2, ad 2m, and a. 3. (Fs)

239a Nonetheless, since two relations follow upon each procession, one may further ask with which relation the procession is really identical. The answer demands a distinction. If a procession is conceived as an origination, it clearly follows that the origination, and therefore the procession, is really in that which is originated; and in this case the procession is really identical with filiation and with passive spiration. But if a procession is conceived as an action, we must make a further distinction: if the action is conceived as being in or from the agent, the procession is really identical with the real relation of the agent; but if the action is conceived as being in the recipient, the procession is really identical with that which is originated, that is, with filiation and passive spiration. (Fs)

239b The importance of this question can be seen if one asks whether in God the procession of word and the procession of love are really distinct. For if the procession is understood as an origin or an action in the recipient, the answer must be yes, since filiation and passive spiration are really distinct. But if the procession is understood as an action in or from the agent, the answer must be no, since, as we will show later, paternity and active spiration are not really distinct. For this reason, we cannot accept without some distinction the thesis and argumentation of J. Brinktrine that 'within God there is only a virtual, not a real, distinction between generation and spiration.'3 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion des Seins; eine all-durchdringende Notion

Kurzinhalt: Die Erfahrung ist dazu da, die Untersuchung des Seins zu ermöglichen. Die Intelligenz ist dazu da, das Denken des Seins zu ermöglichen. Durch das Urteil wird aber das Sein erkannt, ...

Textausschnitt: 4. Eine all-durchdringende Notion

414a Deshalb durchdringt die Notion des Seins alles. Sie untermauert alle Erkenntnisgehalte. Sie geht in sie alle ein. Sie konstituiert sie als erkenntnismäßige. (Fs)

414b Sie untermauert alle Erkenntnisinhalte. Ohne das reine Erkenntnisstreben würde das sinnliche Leben in seiner Routine von Wahrnehmung und Trieb, Instinkt und Gewohnheit, Emotion und Aktion befangen bleiben. Was diesen Zirkel bricht und die intellektuelle Aktivität freisetzt, ist das Sich-Wundern, von dem Aristoteles sagte, es sei der Beginn aller Wissenschaft und Philosophie. Dieses Sich-Wundern ist intelligentes Suchen. Es wählt Daten für die Einsicht aus und unterstützt durch dieses Auswählen sogar die empirische Komponente in unserem Erkennen. Noch offensichtlicher sind alle Ideen und Begriffe Antworten auf das Streben nach Verstehen, und alle Urteile sind Antworten auf die Forderung nach dem Unbedingten. (Fs)

414c Zweitens, die Notion des Seins durchdringt alle Erkenntnisinhalte. Sie ist die höchste heuristische Notion. Vor jedem Inhalt ist sie die Notion des durch diesen Inhalt zu Erkennenden. Wie jeder Inhalt zustandekommt, geht das "Durch-diesen-Inhalt-zu-Erkennende" restlos über in das "Durch-diesen-Inhalt-Erkannte". Eine Leerstelle in der allgemeinen Vorwegnahme wird somit gefüllt, nicht nur, um dieses Element der Vorwegnahme zu beenden, sordern auch, um den Füller zu einem Teil des Vorweggenommenen zu machen. Vor allen Antworten ist also die Notion des Seins die Notion der Gesamtheit, die durch alle Antworten zu erkennen ist. Wenn aber einmal alle Antworten erreicht sind, wird die Notion des Seins zur Notion der durch alle Antworten erkannten Gesamtheit. (Fs)

414d [357] Drittens, die Notion des Seins konstituiert alle Inhalte als erkenntnismäßige. Erfahrung ist nur die erste Ebene der Erkenntnis; sie stellt die zu erkennende Materie vor. Verstehen ist nur die zweite Ebene der Erkenntnis; sie definiert das, was zu erkennen ist. Das Erkennen erfährt einen vollständigen Zuwachs nur durch das Urteil, nur wenn das bloß Erfahrene gedacht und das bloß Gedachte bejaht worden ist. Der Erkenntniszuwachs wird aber immer auf dieselbe Weise vervollständigt. Die Erfahrung ist ein kaleidoskopischer Fluß. Die Gedankenobjekte sind so verschieden wie der Erfindungsgeist der menschlichen Intelligenz. Aber der Beitrag des Urteils zu unserem Erkennen ist immer ein bloßes "Ja" oder "Nein", ein bloßes "Es ist" oder "Es ist nicht". Die Erfahrung ist dazu da, die Untersuchung des Seins zu ermöglichen. Die Intelligenz ist dazu da, das Denken des Seins zu ermöglichen. Durch das Urteil wird aber das Sein erkannt, und im Urteil wird das, was erkannt wird, als Sein erkannt. Daher ist das Erkennen Erkennen von Sein, aber das Erkannte ist nie bloßes Sein, so wie das Urteil nie ein bloßes "Ja" ist, getrennt von der Frage, auf die das "Ja" antwortet. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Bedeutung: Quellen, Akte, Termine, Kern; Intention der Bedeutung: Sein; Urteil: wahr - falsch; Empirismus, Gesten

Kurzinhalt: Der allumfassende Terminus der Bedeutung ist nun das Sein; denn außer dem Sein gibt es nichts. Umgekehrt ist der Kern aller Bedeutung die Intention von Sein.

Textausschnitt: 5. Der Kern der Bedeutung

415a So wie die Notion des Seins alle Inhalte untermauert, sie durchdringt und sie als erkenntnismäßige konstituiert, so ist sie auch der Kern der Bedeutung. (Fs)

415b Für unsere gegenwärtigen Zwecke wird es genügen, zu unterscheiden zwischen
(1) den Quellen der Bedeutung,
(2) den Akten des Bedeutens,
(3) den Termini der Bedeutung und [eg: terms of meaning]
(4) dem Kern der Bedeutung. (Fs)
Jedes Element der Erkenntnis kann als Quelle der Bedeutung dienen. Die Quellen der Bedeutung schließen deshalb Daten und Bilder, Ideen und Begriffe, Erfassen des Unbedingten und Urteil und zudem auch das unvoreingenommene und uneingeschränkte Streben nach Erkenntnis ein. (Fs)

415c Akte des Bedeutens gibt es in drei Arten. Sie sind
(1) formal,
(2) voll,
(3) instrumentell. (Fs)

415d Der formale Akt des Bedeutens ist ein Akt der Begriffsbildung, des Denkens, Überlegens, Definierens, Annehmens, Formulierens. Der volle Akt des Bedeutens ist ein Akt des Urteilens. Der instrumenteile Akt des Bedeutens ist die Ausführung eines formalen oder vollen Aktes durch die Verwendung von Wörtern oder Symbolen in einer gesprochenen, geschriebenen, oder auch bloß gedachten Äußerung. (Fs)

415e Termini der Bedeutung sind das, was gemeint wird. Sie sind formal oder voll. Formale Termini der Bedeutung sind das, was begriffen, gedacht, betrachtet, [358] definiert, angenommen oder formuliert wird. Volle Termini der Bedeutung sind das, was bejaht oder verneint wird. (Fs)

425f Der allumfassende Terminus der Bedeutung ist nun das Sein; denn außer dem Sein gibt es nichts. Umgekehrt ist der Kern aller Bedeutung die Intention von Sein. (Fs) (notabene)

415g Jedes gegebene Urteil gehört somit zu einem Kontext von Urteilen und die Bedeutung des gegebenen Urteiles wird aus diesem Kontext heraus bestimmt. Warum aber ist die Bedeutung des gegebenen Urteils eine Funktion eines Kontexts anderer Urteile? Weil jedes Urteil nur eben ein Zuwachs in einem Ganzen ist, das Erkenntnis genannt wird; weil die Bedeutung des Urteils bloß ein Element ist in der Bestimmung der universalen Intention von Sein. (Fs)

416a Ferner, Urteile können wahr oder falsch sein. Das wahre Urteil bejaht, was ist, und verneint, was nicht ist. Im wahren Urteil gibt es Harmonie zwischen dem, was intendiert wird, und dem, was gemeint ist. Im falschen Urteil aber gibt es einen Konflikt zwischen Intention und Bedeutung. Das falsche Urteil intendiert als Urteil das Sein; es intendiert, das zu bejahen, was ist, und das zu verneinen, was nicht ist. Aber das falsche Urteil als falsches versagt in der Ausführung seiner Intention als Urteil. Es bejaht, was nicht ist, und verneint, was ist. Es bedeutet nicht das, was ist, sondern nur das, was wäre, wenn das Urteil nicht falsch, sondern wahr wäre; in seiner negativen Form wiederum bedeutet es, nicht, was nicht ist, sondern was nicht wäre, wäre es nicht falsch, sondern wahr. (Fs) (notabene)
416b Vielleicht hat dieser Konflikt manche Denker zu dem Schluß geführt, daß ein falsches Urteil bedeutungslos sei. Ein solcher Schluß scheint aber erstaunlich falsch. Wäre das falsche Urteil bedeutungslos, dann gäbe es nichts, was falsch wäre. Das falsche Urteil ist falsch, gerade weil es einen Stand der Dinge meint, der das Gegenteil des Standes ist, den man zu bejahen intendiert, des Standes nämlich, der wahr ist. (Fs)

416c Auf der Ebene der Begriffsbildung gibt es einen ähnlichen, wenn auch weniger offensichtlichen, Kontrast zwischen der Bedeutung und ihrem Kern, der die Intention des Seins ist. Pferde und Einhörner, Elektronen und Phlogiston können als formale Termini der Bedeutung gleich gültig sein. Man kann sie annehmen, oder über sie Überlegungen anstellen, oder sie definieren, und das ist alles, was für den formalen Terminus der Bedeutung verlangt wird. Nun scheint es aber, daß Pferde und Elektronen als formale Termini der Bedeutung den Einhörnern und dem Phlogiston vorzuziehen sind. An sich kann man die letzteren denken; aber dieses Denken scheint irgendwie müßig, überflüssig und vergeblich. Der Grund dafür ist, daß das Denken ein Moment im reinen Streben nach Erkennen ist; wenn auch das Gedachte als Gedachtes bloß ein formaler Terminus der Bedeutung ist, wenn auch das [359] Einhorn als formaler Terminus gerade so gültig ist, wie das Pferd; dennoch denken wir nicht bloß. Unser Denken ist zweckgerichtet. Es ist ein versuchsweises Bestimmen der allumfassenden Notion des Seins. Es denkt nicht nur das Gedankenobjekt, sondern nimmt auch das Objekt des Urteils vorweg. Es meint nicht allein den formalen Terminus der Bedeutung, sondern blickt voraus auf den vollen Terminus. Weil das Einhorn und das Phtogiston als erfolglose Bestimmungsversuche des Seins erkannt werden, sind sie formale Termini, an denen der Kern der Bedeutung, die Intention des Seins, nicht mehr interessiert ist. (Fs)

417a In Anbetracht der Vorherrschaft empiristischer Theorien der Bedeutung sollen einige Worte zu den instrumentellen Akten hinzugefügt werden. Gewöhnliche instrumentelle Akte, wie etwa gesprochene oder geschriebene Wörter oder Symbole, sind nicht von besonderem Interesse. Der Empirist aber legt Nachdruck auf ostensive Akte, wie Demonstrativpronomen und -aujektive, und selbstverständlich Gesten. Der Grund für diese Betonung ist leicht einzusehen, wenn wir unterscheiden zwischen der Funktion der Gesten in jeder beliebigen Theorie der Bedeutung und der Funktion, welche Gesten kraft der empiristischen Behauptungen erlangen. In jeder beliebigen Theorie der Bedeutung ist der ostensive Akt ein instrumenteller Akt der Bedeutung; er setzt formale oder volle Akte der Bedeutung voraus, insofern man weiß, was man meint; und er bezieht sich auf formale oder volle Termini der Bedeutung, insofern alle Bedeutung auf das Bedeutete verweist. Ferner, in einer beliebigen Theorie der Bedeutung ist der ostensive Akt operativ, insofern es ihm gelingt, die Aufmerksamkeit eines anderen auf eine sinnesmäßige Quelle der Bedeutung zu ziehen, so daß dieser durch Bezugnahme auf diese Quelle, durch Verstehen und Reflektieren den passenden formalen oder vollen Terminus der Bedeutung erreichen kann, der gemeint ist. Gemäß der empiristischen Notion aber hat der ostensive Akt eine dritte Funktion; der Empirist nämlich identifiziert das gültige Feld der vollen Termini der Bedeutung (d.h. das Universum des Seins) mit dem Bereich der sinnesmäßigen Vorstellungen; für den Empiristen verweist der ostensive Akt deshalb nicht nur auf eine Quelle der Bedeutung, sondern auch auf einen vollen Terminus der Bedeutung. Ob diese empiristische Modifikation der allgemeinen Theorie korrekt ist, hängt von der Frage ab, ob die Sätze, welche den Empirismus formulieren, für wahr oder falsch erklärt werden müssen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein - Bestimmungen: Wesen? Ar, Gattung, Differenz? Definition? analog, univok?

Kurzinhalt: Insofern die Notion von Sein allen anderen Erkentnnisinhalten vorausgeht, ist sie wie eine Gattung, die auf eine Teilung durch Hinzufügung von Differenzen wartet. Insofern aber die Notion des Seins alle anderen Inhalte vorwegnimmt, durchdringt ...

Textausschnitt: 417b Bevor wir uns nun anderen Erklärungen der Notion des Seins zuwenden, ist es angebracht, eine Reihe von Rätseln zu behandeln, die eine gemeinsame Quelle zu haben scheinen. Wie andere Begriffe auch, wird die Notion des Seins vertreten durch instrumentelle Akte, die in diesem Fall durch das Substantiv Sein und das Verb sein sind. In falscher Analogie wird nun abgeleitet, daß die Notion des Seins den Begriffen in ihren anderen Aspekten ähnlich sei. Tatsächlich ist aber die [360] Notion des Seins einzigartig; denn sie ist der Kern aller Akte der Bedeutung; und sie untermauert, durchdringt und übersteigt alle anderen Erkenntnisinhalte. Es ist deshalb müßig, die Notion des Seins charakterisieren zu wollen, indem man sich auf die gewöhnlichen Regeln oder Gesetze der Begriffe beruft. Was erfaßt werden muß, ist ihre Abweichung von solchen Regeln und Gesetzen, und um uns nun den Details zuzuwenden, werden wir eine Reihe von Fragen einer kurzen Betrachtung unterziehen. (Fs)

418a Erstens, resultiert die Notion des Seins aus dem Ausdruck oder der Formulierung eines Verstehensaktes?

Andere Begriffe resultieren aus einer Einsicht entweder in die Verwendung ihrer Namen, oder in die Dinge-für-uns, oder in die Dinge-selbst. Die Notion des Seins durchdringt alle anderen Inhalte und ist deshalb in der Formulierung jedes Begriffes präsent. Sie kann nicht aus einer Einsicht in das Sein resultieren; denn eine solche Einsicht wäre ein Verstehen von Allem über Alles, und wir haben kein solches Verstehen erreicht. Sie ist, wie wir sagten, die Ausrichtung des intelligenten und rationalen Bewußtseins auf ein uneingeschränktes Zielobjekt hin. (Fs)

418b Zweitens, hat die Notion des Seins eine Essenz, oder ist sie eine Essenz?

Weil andere Begriffe aus Verstehensakten resultieren und weil Verstehensakte im Erfassen dessen bestehen, was unter einem bestimmten Gesichtspunkt essentiell ist, sind andere Begriffe Essenzen. Ferner, weil andere Begriffe vor der Frage nach Reflexion vollständig sind, die fragt, ob es eine solche Essenz gibt, sind andere Begriffe bloß Essenzen und sehen von der Existenz oder Aktualität ab. Die Notion des Seins aber resultiert nicht aus einem Verstehen von Sein; sie beruht nicht auf dem Erfassen dessen, was unter einem bestimmten Gesichtspunkt essentiell ist; und so ist die Notion des Seins nicht die Notion einer Essenz. Außerdem, die Notion des Seins bleibt auf der Ebene der Intelligenz unvollständig; sie geht über den Begriff hinaus zu den Fragen nach Reflexion; sie geht über Einzelurteile hinaus zur Gesamtheit der korrekten Urteile; und deshalb sieht sie nicht von der Existenz und der Aktualität ab. (Fs) (notabene)

418c Drittens, kann die Notion des Seins definiert werden?

Sie kann nicht auf eine der gewöhnlichen Weisen definiert werden, weil sie den Inhalt jeder Definition untermauert und durchdringt und über ihn hinausgeht. Trotzdem besitzt sie einige bestimmte charakteristische Eigenschaften. Sie bezieht sich nämlich auf das uneingeschränkte Zielobjekt unseres Erkennens, das konkrete Universum, die Gesamtheit all dessen, was ist. Sie ist zudem bestimmt, insofern die Struktur unseres Erkennens bestimmt ist, und sie kann deshalb auf einer zweite Stufe definiert werden, indem man sagt, daß sie sich auf alles bezieht, was durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen erkannt werden kann. Andererseits [361] legt diese Definition nicht fest, welche Fragen für unser Erkennen passend sind, oder welche Antworten korrekt sind. Sie läßt es dem Materialisten offen zu behaupten, daß Sein Materiell-Sein bedeutet. Ebenso erlaubt sie es dem Empiristen zu behaupten, daß Sein Erfahren-Sein bedeutet, und dem Idealisten darauf zu bestehen, daß Sein Gedacht-Sein bedeutet, und dem Phänomenalisten zu erklären, daß Sein Erscheinen bedeutet, und so weiter. (Fs) (notabene)

419a Viertens, wie kann eine Notion derart verschiedene Bedeutungen haben?

Weil sie nur auf einer zweiten Stufe bestimmt ist. Die Notion des Seins ist die Notion dessen, was durch korrekte Urteile bestimmt wird. Wenn die strategischen korrekten Urteile besagen, daß es Materie gibt, und daß es nichts gibt außer Materie, dann hat der Materialist recht. Wenn die strategischen korrekten Urteile sind, daß es Erscheinung und nichts als Erscheinung gibt, dann hat der Phänomenalist recht. Ähnlich, wenn die Aussagen, die andere Ansichten ausdrücken, korrekt sind, dann ist das Sein so, wie es diese Ansichten haben wollen. Die Notion des Seins bestimmt nicht, welche Position korrekt ist; sie bestimmt lediglich, daß das intelligent Erfaßte und vernünftig Bejahte Sein ist. (Fs)

419b Fünftens, hat die Notion von Sein irgendwelche Voraussetzungen oder Eigenschaften?

Andere Begriffe sind bestimmte Essenzen, und sie haben als solche Voraussetzungen und Implikationen. Wenn X kein Lebewesen ist, dann ist X kein Mensch. Wenn X ein Mensch ist, dann ist X sterblich. Aber die Notion des Seins ist nicht die Notion irgendeiner Essenz. Sie wird bestimmt, nur indem korrekte Urteile gefällt werden, und sie erreicht ihre volle Bestimmung nur, wenn die Gesamtheit der korrekten Urteile vollzogen wird. Das Fällen der Urteile ist allerdings ein bestimmter Prozeß, und man braucht nicht alle Urteile zu fällen, um die Natur dieses Prozesses zu erfassen. Diese Tatsache macht den Erkenntnisprozeß zu einer Basis für Operationen zur Bestimmung der allgemeinen Struktur des konkreten Universums. (Fs)

419c Sechstens, ist die Notion von Sein univok oder analog?

Von Begriffen wird gesagt, sie seien univok, wenn sie in all ihren Anwendungen dieselbe Bedeutung haben, und sie werden analog genannt, wenn ihre Bedeutung systematisch variiert, indem man sich von einem Bereich der Anwendung zu einem anderen begibt. Die Notion des Seins kann als univok bezeichnet werden, insofern sie alle anderen Inhalte untermauert; denn in dieser Hinsicht ist sie das eine Streben nach Erkenntnis und es bezieht sich auf ein uneingeschränktes Zielobjekt, welches das konkrete Universum ist. Die Notion des Seins kann aber auch als analog bezeichnet werden, insofern sie alle anderen Inhalte durchdringt; so kann gesagt werden, daß esse viventium est vivere - das Sein der lebenden Dinge ist Lebendig-Sein. Schließlich kann auch gesagt werden, die Notion von Sein sei weder univok noch analog, weil diese Unterscheidung sich auf Begriffe bezieht, während die Notion des Seins die anderen Inhalte sowohl untermauert wie auch über sie [362] hinausgeht. Es soll allerdings bemerkt werden, daß das, was oft unter der Analogie des Seins verstanden wird, genau das ist, was wir meinen, wenn wir sagen, die Notion des Seins untermauere, durchdringe und gehe über andere Inhalte hinaus. (Fs)

420a Siebtens, ist die Notion des Seins abstrakt?

Soll eine Notion abstrakt sein, dann muß sie einen bestimmten Inhalt besitzen und von anderen Inhalten abstrahieren. Die Notion des Seins abstrahiert von überhaupt nichts. Sie ist allumfassend. Ihr Inhalt wird bestimmt durch die Gesamtheit der korrekten Urteile. (Fs)
420b Es gibt nun aber eine noch größere Gesamtheit möglicher Urteile; innerhalb dieser Gesamtheit gibt es strategische Sätze von Urteilen, die dazu dienen, den allgemeinen Charakter des konkreten Universums in Übereinstimmung mit den variierenden Gesichtspunkten der verschiedenen Philosophien zu definieren. Solche strategische Sätze sind schon erläutert worden, z. B., es gibt Materie und nichts als Materie, oder es gibt die Erscheinung und nichts als die Erscheinung, oder es gibt das Denken und nichts als das Denken, oder die Struktur unserer Erkenntnis ist bestimmt, und somit ist die Struktur des unserer Erkenntnis proportionierten Seins bestimmt. (Fs)

420c Kraft solcher strategischer Sätze von Urteilen ist es nun möglich, zwischen dem allgemeinen Charakter des konkreten Universums einerseits und dem konkreten Universum in all seinen Einzelheiten andererseits zu unterscheiden. Eine Bestimmung des allgemeinen Charakters des konkreten Universums ist offenkundig eine abstrakte Sicht vom Sein; denn sie betrachtet nicht das Ganze des Seins als ein Ganzes, sondern das Ganze des Seins als festgelegt durch einen strategischen Teil oder Aspekt. (Fs)

420d Auf diese Weise gelangt man zu einer allgemeinen Bedeutung für die Redewendung "Sein als Sein". Um aber zu bestimmen, was Sein als Sein in einer bestimmten Philosophie ist, muß man die strategischen Urteile dieser Philosophie überprüfen; und um zu auszumachen, welches die korrekte Bedeutung von Sein als Sein ist, muß man die strategischen Urteile der korrekten Philosophie überprüfen. (Fs)

420f Achtens, ist die Notion von Sein eine Gattung oder eine Art oder eine Differenz?

Insofern die Notion von Sein allen anderen Erkentnnisinhalten vorausgeht, ist sie wie eine Gattung, die auf eine Teilung durch Hinzufügung von Differenzen wartet. Insofern aber die Notion des Seins alle anderen Inhalte vorwegnimmt, durchdringt und einschließt, unterscheidet sie sich von der Gattung, die ein bestimmter Inhalt ist, der vom Inhalt ihrer Differenzen völlig verschieden ist. Das Sein kann so etwa in rote, grüne und blaue Seiende eingeteilt werden; und die Farbe kann in rote, grüne und blaue Farben eingeteilt werden. Aber der Begriff von Rot hat einen Inhalt oder ein Inhaltselement, die im Begriff der Farbe nicht vorkommen, und so differenziert er die Gattung, indem er ihr etwas von außen her hinzufügt. Andererseits hat der Begriff von Rot keinen Inhalt und kein Inhaltselement, die in der Notion des Seins nicht vorkämen; er kann das Sein nicht differenzieren, indem er ihm etwas von außen her hinzufügt; denn ohne Sein, außer dem [363] Sein, gibt es einfach nichts. Schließlich untermauert und durchdringt die Notion des Seins nicht nur alle anderen Inhalte, sondern sie vervollständigt sie auch, insofern das "Ja" des Urteils sie als eigentlich erkenntnismäßig konstituiert und sie so mit einer wirklichen objektiven Referenz versieht. (Fs)

421a Neuntens, wenn man denkt, aber noch nicht urteilt, denkt man entweder an das Sein oder an das Nichts. Denkt man an das Sein, so braucht man nicht zu urteilen, um das Sein zu erkennen. Denkt man an das Nichts, so muß alles Denken identisch sein, weil es immer mit demselben Nichts zu tun hat. (Fs)
Wenn man denkt, betrachtet, annimmt, oder definiert, so tut man das im Hinblick auf das Sein. Wir akzeptieren deshalb die erste Alternative: Das, worüber man denkt, ist Sein. Das Sein zu denken, ist nun eine Sache, das Sein zu erkennen, eine andere. Das Sein zu denken bedeutet, auf der zweiten Ebene des Erkenntnisprozesses zu handeln; es bedeutet, auf dem Weg zu einem vollständigen Erkenntniszuwachs zu sein; aber es bedeutet nicht, irgendetwas erreicht zu haben, was mehr wäre als ein Teilzuwachs, der nur durch ein Urteil vervollständigt werden kann. (Fs)

421b Zehntens, die Notion von Sein ist die Notion des konkreten Universums. Universelle Aussagen sind nun aber abstrakt, und trotzdem können sie in Urteilen bejaht werden. Das Urteil ist also entweder nicht über das Sein, oder aber das Sein ist nicht konkret. (Fs)
Die Notion von Sein ist die Notion des Konkreten in derselben Weise, wie sie die Notion des Universums ist. Sie ist Notion des Universums, weil die Fragen nur dann zu einem Ende gelangen, wenn es nichts mehr zu fragen gibt. Sie ist Notion des Konkreten, weil stets weitere Fragen übrig bleiben, bis das Konkrete erreicht ist. Deshalb kommt nicht das Einzelurteil, sondern die Gesamtheit der korrekten Urteile dem konkreten Universum gleich, welches das Sein ist. (Fs)

421c Das Problem der allgemeinen Aussage kann angegangen werden, indem man zwischen den formalen und den materiellen Aspekten der analytischen Aussage unterscheidet. Formal ist eine analytische Aussage
(1) ein Bedingtes, das
(2) mit seinen Bedingungen durch die Gesetze verbunden ist, welche die Vereinigung der partiellen instrumentellen Bedeutungen von Wörtern in die komplette instrumentelle Bedeutung des Satzes leiten, und zwar so, daß
(3) seine Bedingungen erfüllt werden durch die Bedeutungen oder Definitionen der verwendeten Wörter.

422a Materiell unterscheiden sich die analytischen Aussagen, insofern für die verwendeten Termini und Relationen [364]
(1) erkannt werden kann, daß sie in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen,
(2) nicht erkannt werden kann, daß sie in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen, oder
(3) erkannt werden kann, daß sie nicht in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen. (Fs)

422b Formal bezieht sich jede analytische Aussage auf das konkrete Universum, insofern syntaktische Gesetze tatsächliche Aspekte der Vereinigung partieller Bedeutungen in komplette instrumentelle Bedeutungen sind. Materiell beziehen sich einige analytische Aussagen auf das konkrete Universum entweder tatsächlich, wie im ersten Falle, oder versuchsweise, wie im zweiten. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein - Theorien: Parmenides; Sein als Essenz

Kurzinhalt: Weil das Sein ist, kann es nicht Nicht-Sein und auch nicht Werden oder Aufhören-zu-sein sein. Umgekehrt ist weder Nicht-Sein noch Werden noch Aufhören-zu-sein das Sein;

Textausschnitt: 422c Es wurde unterschieden zwischen der spontan operativen Notion des Seins, die allen Menschen gemeinsam ist, und den theoretischen Darstellungen dieser Notion, welche von einer Philosophie zur anderen differieren. Wir haben unsere eigene theoretische Darstellung gegeben. Wir wollen sie nun weiter klären, indem wir sie mit einigen Sichtweisen kontrastieren, die von anderen vorgeschlagen wurden. (Fs)

422d Für Parmenides war das Sein eines, ohne Ursprung oder Ende, homogen und unteilbar, unbeweglich und unwandelbar, voll und sphärisch.1
Den Ursprung dieser Position wird man sich wie folgt vorstellen müssen. Parmenides eliminierte die Alternative der glatten Verneinung, und deshalb blieb ihm nur die Alternative der Bejahung übrig. Die Bejahung kann vernünftig begründet sein, und dann ist sie der Weg der Wahrheit, oder sie kann der Vernunftgründe entbehren, und dann ist sie der Weg des Scheinens. Parmenides gelangte zu seiner Notion von Sein, indem er dem Weg der Wahrheit folgte. (Fs)

423a Was impliziert nun die Wahl der vernünftigen Bejahung, daß das Sein ist? Wenn man irgendeine Bejahung akzeptiert, dann hat man auch die korrekte Behauptung der Bedeutung, der Annahmen und Konsequenzen dieser Bejahung zu akzeptieren. Jedes Urteil benötigt einen Kontext, und ohne das Bejahen dieses Kontextes verliert das anfängliche Urteil seine Bedeutung. Vernünftiges Bejahen muß deshalb das Bejahen eines Satzes von Urteilen sein, die ein einziges Ganzes bilden, und das Bejahte ist damit ein entsprechendes einziges Ganzes. (Fs)

423b Was ist dieses einzige Ganze, von dem behauptet wird, es sei? Die geeignete Antwort besteht darin, Untersuchen und Reflektieren im Hinblick auf das Ganze der Erfahrung in Gang zu setzen. Das zu erkennende Ganze entspricht der Gesamtheit korrekter Urteile. Parmenides aber wählte eine Abkürzung. Er beachtete die Tatsache nicht, daß Sein nicht mehr als eine Definition zweiter Ordnung zuläßt. Er behandelte die Notion von Sein, als wäre sie ein Begriff wie "Mensch" oder [365] "Kreis". Er nahm an, sie sei eine bestimmte Essenz mit bestimmten Annahmen und bestimmten Konsequenzen. Weil das Sein ist, kann es nicht Nicht-Sein und auch nicht Werden oder Aufhören-zu-sein sein. Umgekehrt ist weder Nicht-Sein noch Werden noch Aufhören-zu-sein das Sein; und deshalb müssen alle drei Nichts sein. Ferner, das Sein kann nicht differenziert werden; was sich vom Sein unterscheidet, ist nicht Sein; und was nicht Sein ist, ist nichts. Ferner, weil es im Sein keine Unterschiede gibt, kann es keine Bewegung oder Veränderung in ihm geben. Schließlich, die Leere, das Vakuum ist nichts; Sein ist nicht nichts, und so kann es nicht Leere sein; deshalb ist es voll, usw. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein - Theorien: Plato; das Unbedingte als Form -> Vermischung der Formen im rationalen Diskurs

Kurzinhalt: Die Unzulänglichkeit dieser Position liegt darin, daß sie nicht zwischen der Ebene der Intelligenz und der Ebene der Reflexion unterscheidet. Ohne diese Unterscheidung wird das Unbedingte erschlichenerweise den reinen Gedankenobjekten zugesprochen ...

Textausschnitt: 423c Platos Formen waren Projektionen in den noetischen Himmel dessen, was die gewöhnliche, sinnliche Erfahrung transzendiert. Die Formen sind dann also die idealen Zielobjekte

(1) der ästhetischen Erfahrung,
(2) der Einsichten des Mathematikers und Physikers,
(3) des Unbedingten des reflektierenden Verstehens,
(4) des moralischen Gewissens und
(5) des intelligent und vernünftig zweckgerichteten Lebens. (Fs)

Das ist eine verworrene Ansammlung, und es scheint, daß der Parmenides-Dialog den Wendepunkt markiert, an dem die Notwendigkeit von Unterscheidungen und einer umfassenderen Theorie offensichtlich wird. (Fs)

423d Im Sophistes wird der Philosoph beschrieben, der sich durch rationalen Diskurs auf die Idee des Seins zubewegt (254 a). Es wird vermerkt, daß die Isolierung jeder Form von allen anderen die Möglichkeit des Diskurses eliminieren würde, die in der Konjunktion unterschiedener Formen oder Kategorien liegt. Es gibt dann also eine Vermischung oder Teilhabe unter den Formen (259 a), und es gibt eine Form des Nicht-Seins, genau so wie es die Form des Großen oder des Schönen gibt (258 c). (Fs)

424a Die Unzulänglichkeit dieser Position liegt darin, daß sie nicht zwischen der Ebene der Intelligenz und der Ebene der Reflexion unterscheidet. Ohne diese Unterscheidung wird das Unbedingte erschlichenerweise den reinen Gedankenobjekten zugesprochen, die dadurch in ewige Formen transformiert werden, und umgekehrt können das "ist" und "ist nicht", durch die das Urteil das Unbedingte setzt, nur Bedeutung haben, wenn sie als Formen aufgefaßt werden. Es resultiert ein Aggregat von Formen, deren jede radikal und ewig von allen andern verschieden ist. Erreicht werden können sie aber nur durch den rationalen Diskurs, und wenn der Diskurs [366] sich auf sie beziehen soll, dann muß es auf ihrer Seite eine Vermischung geben, die dem synthetischen Element im Diskurs entspricht. Was ist dieses Sich-Vermischen verschiedener Formen? Ehe wir eine so schwierige Frage zu beantworten versuchen, ist es wohl besser abzuklären, ob sich diese Frage überhaupt stellt. Wir würden dartun, daß es in der Tat nicht der Fall ist. Ehe das Urteil erreicht wird, ist der Erkenntniszuwachs unvollständig. Ehe das Urteil erreicht wird, ist das synthetische Element bereits vorhanden in der Erkenntnis. Das Urteil fügt der Frage nach Reflexion einzig das "Ja" oder "Nein", das "ist" oder "ist nicht" hinzu. Was bejaht oder verneint wird, kann eine einzelne Aussage sein, oder der Inbegriff der Aussagen, die eine Hypothese ausmachen; denn beide können als bedingt angesehen werden, und beide können als virtuell Unbedingte erfaßt werden. Das Urteil ist also nicht eine Synthese von Termini, sondern die unbedingte Setzung einer solchen Synthese. Dem Urteil entspricht nicht eine Synthese von Formen, sondern das Absolute der Tatsache. Der Platonismus ist glänzend in seiner Hingabe an das reine Erkenntnisstreben. Da er aber die Natur des Urteils nicht erfaßte, führte dies zu seinem Abweichen vom konkreten Universum in den idealen Himmel. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein - Theorien: Aristoteles; Sein als Form

Kurzinhalt: ... und so bezeichnete Aristoteles das ontologische Prinzip Form als den Seinsgrund in den Dingen, und den Erkenntnisakt des Erfassens der Form als die Einsicht, aus der der begriffliche Inhalt, Sein, hervorgeht.

Textausschnitt: 424b Aristoteles hielt an der Platonischen Definition des Urteils als Synthese fest.1 Aber er unterschied scharf zwischen den Fragen nach Einsicht (Was ist es? Warum ist es so?) und den Fragen nach Reflexion (Ist es? Ist es so?)2 mit dem Resultat, daß er den Tatsachen gegenüber einen gesunden und klarsichtigen Respekt zeigte, ohne seine genauen Implikationen zu erreichen. Er wäre mit dem Empiristen nicht einverstanden gewesen, der die Tatsache nicht in das virtuell Unbedingte versetzt, sondern in die sinnliche Erfüllung, durch die das Bedingte als Unbedingtes erfaßt wird. Doch würde man ihn vor eine Frage stellen, die er nicht hinreichend bedacht hatte, fragte man ihn, ob das virtuell Unbedingte eine dritte Komponente in unserer Erkenntnis sei, oder nur ein Signet der Zustimmung, welcher der begrifflichen Vereinung ihrer sinnlichen und intelligiblen Komponenten aufgedrückt wird. (Fs)

425a Diese ungelöste Zweideutigkeit kommt sowohl in seiner Methodologie als auch in seiner Metaphysik zum Ausdruck. Für ihn war die höchste Frage die der Existenz. Doch war dies eine Frage, die schon in der deskriptiven Erkenntnis beantwortet worden war; diese Antwort mußte vorausgesetzt werden bei der Suche nach Erklärung; und die Funktion der Erklärung war einfach die, zu bestimmen, was die Dinge sind, und warum sie die Eigenschaften haben, die sie besitzen. Der wesentlich hypothetische Charakter der Erklärung und daß sie ein weiteres, verifizierendes Urteil braucht, wurden übersehen. Ferner, Aristoteles fragte, was das Sein sei. Diese Frage drückt die Forderung nach Verstehen, nach Erkennen der Ursache aus. [367] Aristoteles antwortete ganz natürlich, daß der Grund von Sein seine immanente Form sei (Met. Z, 17). Sein ist primär, was durch eine substantielle Form konstituiert wird, oder, bei weiterem Nachdenken, durch die Kombination von substantieller Form und Materie. Sekundär ist Sein das, was durch akzidentelle Formen konstituiert wird; "Weiße", "Wärme", "Stärke" sind nicht nichts, auch wenn sie nicht einfach das sind, was unter Sein verstanden wird. Sein ist weiter die Sammlung existierender Substanzen mit ihren Eigenschaften und akzidentiellen Modifikationen; aber wenn Sein auch das tatsächlich Existierende bezeichnet, ist Existieren doch nicht mehr als die Realität der substanziellen Formen zusammen mit ihren hauptsächlich immanenten Voraussetzungen und Konsequenzen3. (Fs) (notabene)

425b Diese Position wird nun evidentermaßen die Frage nach der Einheit der Notion des Seins aufwerfen. Aristoteles brach mit seinen Parmenideischen und Platonischen Vorgängern, indem er das Sein mit dem konkreten Universum identifizierte, so wie es in der Tat zu sein erkannt wird. Aber Aristoteles brach nicht mit ihrer Annahme, daß die Notion des Seins ein begrifflicher Inhalt sei. Er fragte, was das Sein sei. Mit anderen Worten, er setzte voraus, daß das Sein ein begrifflicher Inhalt sei, und er fragte, welcher Verstehensakt vor der Formulierung dieses Inhaltes vorkomme. Wie wir aber gesehen haben, kann das Sein von uns nur indirekt definiert werden, und deshalb war Aristoteles nicht in der Lage, irgendeinen spezifischen Akt des Verstehens anzugeben, der den begrifflichen Inhalt des Seins ergäbe. Der hervorragende Typus aber des Verstehensaktes ist die Einsicht, welche eine intelligible Form erfaßt, die in den sinnlichen Daten aufscheint; und so bezeichnete Aristoteles das ontologische Prinzip Form als den Seinsgrund in den Dingen, und den Erkenntnisakt des Erfassens der Form als die Einsicht, aus der der begriffliche Inhalt, Sein, hervorgeht. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Sein - Theorien: Heinrich von Ghent, Duns Scotus, Cajetan (Sein als Proportion von Essenz zu Existenz);

Kurzinhalt: Auf diese Weise ererbte die mittelalterliche Scholastik ein Problem: Ist die Notion des Seins eine oder viele? ... Duns Scotus behauptete, daß es außer der Einheit des Namens auch eine Einheit des Inhaltes gebe.

Textausschnitt: 426a Auf diese Weise ererbte die mittelalterliche Scholastik ein Problem: Ist die Notion des Seins eine oder viele? Wenn sie eine ist, ist ihre Einheit dann die Einheit eines einzigen Inhaltes, oder ist sie die Einheit einer Funktion von variablen Inhalten?
Heinrich von Ghent scheint die Ansicht vertreten zu haben, daß die Einheit des Seins bloß die Einheit eines Namens sei. Gott ist, und ich bin. In beiden Fällen wird das Sein bejaht. Aber die bejahten Realitäten sind schlechthin disparat. (Fs)

426b Duns Scotus behauptete, daß es außer der Einheit des Namens auch eine Einheit des Inhaltes gebe. Auch wenn kein Teil oder Aspekt von Dir identisch mit einem Teil oder einem Aspekt von mir ist, ist doch keiner von uns nichts. Es gibt also einen gewissen minimalen Begriffsinhalt, der positiv das ausmacht, was negativ [368] durch die Negation von nichts ausgedrückt wird. Was es ist, kann nicht erklärt werden, indem man sich auf andere positive Inhalte bezieht; denn es ist eines der schlechthin letzten Atome des Denkens; es ist einfach einfach. Man kann sich ihm aber annähern, indem man bemerkt, daß Sokrates Mensch voraussetzt, Mensch tierisches Lebewesen voraussetzt, tierisches Lebewesen lebende, materielle Substanz voraussetzt, und Substanz etwas voraussetzt, das noch weniger bestimmt und noch weniger ausschließend ist. Der Begriff des Seins ist der Begriff mit dem geringsten Inhalt und dem größten Umfang. Er ist zudem wesentlich abstrakt. Was er bezeichnet ist nie nur Sein, sondern entweder der unendliche oder irgendein endlicher Modus des Seins, wobei der Modus nicht als ein weiterer und besonderer Inhalt aufzufassen ist, sondern eher als eine innere Variation des unbestimmten Grundinhaltes1. (Fs)

426c Thomas de Vio Caietanus war mit der Scotistischen Sicht nicht zufriedener, als Scotus selbst mit der des Heinrich von Ghent zufrieden gewesen war. Wenn ein einzelner Name ohne eine einzelne Bedeutung nicht genügt, genügt auch eine einzelne Bedeutung nicht, die als einzelne auf die Ordnung des Denkens beschränkt zu sein scheint. Infolgedessen arbeitete Cajetan seine Theorie der Einheit einer Funktion von variablen Inhalten aus. Wie "doppelt" unterschiedslos die Relation von 2 zu 1, 4 zu 2, 6 zu 3 und so weiter bezeichnet, so bezeichnet "Sein" unterschiedslos die Proportion von Essenz zu Existenz, oder, wie wir sagen würden, die Proportion zwischen dem, was durch das Denken formuliert wird, und dem, was ihm durch ein Urteil hinzugefugt wird. Gemäß dieser Position schließt die Notion des Seins immer einen Begriffsinhalt mit ein, aber dieser kann jeglicher Inhalt sein; ferner, das Sein im Akt kann nie ohne irgendein bejahendes Urteil erkannt werden; aber das Bejahen ist nie nur bloßes Bejahen oder das Bejahen eines unbestimmten Inhaltes; es ist immer das Bejahen eines bestimmten Inhaltes, wobei jeglicher bejahbare, bestimmte Inhalt dazu dient. Kurz, Cajetan kann einräumen, daß die atomischen, begrifflichen Inhalte viele und disparat sind; er kann die Scotistische Sicht bestreiten, daß es einen gemeinsamen Faktor, ein positives Gegenstück des "nicht nichts" gibt, das einen absolut allgemeinen Umfang hat; und doch kann er anhand seiner Theorie der Einheit einer Funktion von variablen Inhalten nicht nur über einen einzigen Namen, Sein, und eine einzige Notion des Seins verfügen, sondern auch über eine einzige Notion, die auf alles angewendet werden kann, von dem wir tatsächlich wissen, daß es existiert.1 (Fs)

427a Es soll bemerkt werden, daß, während Scotus für die Parmenideischen und Platonischen Annahmen steht, von denen sich Aristoteles nicht befreite, Cajetan für die Hauptausrichtung des aristotelischen Denkens steht; aber dies gelang ihm nur, indem er über es hinausging. Wenn begriffliche Inhalte Produkte der Verstehensakte [369] sind, die Formen in den sinnlichen Vorstellungen erfassen, so wird man wohl von solchen Inhalten erwarten, daß sie eine disparate Vielfalt sind. Daher beantwortete Aristoteles die Frage "Was ist Sein?" nicht, indem er einen Begriffsinhalt angab, sondern indem er den Grund des Seins im allgemeinen Objekt des Verstehens, der Form, angab. Weil es viele Formen gibt, folgt, daß der Grund des Seins eine Variabel ist; es folgt weiter daß, wenn die Notion des Seins eine sein soll, dann ihre Einheit die Einheit einer Funktion von variablen Inhalten sein muß. Welches sind nun die Variablen innerhalb der einzelnen Funktion? Eine von ihnen ist die Form. Auf den ersten Blick ist die naheliegende Kandidatin für die andere die Materie. Würde sie indes ausgewählt, folgte daraus, daß Aristoteles' immaterielle Substanz nicht zum Universum des Seins gehören würde. Um Aristoteles' Position in ihrer Integrität aufrechtzuerhalten, war es notwendig, das virtuell Unbedingte, das im reflektierenden Verstehen erfaßt und im Urteil bejaht wird, zur zweiten Variabel zu machen. Im allgemeinen Fall ist das die Existenz, die Aktualität, die Tatsache, welche sich mit der reinen Form kombiniert, oder mit der Verbindung von Form und Materie, um ein Seiendes im Akt auszumachen. (Fs) (notabene)

428a Wenn sie auch brillant ist, hat Cajetans Position doch ihre Unzulänglichkeiten. Sie faßt ein Aggregat konkreter Seienden ins Auge, von denen jedes aus Essenz und Existenz besteht. Sie sieht die Einheit der Notion des Seins in der Relation oder Proportion dessen, was begriffen wird, zu dem, was bejaht wird. Aber sie klärt nicht, wie diese Relation als eine einzige Notion in unserer Erkenntnis zustandekommt; und sie liefert keinen Hinweis zur Erklärung des Faktums, daß wir unter "Sein" nicht nur dies und jenes Seiende verstehen, sondern alles, die Gesamtheit, das Universum. Kurz, Cajetan scheint mehr an einer Erklärung der Einheit der Notion des Seins interessiert gewesen zu sein als an der Notion selbst. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; Substanz, Akzidenz

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 5: Can a relation be really identical with a substance?

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 5
Can a relation be really identical with a substance?

267d It may seem that a relation cannot be the same as a substance, for the ten categories of being are really distinct from one another; but relation and substance are different categories, namely, 'something' and 'to something'; therefore, a relation cannot be really identical with a substance. (Fs)

269a Besides, a relation is an accident; but accident and substance are really distinct, and therefore a relation cannot be really identical with a substance. (Fs)
Again, a relation is essence in a qualified sense, whereas substance is simply essence without qualification; but essence in a qualified sense and essence without qualification are not the same, and so a relation cannot be really identical with a substance. (Fs)

Against these arguments, however, is the fact that the real divine relations are distinguished from the divine substance not in reality but only in concept; therefore, at least in God a relation can be really the same as the substance. (Fs)

Moreover, every subsistent is in the category of substance; but the real divine relations are subsistent, and therefore at least in God a relation can be really the same as the substance. (Fs)

269b I respond that two considerations are required to resolve this question: first, the very notions of relation, accident, and substance must be understood exactly; second, the way in which these notions are verified in things must be clearly and distinctly grasped. (Fs)
Regarding the first consideration, note that relation, accident, and substance are generic notions and are derived through different ways of defining. Some things are defined by what they themselves are; others are defined by what they themselves are not, and this is so in two ways, since some are defined in terms of another in which they are, and others are defined in terms of another to which they are. (Fs)

269c For example, a human being is defined by what a human being is: for a human being is defined as a rational animal, where a human being is both animal and rational. But snubness, eclipse, and circle are defined by what they themselves are not. 'Snubness' is defined in terms of 'nose,' 'eclipse' in terms of a heavenly body such as the sun or the moon, and 'circle' in terms of a plane surface. Snubness is not a nose but in a nose, an eclipse is not the sun or the moon but a darkening in the sun or in the moon, and a circle is not a plane surface but in a plane surface. Thus, in these examples the definition is stated in terms of another in which is found what is defined. Finally, all relatives are defined in terms of another; for relatives are those whose existence is to be to another, and so one must take note that relatives are defined not in terms of another in which they are but in terms of another to which they are. (Fs)

269d Now, the essences of things are known through definitions, and so there are as many kinds of essences as there are kinds of definitions. The essences of what are defined by what they themselves are, or through themselves, are essences without qualification. The essences of what are defined through another are essences in a qualified sense, and this in two ways: the essences of what are defined through another in which they are are essences that are in another, and the essences of what are defined in terms of another to which they are are essences that are to another. (Fs)

271a Further, it is proper to each thing to be in accord with its essence. Those whose essences are without qualification are defined through themselves, and so it is proper to them to be through themselves. Those whose essences are qualified in some respect are defined through another, and so it is proper to them to be through another. This is so in two ways: it is proper to those that are defined through another in which they are, to be in another, and it is proper to those that are defined through another to which they are, to be to another. (Fs)

271b From all this, then, it is clear
(1) what substance is,
(2) the various meanings of 'accident,'
(3) in what sense a relation is an accident, and
(4) how generic these definitions are.

First, then, it is clear that a substance is that to which it is proper to be through itself. Second, it is clear that 'accident' is used in two ways: in a broader sense, an accident is whatever has a qualified essence, but in a stricter sense an accident is that to which it is proper to be in another. Third, it is clear that a relation is both an accident in a broader sense, since it is defined through another, and not an accident in the strict sense, since it is not defined through another in which it is, and therefore 'to be in another' is not what is proper to a relation by definition. Fourth, it is clear that these definitions of substance, accident, and relation are not derived proximately from the concrete reality of things, but quite remotely from generic ways of defining, namely, through self, through another, through another in which the defined is, and through another to which the defined is. (Fs) (notabene)

271c Once these notions are understood exactly, we may proceed to the second part of the solution to this question. From notions alone we can conclude to conceptual distinctions, but unless notions are related to things, we shall never arrive at real distinctions. For those things are distinct conceptually when the concept of one is not the concept of the other, and therefore from what we have said it is quite easy to conclude that substance and accident, and also accident in the strict sense and relation, are conceptually distinct. But there is a real distinction when one as real is not the other as real, and so to prove a real distinction we must definitely consider the reality itself to which the notions apply. Although this is universally true, it must especially be observed when the notions are generic and quite remote, since nothing real is merely generic. (Fs)

271d Thus, from the fact that it is proper to a relation to be to another, and to an accident in the strict sense to be in another, it is not legitimate to conclude to anything other than a conceptual distinction between relation and accident in the strict sense. This is clearly demonstrated in the case of material things, in which there are many relations that in fact are in another even though this is not what is proper to relations by definition. (Fs)
273a Again, from the fact that substance is essence without qualification and relation is a qualified essence, it is not legitimate to conclude to anything other than a conceptual distinction between substance and relation. For the generic aspect according to which a given reality is a substance does not at all exclude the possibility of another aspect according to which the same reality may be relative. Thus every finite substance, as substance, is defined through itself and has an essence without qualification, and it is proper for it to be through itself. But every finite substance is also a nature; every finite nature is an intrinsic principle of operation; and every real principle of operation is really related to its really distinct operation. Therefore, once the concrete reality of things is understood, it is clear how the same thing according to one aspect is a substance and according to another aspect is a real relation. (Fs)

273b When all these matters are considered together, it is evident that a relation can be either an accident in the strict sense or a substance. The reason for this is that the opposition between being to another and being in another, or between essence without qualification and qualified essence, is not a contradictory opposition. For what is to another can also be in another; and what according to one aspect of its reality has essence without qualification, according to another aspect of the same reality can have qualified essence. On the other hand, since there is a contradictory opposition between being through itself and being in another - for 'through itself is the same as 'not in another' - it is impossible for the same reality to be both a substance and an accident in the strict sense. It is because of this that the eucharistic accidents, although in fact they are not in another, nevertheless remain accidents, because by their formality and nature it is proper to them to be in another. (Fs) (notabene)

273c If this is the case in creation, all the more must it be acknowledged in God. For God is not in any genus,1 and therefore, although we talk about the divine substance and the divine relations according to our limited way of conceiving things, yet through such concepts we attain little understanding of divine reality itself, and so it would be presumptuous to conclude with certitude from these concepts that the divine substance cannot be really the same as a divine relation. (Fs)

273d Besides, in this life we know, not what God is,2 but rather what God is not. Hence we know merely aspects of divine perfection, and those are for the most part negative ones. We do not enjoy a positive understanding of God so as to be able to understand how these many diverse aspects come together into one. As a result, no serious argument can be made on the basis of the fact that we do not understand how the formality of substance and the formality of relation can come together into one reality. Even in what we know naturally it is better to argue from what we understand than from what we do not understand; and in the case of the divine mysteries we have to seek, not a perfect understanding, but that imperfect understanding that reason enlightened by faith generates when it inquires diligently, reverently, and judiciously. (Fs)

275a Moreover, one cannot say that substance and relation are so incompatible that they cannot exist in one and the same reality, since even one positive example suffices to refute a universal negative assertion. But it is clear from many examples that the reality of substance does not exclude real relations. For every finite substance is composed of potency and act, which are really related to each other; every material substance is really composed of matter and form and existence, which are really related to one another; every finite substance, whether material or immaterial, is a specific nature, which is an intrinsic principle of operations, where the operations are really distinct from the principle and the principle itself is really related to the really distinct operations. (Fs)

275b Again, the more we compare the generic notions of substance and relation with the divine reality itself, the less do being through itself and being to another seem to be opposites. The divine reality does not cease to be through itself because it is communicated by the Father to the Son and by the Father and the Son to the Spirit; for the communication of the substance does not destroy the formality of substance; and yet this very communication is the foundation of the real relations. (Fs)

275c Again, the real relations founded on communication do not relate God to another that is not God; rather, one subsistent relation is related to the other opposite subsistent relation, and since all these relations are really identical with the reality of the divine substance, the being to another of relation as well as the opposition of relation to being through itself are diminished as much as possible. (Fs)

275d In reply to the first contrary argument,3 we say that in metaphysics as in all other sciences, one must distinguish between two kinds of knowledge. The first is a prescientific knowledge of things, in which the causes of things are not yet known. The second is a scientific knowledge of things, in which things are known through their causes. Now, metaphysics is the knowledge of things through ultimate causes. The ultimate constitutive causes are potency and act, matter and form, essence and existence, and the divisions of essences stated above. The ultimate efficient cause and final cause is God. Insofar as things are known through these causes, there is scientific metaphysical knowledge. On the other hand, the ten categories are not the ultimate causes of things but the ultimate kinds of things. These ultimate kinds belong to metaphysical knowledge as prescientific, that is, as directed to investigating and discovering causes, and therefore the categories are treated in logic, not in metaphysics itself.4 (Fs)

277a Since this is so, to argue from categories as such is to proceed without due rigor. For although the kinds of things are ultimate and distinct from one another as far as prescientific metaphysical knowledge is concerned, still this prescientific knowledge is itself but a preparatory stage for properly scientific knowledge. Besides, once one has arrived at scientific knowledge, one must obviously stay with what has been clearly and distinctly demonstrated through causes and should not in any way argue from the categories unless to convince those who either do not grasp metaphysical knowledge or perhaps have as yet not understood it. (Fs)

277b Therefore, in the foregoing reply we reduced substance, accident, and relation to their ultimate real constitutive elements, that is, to essences to which it is proper to be through itself, or in another, or to another; and in accordance with this we have judged whether a substance can be the same as a relation. (Fs)

277c Moreover, practically the same argument applies to the distinction that is made between categorial relations and transcendental relations. The first are those relations that are known by prescientific metaphysical knowledge; these are the ones listed by Aristotle,5 namely, relations according to quantity, according to action and passion, and according to the measurable and the measure. The second are those relations that are known through metaphysical investigation; such relations are both those that are found in the last six categories and those that obtain among the constitutive principles of things.6 (Fs)

277d Again, another difference follows from this distinction between prescientific and scientific knowledge. Categorial relations were investigated by the earliest group of great thinkers; but transcendental relations as such could not have been investigated until after those first great minds had founded and developed metaphysical knowledge. For the metaphysics of metaphysical relation naturally emerges rather slowly. (Fs)

279a But neither the first nor the second difference makes for more than a historical distinction. And the distinction between the former relations, the categorial, and the latter, the transcendental, has this added inconvenience, that it gives the uninformed the pernicious notion that metaphysics is knowledge of things not through ultimate causes but through ultimate categories. (Fs)

Accordingly, we hold that the distinction of relations into subsistent relations, the relations of subsistents, and the relations of the constituents of subsistents, is scientific. For this division of relations corresponds to the ontological degrees of reality.7 (Fs)

279b In reply to the second contrary argument,8 we say that accident can be understood in two ways. First, it signifies that to which it is proper to be in another. Second, it signifies anything that is defined either through another in which it is or through another to which it is. If we take accident in the first sense, we must concede that a substance cannot be really the same as an accident, but we must deny that a relation by definition is an accident in this sense. But if accident is taken in the second sense, we must concede that relation is an accident, but deny that an accident in this broader sense is incompatible with the reality of substance. (Fs)

279c In reply to the third contrary argument,9 we concede that a substance is or has essence in an unqualified sense, while a relation has essence with qualification. But we must deny that it is impossible for one and the same reality to be both an unqualified essence with respect to itself and a qualified essence with respect to its communication.10 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion der Objektivität; Hauptnotion; Problem der Transzendenz

Kurzinhalt: Sechstens, die Hauptnotion der Objektivität löst das Problem der Transzendenz. Wie geht das erkennende Subjekt über sich selbst hinaus auf ein Erkanntes zu?

Textausschnitt: XIII. Kapitel DIE NOTION DER OBJEKTIVITÄT

434a Das menschliche Erkennen ist zyklisch und kumulativ. Es ist zyklisch, insofern der Erkenntnisprozeß von der Erfahrung durch Untersuchung und Reflexion zum Urteil fortschreitet, nur um sich von neuem der Erfahrung zuzuwenden und seinen Aufstieg zu einem anderen Urteil wiederzubeginnen. Es ist kumulativ, nicht nur insofern das Gedächtnis Erfahrungen speichert und der Verstand Einsichten sammelt, sondern auch weil die Urteile sich zu jenem Kontext verbinden, der Wissen oder Mentalität genannt wird. (Fs)

434b Die Komplexität unseres Erkennens zieht eine parallele Komplexität in unserer Notion der Objektivität nach sich. In ihrer Hauptbedeutung ist die Notion der Objektivität in einem Kontext von Urteilen gemäß einem bestimmten Schema enthalten, die als implizite Definitionen der Termini Objekt und Subjekt dienen. Aber neben dieser Haupt- und vollständigen Notion gibt es auch partielle Aspekte oder Komponenten, die innerhalb des Erkenntnisprozesses entstehen. So gibt es einen erfahrungsmäßigen Aspekt der Objektivität, der der Sinneserfahrung und dem empirischen Bewußtsein eigen ist. Es gibt einen normativen Aspekt, der im Kontrast zwischen dem unvoreingenommenen und uneingeschränkten Erkenntnisstreben einerseits und den rein subjektiven Wünschen und Ängsten andererseits enthalten ist. Schließlich gibt es einen absoluten Aspekt, der in den einzelnen und für sich selbst genommenen Urteilen enthalten ist, insofern jedes Urteil auf einem Erfassen des Unbedingten beruht und ohne Vorbehalte gesetzt wird. (Fs)
1. Die Hauptnotion


434c Die Notion der Objektivität ist nach ihrer Hauptbedeutung im Kontext eines bestimmten Schemas von Urteilen enthalten. Denn man kann als Objekte jedes A, B, C, D, ... definieren, wobei A, B, C, D, ... ihrerseits durch die Korrektheit folgenden Satzes von Urteilen definiert werden:

A ist; B ist; C ist; D ist; ...
A ist weder B noch C noch D noch ...
B ist weder C noch D noch ...
C ist weder D noch ...

435a Ferner, man kann ein Subjekt wie jegliches Objekt definieren, z. B. A, wobei es wahr ist, daß A sich als erkennendes Subjekt bejaht in dem Sinne, wie es im Kapitel über Selbstbejahung erklärt wurde. (Fs)
Das unabdingbar Wesentliche der Notion der Objektivität wird erreicht, wenn [376] wir den schon diskutierten Urteilen, nämlich: "Ich bin ein erkennendes Subjekt" und "Dies ist eine Schreibmaschine", das weitere Urteil hinzufügen: "Ich bin nicht diese Schreibmaschine". Eine unbegrenzte Anzahl weiterer Objekte kann hinzugefügt werden, indem wir die entsprechenden weiteren positiven und negativen Urteile fällen. Insofern man schließlich die Existenz anderer erkennender Subjekte außer einem selbst intelligent erfassen und vernünftig bejahen kann, kann man der Liste die Objekte anfügen, die auch Subjekte sind. (Fs)

435b Die Eigenschaften der Hauptnotion der Objektivität müssen nun vorgestellt werden. Erstens, wie schon bemerkt wurde, liegt die Notion in einem Kontext von Urteilen; ohne eine Mehrzahl von Urteilen, die einem bestimmten Muster genügen, entsteht die Notion gar nicht. Zweitens, ein unmittelbares Korollarium folgt: Die Hauptnotion der Objektivität, so wie sie definiert worden ist, ist nicht in einem Einzelurteil enthalten und noch weniger in irgendeinem erfahrungsmäßigen oder normativen Faktor, der im Erkenntnisprozeß vor dem Urteil vorkommt. Drittens, die Gültigkeit der Hauptnotion der Objektivität ist dieselbe wie die Gültigkeit des Satzes von Urteilen, die diese Notion enthalten; wenn die Urteile korrekt sind, dann ist es korrekt, daß es Objekte und Subjekte im definierten Sinne gibt; denn der definierte Sinn ist einfach die Korrektheit des geeigneten Schemas von Urteilen. (Fs)

435c Viertens, um uns nun gewissen weitreichenderen Aspekten der Hauptnotion zuzuwenden, werden Urteile nach dem angegebenen Muster gefällt, und sie werden gemeinhin als korrekt betrachtet. Es folgt, daß die Menschen gemeinhin Objekte und Subjekte erkennen und sich wundern, wenn jemand daran zweifeln sollte. Andererseits folgt daraus nicht, daß die Menschen gemeinhin fähig sind, eine klare Rechenschaft über ihre Erkenntnis von Objekten und Subjekten abzulegen. Denn die klare Rechenschaft verwendet die etwas verborgene Kunst der impliziten Definition, während die Menschen geneigt sind, zur Konklusion zu springen, daß eine so evidente Sache wie die Existenz von Objekten und Subjekten doch auf etwas so Evidentem und Naheliegendem beruhen müsse, wie es der Erfahrungsaspekt der Objektivität ist. Deshalb werden sie einerseits sagen, die Schreibmaschine sei ein Objekt, weil sie es sehen oder betasten; andererseits aber werden sie zugeben, daß sie die Schreibmaschine nicht als Objekt betrachten würden, wenn sie wüßten, daß es wahr ist, daß entweder gar keine Schreibmaschine da war oder daß das, was sie eine Schreibmaschine nannten, identisch mit jedwedem anderen Ding war. (Fs)

436a Fünftens, die Hauptnotion der Objektivität ist eng mit der Notion des Seins verwandt. Das Sein ist das, was durch die Gesamtheit der korrekten Urteile zu erkennen ist. Die Objektivität ist in ihrer Hauptbedeutung das, was durch jeden [377] beliebigen Satz von Urteilen erkannt wird, die einem bestimmten Muster genügen. Kurzum, es gibt Objektivität, wenn es mehrere Seiende gibt, von denen manche sowohl sich selbst als auch andere als andere erkennen. Die Notion von Sein erklärt zudem, warum die Objektivität in ihrer Hauptbedeutung nur durch ein Muster von Urteilen zu erreichen ist. Die Notion des Seins wird nämlich nur bestimmt, insofern Urteile gefällt werden; vor dem Urteil kann man über das Sein denken, aber es nicht erkennen; und jedes Einzelurteil ist nur ein minimaler Zuwachs im Prozeß, es zu erkennen. Ferner, das Sein ist von innen her aufgeteilt; denn außer dem Sein gibt es nichts; es folgt, daß es kein Subjekt geben kann, das außerhalb des Seins steht und von dort das Sein anschaut. Das Subjekt muß sein, ehe es auf das Sein hinschauen kann; und wenn es ist, dann ist es nicht außerhalb des Seins, sondern entweder das Ganze oder ein Teil davon. Wenn es das Ganze des Seins ist, dann ist es das einzige Objekt. Wenn es lediglich ein Teil ist, dann muß es eine Vielfalt von Teilen zu erkennen beginnen (A ist; B ist; A ist nicht B) und hinzufügen, daß ein Teil andere erkennt ("Ich bin A"). (Fs)

436b Sechstens, die Hauptnotion der Objektivität löst das Problem der Transzendenz. Wie geht das erkennende Subjekt über sich selbst hinaus auf ein Erkanntes zu? Die Frage ist, wie ich meine, irreführend. Sie setzt voraus, daß das Erkennende sich selbst kennt und fragt, wie es etwas anderes erkennen könne. Unsere Antwort enthält zwei Elemente. Einerseits behaupten wir, daß das erkennende Subjekt, während es sich selbst erfahren oder ohne Urteil über sich nachdenken kann, sich selbst doch nicht erkennt, so lange es nicht die korrekte Bejahung vornimmt: "Ich bin"; erst dann erkennt es sich selbst Seiendes und als Objekt. Andererseits behaupten wir, daß andere Urteile ebenso möglich und vernünftig sind, so daß durch Erfahrung, Untersuchung und Reflexion eine Erkenntnis von anderen Objekten sowohl als Seienden, wie auch als vom erkennenden Subjekt verschiedenen Seienden entsteht. Wir setzen deshalb die Transzendenz nicht im Hinausgehen über ein erkanntes erkennendes Subjekt, sondern in einer Bewegung auf das Sein hin, innerhalb dessen es positive Unterschiede gibt, und unter diesen Unterschieden auch der Unterschied zwischen Objekt und Subjekt. Insofern solche Urteile vorkommen, gibt es tatsächlich Objektivität und Transzendenz; und ob solche Urteile korrekt sind oder nicht, ist eine andere Frage, die gelöst werden muß gemäß den Richtlinien, die in der Urteilsanalyse aufgestellt worden sind. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion der Objektivität; absolute Objektivität; Objektivität von Raum (Zeno) und Zeit

Kurzinhalt: Die Interpretationen des Seins oder der absoluten Objektivität in den Termini von Raum und Zeit sind bloß ungebührliche Einmischungen der Phantasie. Die absolute Objektivität ist einfach eine Eigenschaft des Unbedingten; ...

Textausschnitt: 2. Die absolute Objektivität

437a Außer der Hauptnotion der Objektivität gibt es auch die partiellen Aspekte der erfahrungsmäßigen, normativen und absoluten Objektivität. Es wird nützlich sein, bei der letzten der drei zu beginnen. (Fs)

Der Grund für die absolute Objektivität ist das virtuell Unbedingte, das durch das reflektierende Verstehen erfaßt und im Urteil gesetzt wird. Das formal Unbedingte, das überhaupt keine Bedingungen hat, steht außerhalb des zusammenhängenden [378] Feldes von bedingenden und bedingten Termini; es ist in sich selbst absolut. Das virtuell Unbedingte steht innerhalb dieses Feldes; es hat Bedingungen; es ist selbst eine der Bedingungen für andere Fälle des Bedingten; seine Bedingungen sind aber erfüllt; es ist ein de facto Absolutes. (Fs)

437b Weil der Inhalt des Urteils ein Absolutes ist, entzieht er sich der Relativität zum Subjekt, das ihn ausspricht, zum Ort, an dem er ausgesprochen wird, zur Zeit, da er ausgesprochen wird. Caesars Überschreiten des Rubikon war ein kontingentes Ereignis, das an einem bestimmten Ort und zu einer bestimmten Zeit stattfand. Aber eine wahre Bejahung dieses Ereignisses ist ewig, unveränderlich und definitiv gültig. Denn wenn es wahr ist, daß er den Rubikon überschritten hat, dann kann niemand, zu keiner Zeit und an keinem Orte, bestreiten, daß er es getan hat. (Fs)

437c Kraft dieser absoluten Objektivität gewinnt also unsere Erkenntnis das, was ihre "Öffentlichkeit" genannt wurde. Aus demselben Grunde, aus dem das Unbedingte der Relativität zu seiner Quelle entzogen ist, ist es auch zugänglich nicht nur für das erkennende Subjekt, das es ausspricht, sondern für jedes andere erkennende Subjekt. (Fs)
437d Weiter, es ist die absolute Objektivität des Unbedingten, die in den logischen Prinzipien von Identität und Widerspruch ihre Formulierung findet. Das Prinzip der Identität besagt die unveränderliche und definitive Gültigkeit des Wahren. Das Prinzip vom Widerspruch besagt die Exklusivität dieser Gültigkeit. Es ist, und was im Gegensatz zu ihm steht, ist nicht. (Fs) (notabene)

437e Weiter, die absolute Objektivität gehört zu den Einzelurteilen als einzelnen. Wie wir erwiesen haben, entsteht die Hauptnotion der Objektivität nur durch eine geeignete Konstellation von Urteilen. Aber jedes Urteil in einer solchen Konstellation ist ein Absolutes, und, außerdem, es ist ein Absolutes kraft seiner eigenen Bejahung des Unbedingten. Die Gültigkeit der Hauptnotion ist eine abgeleitete Gültigkeit, die auf dem Satz von Absoluten beruht, die sie miteinschließt. Aber der absolute Aspekt der Objektivität hat seinen Grund im Einzelurteil, zu dem die Objektivität gehört. Dieser Aspekt ist durchaus kompatibel mit der Behauptung, daß es nur ein Seiendes gibt, daß es kein Objekt gibt außer dem bejahenden Subjekt. Infolgedessen impliziert der absolute Aspekt der Objektivität keine Subjekt-Objekt-Beziehung; er macht den Eintritt unserer Erkenntnis in den Bereich des Seins aus; aber er genügt für sich selbst nicht, um Seiende zu setzen, zu unterscheiden und in Verbindung zu setzen. Diese Insuffizienz entsteht allerdings nicht aus einem Mangel der absoluten Objektivität und auch nicht, weil die gesetzten Seienden, ihre Unterschiede und Beziehungen nicht alle unbedingt sind, sondern weil mehrere Urteile benötigt werden, um zu setzen, zu unterscheiden und Beziehungen herzustellen. (Fs)

438a [379] Es ist wichtig, die absolute Objektivität eines beliebigen korrekten Urteils nicht mit der Invarianz zu verwechseln, die dem Ausdruck allgemeiner Urteile eigen ist. Sowohl die allgemeinen Urteile als auch die partikulären Urteile sind absolut objektiv, wenn sie korrekt sind. Die ersteren werden aber invariant ausgedrückt, weil der Ausdruck unabhängig von den Variationen im raumzeitlichen Referenzrahmen ist, während die letzteren relativ ausgedrückt werden, weil ihr Ausdruck sich nicht solcher Unabhängigkeit erfreut. Die Variation des Ausdruckes aber setzt die absolute Objektivität dessen, was ausgedrückt wird, voraus und offenbart sie. Weil "Ich bin jetzt hier" absolute Objektivität hat, gibt es eine identische Wahrheit, die wiederholt werden kann, nur indem man andere Wörter verwendet, etwa: "Er war damals dort."

438b Weiter, die absolute Objektivität impliziert gar nicht einen absoluten Raum oder eine absolute Zeit. Wenn es wahr ist, daß der Raum ist, dann ist das Absolute die Wahrheit und nicht der Raum. Ob der Raum absolut oder relativ ist, ist eine andere Frage. Wenn es wahr ist, daß der Raum aus einer unendlichen Anzahl unbeweglicher und leerer Orte besteht, dann ist Raum absolut. Wenn es wahr ist, daß Raum nicht ein solcher Inbegriff von Orten ist, dann ist Raum relativ. Was ist korrekt? Zumindest kann das Problem nicht gelöst werden, indem man sich auf die Tatsache beruft, daß ein wahres Urteil ein Unbedingtes setzt. (Fs)

438c Ferner, wie Zeno bewiesen hat, impliziert die Behauptung, daß etwas oder etwas anderes ist, nicht, daß es sich im Raum befindet. Würde sie dies implizieren, so könnte man fragen, ob der Raum (in dem dieses etwas ist) ist. Wenn der Raum nicht ist, dann ist er nichts; und zu behaupten, daß die Dinge im Nichts sind, ist sinnlos. Wenn der Raum aber ist, dann wiederholt sich die Frage - weil "sein" ja "im Raum sein" bedeutet. Wenn "X ist" "X ist im Raum" bedeutet, dann scheint zu folgen, daß "der Raum ist" "der Raum ist im Raum" bedeutet; der zweite Raum kann nicht mit dem ersten identisch sein, sonst würde er ihn nicht enthalten; und wenn er verschieden ist, dann kann er sein, nur wenn er in einem weiteren Raum ist, und so weiter ins Unendliche. (Fs) (notabene)

439a Dasselbe Argument gilt für das Sein in der Zeit. Wenn "sein" "sein zu irgendeiner Zeit" bedeutet, dann gibt es entweder die Zeit, oder es gibt die Zeit nicht. Wenn es die Zeit nicht gibt, dann ist "sein zu irgendeiner Zeit" einfach "sein". Wenn es die Zeit gibt, dann muß sie zu irgendeiner Zeit sein, und diese zu irgendeiner Zeit, und so weiter ins Unendliche. (Fs) (notabene)

439b Die Interpretationen des Seins oder der absoluten Objektivität in den Termini von Raum und Zeit sind bloß ungebührliche Einmischungen der Phantasie. Die absolute Objektivität ist einfach eine Eigenschaft des Unbedingten; und das Unbedingte als solches sagt nichts über Raum und Zeit. Wenn die eigene Phantasie den Gebrauch der Präposition "in" aufzwingt, dann könnte man sagen, daß jedes Urteil sich im Kontext anderer Urteile befinde und jedes Unbedingte in einem Universum des Seins. Dann "der Raum ist", insofern er im Universum des Seins ist, und "die [380] Zeit ist", insofern sie im Universum des Seins ist, wobei "im Universum des Seins zu sein" "unbedingt zusammen mit anderen Fällen des Unbedingten zu sein" bedeutet. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion der Objektivität; normative Objektivität; dynamische Ausrichtung - Zielobjekt; Prinzip vom ausgeschlossenen Dritten

Kurzinhalt: Der Grund der normativen Objektivität liegt in der Entfaltung des uneingeschränkten, unvoreingenommenen und uneigennützigen Erkenntnisstrebens.

Textausschnitt: 3. Die normative Objektivität

439c Der zweite Teilaspekt der Objektivität ist der normative. Es ist die Objektivität als Gegensatz zur Subjektivität des Wunschdenkens, der voreiligen oder übertrieben vorsichtigen Urteile, des Sich-Einmischens von Freude oder Traurigkeit, Hoffnung oder Furcht, Liebe oder Abscheu, in den richtigen Verlauf des Erkenntnisprozesses. (Fs)

439d Der Grund der normativen Objektivität liegt in der Entfaltung des uneingeschränkten, unvoreingenommenen und uneigennützigen Erkenntnisstrebens. Weil dieses Streben uneingeschränkt ist, stellt es sich dem Obskurantismus entgegen, der die Wahrheit verbirgt oder den Zugang zu ihr völlig oder teilweise versperrt. Weil es unvoreingenommen ist, stellt es sich den Hemmungen des Erkenntnisprozesses entgegen, die ihre Quelle in anderen menschlichen Wünschen und Tendenzen haben. Weil es uneigennützig ist, stellt es sich der gut gemeinten aber verhängnisvollen Verstärkung des Erkenntnisprozesses von Seiten anderer Wünsche entgegen, die in der Tat die Ausrichtung des Erkenntnisstrebens in die engen Grenzen ihrer beschränkten Tragweite hineinzwängen. (Fs) (notabene)

440a Die normative Objektivität besteht in dem Erfordernis, das dem reinen Erkenntnisstreben beim Trachten nach seinem uneingeschränkten Zielobjekt innewohnt. Eine dynamische Ausrichtung definiert das Zielobjekt dieses Strebens. Sie definiert ebenfalls die Mittel, um sein Zielobjekt zu erreichen. Nicht nur zielt das reine Streben nach dem Universum des Seins, sondern es tut dies auch, indem es zu verstehen und das Verstandene als Unbedingtes zu erfassen sucht. Objektiv zu sein in normativem Sinne des Terminus bedeutet daher, dem reinen Streben - seinen Fragen nach Einsicht und seinen Fragen nach Reflexion - die Zügel schießen zu lassen. Weiter bedeutet es zu unterscheiden zwischen Fragen nach Einsicht, die unmittelbare Lösungen gestatten, und anderen Fragen desselben Typs, die zur Zeit noch nicht gelöst werden können. Ähnlich bedeutet es, zwischen gesunden Fragen zu unterscheiden und andererseits Fragen, die sinnlos oder inkohärent oder illegitim sind. Denn das reine Streben strebt nicht nur; es strebt intelligent und vernünftig; es will verstehen, weil es intelligent ist, und es will das Unbedingte erfassen, weil es vernünftig sein will. (Fs) (notabene)

440b Auf den normativen Erfordernissen des reinen Strebens beruht die Gültigkeit aller Logik und Methode. Eine Logik oder Methode ist nicht ein schlechthin Letztes, das nur durch den Lärm einer unrealistischen Lobpreisung für mittelalterliche Philosophie oder für moderne Wissenschaft eingesetzt werden kann, zusammen mit [381] einem unsicheren Ressentiment gegen alles andere. Logik und Methode sind intelligent und rational; ihre Gründe sind nicht Glaube oder Propaganda oder die pragmatische Nützlichkeit von Atombomben und Nylonstrümpfen; ihre Gründe sind die inneren Erfordernisse des reinen Erkenntnisstrebens. Sie müssen akzeptiert werden, insofern es ihnen gelingt, diese dynamischen Erfordernisse zu formulieren; und sie sind zu revidieren, insofern sie versagen. (Fs)

440c Diese Abhängigkeit wurde schon auf verschiedene Weisen festgestellt. So resultieren die logischen Prinzipien von Identität und Widerspruch aus dem Unbedingten und dem Zwang, den es auf unsere Vernunft ausübt. Das Prinzip vom ausgeschlossenen Dritten besitzt eine letzte, aber nicht unmittelbare Gültigkeit; es besitzt eine letzte Gültigkeit; denn wenn ein Urteil vorkommt, muß es entweder eine Bejahung oder eine Verneinung sein; es besitzt keine unmittelbare Gültigkeit, weil bezüglich jeder Aussage das rationale Bewußtsein vor den drei Alternativen der Bejahung, der Verneinung und der Suche nach einem besseren Verständnis und damit nach einer adäquateren Formulierung des Problems steht. Ferner, die Vorgehensweisen der empirischen Methode in ihren klassischen und statistischen Phasen wurden erklärt durch die Bewegung des reinen Strebens nach Verstehen, und zwar nach einem Verstehen, das die Dinge betrachtet, nicht nur insofern sie auf uns durch unsere Sinne bezogen sind, sondern auch insofern sie funktionell aufeinander bezogen sind; nach einem Verstehen, das Daten voraussetzt, die in der klassischen Phase eine Systematisierung zulassen, während sie in anderen Hinsichten nicht-systematisch sind und so eine statistische Phase notwendig machen. Schließlich können Vorschriften für Urteile aus der allgemeinen Anforderung des Unbedingten abgeleitet werden und aus den besonderen Umständen der verschiedenen Arten von Urteilen, die ursprünglich oder abgeleitet, theoretisch oder konkret, beschreibend oder erklärend, gewiß oder wahrscheinlich sein können. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Notion der Objektivität; erfahrungsmäßige Objektivität; das Gegebene: unbezweifelbar, diffus, unbestimmt; Bestimmung des Gegebenen vom Erkenntnisstreben aus

Kurzinhalt: Ebenso ist das Gegebene unbezweifelbar. Was bezweifelt werden kann, ist die Antwort auf eine Frage nach Reflexion ...

Textausschnitt: 4. Die erfahrungsmäßige Objektivität

441a Der dritte Aspekt der Objektivität ist der erfahrungsmäßige. Er ist das Gegebene als gegebenes. Er ist das Feld der Materialien, über die man die Untersuchung anstellt, in denen man die Erfüllung der Bedingungen für das Unbedingte findet, zu denen der Erkenntnisprozeß immer wieder zurückkehrt, um die Reihe der Untersuchungen und Reflexionen zu schaffen, welche die Menge der Urteile ergeben, die den Kontext ausmachen. (Fs)

441b Ferner, das Gegebene ist unbestreitbar und unbezweifelbar. Was durch die Antwort auf Fragen konstituiert wird, kann durch andere Fragen umgeworfen werden. Das Gegebene aber ist unabhängig vom Fragen konstituiert; es bleibt dasselbe, was immer das Resultat des Fragens sein mag; es ist unbestreitbar in dem Sinne, daß es außerhalb der Erkenntnisebenen liegt, welche sich durch Fragen und Antworten [382] konstituieren. Ebenso ist das Gegebene unbezweifelbar. Was bezweifelt werden kann, ist die Antwort auf eine Frage nach Reflexion; ein "Ja" oder ein "Nein". Aber das Gegebene ist nicht die Antwort auf irgendeine Frage; es geht jeder Frage voraus und ist unabhängig von jeglicher Antwort. (Fs)

441c Ferner, das Gegebene ist residual und von sich aus diffus. Es ist möglich, im Gegebenen Elemente auszuwählen und diese klar und präzise anzugeben. Die Auswahl und die Angabe aber sind das Werk von Einsicht und Formulierung, und das Gegebene ist das Residuum, das übrigbleibt, wenn man vom Angegebenen

(1) den instrumentellen Akt der Bedeutung, mit dem man angibt;
(2) die Begriffe, die durch diesen instrumentellen Akt ausgedrückt werden;
(3) die Einsichten, auf denen die Begriffe beruhen, wegnimmt. (Fs)

Weil nun das Gegebene einfach das Residuum ist, weil es nur durch intellektuelle Handlungen ausgewählt und bezeichnet werden kann, ist es von sich aus diffus; das Feld des Gegebenen enthält Unterschiede, aber insofern diese einfach in diesem Felde liegen, sind die Unterschiede unbestimmt. (Fs) (notabene)

442a Ferner, das Feld des Gegebenen ist in all seinen Teilen in gleicher Weise gültig, in seinen verschiedenen Teilen aber verschieden bedeutsam. (Fs)

Es ist in gleicher Weise gültig in all seinen Teilen in dem Sinne, daß es vor der Untersuchung keine Auswahl gibt. Die Auswahl ist die Frucht der Untersuchung. Sie findet statt, erst wenn die Untersuchung begonnen hat. (Fs)

442b Es ist in seinen verschiedenen Teilen von verschiedener Bedeutung in dem Sinne, daß einige Teile für einige Abteilungen der Erkenntnis bedeutsam sind und andere für andere. Der Physiker hat abzusehen von dem, was er sich bloß in seiner Phantasie vorstellt, sich erträumt oder aus seinem persönlichen Beobachtungsfehler ableitet. Der Psychologe hat die Vorstellungen der Phantasie, die Träume und die persönlichen Beobachtungsfehler zu erklären. Wenn also die Untersuchung begonnen hat, dann besteht der erste Schritt in der Auswahl des relevanten Feldes des Gegebenen. (Fs)

442c Wir verwenden den Terminus "Gegebenes" in einem sehr breiten Sinne. Er schließt nicht nur die mit der Wirklichkeit übereinstimmenden Lieferungen der äußeren Sinne mit ein, sondern auch Bilder der Phantasie, Träume, Illusionen, Halluzinationen, persönliche Beobachtungsfehler, subjektive Befangenheit und so fort. Zweifellos wäre eine engere Verwendung des Terminus erwünscht, wenn wir vom beschränkten Gesichtspunkt der Naturwissenschaft sprächen. Wir arbeiten hier jedoch an einer allgemeinen Theorie der Objektivität und haben deshalb nicht nur die Materialien, welche die Naturwissenschaft untersucht, als gegeben anzuerkennen, sondern auch die Materialien, über die der Psychologe oder Methodologe oder Kulturhistoriker Untersuchungen anstellt. (Fs)

[383] Es gibt einen tieferen Grund. Unsere Erklärung des Gegebenen ist äußerlich. Sie schließt keine Beschreibung des Stromes des sinnlichen Bewußtseins mit ein. Sie schließt keine Theorie dieses Stromes mit ein. Sie erörtert weder den Beitrag des empirisch bewußten Subjektes noch den Beitrag anderer "äußerlicher" Wirkursachen. Sie bemerkt einfach, daß Reflexion und Urteil ein Verstehen voraussetzen, daß Untersuchen und Verstehen Materialien für die Untersuchung und etwas, das verstanden werden soll, voraussetzen. Solche vorausgesetzten Materialien sind unbestreitbar und unbezweifelbar, insofern sie nicht durch Antworten auf Fragen konstituiert sind. Sie sind residual und diffus, weil sie das sind, was übrigbleibt, wenn die Erträge des Untersuchens und Reflektierens von den Erkenntnisinhalten abgezogen werden. (Fs)

442d Nun müssen solche unbestreitbaren und unbezweifelbaren, residualen und diffusen Materialien für die Untersuchung und die Reflexion als in allen ihren Teilen in gleicher Weise gültig angesehen werden. Wären sie alle ungültig, dann könnte es weder eine Untersuchung noch eine Reflexion geben, und so könnte auch nicht vernünftig behauptet werden, daß sie ungültig sind. Wären einige gültig und andere ungültig, dann müßte es ein vernünftig bejahtes Selektionsprinzip geben; ein solches Prinzip kann aber nur erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht werden, wenn die Untersuchung einmal begonnen hat. Vor der Untersuchung kann es keine intelligente Unterscheidung und keine vernünftige Zurückweisung geben. (Fs)

443a Es gibt einen noch tieferen Grund. Warum muß das Gegebene äußerlich definiert werden? Weil alle Objektivität auf dem uneingeschränkten, unparteiischen und uneigennützigen Streben nach Erkenntnis beruht. Dieses Streben stellt die kanonischen Prinzipien für die normative Objektivität auf. Dieses Streben läßt die absolute Objektivität aufkommen, die im Urteil impliziert ist. Dieses Streben ergibt die Konstellation der Urteile, die implizit die Hauptnotion voneinander unterschiedener Objekte im Universum des Seins definieren, von denen einige andere erkennen. Die erfahrungsmäßige Objektivität muß auf derselben Basis beruhen, und so wird das Gegebene nicht unter Bezugnahme auf den sinnlichen Prozeß definiert, sondern durch das reine Erkenntnisstreben, das den Strom des empirischen Bewußtseins als die Materialien für seine Handlungen betrachtet. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Methode der Metaphysik; Grundproblem; polymorphes Bewusstsein; "Jetzt-schon-da-draußen"

Kurzinhalt: Dem konkreten Universum des Seins ... steht in zeitlich früherer Vollständigkeit die Welt der Sinne entgegen, in welcher das "Reale" und das "Scheinbare" Unterabteilungen sind innerhalb eines vital vorweggenommenen "Jetzt-schon-da-draußen".

Textausschnitt: 1. Das zugrundeliegende Problem

445a Es dürfte nicht allzu schwer fallen, Gegenthesen zu den in den drei vorhergehenden Kapiteln gezogenen Schlüssen aufzustellen. Der auf intelligenter Untersuchung und kritischer Reflexion aufbauenden Objektivität steht die fraglose1 Ausrichtung des extravertierten biologischen Bewußtseins entgegen und sein unkritisches Überleben nicht nur im dramatischen und praktischen Leben, sondern auch in einem Großteil des philosophischen Denkens. Dem konkreten Universum des Seins, d.h. all dessen, was intelligent erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht werden kann, steht in zeitlich früherer Vollständigkeit die Welt der Sinne entgegen, in welcher das "Reale" und das "Scheinbare" Unterabteilungen sind innerhalb eines vital vorweggenommenen "Jetzt-schon-da-draußen". Der Selbstbejahung eines Bewußtseins, das zugleich empirisch, intellektuell und rational ist, steht die natürliche Verwirrung des existentiellen Subjektes entgegen, das - mit Abscheu gegen die reine Animalität erfüllt, unsicher bezüglich seines Weges durch das Labyrinth der Philosophien - versucht, ohne ein ihm bekanntes Ziel zu leben, das leidet trotz seinem unmotivierten Willen, das bedroht ist vom unausweichlichen Tod, und vor dem Tode, von Krankheit und sogar Wahnsinn. (Fs) (notabene)

445b Die Eigenheit dieser Gegenthesen verdient besondere Aufmerksamkeit. Sie sind nicht einfach in Konflikt stehende Aussagen. Sie sind nicht einfach logische Alternativen, von denen die eine ganz einfach wahr und die andere völlig falsch ist. In jedem Fall haben sowohl These wie Gegenthese ihren Grund in jener konkreten Einheit in Spannung, die der Mensch ist. Denn das menschliche Bewußtsein ist polymorph. Das Muster, nach welchem es fließt, kann biologisch, ästhetisch, artistisch, dramatisch, praktisch, intellektuell oder mystisch sein. Diese Muster lösen sich wechselseitig ab; sie verschmelzen oder vermischen sich; sie können einander beeinträchtigen, in Konflikt geraten, ihren Weg verlieren, zusammenbrechen. Das intellektuelle Muster der Erfahrung wird vorausgesetzt und kommt zum Ausdruck in unserer Darstellung von Selbstbejahung, Sein und Objektivität. Doch niemand wird in dieses Muster hineingeboren; niemand erreicht es leicht; niemand verbleibt permanent in ihm; und wenn ein anderes Muster die Oberhand gewinnt, dann scheint das Ich unserer Selbstbejahung als etwas vom tatsächlichen Selbst recht verschiedenes, das Universum des Seins scheint so unreal wie Platos noetischer Himmel und Objektivität wird spontan zu einer Angelegenheit des Sich-Treffens mit Personen und des Umgangs mit Dingen, die "wirklich da draußen" sind. (Fs) (notabene)

446a Nicht [386] nur sind die Antithesen im polymorphen Faktum eines proteusartigen Bewußtseins begründet, sondern anfänglich herrscht das verwirrende Faktum ohne klare Antithesen. Um zu jener scharfen Formulierung zu gelangen, mußten wir mit der Einsicht beginnen, ihr Funktionieren im Feld der Mathematik, der empirischen Wissenschaft und des Common Sense erforschen, um uns dann dem reflektierenden Verstehen und dem Urteil zuzuwenden, und es dabei stets vermeiden, uns auf die offensichtlich so drängenden Probleme der Natur der Erkenntnis, der Wirklichkeit und der Relation zwischen beiden einzulassen. Sogar bei der Ausarbeitung des Prozesses, der in der Selbstbejahung endet, waren wir noch nicht bereit zu sagen, ob die Selbstbejahung nun die Erkenntnis des Ich bedeutet. Die Selbstbejahung wurde zur Selbsterkenntnis, als erkannt wurde, daß das Sein erkennen es zu bejahen heißt; und das Sein erkennen wurde zu objektiver Erkenntnis durch ein Erfassen der Natur der erfahrungsmäßigen, der normativen, der absoluten Objektivität und der folgenden Hauptobjektivität. (Fs) (notabene)

446b Wenn nun aber auch eine klare und scharfe Formulierung der Antithesen erst am Ende einer langen und schwierigen Forschungsarbeit steht, so ist heute diese Forschungsarbeit doch vorbereitet und gestützt in einer Art und Weise, die in früheren Jahrhunderten nicht zur Verfügung stand. Die Entwicklung der Mathematik, die Reife einiger Zweige der empirischen Wissenschaften, die Untersuchungen der Tiefenpsychologie, das Interesse an historischer Theoriebildung, die von Descartes, Hume und Kant aufgebrachten epistemologischen Probleme, die Konzentration der modernen Philosophie auf Erkenntnisanalyse - all dies dient dazu, eine Untersuchung des menschlichen Verstandes zu erleichtern und zu erleuchten. Wenn es aber für spätere Generationen möglich ist, das zu ernten, was frühere Generationen gesät haben, so gab es dennoch vor und während dem Säen keine Ernte, die geerntet werden konnte. (Fs)

446b Kein Wunder deshalb, daß es viele verschiedene, einander widersprechende und disparate Philosophien gegeben hat. Denn ein solches Erstaunen drückt nur die falsche Annahme aus, daß die Aufgabe der Philosophie darin bestehe, eine einfache Entität durch einen einfältigen Verstand zu beobachten oder auszudrücken. In der Tat ist der Verstand aber polymorph; er muß erst seines Mannigfaltigen Herr werden, ehe er bestimmen kann, was eine Äußerung ist, oder was geäußert wird, oder was die Relation zwischen beiden ist; und wenn er das tut, findet er seine eigene Komplexität an der Wurzel der antithetischen Lösungen. Aus dem Durcheinander der miteinander in Konflikt stehenden philosophischen Definitionen und dem Babel endloser philosophischer Argumente wurde geschlossen, daß das Objekt der Philosophie entweder nicht existiere oder nicht zu erreichen sei. Aber diese Konklusion übersieht zwei Tatsachen. Einerseits waren die Philosophen Menschen von besonderem Scharfsinn und Durchblick. Andererseits können die verschiedenen, einander widersprechenden und disparaten Philosophien verstanden werden als Einzelbeiträge zur Klärung eines grundsätzlichen aber polymorphen Faktums. Weil [387] dieses Faktum fundamental ist, beziehen sich seine Implikationen auf das ganze Universum; weil es aber polymorph ist, begründen seine alternativen Formen verschiedenartige Sätze von Implikationen. (Fs)

447a Derart ist also die Sichtweise, die in der vorliegenden Darstellung der philosophischen Methode entwickelt werden soll. So wie in unseren Ausführungen über die Mathematik, die empirische Wissenschaft und den Common Sense, ist auch hier unser einziges Objekt die Natur und die Tatsache der Einsicht. Philosophen und Philosophien interessieren uns dabei nur als Beispiele und Produkte der untersuchenden Intelligenz und der reflektierenden Vernunft. Aus diesem Gesichtspunkt wird eine Einheit nicht nur des Ursprungs sondern auch des Ziels ihrer Tätigkeiten hervortreten. Diese zweifache Einheit ist der Grund dafür, daß wir in jeder gegebenen Philosophie eine Bedeutung finden können, welche sich über den Horizont des einzelnen Philosophen hinaus erstrecken und - sogar in einer Weise, die er nicht erwartete - zur dauerhaften Entwicklung des menschlichen Verstandes gehören kann. (Fs)

447b Dem Leser ist die Möglichkeit einander widersprechender Beiträge zu einem einzigen Ziele bereits in ihren Hauptlinien bekannt. Neben den direkten Einsichten, welche das Systematische erfassen, gibt es die inversen Einsichten, die sich mit dem Nicht-Systematischen befassen. Wie der Mathematiker, der empirische Wissenschaftler, der Tiefenpsychologe und der Geschichtstheoretiker auf beide Typen von Einsichten angewiesen ist, so ist es auch der Philosoph. Mehr noch, indem der Philosoph sowohl direkte wie auch inverse Einsichten benützt in seinem Überblick und seiner Einschätzung des philosophischen Prozesses, werden sein Verstand und sein Erfassen zum einzigen Zielpunkt, in welchem sich widersprechende Beiträge ihre komplexe Einheit erreichen. Und schließlich läßt sich die heuristische Struktur dieser Einheit durch das Prinzip bestimmen, daß die Positionen zu einer Vorwärtsentwicklung auffordern, die Gegenpositionen hingegen zu einer Umkehrentwicklung. Dieses Prinzip müssen wir jetzt erläutern. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Methode der Metaphysik; Position - Gegenposition; Beispiel: Descartes; Philosophie: Basis (Erkenntnistheorie) - Erweiterung

Kurzinhalt: Drittens, die unvermeidbare philosophische Kompenente, die der Formulierung einer Erkenntnistheorie immanent ist, wird entweder eine Basis-Position oder eine Basis-Gegenposition sein.

Textausschnitt: 447c Erstens, in jeder Philosophie ist es möglich, zwischen ihrer Erkenntnistheorie und, andererseits, ihren Aussagen zu metaphysischen, ethischen und theologischen Fragen zu unterscheiden. Wir wollen die Erkenntnistheorie die Basis, die übrigen Aussagen die Erweiterung nennen. (Fs)

448a Zweitens, die Basis hat zwei Aspekte. Einerseits wird die Erkenntnistheorie dadurch bestimmt, daß man sich auf die Daten des Bewußtseins und die historische Entwicklung der menschlichen Erkenntnis beruft. Andererseits kann eine Erkenntnistheorie nicht vollständig formuliert werden, ohne zu Grundfragen der Philosophie Stellung zu beziehen. (Fs)

448b Drittens, die unvermeidbare philosophische Kompenente, die der Formulierung einer Erkenntnistheorie immanent ist, wird entweder eine Basis-Position oder eine Basis-Gegenposition sein. [388]

Sie wird eine Basis-Position sein,
(1) wenn das Wirkliche das konkrete Universum des Seins und nicht eine Unterabteilung des "Jetzt-schon-da-draußen" ist;
(2) wenn das Subjekt dadurch erkannt wird, daß es sich selbst intelligent und vernünftig bejaht und deshalb nicht schon in einem vorhergehenden "existentiellen" Zustande als erkannt gilt; und
(3) wenn die Objektivität aufgefaßt wird als eine Konsequenz intelligenter Untersuchung und kritischer Reflexion und nicht als eine Eigenschaft vitaler Vorwegnahme, Extraversion und Befriedigung. (Fs) (notabene)
Andererseits wird sie eine Basis-Gegenposition sein, wenn sie einer oder mehreren der Basispositionen widerspricht. (Fs)

448c Viertens, jede philosophische Aussage zu einer epistemologischen, metaphysischen, ethischen oder theologischen Frage wird eine Position genannt werden, wenn sie kohärent ist mit den Grundpositionen bezüglich des Wirklichen, der Erkenntnis und der Objektivität; und sie wird eine Gegenposition genannt werden, wenn sie kohärent ist mit einer oder mehreren der Basis-Gegenpositionen. (Fs)

448d Fünftens, alle Gegenpositionen fordern eine Umkehrung heraus. Denn jedes Fehlen von Kohärenz ruft den intelligenten und vernünftigen Forscher dazu auf, Kohärenz zu schaffen. Die Gegenpositionen aber, wenn sie auch unter sich kohärent sind, wenn auch die Eingabe ihrer symbolischen Äquivalenten in ein elektronisches Datensystem zu keinem Zusammenbruch desselben führen würde, sind doch inkohärent mit den Tätigkeiten, mit denen sie intelligent erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht werden. Denn diese Aktivitäten enthalten die Basis-Positionen; und die Basis-Positionen widersprechen jeglicher Gegenposition. Man kann eine Gegenposition erfassen und akzeptieren, vorschlagen und verteidigen; aber diese Aktivität verpflichtet einen dazu, das eigene Erfassen und Akzeptieren zu erfassen und zu akzeptieren; und diese Verpflichtung beinhaltet ein Erfassen und Akzeptieren der Grundpositionen. Es gibt nur einen kohärenten Weg, eine Gegenposition aufrechtzuerhalten, nämlich den des Tieres; denn die Tiere sprechen nicht nur nicht, sie geben auch keine Rechtfertigung ihres Schweigens. (Fs) (notabene)

449a Sechstens, alle Positionen fordern eine Entwicklung heraus. Denn sie sind nicht nur kohärent miteinander, sondern auch mit den Tätigkeiten der untersuchenden Intelligenz und der reflektierenden Vernunft; weil diese Tätigkeiten kohärent sind mit dem schon Erreichten, ist ihr Vollzug möglich, weil das schon Erreichte noch unvollständig ist, ist eine weitere Entwicklung gefordert. (Fs)

449b Ein einfaches Beispiel mag den Sinn dieser abstrakten Aussagen erhellen. Gehen wir davon aus, daß der Kartesische Dualismus sowohl eine Basis-Position wie auch eine Basis-Gegenposition enthält. Die Basis-Position ist das cogito, ergo sum, und weil Descartes es nicht mit der erforderlichen Klarheit und Bestimmtheit [389] ausstattete, führt dies zu seiner Weiterentwicklung durch Fragen vom Typ wie "Was ist das Ich?", "Was heißt Denken?", "Was ist das Sein?", "Welches sind die Beziehungen zwischen ihnen?" Andererseits ist die Basis-Gegenposition die Behauptung der res extensa; sie wird als wirklich vorgestellt im Sinne einer Unterabteilung des "Jetzt-schon-da-draußen"; ihre Objektivität ist eine Angelegenheit der Extraversion; Erkennen ist nicht eine Angelegenheit der Untersuchung und der Reflexion. Diese Gegenposition fordert eine Umkehrung heraus, nicht nur wegen ihrer Verbindung mit der anderen erwähnten Komponente im Kartesischen Denken, sondern auch wenn sie für sich allein im Denken eines Subjektes gesetzt wird. So versuchte Hobbes Descartes' Dualismus dadurch zu überwinden, daß er der res cogitans nur dann Wirklichkeit zugestehen wollte, wenn sie ebenfalls als res extensa aufgefaßt würde, als ein anderer Fall nämlich von Materie in Bewegung. Hume überwand Hobbes dadurch, daß er alle Fälle des "Jetzt-schon-da-draußen Wirklichen" auf ebensoviele Fälle des Mannigfaltigen der Sinneseindrücke reduzierte, die durch Gewohnheiten und Meinungen verbunden sind. Die Intelligenz und Vernünftigkeit von Hume bei seiner Kritik waren nun aber offensichtlich sehr verschieden von der Erkenntnis, die er so erfolgreich kritisierte. Können wir nicht die Erkenntnis eher mit der kritisierenden Aktivität gleichsetzen als mit den kritisierten Materialien? Wenn dem so ist, dann wird der Kartesische Dualismus auf einer anderen Marschroute eliminiert. Man ist dann zurückgeworfen auf das denkende Subjekt, und am Ende dieser Rück-Wendung wird die eigene Philosophie nicht nur durch eine stärkere Bejahung der Grundposition bereichert, sondern auch durch eine explizite Verneinung der Basis-Gegenposition. (Fs)

449c Im Lichte dieser Dialektik wäre dann die historisch gegebene Reihe von Philosophien als eine Reihenfolge von Beiträgen zu einem einzigen aber komplexen Ziel zu betrachten. Bedeutsame Entdeckungen, die ja nicht das Prärogativ völlig erfolgreicher Philosophen sind, werden entweder als Positionen oder als Gegenpositionen ausgedrückt. Die Positionen aber fordern zu einer Entwicklung auf, und deshalb sollte die Reihenfolge der Entdeckungen, die als Positionen ausgedrückt werden, eine vereinheitlichte kumulative Struktur bilden, die durch die Hinzufügung jener Entdeckungen bereichert werden kann, die anfänglich als Gegenpositionen ausgedrückt wurden. Andererseits, weil die Gegenpositionen zu einer Umkehrung auffordern, sollte eine freie Entfaltung des menschlichen Denkens dahin tendieren, die Entdeckung von den Entstellungen ihres Urhebers zu trennen, indem sie die Voraussetzungen dieser Entdeckung untersucht und ihre Implikationen überprüft. (Fs)

450a Nun geht aber die Dialektik selbst von einer nicht unbedeutenden Vorannahme aus, daß nämlich die Erkenntnistheorie einen grundlegenden Einfluß auf Metaphysik, Ethik und theologische Aussagen ausübt. Diese Vorannahme verdient es, weiter untersucht zu werden. Im vorliegenden Kapitel soll deshalb der Versuch unternommen werden, die Metaphysik zu definieren, ihre Methode darzulegen und diese Methode dadurch zu klären, daß wir sie anderen Methoden gegenüberstellen. In den [390] nachfolgenden Kapiteln werden wir die Methode in einem Umriß der Metaphysik, einer Skizze der Ethik und einer Darstellung der transzendenten Erkenntnis zu artikulieren versuchen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Metaphysik; als das Ganze der Erkenntnis, aber nicht als ganze Erkenntnis

Kurzinhalt: Die Metaphysik entspringt dem reinen Erkenntnisstreben; sie ist frei von den Beschränkungen der partikulären Gesichtspunkte; sie unterscheidet die Positionen von den Gegenpositionen im Gesamt des Wissens; sie ist ein transformierendes Prinzip,

Textausschnitt: 2. Eine Definition der Metaphysik

450b Wie die Notion des Seins allen anderen Notionen zugrundeliegt, sie durchdringt und überschreitet, so ist auch die Metaphysik jene Abteilung der menschlichen Erkenntnis, welche allen anderen Abteilungen zugrundeliegt, sie durchdringt, transformiert und zu einer Einheit bringt. (Fs)

450c Sie liegt allen anderen Abteilungen zugrunde; denn ihre Prinzipien sind weder Termini noch Aussagen, weder Begriffe noch Urteile, sondern der unparteiische und uneigennützige Trieb des reinen Erkenntnisstrebens und seine Entfaltung im empirischen, intellektuellen und rationalen Bewußtsein des sich selbst bejahenden Subjektes. Aus der Entfaltung dieses Triebs gehen alle Fragen hervor, alle Einsichten, alle Formulierungen, alle Reflexionen und alle Urteile; und in diesem Sinne liegt die Metaphysik der Logik und der Mathematik, den verschiedenen Wissenschaften und der Myriade von Beispielen des Common Sense zugrunde. (Fs) (notabene)

450d Sie durchdringt alle anderen Abteilungen. Denn die anderen Abteilungen sind durch dieselben Prinzipien konstituiert wie die Metaphysik. Sie sind insofern Einzelabteilungen, als sie auf einen bestimmten Gesichtspunkt und auf ein bestimmtes Feld beschränkt sind. Doch trotz der Beschränkungen, die sie zu Spezialgebieten machen, gehen alle Abteilungen aus derselben Quelle hervor und suchen nach gegenseitiger Kompatibilität und Kohärenz, und in diesen beiden Hinsichten werden sie durchdrungen von der Metaphysik. (Fs)

451a Sie transformiert alle anderen Abteilungen. Das menschliche Bewußtsein ist ja polymorph, und deshalb unterliegt es der konstanten Gefahr, seine Entdeckungen nicht als Positionen zu formulieren, sondern als Gegenpositionen. Der Common Sense unterliegt einer dramatischen, einer egoistischen, einer Gruppen-, und einer allgemeinen Befangenheit, welche die komplexen theoretischen Probleme, in die er einbezogen ist und deren langfristige Konsequenzen, an denen er blind leidet, übersieht. Die Wissenschaftler sind nicht bloß Wissenschaftler, sondern auch Menschen des Common Sense; sie teilen die Befangenheit des Commons Sense, insofern ihre Spezialisierung diese nicht korrigiert; und insofern ihre Spezialisierung der Befangenheit des Common Sense entgegenläuft, finden sie sich uneins und in der Frage nach einer kohärenten Weltsicht verwirrt. Die Metaphysik entspringt dem reinen Erkenntnisstreben; sie ist frei von den Beschränkungen der partikulären Gesichtspunkte; sie unterscheidet die Positionen von den Gegenpositionen im Gesamt des Wissens; sie ist ein transformierendes Prinzip, das die Positionen zu vollerer Entwicklung auffordert und, indem sie die Gegenpositionen umkehrt, die Entdeckungen von den Fesseln befreit, in denen sie anfanglich formuliert wurden. (Fs)

451b Sie vereinheitlicht alle anderen Abteilungen. Denn alle anderen Abteilungen befassen sich mit partikulären Bereichen von Fragen; sie aber ist die ursprüngliche, [391] totale Frage und sie bewegt sich auf die totale Antwort zu, indem sie alle anderen Antworten transformiert und zusammenstellt. Die Metaphysik ist also das Ganze der Erkenntnis, aber nicht die ganze Erkenntnis. Ein Ganzes existiert nicht ohne seine Teile, noch unabhängig von ihnen, noch identisch mit ihnen. Und darum gilt es, daß die Prinzipien der Metaphysik zwar aller anderen Erkenntnis vorausgehen, aber die Erringung der Metaphysik der Eckstein ist, der auf den anderen Teilen beruht und sie zur Einheit eines Ganzen fugt. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Metaphysik; drei Stufen: latent, problematisch, explizit

Kurzinhalt: Auf einer ersten Stufe ist sie latent. Das empirische, das intellektuelle und das rationale Bewußtsein sind immanent und operativ in allem menschlichen Erkennen ...

Textausschnitt: 451c Von unserer Darstellung ergibt sich, wie es scheint, daß die Metaphysik auf drei Stufen oder in drei Formen existieren kann. Auf einer ersten Stufe ist sie latent. Das empirische, das intellektuelle und das rationale Bewußtsein sind immanent und operativ in allem menschlichen Erkennen; ihnen entspringen sowohl die verschiedenen Abteilungen des Wissens als auch die Versuche, die Gegenpositionen umzukehren und zu Kohärenz und Einheit zu gelangen. Aber die gemeinsame Quelle allen Erkennens ist nicht mit hinreichender Karheit und Präzision erkannt; das dialektische Prinzip der Transformation ist nicht eine wohlentwickelte Technik; und die Anstrengungen zu einer Vereinheitlichung bleiben zufällig und sprunghaft. (Fs)

452a Auf ihrer zweiten Stufe ist die Metaphysik problematisch. Die Notwendigkeit einer systematischen Anstrengung zu einer Vereinheitlichung wird empfunden; Studien über die Natur der Erkenntnis sind in Fülle vorhanden; aber diese Studien sind selbst in der Unordnung von Positionen und Gegenpositionen befangen, die aus dem polymorphen menschlichen Bewußtsein stammen. Auf ihrer dritten Stufe wird die Metaphysik explizit. Der latenten Metaphysik, die immer operativ ist, gelingt es, sich selbst auf den Begriff zu bringen, indem sie ihre Implikationen und Techniken ausarbeitet, und die Konzeption, die Implikationen und Techniken bejaht. (Fs)

452b Was ist diese explizite Metaphysik? Im vorliegenden Kapitel werden wir die Fragestellung dadurch vereinfachen, daß wir absehen von der komplizierten und umstrittenen Frage nach der Möglichkeit des menschlichen Erkennens von dem, was die Grenzen menschlichen Erfahrens übersteigt. Wir führen deshalb die Notion des proportionierten Seins ein. In seinem ganzen Umfang ist das Sein all das, was durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen zu erkennen ist. Aber das der menschlichen Erkenntnis proportionierte Sein soll nicht nur verstanden und bejaht, sondern auch erfahren werden. Das proportionierte Sein kann deshalb definiert werden als all das, was durch menschliche Erfahrung, intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen zu erkennen ist. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Explizite Metaphysik: heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins

Kurzinhalt: Nun wollen wir die These aufstellen, daß die explizite Metaphysik die Konzeption, Bejahung und Umsetzung der vollständigen, heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins ist.

Textausschnitt: 452c Nun wollen wir die These aufstellen, daß die explizite Metaphysik die Konzeption, Bejahung und Umsetzung der vollständigen, heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins ist. Bedeutung und Implikationen dieser Aussage sollen in der Folge untersucht werden. (Fs)

452d Erstens, was ist mit der vollständigen, heuristischen Struktur gemeint? Wir wollen die Antwort aus Einzelteilen zusammensetzen. Begriffliche Inhalte können ursprünglich oder abgeleitet sein. Die abgeleiteten werden mit Bezug auf ursprüngliche definiert; die ursprünglichen werden festgelegt, insofern Termini und Relationen aus einem einzelnen Verstehen hervorgehen, wobei die Relationen durch die Termini und die Termini durch die Relationen bestimmt werden. Nun gibt es aber vor dem Verstehen, das in Antworten mündet, die Fragen, die die Antworten vorwegnehmen; und, wie wir gesehen haben, kann eine solche Vorwegnahme systematisch zur Bestimmung von Antworten eingesetzt werden, die noch unbekannt sind. Denn während der Inhalt eines zukünftigen Erkenntnisaktes unbekannt ist, können die allgemeinen Charakteristika des Aktes nicht nur bekannt sein, sondern auch eine Prämisse liefern, die zum Akt selbst hinführt. Eine heuristische Notion ist dann also die Notion eines unbekannten Inhaltes und sie wird bestimmt durch die Vorwegnahme des Typs des Aktes, durch den das Unbekannte erkannt werden kann. Eine heuristische Struktur ist ein geordneter Inbegriff heuristischer Notionen. Eine vollständige heuristische Struktur schließlich ist der geordnete Inbegriff aller heuristischen Notionen. (Fs) (notabene)

453a Um dies zu erläutern, weisen wir auf die Definition des proportionierten Seins hin. Es ist, was immer durch menschliche Erfahrung, intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen erfaßt werden kann. Die Definition bestimmt keinerlei Inhalt von Erfahrung, Einsicht und Bejahung. Aber sie gibt einen geordneten Satz von Typen von Akten an, und sie impliziert, daß jegliches proportionierte Seiende durch einen derart geordneten Satz erkannt werden muß. Die Definition ist also ein Beispiel heuristischer Struktur; aber sie ist nicht ein Beispiel einer vollständigen heuristischen Struktur; denn sie schöpft nicht die ganzen Möglichkeiten des menschlichen Verstandes aus in seiner Vorwegnahme dessen, was zu erkennen ist. (Fs)

453b Zweitens, die implizite Metaphysik würde explizit werden, wenn die vollständige heuristische Struktur des proportionierten Seins begriffen, bejaht und umgesetzt würde. Denn die latente Metaphysik ist die dynamische Einheit des empirischen, intellektuellen und rationalen Bewußtseins, insofern es den anderen Abteilungen der Erkenntnis zugrundeliegt, sie durchdringt, transformiert und vereinheitlicht. Nun aber würde eine vollständige heuristische Struktur des proportionierten Seins diese Aufgaben in einer ausdrücklichen Art und Weise erfüllen. Als heuristische würde sie aller anderen Erkenntnis zugrundeliegen. Als die Fragen, die von anderen Wissenssparten beantwortet werden, würde sie die anderen Abteilungen durchdringen. Als dialektische würde sie diese Antworten transformieren. Als vollständige enthielte sie in sich die Ordnung, die die anderen Abteilungen der Erkenntnis zu einem einzigen intelligiblen Ganzen verbindet. (Fs)

453c Drittens, eine solche explizite Metaphysik wäre progressiv. Denn die heuristischen Notionen und Strukturen werden nicht dadurch entdeckt, daß man sich platonisch an einen früheren Zustand kontemplativer Glückseligkeit erinnert. Sie [393] resultieren aus der Findigkeit der handelnden menschlichen Intelligenz. Sie können nur erkannt werden durch eine Analyse der Handlungen, die vertraut geworden sind und einer Untersuchung unterzogen werden. Wie die anderen Erkenntnisabteilungen Fortschritte machen, indem sie neue Methoden entdecken, so schreitet die Metaphysik fort, indem sie diese Entdeckungen ihrer Darlegung der vollständigen heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins hinzufügt. (Fs)

453d Viertens, eine solche ausdrückliche Metaphysik wäre nuanciert. Sie wäre ein Ganzes aus vielen Teilen, und die verschiedenen Teile würden verschiedene Grade von Klarheit und Präzision, Evidenz und Unvermeidbarkeit aufweisen. Daraus folgt, daß nicht alle Teile mit demselben Grade der Überzeugung bejaht werden können, daß manche als gewiß, andere als höchst wahrscheinlich betrachtet, andere faute de mieux empfohlen, wieder andere als zweifelhaft und weiterer Bestätigung bedürftig angesehen werden können. (Fs)

454a Fünftens, eine solche Metaphysik wäre tatsachenbezogen. Das proportionierte Sein ist nicht das lediglich Mögliche und braucht auch nicht das absolut Notwendige zu sein. Es ist das, was tatsächlich ist, und die Wissenschaft, die es als Ganzes betrachtet, kann sich damit begnügen, das festzustellen, was in der Tat wahr ist. Weiter gilt, daß die empirischen Wissenschaften und die unzähligen Fälle des Common Sense nichts anderes beabsichtigen, als das zu erkennen, was in der Tat so ist; die Metaphysik ist nun aber ihre Vereinheitlichung; als Prinzip geht sie ihnen voraus; aber als realisierte folgt sie ihnen, geht aus ihnen hervor, hängt von ihnen ab; und so wird sie - wie diese auch - tatsachenbezogen sein. (Fs)

454b Sechstens, die Abhängigkeit einer solchen Metaphysik von den Wissenschaften und dem Common Sense würde nicht die Abhängigkeit der Konklusion von den Prämissen oder einer Wirkung von ihrer Ursache sein, sondern die Abhängigkeit eines erzeugenden, transformierenden und vereinheitlichenden Prinzips von den Materialien, die es erzeugt, transformiert und vereinheitlicht. Die Metaphysik stellt sich weder die Aufgabe, Wissenschaft zu entdecken, noch sie zu lehren; und sie unternimmt es auch nicht, den Common Sense zu entwickeln oder beizubringen; sie maßt sich auch nicht an, das Universum unabhängig von der Wissenschaft und dem Common Sense zu erkennen; was sie tun kann und in der Tat auch tut, ist, die Resultate solcher einzelnen Bemühungen zu übernehmen, sie zu einer kohärenten Form zu bringen, indem sie ihre Gegenpositionen umkehrt, und sie zu einer Einheit zu verbinden, insofern sie in ihnen die konkreten Verlängerungen der vollständigen heuristischen Struktur erkennt, welche sie selbst ist. (Fs)

454c Siebtens, eine solche Metaphysik würde nach Überwindung ihrer anfänglichen Schwierigkeiten stabil sein. Sie wäre offen für akzidentelle Modifikationen und Verbesserungen, aber sie wäre nicht den revolutionären Veränderungen unterworfen, welche die empirischen Wissenschaften kennen. Das liegt daran, daß eine [394] Wissenschaft für revolutionären Wandel soweit offen liegt, als es möglich ist, einen höheren Gesichtspunkt zu erreichen und infolgedessen die Inhalte ihrer Basistermini und -relationen zu verändern. Es ist aber nur innerhalb des Rahmens der untersuchenden und kritischen Intelligenz möglich, einen höheren Gesichtspunkt zu erreichen; es gibt im menschlichen Erkennen keinen Gesichtspunkt, der den Rahmen selbst überstiege und die intelligente Untersuchung und die kritische Reflexion durch irgendein Surrogat ersetzte. Nun aber ist der Gesichtspunkt der Metaphysik genau durch die untersuchende Intelligenz und die kritische Reflexion konstituiert. Außerdem kann ein höherer Gesichtspunkt die Basistermini und -relationen in ihrem Gehalt nur dann verändern, wenn dieser Gehalt ein genau bestimmtes Objekt des Denkens oder Bejahens ist. Die Aristotelische, Galileische, Newtonsche und Einsteinsche Erklärung des freien Falls von schweren Körpern sind alle für Revisionen offen, insofern sie alle bestimmte Inhalte besagen. Eine rein heuristische Erklärung hingegen ist der Revision nicht zugänglich. Man kann die heuristische Notion, daß die Natur des freien Falls das ist, was erkannt werden kann, wenn der freie Fall korrekt verstanden wird, nicht revidieren; denn diese heuristische Notion geht sowohl jeder bestimmten Erklärung voraus und folgt auch jeder und ist das Prinzip der Revision jeder Erklärung. Weil Metaphysik also die vollständige heuristische Struktur des proportionierten Seins ist, weil sie eine Struktur ist, die mit der forschenden Intelligenz und der kritischen Reflexion koinzidiert, ist Metaphysik nicht offen für einen revolutionären Wandel. (Fs) (notabene)

455a Achtens, die Metaphysik betrachtet das Sein primär unter dem Aspekt des Erklärtseins, schließt aber sekundär auch das Sein als Objekt der Beschreibung ein. Primär betrachtet sie das Sein deshalb unter dem Aspekt des Erklärtseins, weil sie eine heuristische Struktur ist, und eine heuristische Struktur richtet sich auf das, was erkannt werden kann, wenn man versteht. Sekundär schließt sie auch das Sein unter dem Aspekt des Beschriebenseins ein. Denn die Erklärung befaßt sich mit den Relationen der Dinge untereinander; die Beschreibung mit den Relationen der Dinge zu uns; und weil wir selbst Dinge sind, müssen die deskriptiven Relationen mit einigen erklärenden Relationen identisch sein. (Fs) (notabene)

455b Es ist darauf hinzuweisen, das der Einbezug deskriptiver Relationen in die Metaphysik implizit, allgemein, vermittelt und intellektuell ist. Er ist implizit, weil die Metaphysik explizit betrachtet die Dinge als erklärt. Er ist allgemein, weil die Metaphysik nur eben eine heuristische Struktur ist und deshalb nur in allgemeinster Weise zu bestimmen vermag, welche erklärenden Relationen identisch sind mit beschreibenden Relationen. Er ist vermittelt, insofern die Metaphysik Wissenschaften und Common Sense zusammenbringt und durch sie exakt zu bestimmen vermag, welche erklärenden Relationen auch deskriptiv sind. Schließlich ist der Einbezug intellektuell; denn er findet statt auf der Ebene der Intelligenz und des Urteils und nicht auf der Ebene der Sinneserfahrung. Genauso wie uns nicht wärmer oder kälter wird, wenn wir thermodynamische Gleichungen denken, so wird die [395] Metaphysik der Wärme die Sinnesempfindung von Wärme nicht produzieren können. Und ebenso wird keine Metaphysik, selbst wenn sie die mathematische Wissenschaft als oberflächlich betrachtet und versucht, die eigene spezifische Realität der Qualität aufrechtzuerhalten, einem Blinden die Sinneserfahrung von Farbe als gesehene oder einem Tauben die Sinneserfahrung eines Schalls als gehörter vermitteln können. (Fs)

456a Auf der Basis dieses letzten Punktes wird übrigens klar, daß metaphysische Versuche, die eigene spezifische Realität sinnlich wahrnehmbarer Qualität aufrechtzuerhalten, nichts aufrechtzuerhalten haben. Denn wenn die Metaphysik das sinnlich Wahrgenommene nicht als sinnlich Wahrgenommenes reproduzieren kann, dann kann sie die sinnlich wahrnehmbare Qualität nur dadurch aufrechterhalten, daß sie dieser eine entsprechende Intelligibilität zuweist. Nun aber bietet die mathematische Wissenschaft schon eine entsprechende Intelligibilität an, und wenn die Materialien der mathematischen Intelligibilität auch quantitativ, oder genauer ordnungsfähig sind, ist die mathematische Intelligibilität selbst nicht quantitativ. Der Unterschied zwischen einer trigonometrischen und einer Exponentialfunktion ist nicht ein Größenunterschied; er ist ein Unterschied in bezug auf das intelligible Gesetz, das für die Relationen zwischen kontinuierlich ordnungsfähigen Elementen gilt. (Fs)

456b Ein weitaus interessanteres Korollarium betrifft die zehn Kategorien, die gemeinhin Aristoteles zugeschrieben werden. Diese sind deskriptiv. Ein Zoologe wird Gattung, Art und Einzelbeispiel (Substanz) eines Tieres bestimmen, dessen Größe und Gewicht (Quantität), seine Farbe, Form, Eigenschaften, Neigungen (Qualität), seine Ähnlichkeiten und seine Unterschiede zu anderen Tieren (Relation), seine Leistungen und seine Empfänglichkeiten (actio und passio), sein Habitat und seine Veränderungen im Jahreskreislauf (Ort und Zeit), seine Fortbewegungsart und seine Art des Ruhens (Haltung), seine Ausstattung mit Dingen wie Klauen, Krallen, Hufe, Pelz, Federn und Hörnern (Habitus). Die Metaphysik aber, so wie wir sie hier auffassen, ist eine heuristische Struktur, die sich auf das Sein als erklärtes bezieht, und nur implizit, generell, vermittelt und intellektuell das Sein als beschriebenes einbezieht. Es folgt daraus, daß Aristoteles' zehn Kategorien, wenn sie sich auch auf das proportionierte Sein beziehen, trotzdem nicht zur konstitutiven Struktur der Metaphysik gehören1. (Fs)

456c Es ist damit wahrscheinlich genug gesagt worden, um unsere Notion von Metaphysik zu klären. Das unparteiische und uneigennützige Erkenntnisstreben und seine Ausfaltung in der Untersuchung und Reflexion machen nicht allein eine Notion des Seins aus, sondern erlegen den menschlichen Erkenntnisakten auch eine normative Struktur auf. Eine solche Struktur liefert die Relationen, mithilfe derer die unbekannten Inhalte der Akte heuristisch definiert werden können. Diese heuristische Struktur ist immanent und operativ in allem menschlichen Erkennen, doch (396) ist sie anfanglich latent, und die Polymorphie des menschlichen Bewußtseins macht sie problematisch. Trotzdem kann sie erfaßt, bejaht und umgesetzt werden, und aus dieser Durchführung ergeben sich eine Umwandlung und eine Integration der Wissenschaften und der Myriade von Fällen des Common Sense. Erkennen ist aber das Sein erkennen. Aus diesem Grund ist die vollständige heuristische Struktur des v-v' proportionierten Seins, als durch die Wissenschaften und den Common Sense bestimmte, eine Erkenntnis der organisierenden Struktur des proportionierten Seins. Wie schon gesagt wurde, ist eine solche Metaphysik progressiv, nuanciert, tatsachenbezogen, formell von der Erkenntnistheorie und materiell von den Naturwissenschaften und dem Common Sense abhängig, stabil, und in ihrer Aussicht erklärend. (Fs)

457a Es verbleibt die Klärung, die aus einer Methodendiskussion resultiert, und dieser wenden wir nun unsere Aufmerksamkeit zu. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche Relationen: voneinander unterschieden - identisch mit der göttlichen Substanz?; Identität: Relative - Absolute; Unterschied: logisch - real; real und begrifflich - real und nicht begrifflich; Aristoteles: Identität: Bewegung: actio, passio

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 6 - Is it possible for the real divine relations to be really distinct from one another and really identical with one and the same divine substance?

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 6
Is it possible for the real divine relations to be really distinct from one another and really identical with one and the same divine substance?

279d It seems impossible, since two things that are the same as a third thing are identical with one another. Hence, if real relations are really distinct from one another, they cannot be really identical with one and the same divine substance. If, however, they are really identical with one and the same divine substance, they cannot be really distinct from one another. (Fs)

281a But against this is the fact that the Father is not the Son, and nevertheless one and the same God is the Father and is the Son. (Fs)

In replying to this question, we must point out that it has two aspects. The first aspect is logical, in that an appeal is made to the principle of compared identity, namely, that two that are identical with a third are identical with each other. The other aspect is real, since absolutes and relatives are not real in the same way and are not really distinct from each other in the same way. (Fs)

281b As far as the logical aspect is concerned, the formality of the principle of identity is the same as that of the principle of contradiction; for the principle of identity is simply the positive statement of that whose opposite is negated by the principle of contradiction. Now all agree that it is illegitimate to apply the principle of contradiction whenever the question is about either different things or about the same thing under different aspects; therefore, the only thing denied by the principle of contradiction is that the same thing in the same way - the same both really and conceptually - both is and is not. It is similarly illegitimate to apply the principle of identity whenever the question is about different things or about the same thing under different aspects; therefore, the only thing that falls under the principle of identity is the same thing under the same aspect - the same thing both really and conceptually. (Fs)

281c In view of this it is quite easy to reply to the above objection, since it incorrectly appeals to the principle of compared identity. The real divine relations are identical with the divine substance in reality but not conceptually. Therefore the principle of identity does not apply, since it regards only those things that are the same not only really but also conceptually. (Fs)

Since, however, a strictly logical solution can seem to be merely an evasion if there is no added explanation about the things themselves, we must also consider how the distinction we have made applies in different cases. (Fs)

281d To begin, then, if an absolute, A, is really the same as an absolute, C, and an absolute, B, is likewise really the same as an absolute, C, then the distinction between A and C and between B and C can be only verbal: for example, A is this vestment, B is this garment, and C is this tunic, where 'vestment,' 'garment,' and 'tunic' are but different nouns for a thing that is entirely the same. This is so because, if two absolutes are really the same, there is no intelligibility in one that is not identical with the intelligibility of the other. And when they are the same both in reality and in intelligibility, they can be distinct only verbally. For this reason, if only absolutes are being considered, the distinction we have made between 'really and conceptually' and 'really but not conceptually' is quite meaningless. (Fs)

283a Next, if a relative, A, is really identical with an absolute, C, and a relative, B, is really identical with the same absolute, C, the distinction between A and C or between B and C cannot be merely verbal. For an absolute is such that it contains and encloses its essential meaning within its own reality, whereas a relative is such that by reason of its essential meaning it goes beyond its own reality to look towards another. Therefore, an absolute and a relative are not only verbally distinct but are also necessarily distinct in intelligibility, since it is impossible that the same meaning be both totally contained within its own reality and at the same time look towards another reality beyond its own. This is why when two relatives are related to the same absolute, our distinction between 'really and conceptually' and 'really but not conceptually' necessarily signifies not only different words for the same reality but also different intelligibilities of the same reality. (Fs) (notabene)
283b The classic example of this is the real identity that Aristotle affirmed between motion and action and between motion and passion. He defines action as 'the act of a thing considered as being from this thing,' that is, an act of an agent considered as proceeding from the agent, and passion he defines as 'the act of a thing considered as being in this thing,' that is, the act of a recipient considered as being received in the recipient. And since the act that proceeds from the agent is the same as that which is received in the recipient, namely, the motion produced by the agent and received in the recipient, it follows that both action and passion are really identical with motion. One can see from this example why this theorem is apparently so difficult for so many. For 'action' and 'passion' add to motion the relations 'as from this' and 'as in this'; but this added intelligibility is far different from the intelligibility of the motion of an absolute, and therefore to many it seems extremely difficult to see that such diverse intelligibilities of the absolute and of relatives are present in one and the same reality. (Fs) (notabene)

283c Finally, when two relatives are really identical with the same absolute, not only must they be distinct in intelligibility from the absolute but also they can be really distinct from each other. For, as we demonstrated above, relations that are both real and mutually opposed are necessarily really distinct from one another. But relations that are really identical with the same absolute are real relations. Therefore, if their intelligible conceptions are opposed to one another, such relations are really distinct from one another. (Fs)

283d This surely is the key to the solution of our whole problem. Absolutes are such that there is no real distinction between them unless the same conception can be posited of one and not of the other. In the case of relatives, on the other hand, there is the further fact that they are really distinct from one another not only by the positing and non-positing of the same conception but also by the mutual opposition of diverse conceptions. This opposition, as real, depends upon the reality of the relations, and this reality can be had from one and the same absolute. But this same opposition, as opposition, depends solely upon the conceptions. For relations are opposite inasmuch as each is the term of the other, and each is the term of the other not because the relations are real but because their conceptions regard one another. Hence, what are identical with the same third are not necessarily identical with one another. For two relatives can be really identical with the same third; but if they are really identical, they are distinguished from the absolute at least by an intelligible conception. And if their conceptions are such that they are mutually opposed, the relatives must also necessarily be really distinct from one another.1 (Fs)

285a Still, we must admit that there is no example of this to be found in creation. Action and passion in the Aristotelian sense, which are really identical with motion, are not mutually opposed, since action regards the agent and passion the recipient. In fact, since 'from the agent' and 'in the recipient' pertain to one undivided intelligibility, they stand in a single order and constitute but one order or one real relation. (Fs)

285b If, however, action is understood as a relation of the agent to the recipient and passion as a relation of the recipient to the agent, then indeed we have relations that are real and mutually opposed. Nevertheless, action and passion understood in this way cannot be really identical with the same third, since action supposes act, passion supposes potency, and the same reality in the same respect cannot be both in act and in potency. (Fs) (notabene)

Only in God, then, are to be found relations that are real, mutually opposed, and really identical with the same absolute, inasmuch as through one infinite act there are in God the principle of the word, the word, and proceeding love. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relation: Vater - Sohn: identisch mit Gott real, aber nicht begrifflich; Beispiel: sterblich - unsterblich, Vater - Sohn

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 6/2 - Is it possible for the real divine relations to be really distinct from one another ...; we grant that what are identical with one third thing both really and conceptually are identical with one another; but what are identical with one ...

Textausschnitt: 285c The objection that was put at the beginning of this question can be stated as follows, together with the replies and the further objections. (Fs)

What are identical with one third thing are identical with one another; but the Father and the Son are identical with the one God, and therefore are identical with one another. (Fs)

In response, we grant that what are identical with one third thing both really and conceptually are identical with one another; but what are identical with one third thing in reality but not conceptually are not identical with one another. And we deny that the Father and the Son are identical with the one God both in reality and conceptually; we do concede that they are identical with the one God in reality but not conceptually. (Fs)
(notabene)

287a It might be urged that a conceptual distinction can contribute nothing to making a real distinction. (Fs)
In response, we grant that through a merely verbal distinction, nothing is produced pertaining to a real distinction. We deny that nothing is produced pertaining to a real distinction when diverse intelligible conceptions, namely, that of the absolute and that of the relative, are verified in the same reality. (Fs)
287b It might be urged further that there cannot be verified in the same reality intelligible conceptions so diverse as to be able to ground a real distinction. (Fs)

In response, we grant that in the same reality there cannot be verified intelligible conceptions so diverse as to be able to ground a real distinction between absolutes, or a real distinction between relatives that are not mutually opposed; but we deny that diverse intelligible conceptions verified in the same reality cannot ground a real distinction between relatives that are mutually opposed. The reason is that both absolutes and relatives not mutually opposed are really distinguished only through affirmation and nonaffirmation of the same conception, and obviously a single conception cannot be simultaneously affirmed and not affirmed by reason of the same reality. On the other hand, we have shown that real and mutually opposed relatives are really distinct by reason of their mutual opposition; and there is no contradiction in the fact that mutually opposed relatives are verified in the same reality. (Fs) (notabene)

287b It might be urged further that there cannot be verified in the same reality intelligible conceptions so diverse as to be able to ground a real distinction. (Fs)

In response, we grant that in the same reality there cannot be verified intelligible conceptions so diverse as to be able to ground a real distinction between absolutes, or a real distinction between relatives that are not mutually opposed; but we deny that diverse intelligible conceptions verified in the same reality cannot ground a real distinction between relatives that are mutually opposed. The reason is that both absolutes and relatives not mutually opposed are really distinguished only through affirmation and nonaffirmation of the same conception, and obviously a single conception cannot be simultaneously affirmed and not affirmed by reason of the same reality. On the other hand, we have shown that real and mutually opposed relatives are really distinct by reason of their mutual opposition; and there is no contradiction in the fact that mutually opposed relatives are verified in the same reality. (Fs) (notabene)

287c Still, one might object, at least there is no concrete possibility for mutually opposed relatives to be verified in the same reality. For there is no instance of this whatever in creation; and in God this can be conceived only by positing a real procession in which the really same act somehow or other originates from itself. (Fs)
To this we answer that, although there is in the created world no instance that has been proven or is perfectly understood by us of mutually opposed relations being verified in the same reality, nevertheless such an instance is to be believed with certitude from divine revelation, and is to some extent understood by us. (Fs)

For from faith we are certain that the same God is Father and Son, and that the Father is not the Son. (Fs)
287d We understand this to a certain extent through the psychological analogy. For the present problem is but a transposition of the problem with which we began, namely, how the Son is both from himself and not from himself, or how there is present both the reality of the emanation and the consubstantiality of that which emanates. For if these two are present, there are also two real, mutually opposed ... relations, really distinct from each other and yet identical with the same divine substance. (Fs) (notabene)

287e As to what the objector adds about an act emerging from the same act, one must note the difference between the statement of the Council of Nicea and that of the Fourth Lateran. The phrase in Nicea, 'God from God,' must be understood to mean that God the Son is from God the Father, in which the name of the divine essence is expressed concretely, without prescinding from the personal relations. But in the statement of the Fourth Lateran Council, '... that reality does not generate nor is it generated nor does it proceed,' the expression 'that reality' is the divine substance, essence, or nature as conceptually distinct from the personal relations. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität, Relation; Vaterschaft, Sohnschaft; Relation "in" und "zu" (being in - being to); göttliche Relationen: real unterschieden voneinander, begrifflich unterschieden von Gottes Wesen

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 7 - What is the value of the distinction between 'being in' and 'being to'?

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 7
What is the value of the distinction between 'being in' and 'being to'?

289c The category of relation differs from the other categories in that relations are distinguished into real relations and conceptual relations. There is no similar distinction for substances or qualities or other predicaments. (Fs)

289d Moreover, a composite concept is reduplicated in two ways: for a real relation can be considered either as it is a relation or as it is real. These two reduplications are usually termed 'being to' and 'being in.' For just as it is proper to a substance to be through itself, and just as it is proper to an accident in the strict sense to be in another, so it is proper to a relation as a relation to be to another. Hence, a real relation as a relation is said 'to be to.' Furthermore, since in general all relations are accidents, they have that reality that is proper to accidents, namely, 'to be in,' and therefore a real relation as real is said 'to be in.' (Fs) (notabene)

291a From this we conclude that 'being to' and 'being in' are not to be conceived after the manner of essence and existence so as to form a whole out of parts, but are to be conceived as two aspects of one real relation. (Fs)

291a This distinction, based on reduplication, is valuable in two ways, and has one danger. (Fs)

291b It is valuable, first, because the real distinctions among the divine persons arise, not from the affirmation and nonaffirmation of the same formality, but in the single real affirmation of mutually opposed relations. In other words, the real distinction of the persons arises proximately from one 'being-to' opposing another 'being-to.'

Second, it is valuable because of the fact that the Son has all that the Father has, except paternity. The Son is not really distinct from God; God is not really distinct from the Father; yet the Son is really distinct from the Father, because the distinction of persons is by reason of the mutual opposition of one 'being-to' and another 'being-to.' The same value is clear from the fact that '... God ... is not less in each one [of the persons] nor greater in all three [together]; for there is no less reality when any one of the persons is individually called God, nor is there more when all three persons are declared to be one God' (DB 279, DS 529, ND 312). That is to say, the distinction of the persons is grounded not on real contradictory affirmations but on the mutual opposition of one 'being-to' and another 'being-to.'

291c The one danger is that one may lose sight of the fact that 'being to' is only a reduplicated aspect of a real relation, and this occurs more easily when the discussion concerns a mystery. In fact, there would be no mystery of the Trinity at all if three merely conceptual beings were attributed to one pure infinite act. This seems sometimes to be supposed, when difficulties and problems are solved too neatly and efficiently. (Fs) (notabene)

291d Hence, it is most important to note that we apprehend the same divine reality that is both truly one and truly threefold according to two conceptually distinct aspects, so that according to the absolute aspect there is one God and according to the relative aspect there are three subsistent relations really distinct from one another. The three relations, therefore, are no less real than the one essence, since the relations as well as the essence are equally present in the supreme divine reality. And yet there is no real distinction between essence and each real relation, since there is only a conceptual distinction between the absolute and the relative aspects of God. (Fs) (notabene)

293a Accordingly, when a real relation is reduplicated to consider a real relation as relation (being to) and a real relation as real (being in), it is entirely true that the real distinction between the relations arises proximately from 'being to.' But it is equally true that the same distinction between the relations would not be real but only conceptual if there were only the 'being to' without a real 'being in'; for if they are not real, then mutually opposed relations are not really distinct from one another. (Fs)

Further, it is entirely true that the Son has all that the Father has, except paternity, since filiation is really identical with deity and deity with paternity. But it is no less true that both paternity and filiation are real, and that the distinction between real paternity and real filiation is a real distinction. (Fs)

293b Again, it is entirely true that God is not diminished in each or increased in the Three, because the whole divine reality is possessed by each, and nothing more than the whole divine reality is possessed by the Three together. But it is equally true that the three real relations, which are all really distinct from one another, are conceptually distinct from the divine essence. (Fs)

Having understood this, one can easily see the value and at the same time the danger of this distinction. Since truth is one thing and the whole truth is another, it is one thing to throw more light on the divine unity and quite another to throw more light simultaneously on both the divine unity and the divine trinity. The former is what this distinction does, and therefore it has a very great value. But no short and simple distinction can achieve the latter, since we are dealing with a mystery hidden in God. Therefore, since we confess both trinity in unity and unity in trinity, we may by no means argue on the basis of this distinction between 'being to' and 'being in' as if the whole doctrine of the Trinity were contained in this distinction alone. Although this distinction is true, although it is most useful, and although there is no danger in it as long as abuse is avoided, still abuse creeps in as soon as one supposes, even implicitly, that any partial truth is the whole truth.1 (Fs)

Fußnote "whole truth":

29 [Lonergan's remark in this question that difficulties and problems concerning the unity and the threefoldness of God are solved 'too neatly and efficiently' through the use of the distinction between 'being in' and 'being to' is an obvious reference to some of the trinitarian literature with which he was familiar. In that literature, it seems, the distinction occasioned a perhaps unwitting semirationalist distortion of trinitarian theology, of the kind condemned by Vatican 1. Accordingly, Lonergan has a twofold concern in this question. First, he is concerned to emphasize that, while the distinction based on the reduplication of the composite concept 'real relation' does not capture the whole truth of the doctrine of the Trinity, it is a legitimate, valuable, and fruitful instrument of understanding when judiciously employed. For with the context of the preceding discussion, the distinction facilitates one in holding together in imperfect understanding and affirming that in God there is both real trinity in unity and real unity in trinity. At the same time, however, he is at pains to warn against the semirationalist distortion of the distinction that overlooks or forgets that 'being to' is only a reduplicated aspect of a real relation.]

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Große - kleine begriffliche Unterscheidung zw. göttlicher Substanz und Relationen; Lösung: Unterschied zw. Philosophie und Theologie im Erkennen Gottes

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 8 -- Is it by a major or a minor conceptual distinction that the divine substance is distinguished from the divine relations and, conversely, ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 8
Is it by a major or a minor conceptual distinction that the divine substance is distinguished from the divine relations and, conversely, that the divine relations are distinguished from the divine substance?

Terminology
295a distinct: one is not the other. (Fs)

conceptual distinction: the concept of one is not the concept of the other.

major or adequate conceptual distinction: the concept of one does not actually express the concept of the other, even implicitly.

minor or inadequate conceptual distinction: at least implicitly the concept of one actually expresses the concept of the other.

substance: that to which it is proper to be through itself.

divine substance: pure act.

relation: the order of one to another; that to which it is proper to be to another.

divine relations: paternity, filiation, active spiration, passive spiration. (Fs)

Opinions
295b Among those who defend a major distinction in both cases are Ferrariensis, Toletus, Molina, Vasquez, Billot, Buonpensiere, and Boyer.1 (Fs)

Others hold for a minor distinction in both cases: perhaps Cajetan, certainly John of St Thomas, and Galtier.2
Still others, such as Suarez and Ruiz, hold that the divine substance is distinct from the relations by a major distinction, but the relations are distinct from the substance by a minor distinction. (Fs)

295c Note that this is an open question, lacking any theological note. (Fs)

Solution
297a Since every concept proceeds from an act of understanding and expresses what is grasped by understanding, the determination of what is expressed in a concept proceeds remotely from the object of understanding and proximately from the act of understanding itself. (Fs) (notabene)

Moreover, when different authors affirm that concepts are different, their acts of understanding are no doubt different, as well as the formal objects of these acts. (Fs)

297b The present question, therefore, seems to require only that we explain from which acts of understanding concerning which formal objects the different concepts of different authors proceed. (Fs)

297c First of all, then, there is the case in which the formal object is the divine reality itself as apprehended by faith and by reason enlightened by faith. This object is, indeed, a rationally conscious infinite act that is conceived by us according to the two formalities of substance and relation. In speaking of an infinite act of existence, of understanding, of conceiving, of judging, and of loving, we are referring to the divine substance. But in speaking of two rationally conscious emanations, namely, of word from speaker and of love from both, we are referring to the divine relations. From this it is clear that the relations are distinct from the substance by a minor distinction, since the rationally conscious relations cannot be had without an act of understanding, of speaking, and of loving. The substance is similarly distinct from the relations by a minor distinction; for although the natural light of human reason is not capable of grasping that an infinite act of understanding is necessarily such that it utter a word and through the uttered word spirate love, nevertheless reason enlightened by faith understands this to some extent, and in accordance with this limited understanding it does not conceive the divine substance without also at least implicitly affirming the intellectual emanations and the consequent relations. (Fs) (notabene)

297c In contrast, there is the case where the formal object is the divine reality not as understood and conceived in theology, but as understood and conceived under the wholly generic concepts of substance and relation. Now, the generic concept of substance is the concept of that to which it is proper to be through itself, and the generic concept of relation is the concept of that to which it is proper to be to another. Since the concept of substance does not actually indicate 'other,' even implicitly, it is set off from the concept of relation by a major conceptual distinction; and this major distinction is not denied by the fact that this concept taken precisely is applied to the divine reality. Similarly, the generic concept of relation explicitly indicates only that to which it is proper to be to another; and although from this concept alone one can conclude to a subject, another premise is certainly required to demonstrate that the subject is a substance. For among creatures that which is referred to another by a relation may be not only a substance but also an accident (such as a word related to the act of understanding, or love to both), or an intrinsic principle of being (such as potency related to act, and so on), or a conceptual being (such as difference related to genus); but in God, the subject that is referred to another by a relation is not the divine substance, [eg: rein unter dem Formalobjekt einer Philosphie] since the divine substance does not generate and therefore is not related to the Son, is not generated and therefore is not related to the Father, does not spirate and therefore is not related to the Spirit, and is not spirated and therefore is not related to the Father and the Son together. (Fs)

299a It is clear from this how all the opinions of the theologians have some foundation. Those who hold for a minor conceptual distinction from both sides argue from a theological understanding of the divine reality itself. But those who defend a major conceptual distinction from both sides argue from systematically defined generic concepts. Finally, those who follow a middle course seem to base their judgments on the stronger arguments of other theologians. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Person; Frage: Augustinus; Definitionen: Boethius, Thomas -> Übereinstimmung in der Frage

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 10/1 -What should be understood by the word 'person'?;
What was new in the definitions of Boethius, Richard, and St Thomas is that sometimes they asked not the particular question, Three what? or, What is a divine person?

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 10 What should be understood by the word 'person'?

309a From what we have said, it is clear that there are in God three real relations that are subsistent and really distinct from one another, namely, the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. Now we ask whether these relations are truly persons in the proper sense. The first thing to determine, therefore, is what is to be understood by the word 'person.'

309b There are five ways in which this question is answered. First, it was observed that some common word was needed, so that those whom we singly call the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit, we may speak of in common as persons. As St Augustine put it, 'When we ask, Three what? or Three who? we are led to find some special or general word under which we may include all three, and none has occurred to us ...'1 '[Human limitation] asked what it should call the Three. And it replied, "substances" or "persons." By these names it did not wish to convey any idea of diversity, but it wished to avoid any idea of singleness, so that not only would unity be understood by speaking of one essence, but also trinity would be understood by speaking of three substances or three persons.'2 (Fs)

309c Second, after this answer, definitions were formulated, most notably that of Boethius, 'individual substance of a rational nature,' that of Richard of St Victor, 'incommunicable existence of the divine nature,' and that of St Thomas, 'distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature.'
309d Third, theories that were more or less metaphysical were proposed by Scotus, Capreolus, Cajetan, Suarez, Tiphanus, and possibly others. (Fs)

309e Fourth, it seemed that the person should be said to be consciousness, or conscious individuality, or a distinct center of consciousness, or some other psychological reality. (Fs)

309f Fifth, and finally, the person is explained in such a way that it has to be apprehended concretely. Thus, a person is one with whom personal relationships are entered into, or one to whom one can say 'you,' or whatever is simply distinguished from the category of 'things,' or one who is by nature ordered to communication with other persons, and so on. These, however, are not to be understood as definitions but rather as descriptions of what everyone should find by consulting his or her own personal life experience. (Fs)

311a The only unity in all these proposals lies in the question itself. An example of this sort of unity is that, while for Aristotle fire is one of the four elements, now it is understood as a chemical reaction. Yet, however divergent these answers are, both Aristotle and modern scientists have the same thing in mind when they ask what fire is. In asking this question, both in some way have in mind the same nature that is to be understood in specifically the same sensible data. When this question, therefore, this dynamic orientation of the wondering and inquiring mind, is brought to bear upon determinate sensible data or upon determinate truths, it constitutes a heuristic structure,3 which remains somehow one whatever answers are given. (Fs) (notabene)

311b Now if this is granted, then one can understand how the five ways mentioned above are related. (Fs)

With St Augustine the notion of divine person was the question itself, Three what? Here we have already a heuristic structure, but there was apparently no answer yet, only perplexity. (Fs) (notabene)
What was new in the definitions of Boethius, Richard, and St Thomas is that sometimes they asked not the particular question, Three what? or, What is a divine person? but the general question, What is a person?4 (Fs)

311c Further, since these definitions cannot be clearly and distinctly compared to one another unless by raising metaphysical questions one determines what an intellectual nature is, what a substance is, what an individual is, what existence is, what is meant by 'incommunicable,' by 'subsistent,' and by 'distinct,' it is not surprising that Scotus, Capreolus, Cajetan, Suarez, and Tiphanus took the further step of expounding the meaning of person in terms of metaphysical theories. (Fs)

But there were many such metaphysical theories, and person was not the only disputed notion. So philosophers turned to gnoseological questions as being better known quoad nos; and since it was the custom to explain everything else in psychological terms, it was considered quite inappropriate to explain the person in any way other than psychologically. (Fs)

311d Since there was as great a proliferation of gnoseological as of metaphysical theories, in recent times thinkers have decided to cease all speculation and return to concrete life. The more people 'exist'5 as human beings and as persons in the true sense, the more clearly they will perceive how great is the difference in the meanings of different pronouns. For one who is able to say 'I' and one who can be addressed as 'you' are certainly persons; but whatever is referred to as 'it' is not a person but only a thing. This is open to explanation in many different ways, since it means describing the concrete personal experience of life that people have. (Fs)

313a This being the case, it is clear that besides the multitude of opinions about what a person is, there exists a single heuristic structure that has been developing over the course of time. St Augustine's particular question is not left aside when we ask about the person in a general sense. Nor do we overlook the various definitions of person when we inquire more deeply into the metaphysical foundations. Nor does the knowledge of things through the ultimate causes of being exclude a study of conscious being. Nor does a general consideration of conscious being prevent us from investigating being that is conscious of itself in its concrete relationships. Accordingly, we will call the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit persons: persons in name, persons by definition, persons by reason of metaphysical constitution, persons by reason of consciousness, and persons by reason of relations both among themselves and to us. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Person, Bewusstsein: existentialistische Auffassung - im Medium der Wahrheit; Verfehlen der Wahrheit (3 Stufen): Sensismus, Empirismus, Positivismus, Pragmatismus, Idealismus, Phänomenologie; Existenz

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 10/2 -What should be understood by the word 'person'?; ... at one time it takes the form of materialism, then of sensism, third of empiricism, fourth of phenomenalism, fifth of positivism, and sixth of pragmatism. Others, however...

Textausschnitt: 313b However, a more detailed clarification is needed here, since a heuristic structure generally develops in such a way that it not only leads to a fuller knowledge of the truth but also betrays and manifests the darkened mind of fallen humanity. For this reason it seems worth while to say something about individual stages in the process. (Fs)

313c First, then, although Boethius's definition can be correctly explained,1 still this is not easy to do. For if a person is an individual substance of a rational nature, the three persons would seem to be three substances. But we admit only one substance in God, and therefore this definition as it is worded creates more difficulties than it solves. The definition of Richard of St Victor seems to have only a certain historical importance, and so we have felt it sufficient to discuss it in a related question about the meaning of incommunicability.2 Therefore we are left with St Thomas's definition, which we have expounded at greater length elsewhere.3 (Fs)

315a Next, although there has been a great deal of disagreement about the constitution of a finite person,4it is scarcely possible to dispute the constitution of an infinite person, since the simplicity of a divine person is so great that the essence, the act of existence, the relation, the subsistence, the property, and the notional act of the same divine person are one and the same. Therefore, since the realities are beyond dispute, the only disagreements are about the formality of divine person, and we have judged it more convenient to setlle these in related questions. (Fs)

315b Third, the question about consciousness is more profound, more subtle, and more serious. Its seriousness is obvious: if there are as many persons as there are consciousnesses, then either three persons would mean that there are three gods or else God would be one person because of divine unity.5 There is a similar case in Christology, where either the oneness of the person leads to monophysitism or the duality of natures leads to Nestorianism; nor does kenoticism provide a valid third way. (Fs)

315c The subtlety of the question arises from the very nature of consciousness. It is one thing to be conscious, but it is quite another to know, through knowledge in the proper sense, that one is conscious. To be conscious belongs to everyone, for consciousness is simply the presence of the mind to itself. This self-presence is effected by the very fact that our sensitive and intellectual nature is actuated by both apprehending and desiring. It does not matter what object is apprehended or desired, since we as conscious subjects consciously apprehend and desire different things. Nor do we become conscious by adverting to ourselves, since consciousness is on the side of the adverting subject and not on the side of the object adverted to. But when this adverting to ourselves is done, we begin the second step, namely, knowing that we are conscious. For one who is conscious places oneself on the side of the object inasmuch as one understands and conceives consciousness and truly affirms that one is conscious. Therefore, a conscious subject and the consciousness of the subject precede and accompany all understanding and conception and affirmation of oneself as conscious, and remain when these operations regarding oneself are omitted. But unless we define what consciousness is, and unless we truly affirm that we are conscious in the sense of this definition, we do not attain knowledge, properly speaking, of our own consciousness.6 (Fs)

317a In addition to the subtlety of the question there is its profundity. Knowledge that is properly human is achieved in three steps: first, we experience externally or internally; second, through inquiry into the data of sense or of consciousness, we understand and conceive; and third, by reflecting and pondering the evidence we affirm what is true, and through truth as through a medium we know being. But it is one thing to complete the process of knowing through these three steps and quite another to come to know by this same three-step process that our knowledge is achieved in these three steps. For this reason, in completing these three steps, those who come to know only the first step join the ranks of the empiricists, who do not acknowledge that there is anything we can know besides external sensible data and an internal empirical 'ego.' Despite the fact that this position is manifestly in conflict with their own intelligence, nevertheless this same position is defended in many different ways: at one time it takes the form of materialism, then of sensism, third of empiricism, fourth of phenomenalism, fifth of positivism, and sixth of pragmatism. Others, however, in completing this three-step cognitional process, do so in such a way that they clearly and distinctly grasp not only the first step but also the second. And since the same or similar data of sense and data of consciousness are wont to be understood by different persons in different ways, there are some that are called relativists, who cannot consider any intelligible to be absolutely true, or immanentists, for whom truth, through which alone being is attained, is unknown, or idealists, who hold that nothing can be true except a perfect understanding of all intelligibles, or instrumentalists, who hold that any intelligible is true only as long as it leads to successful practical results, and so forth. Others, finally, not only know by the three-step cognitional process but also grasp the nature of those three steps. They are the realists, who affirm that being that is proportionate to our knowing is composed of potency, form, and act, just as our knowing is achieved through experience, understanding, and judging. (Fs) (notabene)

317b In view of this, one who discusses human consciousness will easily fall into error unless he or she has a thorough grasp of virtually all philosophies, discerning what is true from what there is false in them. But if it is so easy to err regarding human consciousness, falsity will even more easily enter in when one proceeds to conceive divine consciousness by analogy with the human. So it was not unreasonable for theologians to remain silent rather than to err on the question of divine consciousness. (Fs) (notabene)

319a In our day, however, this question has become much more acute. For, on the one hand, the deepest meaning of person seems to be more clearly understood: what is said to be proper to and distinctive of a person is that a person is what one has understood one can be and what one has willed to become. This understanding and becoming of the person is for all practical purposes what is meant by Existenz.7 It is not achieved in some ideal isolation, but in the concrete circumstances of human living and together with other persons. On the other hand, while this conception of the human person is true, it is not easy to take the next step and conceive analogically a divine person. Indeed, and far more serious, there is such an emphasis on the subject and such disdain for anything that has the formality of object that this doctrine is incompatible with both faith and traditional theology. Since our faith is an assent to the true (DB 1789, 1791, DS 3008, 3010, ND 118, 120), so that through the mediation of the true we arrive at the divine reality that has been revealed to us, one cannot oppose the whole notion of object and of objectivity without at the same time rejecting our faith itself as understood by Vatican I. Moreover, since the Catholic theological tradition is founded upon truth and being, to despise the object is necessarily to despise traditional theology as well. (Fs)

319b Accordingly, since we ought neither to be ignorant of nor to disregard more recent notions,8 we hold that true contemporary opinions about the person should be separated from those that proceed from philosophical empiricism or immanentism. For a correct understanding concerning the meaning of person is not based on a position that fails to go beyond experience and understanding and to rise, to the third step in human knowing. In fact, to the extent that one ignores rational reflection, the grasp of the virtually unconditioned,9 the autonomous intellectual necessity whereby the uttering of a true word emanates from reflective understanding, and the similarly autonomous intellectual necessity consequent upon it, in which moral obligation and the spirating of volition consist - to that extent one surely ignores those features that are most proper to and distinctive of a person. (Fs)

319c Again, although we speak of objectivity and object in many different ways in keeping with the various steps in which human knowledge is achieved, all other meanings are reducible to this principal one, that objectivity is simply truth, and 'object' denotes only that which is known through the medium of the true. No one who has grasped that the supreme perfection of a person consists in the intellectual emanations in the realms of truth and goodness can reject this meaning. Nor is any other meaning of objectivity or of object required either in order to accept the meaning of faith according to the First Vatican Council or in order to acknowledge the soundness and depth of traditional theology. (Fs) (notabene)

321a However, we should not overlook what apparently misleads many in this matter, namely, that as there are two realisms, naive and critical, so also 'real,' 'object,' 'evident,' 'to know,' and similar notions have two different meanings. The first is a meaning of reality, objectivity, evidence, and knowledge according to which a kind of animal faith is carried toward a world of objects that are each already, out, there, now, and in this sense, 'real.'10 The other, quite different meaning of these very same notions is that according to which the mind, led by questions, conceives the natures of things from an understanding of what it has experienced, affirms the true from grasping an unconditioned, and apprehends being in the true as in a medium.'11 (Fs)

321b Now, the ambiguity of prephilosophic knowledge is that it is realistic in both senses. The misfortune of immanentism is that it rejects naive realism without arriving at critical realism. The character of transcendental phenomenology is that it begins from naive realism, considers this naive reality as a phenomenon by suspending not only judgment but also every 'interest,' recognizes internal as well external phenomena, rejects the naive tendency and orientation that reduces internal phenomena to external (mechanism, behaviorism), and extols a new 'transcendental' orientation that reduces external phenomena to internal.12 All this merely produces an inversion of naive realism: where previously everything was reduced to the object of naive realism, now everything is reduced to the subject of the same realism, conceived, no doubt, in a more subtle way. But this sort of subject is less than human. Nor is anything really achieved towards revealing a human subject until the true is arrived at through an unconditioned, and being is known in the true as in a medium. But if there is no arriving at the true and being, understood in this sense, one can, of course, use the words 'true' and 'false,' 'being' and 'existence,' 'existent' and 'transcendent,' 'presence' and 'participation,' but without thereby really getting beyond the limits of some new immanentism. (Fs) (notabene)

323a We have said all this in order that it may be seen more clearly how we ought to proceed with regard to consciousness. For if consciousness is apprehended and studied under the formality of the true and of being, then at one and the same time there are preserved the meaning and nature of consciousness, the method of traditional theology that treats truths and beings, and Catholic dogma, which through the true attains God as triune. If, however, one is afraid of what seems to be antiquated thinking, if one rejects the notions of the true and of being so that one can examine the subject more intimately, not only does one involve oneself in immanentism, idealism, and relativism, but also willy-nilly one joins the liberals and the modernists. (Fs) (notabene)

323b Thus, we must discuss the consciousness of a divine person as being known through the true. If this is done, there will hardly be any difficulty in dealing with any of these questions. For 'unconscious understanding' makes no sense; similarly, 'understanding unconsciously' makes no sense. But the divine act of existence is the divine act of understanding; the divine act of existence, therefore, is conscious and consciously is. Moreover, the divine processions, the divine subsistent relations, and whatever else is said to be really in God are also really identical with the divine act of existence; they are therefore likewise conscious and consciously are. Hence, if the real, subsistent divine relations really distinct from one another are persons, those persons are conscious and are consciously distinguished from one another. (Fs) (notabene)

323c Finally, the reasoning is practically the same for interpersonal relations. A praiseworthy personalism is one thing, but an exaggerated personalism is quite another. By an exaggerated personalism we mean one which, ignoring the formalities of the true and of being, wants to attend only to the experience of intersubjectivity. But we deem that personalism praiseworthy which so insists upon and adheres to the true that the true is always the measure, and revealed truth is never compromised in order that it may seem to accord more clearly and more easily with concrete personal life experience. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Person; Klärung der Vorfragen um Person

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 10/3 -What should be understood by the word 'person'?; What does it seem should be understood by the word 'person'? The answer is that we understand five things. To begin with ...

Textausschnitt: 323d With all this well understood, we must return to our principal question, What does it seem should be understood by the word 'person'? The answer is that we understand five things. To begin with, 'person' is a common word that answers the question, Three what? Next, a person is, according to St Thomas's definition, 'a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature.' Third, a divine person is a subsistent relation, or a subsistent that is distinct by reason of a relation. Fourth, a divine person is a distinct subject and is conscious of himself both as subject and as distinct. Fifth, by reason of their interpersonal relations the divine persons are not only related to one another but are also constituted as persons. (Fs) (notabene)

325a All of this is so coherent that everything else follows from the definition. Therefore, not all five of the above need to be verified concerning the Father, the Son and the Spirit before we can identify them as persons properly so called; the verification of the definition alone suffices for rightly calling them persons. (Fs)

325b On the other hand, since the notion of person, as we have said, became more fully understood over the centuries, later developments are not found explicitly stated in the earlier tradition. You will look in vain for St Thomas's definition in the works of St Augustine; but it is illegitimate to conclude from this that the Catholic doctrine of the divine persons is merely the convenience of a common name that allows us to speak more easily about the Father, Son, and Spirit taken together. Such a conclusion falls into the category of an opinion that has been condemned as follows: 'One must have recourse to the early sources [of revelation], and the more recent constitutions and decrees of the magisterium are to be explained by means of the ancient documents.'1 Similarly, although medieval theologians usually did not expressly discuss consciousness, it is quite clear that neither Catholic theologians nor even the Catholic faithful ever adored an unconscious God or unconscious divine persons. Who would ever ask for mercy from an unconscious being, and who does not think it must be asked for? But if it belongs to the sensus fidelium that the divine persons are conscious, it belongs to theologians to look for a way to provide a clear and distinct explanation regarding this consciousness, lest they incur the reproach of being useless servants who have buried the talent they have received from the Lord [Matthew 25.14-30]. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität, Gott: keine vierte Person; Erweiterung d. Definition: "distinkt" (Subsistentes in einer intellektuellen Natur) aufgrund der Folgerungen aus d. Trinität

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 11 - In what sense is God a person?; Therefore, one who knows God but does not know the Trinity knows 'a subsistent in an intellectual nature' and does not know that 'a subsistent in an intellectual nature' does not satisfy the definition ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 11 - In what sense is God a person?

329d According to the Fourth Lateran Council (DB 432, DS 804, ND 318), God is Father and Son and Holy Spirit; and therefore, since the Father and the Son and the Spirit are three persons, God also is three persons.1

331a According to the same Council, 'In God there is only a trinity, not a quaternity.' Therefore God is not some fourth person besides the Father, the Son, and the Spirit. The reason is that a person is a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature; and since the Father is God, God is not really distinct from the Father, and so in the case of the other persons. And for the same reason God the Spirator is two persons, namely, the Father and the Son; nor is the Spirator another person besides the Father and the Son. (Fs) (notabene)

331b But it may be further asked in what sense God is a person, since God can be known without the Most Holy Trinity being known. The first thing to say is that this question is not about God but about a concept and, indeed, about a concept as imperfect. Then there is added the fact that a more imperfect concept and a less imperfect concept are two concepts compared to each other not on the basis of the real identity of the object but on the basis of an intentional change in the subject. On these grounds, it must be said that the word 'God' is understood to mean 'having a divine nature,' which means 'subsisting in a divine nature,' which in turn means 'subsisting in an intellectual nature.' Furthermore, according to the supposition the Trinity is unknown, and it is therefore likewise unknown that a person is 'a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature,' since the word 'distinct' was not added to the definition until after the Trinity was known. Therefore, one who knows God but does not know the Trinity knows 'a subsistent in an intellectual nature' and does not know that 'a subsistent in an intellectual nature' does not satisfy the definition of person. In other words, one who is ignorant of both the Trinity and the definition of person thinks of God as a person. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das distinkt Subsistente -> Suppositum; drei Supponierende in Gott

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 12 -- How many are there that subsist in God?; But in God there are three and only three supposits. Therefore, the answer to this question is that in God there are three that subsist.

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 12 -- How many are there that subsist in God?

331c A subsistent is the same as a being in the strict sense, or that which is, or that which is found at such an ontological level that it is more perfect than a constitutive principle of being, or an accident, or a possible being, or a conceptual being. (Fs)

331d However, since we are asking how many there are that subsist, we implicitly add another formality to that of subsistent, for we number only what are distinct from one another. Hence to ask how many distinct subsistents there are is the same as asking how many subsistents there are. (Fs)

331d Now a distinct subsistent is a supposit.1 But in God there are three and only three supposits. Therefore, the answer to this question is that in God there are three that subsist. (Fs)

333a If one objects that God subsists, we answer that we do not in the least deny this. For although God does subsist, God does not subsist as a fourth over and above the Father, the Son, and the Spirit, since God is not really distinct from these three. (Fs)
If one objects that God is conceptually distinct from the persons, our answer is that conceptual distinctions are grounds for numbering not what are in God but what are in our minds. (Fs)

If one objects that in God there is only one subsistent act of existence, one act of subsisting, one principle of subsisting, we fully agree. For according to the mode of signifying, these refer not to that which is but to that by which something is. Clearly, then, they regard not the divine persons but the common substance. (Fs) (notabene)

333b If one objects that the relations do not add any further act of subsisting to subsistent existence itself and therefore cannot bring it about that there be three subsistents, our answer is that the objection contains a false supposition, namely, that the relations really add something to subsistent existence itself and enter into composition with it. But in fact the relations are the same as subsistent existence itself, and, since they are the same, they likewise subsist. But if the three relations really distinct from one another subsist, there are in God three that subsist. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Gott - individuum vagum; Beispiel Sokrates: Gattung, Art, Individuum unbestimm (Person), bestimmt

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 13 -- What does the word 'person' mean in regard to God?; Still, there is this difference between the word 'person' as applied to God and as applied to humans, that it is applied to the latter as a universal, ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 13 -- What does the word 'person' mean in regard to God?

333c In God, 'person' signifies an individual in an indeterminate sense, an individuum vagum.1

To understand this, let us begin with Socrates, whose genus is animal, whose species is human, whose determinate individuality is to be Socrates, but whose individuality in an indeterminate sense is to be a person. Note that generic and specific predicates, even when used in the singular, as 'this animal,' 'this man,' are applied to Socrates by reason of the nature of a rational animal and signify this nature of Socrates. But terms referring to individuals, such as 'Socrates' or 'person,' directly signify a subsistent and indirectly the nature in which the individual subsists. Finally, there is this difference between a determinate individual and an individual in an indeterminate sense, that 'person' is predicated of Socrates or of Plato or of Aristotle, but 'Socrates' is said only of Socrates. (Fs)

333d Accordingly, in God, 'Father,' 'Son,' and 'Spirit' name determinate individuals, while 'person' names an individual indeterminately. But neither in divinity nor in humanity is there anything indeterminate that exists in reality, and therefore the common element that 'person' signifies is what is common according to a formality, namely, the formality of a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature. Still, there is this difference between the word 'person' as applied to God and as applied to humans, that it is applied to the latter as a universal, since it is predicated of many who differ in their acts of existence, whereas it is applied to the divine Three who nevertheless have but one act of existence. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität - Zahl; transzendente (philosophische) Zahl

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 14 -- What do numbers signify in God?; 'The Father is'; 'the Son is'; 'the Spirit is'; 'the Father is not the Son or the Spirit'; 'the Son is not the Spirit'; and

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 14 -- What do numbers signify in God?
335a Numbers can be defined in two ways. (Fs)

According to the first way, they are defined on the basis of the material multiplicity of what are numbered. In this way, you can number your fingers by touching the first, the second, the third, and so on. More subtly, you can count the acts of numbering themselves all the way to infinity. However, since God is absolutely immaterial, numbers in this sense do not apply to God. (Fs)

335b According to the second way, numbers are defined by hypothetical propositions. For if one states the following propositions:

(1) A is; B is; C is; D is; ...
(2) A is neither B nor C nor D nor ...
(3) B is neither C nor D nor ...
(4) C is neither D nor ... (Fs)

then numbers can be defined by the following:
There is one, if propositions (1) are true but not (2), (3), ...
There are two, if propositions (1) and (2) are true but not (3), ...
There are three, if propositions (1), (2), (3) are true but not (4), and so on to infinity. (Fs)

335c Now, numbers defined in this way state only being and negations - being in propositions (1), negations in propositions (2), (3), (4),... Philosophers call numbers of this kind transcendental, since they do not suppose material multiplicity1. (Fs) (notabene; s. Fußote)

Fußnote: [This (Scholastic) philosophical notion of transcendental number is not the same as the mathematical notion of transcendental number. Lonergan refers to the latter in Phenomenology and Logic 60.]


Therefore, since the following propositions are true: 'The Father is'; 'the Son is'; 'the Spirit is'; 'the Father is not the Son or the Spirit'; 'the Son is not the Spirit'; and 'in God there is only a trinity, not a quaternity' (DB 432, DS 804, ND 318), it follows that the transcendental number three must be affirmed in God.2 (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Gott - Person: univok, äquivok, analog; geschaffene Personen: unterschieden durch Substanz; göttliche Personen: unterschieden durch Relation; intellektuelle Natur; Intellekt - Bezug auf Sein: als Potenz - als Akt; Subsistenz

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 15 -- Is 'person' predicated analogously of God and of creatures?; Intellect is defined by its relation to being; for intellect is that which can become all things ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 15 -- Is 'person' predicated analogously of God and of creatures?

337a Univocal predicates affirm the same thing about several individuals; equivocal predicates affirm different things; analogous predicates state the same thing, which, however, is verified differently in different individuals. (Fs)

337b Now, 'person' is not predicated equivocally of God and of creatures, for in each case the same definition is verified, namely, a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature. (Fs)
Nor is 'person' predicated univocally of God and of creatures. For in creatures there are as many persons as there are substances, whereas in God there are three persons but only one substance. (Fs)

It remains, therefore, that 'person' is predicated analogously of God and of creatures, since in each case the same definition is verified, and yet it has truth in different ways in God and in creatures. (Fs) (notabene)

337c This analogy is based proximately on the fact that divine persons and created persons are distinguished differently. Created persons are distinguished on the basis of substance - angels on the basis of specific substantial distinction, humans on the basis of numerical substantial distinction. The divine persons, however, are distinguished not on the basis of substance, since they are consubstantial, but on the basis of relations, as stated by the Council of Florence: 'everything is one where there is no distinction by relational opposition' (DB 703, DS 1330, ND 325). (Fs) (notabene)

337d If you wish to inquire further why there exists this difference between divine and created persons, you must refer to differences in intellectual nature. Intellect is defined by its relation to being; for intellect is that which can become all things, and 'all' is not restricted to any genus. But there is one intellect that is related as act to all being, and this is the infinite intellect of God, which comprehends in itself both itself and everything else. Another kind of intellect is related as potency to all being, and this in two ways: first, as one that is always in act with respect to its own intelligibles, and this is the angelic intellect; and second, as one that proceeds from potency to act, and this is the human intellect.1 (Fs) (notabene)

337e Further, certain differences concerning subsistence follow upon these differences in intellectual nature. (Fs)

If an intellectual nature is the act of all being, it is infinite, a se (from itself), and absolutely simple. Because it is absolutely simple, there is no real distinction between that which is and that by which it is. And because there is no such distinction, all that is in it is that which is and is subsistent, as we have said above concerning the divine relations as subsistents. (Fs)

339a If, however, the intellectual nature is finite, there is an opposition between the finitude of its own reality and the infinity of its adequate object, total being. Because there is this opposition, Aquinas proves that in every finite intellectual nature these four are really distinct: substance, act of existence, operational potency, and operation itself.2 On account of these real distinctions between a subsistent itself and the intrinsic causes by which it is constituted, it is manifest that not everything that is in a finite intellectual nature is also that which is, or subsistent. (Fs) (notabene)

339b Finally, as a consequence of these differences regarding subsistence, there are differences regarding distinction. (Fs)

Since in the infinite intellectual nature there is no distinction between that which is and that by which it is, it follows that the real divine relations are subsistent; and further, since these real relations are mutually opposed, it follows that they are really distinct from one another. Hence, in the infinite intellectual nature a distinct subsistent is a subsistent relation. (Fs) (notabene)

339c In a finite intellectual nature, on the other hand, that which is and that by which it is are different, and therefore it is obvious that the subsistent itself and the intrinsic causes by which it is constituted are not the same, and that none of these causes is subsistent. Therefore, although a finite subsistent in an intellectual nature both is distinct and has relations, nevertheless, just as the subsistent itself has intrinsic causes, so also do the distinction of the subsistent and the relations of the subsistent have intrinsic causes, and none of these intrinsic causes subsists. Hence, in a finite intellectual nature it is impossible for a distinction to result from a subsistent relation; for in such a nature the subsistent, the distinct, and the related are from causes that do not subsist; and since every relation is an order of the subject to another, the distinct subsistent, which is the subject, is prior to its order to another. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität; Person - Kommunikation - Unmitteilbarkeit (incommunicability); Vorüberlegungen: Einheit (dreifach); Analogie: Seiendes (Subsistentes)

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 17/1 -- How is person related to incommunicability and to interpersonal communication?; For an understanding of this question we must begin with the meaning of 'one.' There are three uses of'one.'

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 17 -- How is person related to incommunicability and to interpersonal communication?

345d For an understanding of this question we must begin with the meaning of 'one.' There are three uses of'one.' First, 'one' is used numerically, in relation to discrete quantity; in this way, regarding material objects we distinguish the first, the second, the third, and so on. Second, 'one' is used formally, or in relation to a nature, and in this way we say that a pile of stones is one per accidens but a man is one per se; for there is in a man, but not in a pile as such, a formal, natural principle whence there is unity among the many parts. Third, 'one' is used in an actual sense, and in this way 'one' is defined as that which is undivided in itself and divided from everything else. What this means is simply that everything whatever is subject to the principle of identity ('undivided in itself) and to the principle of noncontradiction ('divided from everything else').1 (Fs; tblVrw) (notabene)
347a Now, numerical unity is not part of the essential meaning of person, since angels and the divine persons are entirely immaterial. Nor does natural unity belong to the essential meaning of person, for in Christ there is one person but two natures, and in God there is one nature but three persons. Therefore, the kind of unity that belongs to person is actual unity. (Fs)

1.Kommentar (23/09/09): Sertillanges, SETH_37; siehe auch Liddy:

347b Thus, actual unity adds only negations to being; for 'undivided in itself negates internal division, and 'divided from everything else' negates commingling with anything else. Therefore, since negations add nothing to things, something is one in the same way and with the same perfection as it is being. But being is predicated analogously. Therefore, actual unity is also predicated by analogy, so that the same notion is verified differently in different things. (Fs) (notabene)

347c Furthermore, the analogy of being implies especially three divisions among beings. First, some are called beings which, however, do not subsist; such are the intrinsic causes of a being; accidents, to which it belongs to exist in another; possible beings, which add nothing in reality to the potency of an agent or even to that of matter; and conceptual beings, which exist only in the mind. Again, some are beings in the strict sense, because they themselves subsist even-though not all that belongs to them subsists; such are minerals, plants, animals, humans, and angels, all of which subsist and yet are composed of intrinsic nonsubsistent principles. Finally, there is the act of existence itself that not only subsists but also is absolutely simple, so that everything that is really identical with it also subsists; such is God, and God alone. (Fs) (notabene)

347d The analogy of actual unity is consequent upon this analogy of being. Just as nonsubsistents are beings in a lesser sense, so they are actually one in a lesser sense. The constitutive principles of a being are mutually related, so that the definition of each implies the definition of another; therefore, although they are undivided in themselves, still they are not simply divided from one another. The same reasoning applies to accidents, and all the more to possible beings and conceptual beings. As created subsistent beings are in the strict sense, so also they are one in the strict sense; yet they are multiple in a certain respect since they are composed of many intrinsic causes. Besides, although subsistents are (in the strict sense of are) on the basis of an act of existence, still in regard to operation they need one another, in accordance with the order of the universe. Since the subsistent act of existence itself is absolutely simple, as it is most perfectly being, so it is most perfectly one. (Fs) (notabene)

349a Once this is grasped, we must add a further point. From intellectual emanations there follow real relations that are really distinct from one another. Now such relations, except those in God, have no greater being or unity than that which is found at the lowest ontological level of the nonsubsistents. And if there are such relations in God, then, since God is absolutely simple, these relations are also God, and therefore subsist; nor do they subsist by participation, as do minerals, plants, animals, humans, and angels; they subsist by essence, since their existence is divine existence and their subsistence is divine subsistence. Therefore, the real divine relations possess the most perfect reality and subsistence. But 'one' adds only negations to being, so that all perfection of unity is both had and measured from the perfection of being. Therefore, just as the real divine relations possess the most perfect reality and subsistence, so also they possess the most perfect unity. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität; Person: Kommunikation - Unmitteilbarkeit (incommunicability); geschaffene Personen: Kommunikationsmöglichkeit durch intellektuelle Natur

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 17/2 -- How is person related to incommunicability and to interpersonal communication?; ... there is no real communication except between things that are really distinct. Nor does incommunicability mean anything more than ...

Textausschnitt: 349b With this in mind, then, we must now consider how the divine persons and created persons are with respect to incommunicability and communication. (Fs)

First, by incommunicability we mean just that real distinction by which one that is real is not another that is real. (Fs)

Second, this incommunicability is not only not opposed to communication but in fact is necessarily presupposed by it [eg: incommunicability]. For there is no real relation except between things that are really distinct. Therefore, there is no real communication except between things that are really distinct. Nor does incommunicability mean anything more than the real distinction by which this is not that. (Fs)

Third, it is through the same real relations that the divine persons are both incommunicable and in communication. For through the real relations they are really distinct from one another and therefore incommunicable, and through the same relations they are in communication with one another, both because one relation includes another in its meaning and because the relations are really identical with the processions by which the Father communicates his essence to the Son, and the Father and the Son communicate the same essence to the Holy Spirit. (Fs)

Fourth, the divine persons are not really distinct from one another on the basis of substance or of existence or of essential operation, since in God everything is one where there is no distinction by relational opposition (DB 703, DS 1330, ND 325). (Fs)

Fifth, created persons are really distinct from one another on the basis of substance, and consequently also on the basis of existence and operation. For the substance of Socrates is not the substance of Plato, and likewise the existence and operation of one of them is not the existence and operation of the other. Created persons, therefore, are incommunicable by reason of substance, existence, and operation. (Fs) (notabene)

351a
Sixth, in the case of created persons, communication results from their intellectual nature. As for communication present in natures below the intellectual, unless it is informed by intelligence, reason, and will, such communication is more fittingly called animal or biological or bodily than personal. On the other hand, since intellectual nature is that which regards the totality of being, truth, and goodness, once there is an intellectual nature, interpersonal relationships and communications follow. (Fs)

Seventh, divine persons differ from created persons as the simple differs from the composite. For it is through the same that a divine person is being and one and subsistent and distinct and intellectual and in communication. A created person, on the other hand, is composed of intrinsic causes, so that it subsists through causes that are not subsistent. Hence, although intellectual nature denotes a relation to the totality of being and therefore to all persons, and although this relation is identical with intellectual nature itself, nevertheless a finite person that exists is not the same as the nature by which it exists, and therefore a created person subsists, whereas that relation by which it is radically related to other persons does not subsist. Otherwise, if a created person were constituted through its own intellectual nature, Christ would have assumed not only a human nature but also a human person; but this is contrary to Christian faith. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Bewusstsein, Definition; bewusst: Prädikat in drei Weisen

Kurzinhalt: Let us therefore define consciousness as that awareness that is had on the side of the subject and that regards not the object but the subject of an act, and the act itself, or even an action of that subject.

Textausschnitt: The Notion of Consciousness

379a 'Conscious' is predicated in three ways: (1) of the subject that is conscious, (2) of the act by which the subject is conscious, and (3) of the action whereby one act of the subject emanates from another act. Thus a man is said to be conscious; so also sensing, understanding, judging, choosing are said to be conscious; and finally reflection, whereby a judgment emanates from a grasp of evidence, and deliberation, whereby a choice emanates from a consideration of means, are also said to be conscious.1 (Fs) (notabene)

379b Consciousness, then, belongs to the genus of knowledge, since it involves some type of awareness; but it is distinguished from other species of knowing in that it denotes awareness not of an object but of the subject and of the act of the subject or even of an action of the subject. Our consciousness, therefore, is not of what we see but of ourselves seeing, not of what we hear but of ourselves hearing, not of what we understand but of ourselves understanding, not of what, we define but of ourselves defining, not of what we affirm but of ourselves affirming, not of what we choose but of ourselves choosing, not of what we desire or fear but of ourselves desiring or fearing. Besides, although we can understand, define, affirm, and love ourselves, even here a distinction must be made between what we know or desire on the side of the object and what we are aware of on the side of the subject, so that the latter belongs to consciousness but the former belongs to another species of knowledge or to appetition. Finally, although this knowledge of oneself on the side of the object is attained only through some type of introspective reflection, it would be quite incorrect to conclude that consciousness itself is attained through some type of reflection or introspection. For whether we are reflecting upon ourselves or are concerned with entirely other things that we are apprehending or desiring, we are present to ourselves in either case; and it is inasmuch as we are thus present to ourselves, and not inasmuch as we know ourselves as objects, that we have consciousness in the true sense of the word.2 (Fs)

381a Let us therefore define consciousness as that awareness that is had on the side of the subject and that regards not the object but the subject of an act, and the act itself, or even an action of that subject. (Fs)

381b Finally, note that 'conscious' adds nothing to being but denotes being itself at a certain degree of ontological perfection. Therefore, whatever is required and sufficient in order to say truly that Peter senses or understands is also required and sufficient to say truly that Peter consciously senses or consciously understands. To speak of sensing unconsciously, or of someone sensing unconsciously, or of understanding unconsciously, or of someone understanding unconsciously, is but an empty figment of the imagination. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Gott, Trinität; Bewusstsein auf der Grundlage der göttlichen Wesenheit

Kurzinhalt: ... first we must consider divine consciousness on the basis of essential act, that is, on the basis of the pure and infinite act itself, prescinding in a way from the emanations and the real relations.

Textausschnitt: Divine Consciousness on the Basis of Essential Act

381c Once these matters are grasped, we must proceed analogically to a consideration of God; and first we must consider divine consciousness on the basis of essential act, that is, on the basis of the pure and infinite act itself, prescinding in a way from the emanations and the real relations.1 (Fs)

381d Now God understands, knows, and wills both God and all that is not God. Nor does an unconscious God unconsciously understand, know, and will; rather, a conscious God consciously understands, knows, and wills. Therefore, in God there is both conscious subject and conscious act of understanding, knowing, and willing. (Fs)
381e Furthermore, the Father and the Son and the Spirit are God. (Fs)

Therefore, the conscious Father consciously understands, knows, and wills; the conscious Son consciously understands, knows, and wills; the conscious Spirit consciously understands, knows, and wills. (Fs)

Moreover, regarding this divine consciousness had through essential act, the following points should be noted. (Fs)

381f First, since consciousness is of the subject as that which is conscious and also of the act as that by which one is conscious, the Father is conscious both of himself and of his act; and the same holds for the Son and the Spirit. (Fs)

Second, since in God there is no real distinction between relations and substance, similarly in God there is no real distinction between the subject that is conscious and the act by which the subject is conscious. (Fs)

Third, since the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are really distinct only on the basis of relational opposition, it is impossible that through essential act, which prescinds from the relations, the Father should have a distinct consciousness of the Son or of the Spirit; and similarly it is impossible that the Son should have a distinct consciousness of the Father or of the Spirit; and the same is true for the Spirit. (Fs)

383a One might object here that the Father through essential act most fully understands both himself and the other persons. (Fs)

To this we reply that we are not speaking here about the object that is understood but about the subject who understands. (Fs)

But, the objector goes on, the Father is conscious not only of himself but also of his act; this act is really identical with the Son and the Spirit; therefore, through essential act the Father is conscious, on the side of the subject, of both the Son and the Spirit. (Fs)

In answer to this we point out that we have not said that there is no consciousness of the other persons, but that there is no distinct consciousness of the other persons. And the reason was that, as essential act prescinds from the relations, it likewise prescinds from the distinctions that are consequent upon the relations. (Fs)

383b Fourth, just as through essential act as such the same divinity is possessed in the same way by the Three, so that the Father and the Son and the Spirit are God, each of them equally, so also through essential act as such the same divine consciousness is possessed in the same way by the three persons, so that each of them is equally conscious both of himself and of his essential act. (Fs)

383c Fifth, this consciousness through essential act is related only analogously to our consciousness. For both in God and in us consciousness is an awareness on the side of the subject of both oneself and one's act. But in us this awareness is preliminary and unstructured: preliminary, because it is a prerequisite for us to know ourselves clearly and distinctly on the side of the object; unstructured, because it lacks that clarity and distinctness that is present in knowledge on the side of the object. In God, on the other hand, essential act is not preliminary to another act, and it does not go, by means of another act, from what is obscure and vague to what is clear and distinct; rather, God is understanding itself, in whom there is no real distinction between the subject as divine and the object as divine. (Fs)

383d Sixth, although there is no real distinction between the subject as divine and the object as divine, it by no means follows that the notion of consciousness on the basis of essential act is superfluous. For there is not only the object as divine but also the secondary objects, and these God as conscious consciously knows as objects and indeed as distinct from the subject. Besides, in the Trinity each person through essential act comprehends the three persons on the side of the object; nor does an unconscious person unconsciously comprehend the Three. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität: Bewusstsein auf der Grundlage d. notionalen Akte; ein göttliches Bewusstsein je verschieden gehbat von Vater, Sohn, Geist

Kurzinhalt: Divine Consciousness on the Basis of the Notional Acts;

Textausschnitt: Divine Consciousness on the Basis of the Notional Acts

385d The existence of this divine consciousness is easily demonstrated. For the two divine processions are really identical with the four relations, since in God, where there is no motion, there is no procession other than the relation of a principle to its term and the relation of a term to its principle. Besides, these four relations are subsistent, so that the subject that is related by a relation and the relation itself by which it is related are really the same. Again, the processions themselves are intellectual and intellectually conscious emanations, and therefore whatever are really identified with the processions are likewise intellectual and intellectually conscious. Therefore (1) the subjects that are related to one another by relations and (2) the relations themselves by which the subjects are related to one another are intellectual and intellectually conscious. Thus, on the basis of this consciousness, the Father and the Son and the Spirit are, each of them, conscious both of himself and of each of the others, since it is impossible for anyone to be consciously related to another without by that very fact being conscious both of oneself and of the other to whom one is related. (Fs)

387a Further, this divine consciousness on the basis of the notional acts is one consciousness. There is necessarily only one consciousness when from a single act of understanding a single word is once and eternally spoken, when from a single act of understanding and a single word a single act of love is once and eternally spirated, and when the act of understanding, the word, and the act of love are consubstantial. (Fs) (notabene)

387b But, although this divine consciousness on the basis of the notional acts is one, nevertheless since distinct notional acts are proper to distinct persons, one and the same consciousness is had distinctly by the distinct persons. The intellectually conscious Father generates the Son by intellectual consciousness; the intellectually conscious Son is generated into intellectual consciousness by the Father; the intellectually conscious Father and Son spirate the Holy Spirit by intellectual consciousness; and the intellectually conscious Spirit is spirated into intellectual consciousness by the Father and the Son. But to generate and to be generated are really distinct from each other, and similarly to spirate and to be spirated are really distinct from each other; and to generate consciously, to be generated consciously, and to be spirated consciously are no less distinct from one another. We must, then, most certainly conclude that the one divine consciousness, considered on the basis of the notional acts, is possessed by the Three in three distinct ways. This is surely necessary, if indeed the Father, the Son, and the Spirit are, each of them, conscious both of himself and of each of the others, since they could not be conscious of the others by one consciousness unless each of them possessed the same consciousness in a distinct way. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität: reales Bewusstsein; intellektuelles Bewusstsein - psychologische Analogie

Kurzinhalt: Furthermore, just as the psychological analogy itself is taken solely from intellectual consciousness in the most proper sense, so divine consciousness, which is conceived on the basis of the notional acts by way of this analogy, is surely ...

Textausschnitt: How This Consciousness Is Consciousness in the True Sense

387d It is most important to acknowledge that this is consciousness in the true sense of the term. Without doubt, the Father, the Son, and the Spirit alike know on the side of the object that the Father consciously generates the Son, and that the Son is consciously generated by the Father, and that the Father and the Son consciously spirate the Spirit, and that the Spirit is consciously spirated by the Father and the Son. But what the Father, the Son, and the Spirit know on the side of the object, theologians conclude to on the side of the object. But the very same reality that is known by the divine persons and concluded to from faith by theologians is not only known or concluded to, but also exists. And as to existence, it is on the side of the subject, namely, on the side of the subject that is the Father in consciously generating the Son, on the side of the subject that is the Son in being consciously generated by the Father, on the side of the subject that is the Father and the Son in consciously spirating the Spirit, and on the side of the subject that is the Spirit in being consciously spirated by the Father and the Son. (Fs)

389a Furthermore, just as the psychological analogy itself is taken solely from intellectual consciousness in the most proper sense, so divine consciousness, which is conceived on the basis of the notional acts by way of this analogy, is surely intellectual consciousness not only in the most proper sense but also in the most perfect reality. For what else do we mean by the intellectually conscious emanation of a word than that ordering to the uttering of a word which as conscious and consciously compelling arises from the grasp of manifest intelligibility? What else do we understand by the intellectually conscious emanation of love than that ordering to loving which as conscious and consciously obligating arises from the grasp and affirmation of goodness? Finally, what is more intimate to us or of greater excellence within us than to be intellectually constrained to the truth and morally obligated to the good? And yet in all this a human being is but an imperfect and distant image of those intellectual and intellectually conscious emanations in which the Son is generated by the Father and the Spirit proceeds from both. For we have many acts of understanding and few of them complete, many words and not all of them true, many loves and not all of them good. Besides, in us the subject is really one thing, its act of understanding another, its word something else, and its love something else again. But in God there is but one infinite act at once of understanding and knowing and willing, and since there is no subject really distinct from this act, three subjects really distinct from one another are constituted by the subsistent relations that are really identical with the intellectual and intellectually conscious emanations. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität: Personen - Seinsweisen (Karl Barth); Kappadokische Väter, Kappadokier: tropoi tes hyparxeos; Seinsweise: nicht Subsistenz, sondern wodurch etwas subsistiert; Anrede der göttlichen Personen; Wahrheit - Erfahrung

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 19 - Are the Father, the Son, and the Spirit more appropriately called modes of being (Seinsweisen) than persons? ... Therefore, there are in God three who can be addressed as 'you.'

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 19 - Are the Father, the Son, and the Spirit more appropriately called modes of being (Seinsweisen) than persons?

391b Karl Barth, having judged the definition of person that is ancient to be also obsolete, prefers to call the Father, the Son, and the Spirit Seinsweisen, 'modes of being.'1 (Fs)

In doing so, he thinks he is being faithful to what the early Protestant theologians and also contemporary Catholic theologians really understand by the term 'divine person.' (Fs)
391c But there is reason to doubt this fidelity, since he asserts that there are not three who subsist in God but only one: '... was proprie subsistit, ist ja nicht die Person als solche, sondern Gott in den drei Personen, aber eben: Gott als dreifach proprie subsistens.'2 (Fs) (notabene)

393a This opinion is rejected by J. Brinktrine.3 Claude Welch admits that it contradicts the Augsburg Confession.4 On the contrary, Hermann Volk has interpreted Seinsweise as making 'person' equal to 'Existenz,' and considers that there is only a difference of emphasis between this conception and the traditional notion of person.5 In my uncertainty on this point, I consulted Fr Witte,6 who remarked how clearly Barth taught that Christ was one subject of two natures. (Fs)

393b But whatever may be said about the interpretation of Barth, Welch not only holds that the divine persons are modes of being or of existing but also recognizes in God only one who can be addressed as 'Thou.'7

Hence it seems worth while to determine (1) whether a divine person can truly be said to be a mode of being, (2) whether there are three in God who can each be addressed as 'you,' (3) whether the divine persons among themselves say 'I' and 'you,' and (4) how the existential conception of person is admissible in God.8 In all this our intention is not to pass judgment on authors but to investigate the matter itself. (Fs) (notabene)

393c First, then, the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit subsist as properly as God subsists. For since God subsists, and the Father is God, clearly the Father equally subsists; and by the same reasoning we conclude that the Son and the Spirit equally subsist. (Fs)
393d Second, if one asks whether the Father as such (die Person als solche) subsists, the answer is the same. For the Father is a subsistent relation, and obviously a subsistent, as subsistent, subsists. (Fs)

393e Third, if one asks whether paternity as such subsists, the question is either about our concepts or about the reality itself. If the question is about our concepts, the answer is that it is customary to draw a conceptual distinction between the relation as relation and the relation as subsistent; and therefore the concept of paternity as such is conceptually distinct from the concept of Father as such. But if the question is about the reality, since there is no real distinction between divine paternity and God the Father, it must by all means be said that divine paternity subsists. (Fs)

395a Fourth, a mode of being is contradistinguished from a subsistent, since 'subsistent' denotes that which is, but 'mode of being' denotes the mode by which something is. Therefore, since from the point of view of what is meant the Father subsists, and the Father as such subsists, and divine paternity subsists, then from the point of view of what is meant neither the Father, nor the Father as such, nor divine paternity is a mode of being. (Fs) (notabene)

395b Fifth, what is true in the contrary opinion regards not the divine reality but our concepts. Inasmuch as we conceive relations as relations, relations can be said to be conceived as modes of being. Thus one who states that the Father is distinguished from the Son through paternity conceives paternity as paternity, and this concept does not include the concept of subsistent; for a distinct divine subsistent is distinguished from another distinct divine subsistent neither by 'divine' nor by 'subsistent' but by 'distinct.' (Fs) (notabene)

395c Sixth, as to the arguments that Barth adduces to show that his opinion is traditional, a distinction is needed. The Fourth Lateran Council very clearly teaches that 'there is one supreme reality ... which truly is the Father, and the Son, and the Holy Spirit; three persons taken together, and each one of them taken singly; ... each of the three persons is that reality ...' (DB 432, DS 804, ND 318). As for the Cappadocian Fathers, who conceived the persons as tropoi tes hyparxeos, 'modes of being,' one must keep in mind the difference between revealed truth, the understanding of which is sought by theology, and this understanding itself, which develops in the course of time. Besides, it is clear that the revealed truth is that the Father is God, the Son is God, and the Spirit is God; and furthermore it is clear that the Cappadocian Fathers acknowledged this revealed truth; and finally, it is clear that the Cappadocian Fathers spoke of tropoi tes hyparxeos by way of explaining this truth. Nor is a simply regressive opinion truly traditional; otherwise there would be eliminated that 'growth in understanding, knowledge, and wisdom,' in the words of Vincent of Lerins, which are quoted with approval by the First Vatican Council. (Fs) (notabene)

395d Seventh, we are fully aware that the syllogisms and distinctions we are presenting have little in common with the method of dialectical theology, which aims at reaching up to the divine Subject in such a way as to avoid an erroneous objectivity. But if this method does not clearly arrive at three divine Subjects, it reveals its own insufficiency. (Fs)

395e Eighth, if in God there is only one subsistent, certainly in God there is only one who can be addressed as 'you.' For we do not usually converse with modes of being. But from what we have shown, it is clear that in God there are three who subsist; and therefore following this reasoning we do not conclude to a single divine 'you.' (Fs) (notabene)

397a Ninth, it is quite clear from scripture that God the Father is one who can be addressed as 'you.' We pray, 'Our Father ...' And our Lord himself prays, '... that all may be one. As you, Father, are in me and I am in you, may they also be one in us' (John 17.21). But if the Son himself says 'I' and the disciples address him as 'you,' there is another divine person to whom, according to scripture, one can say 'you.' Finally, since the Holy Spirit is consubstantial and coequal with the Father and the Son, there cannot be denied to the Spirit what is granted to the Father and the Son. Therefore, there are in God three who can be addressed as 'you.' (Fs)

397b Tenth, if the further question is asked whether our interpersonal relations with the three divine persons are such that we can say 'you' to each of them, again a distinction is needed. For if there are included those interpersonal relations which we enter into insofar as we know the real through the true, then certainly, since through the truth revealed by God and accepted by faith we acknowledge three divine persons, we can thereby converse with the Three, addressing each one as 'you.' But if the only interpersonal relations recognized as such are those that are known to the subject through the experience of his or her own intersubjectivity, there arises a whole new and quite complex series of questions that we think best to omit here. For this question1 is really rather abstract and unreal and complex, both because no one knows the Holy Trinity except through revealed truth (DB 1795, DS 3015, ND 131) and because no one is of such feeble intelligence as never to have known the real through the true. (Fs)

1.Kommentar (31/10/09): wichtig; letzter Satz oben; wir erkennen die Realität nur durch die Wahrheit.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität: göttliche Personen - Ich und Du?; das Wort: in Bezug auf den Vater - durch das Wort auf alles Verstandene (Schöpfung ...)

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 20 - Do the divine persons say to one another 'I' and 'You'? ...
Therefore, all that can be signified through the pronouns 'I' and 'you' are spoken by the Father through the Word; ...

Textausschnitt: 397c Our answer is that within God, just as only one person is generating, so only one is speaking. For as the one generating stands to the Son, so the one speaking stands to the Word; and just as the same property is signified by 'Word' as by 'Son,' so the same property is signified by 'speaking' as by 'generating.' Therefore, within God no one speaks except the Father. (Fs)

397d That which is spoken, however, can be taken in two ways: according to the relation to the one speaking, and then the Word is spoken; and according to the relation to objects that are known, and in this latter way, as the Father speaks from his understanding of God and of the Father and of the Son and of the Holy Spirit and of all created things and of all possible beings, so through the Word are spoken God and Father and Son and Spirit and all created things and all possible beings.1 Therefore, all that can be signified through the pronouns 'I' and 'you' are spoken by the Father through the Word; but within God no material sounds are heard, nor are there many distinct concepts, but one alone who is the Word. (Fs; s. Fußnote LBTS_217b)

399a Externally to God, however, nothing prevents the occurrence of an utterance that proceeds from the divine will, whether it be one in which the incarnate Word says, 'As you, Father, are in me and I am in you,'2 or one that states that 'God has sent the Spirit of his Son into our hearts, crying, "Abba! Father!'"3 But within God there is nothing that proceeds from an act of the divine will as from a really distinct principle.4

399b Finally, since these pronouns, 'I' and 'you,' in a certain metaphorical way signify the most perfect interpersonal relationships, what follows below will make sufficiently clear what must be said about such relationships within God. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Subjekt: relativer Ausdruck, viele Bedeutungen; Unterschied: zeitliches - ewiges S.; subsistente Identität bei substantiellen und akzidentellen Änderungen; Substanz: relativer Ausdruck

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 21/1 - What is the analogy between the temporal and the eternal subject? ... Note that temporal subjects really and truly change and yet remain the same in their subsistent identity through both substantial changes (death, resurrection) and ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 21 - What is the analogy between the temporal and the eternal subject?1

399c That which is verified in different ways in different subjects is said to be analogous. (Fs)

399d 'Subject' is a relative term. It has as many different meanings as there are specific instances where something is a subject. (Fs)

We are dealing here not with a logical subject (anything concerning which a predication is made) nor with a recipient subject (that in which something is received, as when act is received in potency, existence in essence, form in matter, or an accident in a substance) nor with a subject of a habit (which is related to a habit as an object is to an act; in this last sense, God is said to be the subject of the science of theology). (Fs)

401a We are dealing rather with a subject that is a person and, indeed, a person as conscious. Hence 'subject' is understood as a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature; and this subject is considered in relation to his intellectual nature. (Fs)

401b The analogy, then, about which we are inquiring is the analogy of the subject as subject; for a temporal subject as well as an eternal subject is a distinct subsistent in an intellectual nature, but a temporal subject and an eternal subject are related to their respective intellectual natures in different ways. (Fs)

An eternal subject is one that is intrinsically immutable. (Fs)
A temporal subject is one that is not only mutable but also material. (Fs)

401c Consequently, the now of an eternal subject is always the same, while the now of a temporal subject changes. For now is to a subject as time is to the motion of a subject; and therefore the now of an immutable subject is always the same, while the now of a mutable and material subject is continuously flowing.2

401d Note that temporal subjects really and truly change and yet remain the same in their subsistent identity through both substantial changes (death, resurrection) and accidental changes. For a subject is a distinct subsistent, that is, a being in the strict sense, that which is, that which has a substantial essence and other constitutive principles. Therefore, since a subsistent is really and truly constituted by its own intrinsic principles, when they change the subsistent itself really and truly changes; and yet, since the subsistent is not adequately3 the same as its constitutive principles, it remains the same in its subsistent identity even though, within certain limits, its principles may change. (Fs) (notabene)

1.Kommentar (04.11.09): Diese Beständigkeit der zeitlichen Substanz bei allen substantiellen und akzidentellen Änderungen ist Verstehensbrücke zu: Ewige Wahrheit - Geschichte; Eucharistie - Ewigkeit eines geschichtlichen Ereignisses

401e Here one must be aware of the manifold ambiguity of the term 'substance,' which denotes either (1) a substantial essence composed of this form and this matter, or (2) that which has a substantial essence, or (3) in premetaphysical knowledge, the genus or predicament that is divided into first and second substance, or (4) many other and sometimes strange things, in accord with various crude or erroneous notions of substance. And since the word 'accident' is even more ambiguous, one must continually have recourse to basic metaphysical notions whenever objections are raised premised upon a concept of substance or accident or both. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sujekt: zeitliches, ewiges S. in Relation auf die intellektuelle Natur; temporales Subjekt 1-4; intellektuelle Tätigkeit - 2 Phasen: spontan - habituell

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 21/2 ... First, then, temporal subjects are subjects of another nature besides the intellectual. For an intellectual nature as such is immaterial, ...

Textausschnitt: 403a With these observations in mind, we will relate, first temporal and then eternal subjects, to what they are subjects of in their respective intellectual natures. (Fs)

403b First, then, temporal subjects are subjects of another nature besides the intellectual. For an intellectual nature as such is immaterial, and therefore a subject lacking another and material nature would not be a temporal subject. (Fs) (notabene)

403c Second, the intellectual nature of a temporal subject is potential, and that in two ways. First, temporal subjects are said to be in the genus of intellectual beings only as potency, since initially our intellect is a tabula rasa, a slate upon which nothing has been written. Second, the actuation of our intellectual nature is, in a sense,1 only a form and an act presupposing sentient life. It is in a sense a form, in accordance with the first operation of the intellect, that is, insofar as we inquire about sensible data, understand causes in these data, and conceive the causes understood, together with abstract common matter. And it is in a sense an act, in accordance with the second operation of the intellect and the consequent operation of the will, that is, insofar as by reflecting on concepts we ask whether something is so, weigh the evidence, make speculative or practical judgments, and make choices in accord with our judgments. This intellectual informing and actuation of sentient life presupposes that sentient life; for unless we are rendered conscious through the operation of our senses, we cannot operate at all by intellect or will, since in this life we actually understand absolutely nothing except in a phantasm.2

403d Third, temporal subjects are per accidens the subjects of their intellectual nature as actuated before they are per se the subjects of their intellectual nature as actuated. (Fs)

403e Anything whatever is said to be per se or per accidens depending upon whether it comes to be by the intention of the agent or apart from the intention of the agent. Now, if one considers the intention of that agent who created and conserves the nature of a temporal subject and who applies it to its action, it is quite clear that the intellectual nature of a temporal subject is actuated per se. But if one considers the intention of temporal subjects themselves, it is also clear that the actuation of their intellectual nature cannot be intended before they know that they have an intellectual nature; nor is it any less evident that temporal subjects cannot know that they have an intellectual nature before this nature has been actuated. (Fs)

405a Besides, just as temporal subjects become actually inquiring, understanding, judging, and willing not by their own intention but by a natural spontaneity, so also the same temporal subjects conduct their intellectual operations spontaneously before they learn how to direct them in accordance with their own understood and approved and chosen intention. For this fully conscious and deliberate self-direction presupposes an exact and very difficult knowledge of their own intellectual nature in all its intrinsic norms and exigencies, and this exact and difficult knowledge can be had only through their intellectual operations. Consequently, until this knowledge is acquired, the intellectual operations of temporal subjects must necessarily be conducted in accord with the spontaneity of that intellectual light which in us is a created participation in uncreated light. (Fs) (notabene)

405b From this it is clear that there are two phases of a temporal subject: the first is a prior phase, when by one's natural spontaneity one is the subject of one's actuated intellectual nature; the second is a subsequent phase, when, as knowing and willing, one is by one's own intention the subject of one's intellectual nature both as actuated and as to be actuated further. (Fs) (notabene)

405c Fourth, the condition of a temporal subject is such that one can hardly make the transition from the first phase to the second apart from the influence of other temporal subjects. (Fs)

405d For temporal subjects intellectually inform and actuate their sense life by their own intention to the extent that they experience a true self-revelation and a genuine self-acceptance. This revelation takes place either concretely and symbolically or technically and exactly: concretely and symbolically, as a particular human culture or way of life develops as delineated and expressed in its mores, customs, precepts, and stories; technically and exactly, as human nature is studied in science and philosophy.23 But it is obvious that both objectifications of human nature presuppose collaboration on the part of many; and it is also clear that all temporal subjects are greatly helped through the influence of others to come to a willing acceptance of this revelation of their human nature. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Person, temporales Subjekt 5-7; Übergang: spontane -> habituelle intellektuellen Tätigkeit (3 Arten); Imagination (künstlerisch, dramatisch, praktisch); Verwirrung, Irrtum; Wille

Kurzinhalt: Besides, until temporal subjects arrive at what we have termed the subsequent phase, it is impossible for them to direct and govern themselves wisely and effectively ... Those who are in the prior phase not only perceive the excellence of the ...

Textausschnitt: 405e Fifth, there are three ways in which this transition from the prior to the subsequent phase of a temporal subject can be made. First, it is possible for temporal subjects, whether through symbolic representation or technically, to understand their intellectual nature along with that nature's intrinsic norms, and because they understand it, to affirm and approve of it, and because they approve of it, to embrace it by their own will and to intend to follow its norms. In the second way, temporal subjects, although they may themselves have little understanding of their own nature, can nevertheless hear and believe the words of another who does understand, and by their own will and intention live according to what they believe, and finally even arrive at an understanding of it, in accordance with the dictum, 'Believe in order to understand.' In the third way, temporal subjects can be so intimately one with another through love that this loving union leads to oneness in belief, and oneness in belief in turn leads to understanding. Hence, if we look at the ways by which temporal subjects become persons of the subsequent phase, we see that some come to it more by way of understanding, others more by way of the true word, and still others by way of genuine love. (Fs)

407a Sixth, in the state of fallen human nature, there are many obstacles that prevent temporal subjects from truly and genuinely becoming persons of the subsequent phase. (Fs)

For, insofar as temporal subjects are the subjects of a sentient nature, they are centers of apprehensions, desires, and other operations that occur and are regulated by a certain natural spontaneity. But insofar as one is the subject of an intellectual nature, one ought to proceed to understanding an objective order of reality, to perceiving one's own role within that order, and to accepting one's own subordination to the same order. Finally, insofar as one is the subject of both a sentient and an intellectual nature, one's imagination develops greatly and the life of the senses is greatly liberated, so that intelligence can proceed to understand the full range of being, while the senses can live in accord with the discoveries and dictates of intelligence.1

407b But as a result of this very development of the imagination and liberation of the life of the senses, temporal subjects enter a total field of operations which, since it consists in finding and using signs and instruments, is not at all regulated or directed by laws that are innate in animals. Besides, until temporal subjects arrive at what we have termed the subsequent phase, it is impossible for them to direct and govern themselves wisely and effectively. Thus in the prior phase temporal subjects are freed from the law of animals to engage in the artistic, dramatic, or practical fields of activity, without having arrived at their own law understood by intelligence, imposed by reason, and chosen by the will. (Fs)

407c In this state a temporal subject, influenced by other subjects, can, of course, through love and belief embrace and learn whatever those other subjects have learned and embraced. But temporal subjects much more easily learn what is useful and convenient for daily living, where experience itself reveals our mistakes through their obvious consequences. But what concerns the inner nature and true role of a person in this life and the meaning and purpose of this life, no empirical method can determine through their obvious consequences. So these matters are generally left to the speculations of priests, poets, and philosophers, so that others, as if by a division of labor, are freer to attend to their own interests. Because of this, primitive peoples are found to be given to myths, and although through the advancement of the arts and sciences ever more perfect means are provided for revealing to one one's proper nature and making its intrinsic norms clear, nevertheless there is also a corresponding increase in the opportunity for, and the amount and influence of, confusion, ignorance, and error. (Fs)

409a Added to all these problems is the fact of a less than upright will. Those who are in the prior phase not only perceive the excellence of the subsequent phase less clearly, but also will their conversion to it less effectively. Those who could believe the teachers who teach what is true prefer to listen to others who urge them to choose what is easier. Those who could have more upright friends nevertheless go along with those who live a life of enjoyment and pleasure. Thus the greater part of humanity, bypassing the narrow gate, take the broad road instead.1 They have little knowledge of what a human being ought to be, and they do not want to put into practice the little they know. As their intellect falls short of intelligible truth, so also their will shies away from knowledge that is intelligible and true. The consequences of this deficiency and avoidance do not remain within single individuals, not only because people believe those who are in error and friends consent to the sins of their friends, but also because human actions that are contrary to reason create human situations that are absurd, and the very absurdity of these situations is seen by the thoughtless to be empirical evidence that proves the ineptitude of those who wish to follow reason.2

409b Seventh, if the belief and friendship of temporal subjects are so ambivalent that, while they may be very helpful, they nevertheless frequently draw temporal subjects away from intelligible truth and true good and lead them into an all too human mediocrity, then we must take refuge in the eternal divine subjects. Let our belief, then, be in the eternal Word made flesh, let our friendship be in the Holy Spirit; and in the Spirit through the Son let us dare to cry out, 'Abba, Father'; so that being by God's intention created in the divine image we may by our own intention live according to that image, and hope that we may become faithful citizens of the city of God in this life and blessed in the life to come. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Person, ewiges Subjekt; Unterschied, Ähnlichkeit -> zeitliches Subjekt; intellektuelle Natur, Wort, Hauchung, Zeugung; Intellekt - Sein: als Akt - Potenz

Kurzinhalt: Besides, just as we become subjects of an actuated intellectual nature inasmuch ... so also eternal subjects are subjects inasmuch as a Word is spoken in accordance with truth, and Love is spirated in accordance with goodness.

Textausschnitt: 411a With this in mind, let us proceed to the analogy of the eternal subject, so as to determine what is similar and what different when an eternal subject is related to his intellectual nature. (Fs)

411b First and foremost, eternal subjects as such, since they are immaterial, have no nature other than the intellectual. Nor is it as potency that they are in the genus of intellectual being: their intellect is the infinite act of all being. For them there is not one phase after another, so that they are per accidens subjects of an actuated intellectual nature in an earlier phase, and per se in a later phase, since the infinite act of understanding comprehends from eternity what understanding is and what the norms intrinsic to intelligence are. Thus, there is the greatest possible difference between eternal subjects and temporal subjects. (Fs) (notabene)

411c Still, there is this small similarity, in that both are subjects of an intellectual nature. Just as the divine intellect is as act with respect to all being, so the human intellect is as potency with respect to all being. For our intellect asks with regard to everything, 'What is it?' and 'Is it?' and this natural desire, manifested in questions, does not rest until it knows God by essence.1

411d Besides, just as we become subjects of an actuated intellectual nature inasmuch as we rise above sensible realities through inquiry, make judgments in accordance with truth through understanding, and spirate an act of will through judging in accordance with goodness, so also eternal subjects are subjects inasmuch as a Word is spoken in accordance with truth, and Love is spirated in accordance with goodness. (Fs) (notabene)

411e Again, just as we become subjects per se, subjects of the second phase, inasmuch as we understand our intellectual nature and manifest it to ourselves by conceiving and judging, and so love it as understood and manifested that we will to follow it in all things, so also the eternal subjects are subjects from eternity inasmuch as the infinite intellectual nature understands itself and manifests itself to itself by the Word, and by infinite Love loves itself as understood and manifested. (Fs) (notabene)

411f Moreover, just as we attain the perfection of the second phase either more by way of understanding or more by way of belief or more by way of love, so the eternal subjects are subjects, one inasmuch as from understanding he speaks the Word, another inasmuch as he is the Word spoken from understanding, and the third inasmuch as he is Love proceeding from understanding speaking and the Word spoken. (Fs)

411g Again, just as we depend upon one another both for our very existence through carnal generation and for becoming persons of the second phase through teaching and faith and love, so also the eternal subjects are so ordered among themselves that the Father is ungenerated, the Son is from the Father by way of intellectual generation, and the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father and the Son by way of holiness. (Fs)

413a In all these there is a similarity, but in each of them the dissimilarity is much greater. There is an infinite distance between an intellect that is to all being as potency and an intellect that is to all being as act. Moreover, one who understands by an infinite act is not moved to understanding by inquiring about sensible data. Again, an eternal subject is never caught in a tension between the poles of liberation from animal limitations and the understanding of intellectual nature. Nor is he first conscious of himself by way of a preliminary and unstructured awareness in order later clearly and distinctly to manifest himself to himself in a word. He does not proceed through intermediate acts to more perfect acts of understanding, or speak many words, or love in many acts, nor he is capable of failing in his procession by way of truth or in his procession by way of holiness, but the selfsame eternal and infinite act is an act of understanding and of affirming and of loving. Again, infinite act is not specified by finite objects but rather by that which is being by essence and true by essence and good by essence. Nor is there here a real distinction between substance and accident, or between existing and operating, or between subject and act. Nor is there one constitution of the subject's existence and another constitution for a person of the second phase to exist by his own intention in accordance with his intellectual nature. Again, the Speaker is not understanding without being at the same time infinite affirmation and infinite love; and the Word is not the spoken truth without being at the same time infinite understanding and infinite love; and proceeding Love is not love without being at the same time infinite understanding and infinite affirmation. But eternal subjects are from eternity one and the same infinite act; and through those very emanations by way of truth and of holiness they are subjects and distinct from one another and ordered among themselves in an order that is an order of origin and, at the same time, intellectual and personal. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität; Perichorese, Circumincessio: auf der Ebene der göttlichen Wesenheit; Bibelbelege

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 13/1 - The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit dwell within one another ... In terms of the divine essence, the explanation is as follows. In each and every thing there is its essence and all that ...

Textausschnitt: ASSERTION 13
The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit dwell within one another both ontologically and psychologically. (Fs)

413b The doctrine of the circumincession1 (circumincessio, circuminsessio, perichoresis) of the divine persons is taught in scripture, in the Fathers, and in the Council of Florence. (Fs)

415a John 10.38: '... even though you do not believe me, believe the works, so that you may know and believe that the Father is in me and I am in the Father.'
John 14.10: 'Do you not believe that I am in the Father and the Father is in me?'

John 17.21: '... that they may all be one. As you, Father, are in me and I am in you, may they also be one in us.'

1 Corinthians 2.10-11: '... the Spirit scrutinizes all matters, even the deep things of God. Who, for example, knows a man's innermost self but the man's own spirit within him? Similarly no one knows what lies at the depths of God but the Spirit of God.'2

Matthew 11.27: '... no one knows the Son except the Father, and no one knows the Father except the Son and anyone to whom the Son chooses to reveal him.'

Let St Fulgentius, whom the Council of Florence quotes, represent the Fathers:3 'Because of this unity the Father is entire in the Son, entire in the Holy Spirit; the Son is entire in the Father, entire in the Holy Spirit; the Holy Spirit is entire in the Father, entire in the Son' (DB 704, DS 1331, ND 326). (Fs)

415b Therefore this circumincession, as expressed in these statements, is a matter of divine and catholic faith. It is explained by St Thomas in terms of the divine essence, in terms of the personal relations, and in terms of the origins or processions.4 (Fs) (notabene)

415c In terms of the divine essence, the explanation is as follows. In each and every thing there is its essence and all that is really identical with the essence. But each of the divine persons is the divine essence itself since none of them is really distinct from the divine essence. Therefore, the Father is in the Son, because the Father is his essence, and his essence is really identified with the essence of the Son, and the essence of the Son is in the Son. And similarly, the Son is in the Father, the Father and the Son are in the Holy Spirit, and the Holy Spirit is in the Father [and in the Son]. (Fs)

415d The same conclusion follows from the fact that each divine person is conscious through the essential divine act and, moreover, is really identical with the essential divine act. For whoever is really within the consciousness of another is really in that other. But the essential divine act, by which each of the persons is conscious, is within the consciousness of each of the persons. And besides, each person is this essential act itself. Hence, each person is really within the very consciousness of each of the other two.5

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität; Perichorese, Circumincessio: auf der Ebene der Relationen

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 13/2 - The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit dwell within one another ... Next, circumincession can be explained in terms of relation.

Textausschnitt: 417a Next, circumincession can be explained in terms of relation. It belongs to an absolute to be per se and in itself, because it has its total meaning through its proper reality and encloses it within its own reality. It belongs to what is relative, on the other hand, that its existence or meaning is to be related to another, because the very meaning of the relative includes within itself the meaning of another, and its very reality is just a relation to another. Thus, the Father is Father because he has a Son, and conversely the Son is Son because he has a Father. 'Son,' therefore, is included in the meaning of 'Father,' and 'Father' is included in the meaning of 'Son.' But the reality of the Father is the reality of this meaning itself, and likewise the reality of the Son is the reality of the meaning of 'Son.' Therefore, as 'Father' is included in the meaning of 'Son,' consequently the Father is in some way included in the relational reality of the Son, and similarly the Son is in some way included in the relational reality of the Father. And the same reasoning applies to the Holy Spirit. (Fs)

417b This is more clearly seen when we further consider that the real divine relations are intellectually conscious. For not only is what we have said above concerning the mutual inclusion of the divine persons in the real relation of each to each of the others known on the side of the object by each of the persons (as it is also known by us), but also that very reality which the divine persons are is an intellectually conscious ordering. Paternity is the intellectually conscious ordering from grasped evidence to the Word to be spoken and to the Word spoken; and this paternity is the Father himself. Filiation is likewise the intellectually conscious ordering of the Word spoken to the grasp of infinite evidence from which it is spoken; and this filiation is the Son himself. Passive spiration, finally, is the intellectually conscious ordering to the infinite good grasped by intellect and affirmed in an eminently true judgment; and this passive spiration is the Holy Spirit himself. (Fs)

417c Thus, we can expound the teaching of St Thomas, that 'one of the relatively opposed is in the other on the basis of intellect' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 42, a. 5), not only from the perspective of our intellect inasmuch as we understand the divine relations, but also from the perspective of the divine intellect inasmuch as the divine persons comprehend the divine relations, and not only in accordance with the divine intellect inasmuch as these relations are understood on the side of the object, but also inasmuch as, on the side of the intellectually conscious subject, each person is conscious of the other two. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität; Perichorese, Circumincessio: auf der Ebene der Ursprünge

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 13/3 - The Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit dwell within one another ... Finally, in terms of origins circumincession can be explained as follows.

Textausschnitt: 419a Finally, in terms of origins circumincession can be explained as follows. Because an intellectual emanation is within the reality and the consciousness of that from which it is, the Son is within the reality and the consciousness of the Father, and similarly the Holy Spirit is within the reality and the consciousness of the Father and the Son. Besides, although in our case each of us is but one person and one conscious subject, in God there are three persons and three conscious subjects. Consequently, not only the Father as the principle of the Son, and the Father and the Son as the principle of the Holy Spirit, have another person within their consciousness and their reality as the one proceeding from them, but also the Son as proceeding from the Father, and the Spirit as proceeding from the Father and the Son, have, respectively, the Father, and the Father and the Son, within their own consciousness and reality. (Fs)

419b This can be explained in another way. God is being by essence and the very act of understanding, is true by essence and the very act of affirming, is good by essence and the very act of loving. These three are distinguished from one another only conceptually, so that the divine reality is an intelligible actually understood, and by identity divine truth actually affirmed, and by identity divine goodness actually loved. But the Father is God understanding as the principle of the Word, and the Word is God affirming as proceeding from the Father, and the Spirit is God loving as proceeding from the Father and the Son. Therefore, each person is in another inasmuch as that person is being and understanding, and so in the Father; inasmuch as he is true and affirming, and therefore in the Son; and inasmuch as he is good and loving, and therefore in the Spirit. (Fs) (notabene)

419c There is still another way of explaining this. Since in God intentional existence and natural existence are one and the same, the Word is God not only on the basis of intentional existence but also on the basis of natural existence; therefore, the other persons are in the Word, since their natural existence is also intentional existence. And according to this, God is said to be in the divine understood intention of God, that is, in the Word.1 Besides, although in us love effects only a quasi identification between the lover and the beloved, whereby a friend is said by the poet to be dimidium animae meae, 'half of my soul,'2 in God love involves a true and full identity between the lover and beloved, and according to this, God as loved is most truly said to be in God as loving.3 Therefore, inasmuch as the Father and the Son are loved by proceeding Love, which is the Holy Spirit, they are in this very love. Again, although the Father and the Son are consubstantial by reason of divine generation, they are also consubstantial by reason of the love that joins the two into one; and it is according to this that the Holy Spirit is said to be the bond between the Father and the Son, not as a go-between by way of a procession, but because diose whom nature has made consubstantial, infinite love also makes one from eternity on other grounds.4

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit; Akt als perfectio

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 14/1 - Perfection has two formalities ... First, act denotes perfection.

Textausschnitt: 423b Since it is impossible to agree with all of these disparate opinions, we opt to defend the following view, that just as the divine substance and the divine relations are one reality, so also is there one real perfection, and that similarly, just as the formality of substance and the formality of relations are different, so also the formality of perfection attributable to the substance is different from the formality of perfection attributable to the relations. Therefore, we agree with the first and third of the above opinions, that there is one real divine perfection, and with the second and third insofar as they contend that the great perfection of God is revealed in the dogma of the Trinity. (Fs)
Argument

423c
First, act denotes perfection.
Being is divided into potency and act in such a way that it is limited by potency and perfected by act; therefore, each individual being is lacking in perfection to the extent that it is limited by potency, and is endowed with perfection to the extent that it is in act. (Fs)

[...]

427c
Third, from the standpoint of the formality of perfection that is grounded upon act, the divine substance is infinite in perfection. (Fs)

The divine substance is pure act without any admixture of potency. But each being is limited through potency and perfected through act. Therefore, the divine substance, because of act, is perfect, and because of the denial of potency is infinite in perfection. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit; Ordnung der Einheit als perfectio; Endziel; Beispiele: Universum, Engel, Mensch

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 14/2 - Perfection has two formalities ... Second, there is another formality of perfection, which is found in the unity of order.

Textausschnitt: 423d
Second, there is another formality of perfection, which is found in the unity of order. (Fs)

Note that order can be understood in two ways: first, according as relation is defined as the order of one to another; second, according as many things are ordered to one another in such a way as to constitute a unity. In the first sense, therefore, any relation is an order; but in the second sense, there is no order except insofar as many things compose an intelligible unity through many mutual relations. A pile of stones or of wood, for example, lacks the unity of order, and yet stones and wood properly arranged make one house. (Fs)

423e Note too that nothing can have the formality of end unless it has the formality of perfection. For the end is the final perfection of each thing, and therefore each and every thing, inasmuch as it exists, is a being in the strict sense, but inasmuch as it attains its end, it is good in the strict sense and perfect in the strict sense.1 (Fs) (notabene Fußnote)

425a Furthermore, the formality of end and of final perfection applies not only to individual things as individual but also to many individual things as many. For every agent acts because of an end, and so if there occur many, they occur because of an end. (Fs)

But of course this end cannot be the material multitude itself, for a multitude as material lacks a definite term. For example, if it is thought better to make two things than one, it follows that it is much better still to make three than two, and so on to infinity. But this infinity is contrary to the formality of end.2

Nor can the end of the many be to make one substance out of many substances, since that would mean the destruction rather than the perfection of the many. (Fs)

Nor can the end of the many be that each individual as individual attain its maximum perfection, for this leaves the many, precisely as many, without an end. (Fs)

425b We must conclude, then, that the end and final perfection of the many consists in the unity of order. This unity does not do away with the multitude or multiply it indefinitely or leave it unstructured, but perfects it precisely as a multitude. This is confirmed by a number of examples. (Fs)

425b First of all, 'the universe as a whole more perfectly participates in and represents the divine goodness than does any single creature.'3 But the universe is not a single whole except through the unity of order.4 This order is the intrinsic end of the universe: 'The end of the universe is a good existing in it, that is, the order of the universe itself.'5 (Fs) (notabene)

Also, the angels are ordered both among themselves and in relation to other creatures.6

425d Moreover, human beings in this life are perfected, not only through the particular goods that each one desires and seeks to obtain, but also through the unity of order, whether domestic or economic or political or social, that the many as many desire all the more eagerly the more clearly they perceive the causes of things and move away from the error of exaggerated individualism. (Fs)

427a Besides, since individual human beings are made up of many parts, these many parts also, as many, tend to their proper perfection. And so the greatest among the goods of the body is considered to be health, which is the well-ordered disposition of the parts both among themselves and for the person as a whole. Similarly, among spiritual goods the greatest is considered to be that interior justice at which supernatural justification terminates, which is a certain Tightness of order according to which the highest element of a person is subordinated to God and the lower powers of the soul are subordinated to the highest, namely, to reason.7 (Fs) (notabene)

427b From all this it seems we must without doubt conclude that perfection has two formalities, since individual beings as individuals attain their end and perfection through act, and these same many beings as many are perfected through the unity of order. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit; Ordnung (perfectio) der Einheit in den Relationen

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 14/3-4 - Perfection has two formalities ... Fourth, the formality of perfection derived from the unity of order is verified in the divine relations taken together

Textausschnitt: 427c
Third, from the standpoint of the formality of perfection that is grounded upon act, the divine substance is infinite in perfection. (Fs)

The divine substance is pure act without any admixture of potency. But each being is limited through potency and perfected through act. Therefore, the divine substance, because of act, is perfect, and because of the denial of potency is infinite in perfection. (Fs)

427d

Fourth, the formality of perfection derived from the unity of order is verified in the divine relations taken together. (Fs)

The formality of perfection that is derived from the unity of order consists in the fact that many things are so ordered among themselves as to constitute an ordered unity. (Fs)

But in the divine relations there is verified that mutual ordering that produces an ordered unity. (Fs)

427e Therefore in the divine relations taken together there is verified the formality of perfection that is found in the unity of order. (Fs)

The major premise of this syllogism is the definition of unity of order. (Fs)

The minor premise is clear from what has been said. For divine paternity is an ordering to the Word that is to be spoken and is spoken; filiation is an ordering of the Word to the Speaker; active spiration is an ordering to Love that is to be spirated and is spirated; passive spiration is an ordering of Love to the Spirator; and since active spiration is the same in reality as paternity and filiation, from these four real relations there is constituted an ordered unity. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit; Ordnung der Einheit (perfectio): formal (3 Grade) - material; nicht Größeres kann gedacht werden

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 14/5 - Perfection has two formalities ... The third degree is the perfection of order that is found within intellectual consciousness per se and consists in the fact that

Textausschnitt: 429a
Fifth, so great is this perfection based on the unity of order that no greater can be thought of.

The kind of perfection that is based on the unity of order can be considered either formally as a certain unity or materially as the many that are to be ordered. But under both aspects the perfection of order in God is supremely great. Therefore, this perfection is so great that no greater can be thought of. (Fs)

For under the formal aspect, three degrees of perfection can be distinguished. The first degree is the perfection of order that is imposed from without [eg: Lat. klarer: ab extrinsceo imponitur] upon what is to be ordered. This sort of perfection is found in artifacts such as stones and wood that are so ordered as to constitute one house. The second degree is the perfection of order that is found in a society, where the good of order is constituted by what is understood, evaluated, and chosen by several persons. The third degree is the perfection of order that is found within intellectual consciousness per se and consists in the fact that the good of a well-ordered consciousness is attained because it is understood and therefore affirmed as good and hence responsibly chosen. (Fs) (notabene)

429b Now, the second degree is more perfect than the first, both because the first is imposed from without while the second emerges from the ordered individuals themselves as intellectual, and because the first exists dividedly in each individual while the second is found intentionally in its entirety in each one. The third degree is more perfect than the second because not only does it emerge from within and exist intentionally in its entirety in what is ordered, but also this total perfection that is intended is achieved in reality by the very fact that, having been understood, it is justly affirmed, and having been affirmed, it is responsibly chosen. (Fs) (notabene)

429c Besides, among intellectual creatures the perfection of order as it occurs between such persons is found only in the second and less perfect way; and the third way is attained only inasmuch as accidental acts within a finite consciousness are ordered among themselves on the side of the rational subject. In God, however, the persons are ordered among themselves in the third and most perfect way, so that the divine society of the three persons is not only understood, affirmed, and loved on the side of the object, but is also, on the side of the subject, and according to the intellectual emanations through the truth of the Word and the holiness of proceeding Love, constituted as that understood, affirmed, and loved society of three. Consequently, under its formal aspect the perfection of the divine order must be said to be so great that no greater can be thought of, especially since this perfection cannot be naturally understood by a created intellect. (Fs)

429d Next, under the material aspect, insofar as there are several to be ordered among themselves, this perfection is again so great that no greater can be thought of. For these individuals are not constituted as several individuals inasmuch as the same note of perfection is affirmed of one and denied to another, but inasmuch as they are mutually opposed relations; nor are some of them these relations while others are subjects that are ordered by the relations, but these relations themselves are subsistent. There are not many accidental acts of understanding, of affirmation, and of love, but one and the same infinite act. What is understood is not some being by participation but being by essence, what is affirmed is not something true by participation but what is true by essence, and what is loved is not some good by participation but the good by essence. There is no real distinction between being and truth and goodness and understanding and affirmation and love. Accordingly, there is a most perfect unity of the one consciousness that is so ordered that three persons are each in their own way conscious through the same consciousness. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit; begriffliche Unterscheidung (distinctio rationis): Akt - Ordnung als perfectio entsprechend: göttliche Substanz - g. Relationen

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 14/6 - Perfection has two formalities ... Sixth, the divine perfection grounded upon act and the divine perfection found in order are conceptually distinct but really identical.

Textausschnitt: 431a
Sixth, the divine perfection grounded upon act and the divine perfection found in order are conceptually distinct but really identical. (Fs)

The perfection grounded upon act is the divine substance, and the perfection found in order is the divine relations taken together. But the divine substance and the divine relations are conceptually distinct and really identical. Therefore, we apprehend one and the same divine perfection through distinct concepts. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit (perfectio); Einwand: die Vollkommenheit einer Relation kann keine absolute Vollkommenheit sein; Antwort

Kurzinhalt: We agree that a distinct absolute reality indicates a distinct perfection; but that a distinct relative reality by itself alone indicates a distinct perfection, we deny.

Textausschnitt: 431b There seems to be in God a threefold relative perfection, distinct from the absolute perfection. For there are three real relations really distinct from one another, and a distinct reality indicates a distinct perfection. Besides, to be conscious is a perfection; but it is one thing for the Father to be conscious of the Son and the Spirit, another for the Son to be conscious of the Father and the Spirit, and still another for the Spirit to be conscious of the Father and the Son. (Fs)

431c We answer this in the following way. We agree that a distinct absolute reality indicates a distinct perfection; but that a distinct relative reality by itself alone indicates a distinct perfection, we deny. We also deny that a distinct relative reality together with its correlative indicates a perfection that is really distinct from the absolute, but we concede that it indicates a perfection that is conceptually distinct from the absolute. (Fs)

431d We reply to the added reason in the same way. For 'to be conscious' can be taken absolutely or relatively, and in God, as there is one act, there is one consciousness. And just as there are three persons, so there are three who are mutually conscious, and this mutual consciousness is not really distinct from that one consciousness whereby the three are mutually conscious. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vollkommenheit (perfectio); Einwand: ein und dieselbe V. kann nicht V. eines Aktes sein und V. einer Ordnung

Kurzinhalt: ... so also we do not perfectly understand that one real perfection has at once the formality of act and the formality of the unity of order. And yet, ...

Textausschnitt: 431e Next, a difficulty from the opposite side. A perfection that is really the same cannot be both the perfection of the act and the perfection of the unity of order. Therefore, the opinion that has been proposed leads to absurdity. (Fs)

433a We answer this as follows. Just as in this life we do not perfectly understand that a divine procession involves simultaneously the reality of an emanation and the consubstantiality of what emanates, or that the divine relations are identical with a third without being identical with one another, or that the divine reality means three persons in one nature, so also we do not perfectly understand that one real perfection has at once the formality of act and the formality of the unity of order. And yet, as the former, so also the latter can be imperfectly understood in the sense that over the centuries this understanding increases (DB 1795, DS 3016, ND 132; DB 1800, DS 3020, ND 136). For by reason of the fact that in God there is one act and one consciousness, perfection is understood in connection with the formality of act; and by reason of the fact that in God through the intellectual emanations there are constituted three conscious subjects within the same consciousness, perfection is understood in connection with the formality of order. (Fs)

433b But, the objector goes on, according to the above-mentioned opinion, there is not as much perfection in each of the persons as in the three together, since the perfection of the unity of order is found not singly in each person but in the three taken together. On the contrary, according to the authorities, there is as much perfection in each of the three as in the three together.1 This opinion, therefore, is inadmissible. (Fs)

433c In reply we assert that also according to our opinion there is as much perfection in each of the persons as in all three together. For we affirm that there is only one real perfection; and where there is only one real perfection, it obviously cannot in itself be more or less. (Fs)

433d As to the reason adduced by the objector, two points should be noted. First, the authorities are concerned mainly with the consubstantiality of the persons,2 lest anyone believe that the Father and the Son are more than the Father, as Peter and Paul are more than Peter alone. Second, the authorities teach the circumincession of the three as clearly as they teach the equality of one with the three. Thus, what may seem to be subtracted through this equality is, so to speak, restored through circumincession. For by reason of their equality, there is no more in the three than in one person; but by reason of their circumincession, the Son is entire in the Father, and the Holy Spirit is entire in the Father, and similarly the other two persons are in the Son and also in the Holy Spirit (DB 704, DS 1331, ND 326). (Fs)

435a Accordingly, the objection is answered by distinguishing between our way of thinking and the reality of God. We concede that when we are thinking of one person and prescinding from the other two we are unable to consider the divine perfection of order. But we deny that in such a consideration we are adverting to the perfection that is present in each of the divine persons; for according to the doctrine of circumincession, there is in each of the divine persons not only the very substance of the other persons but also the relation or personal property that is really identical with this substance. (Fs)

435b Therefore, be careful not to confuse (1) that which a divine person is with (2) the perfection that is in a divine person. The Father is not the Son, but the Father is in the Son (John 10.38, 14.10, 11, 20; 17.21, 23). (Fs)

435c A final objection. At least this matter is easier to understand when the only ground of perfection recognized in God is act. (Fs)

435d Our reply to this is that when one is dealing with mystery, an easier understanding can hardly be a truer one. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Die göttlichen Sendungen; Gott - kontingente Wahrheit: Gründung in Gott, Ziel in der Kreatur

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 15 - What is truly predicated contingently of the divine persons is constituted by the divine perfection itself, but it has a consequent condition in an appropriate external term

Textausschnitt: 439a The principle in all of this is that contingent truths, whether predicated of the divine persons commonly or properly, have their constitution in God but their term in creatures. Therefore, although the external works of God are necessarily common to the three persons, the missions in the strict sense are necessarily proper, since a divine person operates by reason of the divine essence but is not really and truly sent except by reason of a relation of origin. Accordingly, the entire question is reduced to a question of fact, namely, whether not only the Son but also the Holy Spirit has really and truly been sent. (Fs)

[...]

Argument

441c First, what is truly predicated contingently of the divine persons is constituted by the divine perfection itself. (Fs)

For where there is present a formality constitutive of infinite perfection, any other formality is superfluous. But each divine person as well as all together are infinite in perfection. Therefore, any constitutive formality other than the divine perfection itself is superfluous for constituting whatever is truly predicated contingently of the divine persons. (Fs)

441d Second, what is truly predicated contingently of the divine persons has no correspondence of truth without an appropriate external term. (Fs)

For the correspondence of truth is lacking where a truth is contingent but the corresponding reality is absolutely necessary. But our inquiry is explicidy about contingent truths, and the divine perfection is absolutely necessary; therefore, if there is no external term, there is no correspondence of truth. (Fs)

441e Third, the necessary external term is not a constitutive cause but only a condition, and indeed a condition that is not prior or simultaneous but consequent. (Fs)

443a It is not a constitutive cause, both because that is superfluous where infinite perfection is present, and because each thing is constituted by its own reality and not by that of another. (Fs)

It is only a condition, because it is not a cause, and yet it is necessarily required. (Fs)

It is not an antecedent or a simultaneous but a consequent condition, because the divine persons are absolutely independent with respect to all created things. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vater, Sohn: Sendung, um die Menschen zu erlösen; Bibelstellen; Schlossfolgerung

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 22 - Did God the Father send his Son to redeem the human race?

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 22 - Did God the Father send his Son to redeem the human race?

447a Our answer is that sacred scripture most clearly teaches that God the Father sent his Son to redeem the human race. Still, lest the question regarding the missions of the divine persons seem to be about concepts rather than realities, it is best to quote the following texts. (Fs)

Galatians 4.4: 'But when the fullness of time had come, God sent his Son, born of a woman, born under the law, in order to redeem those who were under the law, so that we might receive adoption as children.'

447b St John has more fully expounded this same teaching. For the one who sends is God the Father (John 3.16-17, 5.23, 8.16, 14.24, 20.21), the living Father (6.57), the Father testifying (5.37), the Father drawing [people to Jesus] (6.44), the Father giving a command [to Jesus] (12.49), the only true God (17.3), whom the persecutors do not know (15.21). (Fs)

The Son who was sent teaches not a doctrine of his own but that of the one who sent him (John 7.16, 7.18, 8.28, 12.49, 14-24); similarly, the Son who was sent seeks not a will of his own but the will of the one who sent him (4.24, 5.30, 6.38, 8.29); indeed, the Son can do nothing by himself (5.19, 5.30). (Fs)

447c The Son was not sent to be alone (John 8.16, 8.29, 10.30, 38), nor did he come on his own (7.28, 8.42); but he knows the one from whom he is and who has sent him (7.29), and he can say, 'Whoever sees me sees him who sent me' (12.45), and finally, he goes to him 'who sent me' (7.33, 16.5). (Fs)

The Son was sent out of the Father's love (1 John 4.9; John 3.16; Romans 8.32), was sent in the likeness of sinful flesh (Romans 8.3), for the salvation of the world (John 3.17), that we might live through him (1 John 4.9), that the world might believe and know the Father who sends and the Son who is sent (John 5.24, 6.29, 11.42, 17.8, 21, 23, 25) and have eternal life (John 5.24, 17.3). (Fs)

447d This mission has its extension. For just as the Father sends the Son, so the Son sends the apostles (John 17.18, 20.21). 'Just as the living Father sent me, and I live because of the Father, so whoever eats me will live because of me' (John 6.57; see 5.26). 'Whoever receives one whom I send receives me; and whoever receives me receives him who sent me' (John 13.20; see Matthew 10.40, Luke 10.16); conversely, 'Anyone who does not honor the Son does not honor the Father who sent him' (John 5.23). (Fs)

449a It is clear, therefore, (1) that a divine person is the one sending, (2) that another divine person is sent, (3) that the divine person who is sent lives because of the one sending, teaches the doctrine of the one sending, wills the aim of the one sending, and performs the works of the one sending, (4) that the divine person is sent to human persons in order that they may live, believe, know, love, and perform greater works (John 14.12; see 9.3-4, 10.32, 10.37, 14-10-11, 15.24, 174), and (5) that through the mediation of others this mission extends to other human persons. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vater, Sohn: Sendung des Geistes; Bibelstellen

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 23 - Do the Father and the Son send the Holy Spirit?

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 23 - Do the Father and the Son send the Holy Spirit?

449b Our answer is that sacred scripture clearly and with certitude teaches the sending of the Holy Spirit by the Father and the Son, although there are fewer texts concerning this mission. (Fs)

Galatians 4.6: 'And because you are children, God has sent the Spirit of his Son into your hearts, crying, "Abba, Father.'"
John 14.26: 'But the Advocate, the Holy Spirit, whom the Father will send in my name, will teach you everything, and remind you of all that I have said to you.' See John 14.16-17. (Fs)

John 15.26: 'When the Advocate comes, whom I will send to you from the Father, the Spirit of truth who comes from the Father, he will testify on my behalf.' See John 16.7 and 1 Peter 1.12. (Fs)

449c Hence, the Holy Spirit who is sent is said to be given (John 14.15; Romans 5.5; 1 Thessalonians 4.8; 1 John 3.24, 4.13), to be received (Romans 8.15; 1 Corinthians 3.2; Galatians 3.2; John 20.22; see 2 Corinthians 11.4), to be had (Romans 8.9; 1 Corinthians 7.40; see Hebrews 6.4;Jude 19), indwelling (Romans 8.9, 11; 1 Corinthians 3.16, 6.19; 2 Timothy 1.14), to be poured out (Titus 3.5; Acts 2.33), to be supplied (Galatians 3.5), to be the pledge of our inheritance (Ephesians 1.14; see 2 Corinthians 1.22; Romans 8.23), to be a seal (Ephesians 1.13, 4.30). (Fs)

449d Besides, as the doctrine of the Son who is sent is not his own but that of the Father, so also the Spirit who is sent does not teach his own doctrine; John 16.13: 'When the Spirit of truth comes, he will guide you into all the truth; for he will not speak on his own, but will speak whatever he hears ...'

451a Furthermore, as the Son who is sent is not alone (John 8.16, 29), so also the Spirit who is sent and indwelling is not alone. For after John tells about the Advocate who is to be sent 'to be with you forever' and says that 'he abides with you, and he will be in you' (John 14.16-17), he soon adds, 'We will come to them and make our home with them' (John 14.23). St Paul likewise very easily goes from the Spirit to Christ: '... since the Spirit of God dwells in you' (Romans 8.9), and 'if Christ is in you' (Romans 8.10). Thus, both John and Paul sometimes speak of God abiding (1 John 4.12, 13, 16), and of the temple of God (1 Corinthians 3.16, 6.16). (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vater, Son, Geist; Sendung (missio): zwei Arten; Bibelstellen

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 24 - Is a divine person sent by the one or those from whom he proceeds? ...
Influenced by these authorities, St Thomas distinguished two senses of the word 'mission.' In the first sense, ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 24 - Is a divine person sent by the one or those from whom he proceeds?

451b Our answer is that 'mission' can be understood in two ways: in the first way, according to the teaching and manner of speaking found in the New Testament itself; in the second way, according to the teaching and manner of speaking found in other documents. (Fs) (notabene)

451c If 'mission' is understood in the first way, it is clear that a divine person himself is sent and indeed is sent by that person or by those persons from whom he proceeds. For in the New Testament (1) the Father alone among the divine persons is not sent; (2) the Son is sent to the world by the Father to teach not his own doctrine but that of the Father, to seek not his own will but that of the Father, to perform not his own works but those of the Father; (3) the Holy Spirit is sent by the Father and the Son, not to speak on his own but to teach what he has heard; (4) St Paul in the very same text (Galatians 4.4-6) uses the word exapostello twice, first to designate the mission of the Son and then to designate the mission of the Spirit of the Son; and (5) in the New Testament the words apostello, apostolos, exapostello, and pempo generally have a somewhat technical meaning, namely, that the person sent receives authority from the one sending to fulfil some duty towards others.1 (Fs)

451d For this reason Catholic theologians regularly teach that the relation of origin of the person sent is included in the formality of mission,2 and accordingly regularly argue that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Son because he is sent by the Son. (Fs)

453a Still, not all documents speak in the same way as the New Testament. For Isaiah 48.16 reads, 'And now the Lord God and his Spirit has sent me.'3 This text St Augustine4 and the Eleventh Council of Toledo5 understood as the sending of the Son by the Holy Spirit. Influenced by these authorities, St Thomas distinguished two senses of the word 'mission.' In the first sense, the person sending is understood as the principle of the person sent; in the second sense, the person sending is understood as the principle of any effect produced externally.6 The New Testament uses the word in the first sense, as seems quite clear from the texts cited above. Some other documents are to be understood in the second sense, since in fact they are only about an effect produced in Christ as man.7

453b With all this well understood, we proceed to answer this question. When the sense is that a divine person is really and truly sent by a divine person, as is the case in the New Testament, a real relation 'who from another' is included in the very formality of mission; and since this sort of real relation in God is not really distinct from the relation of origin, it necessarily follows that a divine person is not sent except by the one or by those from whom that person proceeds. When, however, the sense is that any finite effect is produced externally, 'mission' is broadly understood as production, and in reality the three divine persons equally produce this effect, even though by appropriation it is predicated of only one or of two. (Fs) (notabene)

453c In what follows, note that, unless some other meaning is clear, 'mission' is always understood in the technical sense, as in John 20.21, 'As the Father has sent me, so I send you.'

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Heiliger Geist: Sendung (drei Weisen)

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 25 - Is it by appropriation that the Father and the Son are said to send the Holy Spirit? ... first, that a finite spiritual effect is produced in a creature; second, that the third divine person himself comes into a creature ...

Textausschnitt: 453d That the Holy Spirit is sent can be understood in three ways: first, that a finite spiritual effect is produced in a creature; second, that the third divine person himself comes into a creature; third, that the third divine person himself is really and truly sent by the other two. (Fs) (notabene)

455a The first sense of the Holy Spirit being sent is possible only by appropriation; for all works of God ad extra are common to the three persons. (Fs)

455b In the second sense, there is clearly no more than appropriation, for 'to come' in itself does not imply a relation of origin, and where there is no distinction by relational opposition, everything is common. (Fs)

455c In the third sense, there can be no appropriation. For if the Holy Spirit is really and truly sent by the others, there is in the Holy Spirit himself a true and real relation according to which he is ordered to the ones who send as to those from whom. This real relation of the Holy Spirit can only be passive spiration, which is wholly proper to the Holy Spirit. (Fs)

Thus, this third sense seems to be more in keeping with the teaching of the New Testament, as presented above. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Hervorgang (processio) - Sendung (missio); Problem: absolute Vollkommenheit - kontingente Ursache -> 3 Thesen; Lösung: konstituiert in der göttlichen Relation bei nachfolgender kontingenter Realität

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 17/1 - The mission of a divine person is constituted by a divine relation of origin in such a way that it still demands an appropriate external term as a consequent condition.

Textausschnitt: ASSERTION 17

The mission of a divine person is constituted by a divine relation of origin in such a way that it still demands an appropriate external term as a consequent condition.
Meaning of the assertion

455d Since it is clear from the foregoing that the Son is sent by the Father, and the Holy Spirit by the Father and the Son, we now go on to ask about the ontological constitution of a mission. (Fs)

455e Since we have more fully explained elsewhere what is meant by 'ontological constitution,"1 it will suffice here to illustrate this notion by an example. Let us suppose that it is true that 'Peter is this wise man.' Then, to ask about the ontological constitution of this truth is nothing else than to ask what in reality is required and is sufficient for it to be true that Peter is this wise man. Now, the following are required and are sufficient: (1) an act of existence, for it to be true that Peter is, (2) individuating matter, for it to be true that Peter is this, (3) a human substantial form, for it to be true that Peter is this man, (4) the habit of wisdom received in his possible intellect, for it to be true that Peter is wise, and (5) a being-which, a subsistent, composed of all the above, in order to have Peter with these attributes. (Fs) (notabene)

457a We ask, therefore, what is required and is sufficient for it to be true that the Son is sent by the Father, and that the Holy Spirit is sent by the Father and the Son. (Fs)

457b We answer this question with two assertions: first, that the mission of a divine person is constituted by a divine relation of origin itself; second, that although such a mission is constituted by a relation of origin alone, nevertheless an appropriate external term is required. Therefore we are saying nothing more than what we have said previously, in a general way in assertion 15 concerning all that are truly predicated contingently of the divine persons, and in the same general way concerning those predications that attribute a cognitive, volitional, or productive contingent operation to a divine person as divine, and in a particular way when treating elsewhere the ontological constitution of Christ.'2
For the present we are not determining the nature of the appropriate term of the missions but will leave that for later questions. (Fs)

Various opinions

457c Regarding what is truly predicated contingently of one or other divine person as divine, two points are clear, namely, (1) that nothing real and intrinsic is added to a divine person as divine on account of such a truth, and (2) that such a truth has no correspondence with reality without an appropriate external term. The first is clear, because a divine person as divine is immutable; the second is also clear, because there can be no contingent truth without a contingent reality. (Fs) (notabene)

457d However, regarding the constitution of these contingent truths, there are three principal divisions among theologians. (Fs)

To the first group belong those who hold that such a contingent truth is constituted not by the unchanged divine reality but by the appropriate external term - that is to say, inasmuch as this term regards in a special way the divine person about whom a true contingent predication is made. Thus, concerning the incarnation, the followers of Scotus and Tiphanus posit a special relation in the assumed nature to the assuming Word alone. Similarly, concerning the uncreated gift of the Holy Spirit, many authors hold that this gift is constituted as given by the fact that there is in sanctifying grace a special relation to the divine gift, which gift is in fact either the Holy Spirit himself or is said to be the Holy Spirit by appropriation. (Fs) (notabene)

457e Others, however, are of the opinion that each and every thing is constituted by its own proper reality and that therefore the relation alone of the term does not suffice. Hence, to this second group belong those who say that these contingent truths are constituted by some sort of union of the infinite and the finite. They hold that just as matter and form are united, or essence and existence, or potency and act, so also the infinite and the finite are united in some preeminent manner. Concerning the incarnation, this is the opinion of those who suppose some eminent actuation of the assumed human essence through the divine existence of the Word; and, in a similar way, a number of theologians since Petavius want to conceive the uncreated gift of the Holy Spirit as given somehow by way of some form of our sanctification or at least of adoption.3 (Fs)

459a Still others consider that the finite is composed of intrinsic causes because it is finite, so that there is no true similitude between the constitution of the infinite and the composition of a finite being. And since these also hold that each thing is constituted by its proper reality, they have recourse to the infinite divine reality as infinite. (Fs) (notabene)
459b The opinion of the third group, which we are defending, distinguishes first of all between that which is added to the infinite, namely, nothing, and that which is constituted by the infinite, namely, what is not finite. (Fs)

459c Next, it finds an analogy, not in created things, but in divinity itself. For just as God knows that contingent things exist through his own knowledge, and not through an external term, which is nevertheless required, and just as God wills that contingent things exist through his own volition, and not through an external term, which is nevertheless required, and just as God makes contingent things exist through his own omnipotence and not through an external term, which is nevertheless required, so also the [incarnate] Son is all that he is through his own proper divine act of existence and not through an external term, which is nevertheless absolutely required,4 and the Holy Spirit is sent through that which the Holy Spirit is and not through an external term, which is nevertheless absolutely required. (Fs) (notabene)

459d According to this third opinion, then, both what is common and what is proper, and what is necessary and what is contingent, are truly predicated of divine persons as divine. All of these are constituted by the very reality of the divine person, the common by their common reality, the proper by their proper reality, the necessary without any condition, and finally the contingent with a consequent condition. But if no one can deny that common contingent truths are constituted by the divine reality, with a consequent condition - that God knows that contingent things exist by his own knowledge,5 and so on - one can hardly assign a reason why proper contingent truths are not likewise constituted by the very reality of a divine person, with a consequent condition. (Fs) (notabene)

461a We have considered the opinions of these three groups separately. Considerable clarity will be added if we compare them with one another. (Fs)

461b The greatest difference is between the first and the third. In the first, a divine procession is presupposed, but a mission is found formally in an external term. In the third, however, an external term is indeed required as a consequent condition, but the mission of a divine person itself is constituted by a divine relation of origin. The second group occupies the middle ground between these two extremes, maintaining that a mission is constituted according to some remote analogy taken from composite things. (Fs) (notabene)

461c Now, from the first opinion there follows the corresponding doctrine put forth by Galtier: that while a procession belongs to the formality of a mission, still a term is what determines and constitutes it;6 that a mission presupposes and includes an eternal procession, but exists formally from the production of a new effect;7 that external operations are common, that relations of a creature to God are consequent upon these operations, and since there is nothing proper to the Holy Spirit in an operation, there can be nothing proper to the Holy Spirit in such a relation; that therefore it is by appropriation that the Holy Spirit is said to be sent invisibly;8 and that the Greek Fathers themselves do not assert such a proper operation or a consequent relation.9

461d The third opinion proceeds in the opposite way. For if the Holy Spirit is really and truly sent by the Father and the Son, there is present in the Holy Spirit himself a real relation, 'who from others.' This real relation is really identical with passive spiration but conceptually distinguished from it. It is really identical, because nothing real and intrinsic can be added to the infinite perfection of a divine person; it is conceptually distinct, because passive spiration is eternal and necessary and needs no created term, whereas a mission is temporal and contingent and requires a created consequent term as a condition. You can hardly say that this is most strange, since it is exactly what you hold with regard to God as really and truly knowing, willing, and creating contingent things, namely, that such knowing, willing, and creating adds nothing to pure act except a conceptual relation. (Fs) (notabene)

463a But the greatest theological difference is between the first and the third opinion. For according to the third opinion, a term follows a mission, and therefore if there is a mission there is necessarily a term. Nor is there any requirement that scripture or the Fathers posit a term that theologians consider appropriate; it is quite sufficient that the sources of revelation affirm that one divine person is the one sending and another the one sent.10 But according to the first opinion, a mission follows a term, and unless an appropriate term as such is clearly and distinctly affirmed in the documents, a theologian can doubt whether the question here is really about a mission in the proper sense.11 (Fs) (notabene Fußnoten)

463b The second and third opinions differ in the analogies they use. The second opinion seeks an analogy in composite created things, so that the union of the just and the Spirit that is given is conceived as somehow like the union of matter and form or of potency and act.12 The third opinion, however, seeks its analogy in the divinity itself: just as proper contingents are predicated of one or other of the divine persons, so common contingents are predicated of the three divine persons; and just as the latter are constituted by infinite act with the addition of a conceptual relation, so also the former are similarly constituted by an infinite relation of origin with the addition of a conceptual relation. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Hervorgang (processio) - Sendung (missio); Argumente, Begründung; Sendung als kontingente Wahrheit erfordert einen "äußeren" Term

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 17/2 - The mission of a divine person is constituted by ... Whatever is contingently true cannot have the correspondence of truth through a reality that is simple and necessary ...

Textausschnitt: Argument

463c It is argued, first, that the mission of a divine person is not constituted without a divine relation of origin; second, that nothing more is required for a mission to be constituted than a relation of origin; third, that a mission as contingent and temporal requires an appropriate external term, not as a constitutive but only as a consequent condition. (Fs) (notabene)

Argument for the first part

465a Inasmuch as it is true that the Father sends the Son, it is true that the Father is the one sending, that the Father is not the one sent, that the Son is not the one sending, and that the Son is the one sent. Now, opposites are not really and truly predicated of the divine persons except according to relations of origin; but 'to be sending' and 'to be sent' are opposites that are really and truly predicated of divine persons; therefore they are predicated according to relations of origin. (Fs)

The major premise is clear and certain from the principle that everything is one where there is no distinction by relational opposition (DB 703, DS 1330, ND 325). (Fs)

The minor is clear from sacred scripture, as has been already established. (Fs)

465b Similarly, inasmuch as it is true that the Father and the Son send the Holy Spirit, it is true that the Father and the Son are the ones who send and not the ones sent, and that the Holy Spirit is the one sent and not the one sending. Thus, the argument here is the same as above. (Fs)

Argument for the second part

465c Where there is present a cause or constitutive reason that is infinite in perfection, every other cause or constitutive reason is superfluous. (Fs)

But for the divine missions to be constituted there is a cause or reason that is infinite in perfection, namely, a real relation of origin, which is really identical with the divine essence. (Fs)

465d Therefore, for the divine missions to be constituted, any other cause or constitutive reason besides a relation of origin is superfluous. (Fs)

The major premise is clear from the very notion of the infinite. For what is infinite is not limited to this or that; and what is in no way limited is at least sufficient for all that is known with certainty.1

The minor is clear from the reason given for it. (Fs)

465e Therefore, just as a divine person is and knows and wills and operates by the divine essence, and is distinguished as generating or generated, or as spirating or spirated, by a divine relation of origin, so also a divine person is constituted as sending or as sent by a divine relation of origin. (Fs)

Argument for the third part

465f Whatever is contingently true cannot have the correspondence of truth through a reality that is simple and necessary and this alone. (Fs) (notabene)

467a But the fact that a divine person sends or is sent is contingently true; for all that can be or not be exists by a sovereignly free divine decision; and absolutely speaking, creation, incarnation, and sanctification could have not been. (Fs)

Therefore, the fact that a divine person sends or is sent cannot have the correspondence of truth through the divine perfection alone, and therefore requires an appropriate external term. (Fs)

467b Besides, this term is required as a condition consequent upon the mission itself. For the person sending and also the person sent in no way depend upon a creature and therefore, although the term is a condition because it is necessary, still it cannot be either a prior or a simultaneous condition. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Hervorgang (processio) - Sendung (missio); S.: Konstitution, Schöpfung: aktiv und passiv (Unterschiede); Inkarnation, Gabe des Geistes: materialer äußerer Term; Kategorie der Substanz - Qualität (heiligmachende Gnade); 4 übernatürliche Realitäten

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 26 - In what ways is an appropriate external term consequent upon a constituted mission? ... In the incarnation the material external term is the nonsubsistent human nature, since ... but in the giving of the Holy Spirit the material ...

Textausschnitt: 467c To understand the previous assertion, note that God is both being by intellect and agent by intellect. God is being by intellect since God's being is God's understanding and willing; God is agent by intellect since God's creating is again God's understanding and willing. For this reason, by the very fact that the Father and the Son and the Holy Spirit conceive1 and will the sending of a divine person, the constituted mission itself and the appropriate created external term are already present.2 The constitution is present because God is being by intellect and therefore what God understands about God is God. There is the creation because God is agent by intellect and therefore what God understands to be outside God is outside God. (Fs) (notabene)

467d Therefore, if the following are distinguished, (1) constitution in the active sense, (2) constitution in the passive sense, (3) creation in the active sense, and (4) creation in the passive sense, then
(1) constitution in the active sense is common to the three persons, since the Three conceive and will both that the Father send the Son and that the Father and the Son send the Holy Spirit;
469a

(2) constitution in the passive sense is proper to the one sending and to the one sent, since the Three conceive and will, not that three send and that three be sent, but that the Father send the Son and the Father and the Son send the Holy Spirit;

(3) creation in the active sense is common to the three persons, since the Three conceive and will that the appropriate external term be created, and since the very conceiving, together with the will, is the omnipotent act of creating;

(4) although constitution in the active sense and creation in the active sense are common to the three persons, still they are common to the Three not confusedly but distinctly; for the fact itself that the Son understands and wills that he be sent by the Father he has from the Father, just as he has his substance from the Father; and the fact itself that the Holy Spirit understands and wills that he be sent by the Father and the Son he has from the Father and the Son, just as he has his substance from them; and the same must be said concerning creation in the active sense;

(5) creation in the passive sense is the appropriate external term itself as dependent upon its first efficient cause;

(6) nothing real and intrinsic is added to the intrinsically immutable divine persons, whether by constitution in the active sense or by constitution in the passive sense or by creation in the active sense;

(7) and yet through their infinite and unlimited divine perfection, either common or proper according to the case, the Three really and truly constitute, are really and truly constituted as sending and sent, respectively,3 and the three persons really and truly equally create the appropriate terms;
(8) for just as divine immutability makes impossible a real, intrinsic addition, so also divine infinity renders such an addition superfluous. (Fs)

469b Furthermore, the incarnation of the Son and the giving of the Holy Spirit are similar as to the manner of their constitution and creation but differ as to what is constituted and created. They are similar as to the manner, because the above eight statements are verified in each; but as to what is constituted and created, they are in many respects entirely different. (Fs)

469c In the incarnation the material external term is the nonsubsistent human nature, since the union is in the person; but in the giving of the Holy Spirit the material external term is a subsistent human nature, since the union of grace is between persons. Therefore, just as the latter nature subsists through its proper proportionate act of existence, so the former nature does not subsist, since it lacks a proper proportionate act of existence. (Fs) (notabene)

471a Besides, in the incarnation the Son is both God and man through his own divine act of existence. This contingent truth as contingent has its correspondence of truth through a secondary act of existence by which the nonsubsistent nature is assumed; and since this assumption exceeds the proportion of nature, this secondary act of existence likewise exceeds the proportion of the assumed nature.1 But in the giving of the Holy Spirit, it is through his own proper perfection that the Holy Spirit is gift and is given to the just. This contingent truth as contingent has its correspondence of truth through sanctifying grace whereby a subsistent nature is rendered holy and pleasing to God; and since both the uncreated gift and the created holiness exceed the proportion of this nature, sanctifying grace also exceeds the proportion of nature. (Fs) (notabene)

In the incarnation, therefore, the formal external term is a secondary act of existence that is reduced to the category of substance; but in the giving of the Spirit the formal external term is sanctifying grace, which is in the category of quality. (Fs) (notabene)

471b Moreover, although in the incarnation the Son as God is not alone, it is the Son alone who becomes incarnate. But in giving the Spirit, although the Spirit alone according to his proper perfection is gift, still, since to give one's entire love is the same as to give oneself, and since the Father and the Son give their entire proceeding Love, they also give themselves and therefore are said to come and dwell in the just. (Fs) (notabene)

From this we conclude that the Father, the Son, and the Spirit understand, will, constitute, and accomplish different things in the incarnation and in the giving of the Spirit. (Fs)

471ca But if one asks about the supernatural character of the formal terms, it is pertinent to note the following. First, there are four real divine relations, really identical with the divine substance, and therefore there are four very special modes that ground the external imitation of the divine substance. Next, there are four absolutely supernatural realities, which are never found uninformed,1 namely, the secondary act of existence of the incarnation, sanctifying grace, the habit of charity, and the light of glory. It would not be inappropriate, therefore, to say that the secondary act of existence of the incarnation is a created participation of paternity, and so has a special relation to the Son; that sanctifying grace is a participation of active spiration, and so has a special relation to the Holy Spirit; that the habit of charity is a participation of passive spiration, and so has a special relation to the Father and the Son; and that the light of glory is a participation of sonship, and so in a most perfect way brings the children of adoption back to the Father. (Fs)

473a But if one says that God operates externally not according to the relations but according to the common nature, and therefore the real divine relations cannot be participated in in this way, we must answer with a distinction. The objection would be true if God were a natural agent that could produce only something similar in nature, as fire always produces heat and water always causes moisture. But the divine nature common to the Three is intellectual, and just as God by the divine intellect knows the four real relations, so also by the divine intellect, together with the divine will, God can produce beings that are finite yet similar [to the four real relations] and absolutely supernatural. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sendung (missio) - ihre gegenseitige Ordnung; Taufe

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 28 - Are the divine missions ordered to each other? ... From all this, we gain some understanding of the order of the divine missions; for the Son was sent so that the Father might be able to love us as he loves his own Son, ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 28 - Are the divine missions ordered to each other?

479c Our answer is that the divine missions are indeed constituted by the relations of origin themselves of the divine persons, but that they entail an appropriate external term as a consequent condition. Now there is an order in the divine missions as regards both constitution and consequent terms. (Fs)
479d As regards constitution, then, since in God there is an order of nature or origin,1 there is no procession of love except in an order to the procession of the Word.2 Hence also, the Son is not any kind of Word, but the Word breathing forth or spirating Love.3 Therefore, since the missions are constituted by the divine processions and relations, it is clear that as to their constitution the missions have an order to each other. (Fs)

481a That there is an order as regards their terms is clear from the fact that 'God sent his Son ... so that we might receive adoption as children. And because you are children, God has sent the Spirit of his Son into your hearts crying, "Abba, Father!"'4 From these words it seems we must understand that the mission of the Son is to make us children of God by adoption; and that the mission of the Holy Spirit is in accord with this adoption. But precisely what this connection is needs further consideration. (Fs)

481b Now, as we have said above, the Holy Spirit is sent as a special and notional divine love. The special divine love is that according to which the just are loved as ordered to the divine good. But since God does everything in accord with the order of his justice,5 this special love itself supposes a special reason.6 And this special reason cannot be other than God's own Son, who is both mediator and redeemer. (Fs)

481c The Son is mediator because as a divine person he has a human nature.7 This means that God the Father, as he loves the divine Son and gives to him by the Holy Spirit, so he loves the Son as man and gives to him by the Holy Spirit. This is revealed to us in the baptismal epiphany. For as the Father was saying, 'This is my Son, the Beloved, with whom I am well pleased,' the Son coming up out of the water 'saw the Spirit of God descending like a dove and alighting on him.'8 Here at the same time the love of the Father, which is the Holy Spirit himself, is affirmed and is manifested as the Holy Spirit himself coming and alighting on Jesus. (Fs)

481d In like manner, Christ's baptism is the exemplar of our baptism. For on account of the redemptive work of the mediator, God the Father also loves the just as he loves his own Son; as it is said, 'You have loved them even as you have loved me.'9 So then, if the Father loves us as he loves his own Son, the Father loves us as though we were his children; and our adoption as children of God is surely a consequence of this love. Again, if the Father loves us as he loves his own Son, he surely loves us and gives to us by the Holy Spirit. From all this, we gain some understanding of the order of the divine missions; for the Son was sent so that the Father might be able to love us as he loves his own Son, and the Spirit is sent because the Father does love us as he loves his own Son. Indeed, this love, which is, as it were, proper to the divine persons, is what implies and grounds the absolutely supernatural order.10 (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sendung (missio) - Analogie zu Sendung im menschlichen Sinn (7 Punkte); Sendung - Mitarbeit des Menschen; Grund der Inkarnation

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 29 - What is the formality of divine mission? ... Now, the following elements fairly well sum up what is found in a human mission: (1) the movement from one place to another so that either (2) some particular operation or (3) ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 29 - What is the formality of divine mission?1

483a Since we cannot conceive the formality of a divine mission except by analogy to a human mission, we must begin from the latter in order that by way of affirmation, negation, and eminence we may to some extent be able to arrive at conceiving a divine mission. (Fs)

483b Now, the following elements fairly well sum up what is found in a human mission: (1) the movement from one place to another so that either (2) some particular operation or (3) some new series of operations may be accomplished there, whether (4) solely by the person sent or (5) by the persons to whom he or she is sent, (6) to be carried out according to the mind or command of the sender (7) revealed and entrusted to or imposed upon the person sent. (Fs) (notabene)
We must now determine which of these seven elements apply to a divine mission, taking them one at a time. (Fs)

483c First, then, movement from one place to another has to do more with the limitations of the human body than with the essence of mission. Hence, even in the case of a human mission this2 local movement may be absent. If, for example, the Papal Nuncio is sent to the Italian government, there is a true and real mission without any change of locale. Therefore, since the divine persons are not only incorporeal but also omnipresent, movement from one place to another contributes little or nothing to our understanding of a divine mission. For although it is quite devotional and most useful for us to imagine the Son or the Holy Spirit coming down from the heights of heaven, our present quest is for an understanding, not an image, of a divine mission.3 (Fs) (notabene)

485a Second, both the mission of the Son and the mission of the Spirit regard not some particular operation but a whole new series of operations. For the Son has been sent to gather up4 and reconcile5 all things, that God may be all in all.6 And the Holy Spirit is sent, not for this or that particular operation, but to preside over the whole of Christian living in every one of the just. (Fs)

485b Third, the Son and the Holy Spirit are related to their respective operations in different ways. Since the Son has assumed unto himself a human nature, he is able through this assumed nature to perform works that are proper to himself. Therefore, since the Son has been sent as mediator, redeemer, reconciler, head of the church, king, and judge, incarnation evidently belongs to the mission of the Son, since all these functions are envisaged as requiring works that are proper to the Son. On the other hand, since the Holy Spirit has no nature other than the divine, he does no works that the Father and the Son do not likewise do, and from this we conclude that the Holy Spirit is not sent in such a way as to do anything by himself alone, without the other divine persons. (Fs)

485c Fourth, since the end of a mission involves cooperation on the part of others, a mission is carried out not so much that works be done as that new personal relations be initiated and strengthened. The end of the divine missions is not attained without the cooperation of human beings: 'He who created you without you will not justify you without you.'7 Hence, in order to understand a divine mission, one must consider not only the works proper to the person sent but also the personal relations that that person initiates or strengthens in order that the end of the mission may be attained through the cooperation of others. (Fs)

487a There pertains to the mission of the Son, therefore, that friendship which he commends: 'As the Father has loved me, so I have loved you; abide in my love. If you keep my commandments, you will abide in my love, just as I have kept my Father's commandments and abide in his love.'1
Similarly, there pertain to the mission of the Holy Spirit those intimate relations whereby we are not our own: 'Do you not know that your body is a temple of the Holy Spirit within you ... and that you are not your own?'2 'And do not grieve the Holy Spirit of God, with which you were marked with a seal for the day of redemption.'3

487b Fifth, all anthropomorphism must be excluded from a divine mission, and therefore in God both the mind of the sender and the revelation of that mind are nothing other than what we said concerning the constitution of a divine mission. (Fs)

487c Sixth, since the divine missions are ordered to each other, there is a single, total end to both missions. For the Son is sent 'while we were enemies,'4 to initiate through his work as mediator and redeemer and reconciler new interpersonal relations between God the Father and all human persons. And the Holy Spirit will be sent as 'the pledge of our inheritance,'5 when God has 'saved us, not because of any works of righteousness that we had done, but according to his mercy, through the water of rebirth and renewal by the Holy Spirit. This Spirit he poured out on us richly through Jesus Christ our Savior, so that, having been justified by his grace, we might become heirs according to the hope of eternal life.'6

487d Seventh, since there is one overall end to both missions, and since this end is not attained without the cooperation of human persons, the different terms of the missions can be distinguished on the basis of the different stages whereby the end of the missions is brought about. (Fs) (notabene)

487e Therefore, the mission of the Son begins with the incarnation, not because the Son is sent in order to assume a human nature,7 but because through the incarnation the Son is constituted as the mediator sent to us. The mission of the Son was carried on throughout his mortal life, during which time the Son of Man entered into personal relationships with the children of men. A principal objective of his mission was accomplished when in dying on the cross he became the source of eternal salvation for all who obey him.8 The mission of the Son is continued through the apostles and their successors: 'as the Father has sent me, so I send you';9 'whoever welcomes you welcomes me, and who welcomes me welcomes the one who sent me';10 'whoever listens to you listens to me, and whoever rejects you rejects me, and whoever rejects me rejects the one who sent me';11 'Saul, Saul, why do you persecute me?'12 (Fs) (notabene)

489a Yet another principal objective of the mission of the Son is accomplished whenever one who is unjust is justified and a just person is further justified; for 'I came that they may have life and have it abundantly.'13 The ultimate end of this mission, however, is attained in the beatific vision of the citizens of heaven, 'when he hands over the kingdom to God the Father.'14

489b Just as the Son has been sent to all people, since he died for all, so is the Holy Spirit sent to each of the just. 'And because you are children, God has sent the Spirit of his Son into your hearts crying, "Abba, Father!" So you are no longer a slave but a child, and if a child then also an heir, through God.'15 'Do you not know that you are God's temple and that God's Spirit dwells in you? If anyone destroys God's temple, God will destroy that person. For God's temple is holy, and you are that temple.'16 '... God's love has been poured into our hearts through the Holy Spirit that has been given to us.'17 '... those who are in the flesh cannot please God. But you are not in the flesh; you are in the Spirit, since the Spirit of God dwells in you.'18 'If the Spirit of him who raised Jesus from the dead dwells in you, he who raised Christ from the dead will give life to your mortal bodies also through his Spirit that dwells in you.'19 For the Spirit, since he is the pledge of our inheritance, is given with an ordination to eternal life, so that the mission of the Spirit tends to the same ultimate end as the mission of the Son. (Fs)

491a This being so, there is not one formality of divine mission. For although each mission is the sending of a divine person, the mission of the Son is from the Father while the mission of the Spirit is from the Father and the Son. Also, although each mission has the same ultimate end, which is the heavenly city for the glory of the Father, the first mission is that of the Son for the reconciliation of all human persons to God the Father, and the consequent mission of the Spirit is to each one of the just, who have been reconciled. Besides, although the two missions are for the sake of initiating and strengthening new personal relationships between God and human beings, the Son, having assumed another nature beside the divine, not only enters into new personal relationships but also through the nature he assumed, and then through those whom he has sent, performs works that are proper to himself; but the Holy Spirit, not having another nature besides the divine, does not do anything proper to himself, but provides the foundation for cooperation in that it is through the Spirit's self-donation that the new personal relationships are strengthened. Finally, since the divine persons are sent to accomplish such a great task throughout the world by themselves or through others, the [external] term of the missions is assigned not in a brief statement, but rather by distinguishing the successive stages of this, the greatest of all works. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sendung (sichtbar, unsichtbar): Sohn, Geist; das Gute - Bestimmung (in sich - durch Teilnahme); partikuläres Gut, Ordnungsgut (5 Elemente)

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 30/1 - Is it appropriate that the divine persons be sent, the Son visibly and the Spirit invisibly?; Again, five elements come together to constitute the human good of order: ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 30 - Is it appropriate that the divine persons be sent, the Son visibly and the Spirit invisibly?
491b We answer that the appropriateness of an action is determined according to its ordination to an end, that an end is a good, and therefore that we must begin from the notion of the good, so that we may then have a clearer knowledge of the end of the divine missions and, third, have some understanding of their aptness for this end. (Fs)

(1) 'Good' refers to two different things: the first is good by its very essence, and this is the divine perfection itself; in this life we do not know this good except analogically. The second is good by participation, and this in turn has a twofold division. For as we said above,1 in the one divine perfection there are two formalities of perfection, one that concerns act and the other that concerns order; and similarly among created things there is a twofold participation in the one divine perfection, one concerning act and the other concerning order. On this basis we distinguish particular goods, by which particular beings are perfected in themselves, and goods of order, which are certain concrete, dynamic, and ordered totalities of desirable objects, of desiring subjects, of operations, and of results. So, for example, there is a distinction between the particular economic goods of a certain region and, on the other hand, the economic order of the region as a whole. It is quite clear that this order is a supreme good, since particular economic goods are greatly increased or diminished according to whether the overall economy is becoming better ordered or is deteriorating. (Fs)

493a Similarly, the good of order itself is appropriately divided as follows: there is the good of order that is found in inanimate things, in plants, and in animals; and there is the human good of order, which is produced by people understanding and willing. Thus, there are produced domestic, technological, economic, political, cultural, scientific, and religious organizations. (Fs)

493b Again, five elements come together to constitute the human good of order: (1) a certain number of persons, (2) cognitive and appetitive habits, (3) many coordinated operations among many persons, (4) a succession and series of particular goods, and (5) interpersonal relationships. For since every individual needs many things in a more or less steady stream, a succession and series of particular goods are required for living well. Since each person alone is hardly self-sufficient, many coordinated operations on the part of many individuals are required to produce a series of particular goods. Since human beings are potential and, by nature, indeterminate,1 cognitive and appetitive habits are required in order to have many coordinated operations involving many persons. Lastly, since persons who know and will acquire habits, perform coordinated operations, and distribute among themselves the particular goods being produced, they will the good of order itself both for themselves and for others; but to will good to someone is to love,2 and the effect of love is that union and mutual intimacy3 which is the most excellent of personal relationships, and so the human good of order leads to interpersonal relationships. (Fs)

493c However, since every good of order is something intelligible, something that is not knowable by the senses, and since human beings are rather slow to understand, it cannot be thought strange that we only gradually arrive at understanding and willing the good of order. For as infants we want particular goods; as children we turn our attention to a series of particular goods (whereby life becomes good), and so we gladly learn practical skills; as adolescents we see the need for cooperation, and consciously enter into new personal relationships; as young men and women we conceive the goods of order, we think of better orders, we protest against abuses and disorder, and we long for reform and perhaps even for revolution. Finally, philosophers reach the point where, besides recognizing particular goods that are appropriate for particular persons, they also recognize the good of order, which is good on account of its own intelligibility and its participation in the divine good, which is desired by the will because the will is an appetite that follows the intellect, and which can be desired by the will even when the good of order produces particular goods not for the one desiring them but for others only.1

495a Furthermore, although the five elements we have listed all mutually cohere, as it were, organically, nevertheless interpersonal relationships claim a certain priority. For we want to communicate what is good to those whom we love; we gladly cooperate with them to bring about what is good; to make our cooperation more effective, we acquire the necessary habits and detest the contrary defects; and so, supposing the union of love, all the other things follow that make for the good of order, as is most plainly seen in marriage. In addition to this there is the fact that, besides a rational intellect and will, there is in our very sensibility an intersubjectivity that disposes us to interpersonal relationships, as is clearly evident from the phenomena of presence, sympathy, transference, and the like. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sendung (sichtbar, unsichtbar): Sohn, Geist; Ordnungsgut: visio beatifica - Königreich Gottes, Leib Christ, Heilsökonomie;

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 30/2 - Is it appropriate that the divine persons be sent ...; Moreover, it was appropriate for one divine person to be sent visibly and the other invisibly. For a mission has a twofold end: ...

Textausschnitt: 495b (2) With these considerations about the nature of the good well understood, we must now go on to consider the end of the divine missions. The ultimate end is of course the divine good itself communicated immediately in the beatific vision, while the proximate end is that good of order which, according to various analogies with human goods of order, is called either the kingdom of God, or the body of Christ, or the church, or the mystical marriage of Christ with the church, or the economy of salvation, or the city of God. The proximate end is called a kingdom because of its similarity to a good political order, a body because of its similarity to the good of order that obtains among the organs of a single body, a church and a city because of its similarity to a social good of order, a marriage because of its similarity to a domestic good of order, and an economy because of its similarity to the good of order in acquiring, producing, and managing material things. (Fs) (notabene)

495c In this good of order are found all the elements that come together to constitute a good of order. It includes many persons, since Christ died for all. There are cognitive and appetitive habits, since from sanctifying grace flow the infused virtues and the gifts of the Holy Spirit. There are many coordinated operations, since Christians put off the old man, live a new life, and love one another. There are successions and series of particular goods, flowing from the benefits that the new life in Christ constantly produces, from the ministry of the word by which the gospel is preached to every creature, from the ministry of life that is seen in sacrifice, in the priesthood, and in the sacraments, and from the hierarchy that regulates and develops the church. Finally, there are the personal relationships that are formed when Christians love one another as Christ has loved them,1 when in loving one another they love Christ,2 when in loving Christ they are loved by the Father,3 and when the Holy Spirit is sent to them by the Father through Christ.4 Fs) (notabene)

497a (3) Now, it is appropriate that the divine persons are sent to constitute and develop this good of order. For although the other goods of order externally imitate that supreme good of order that we observe in the Holy Trinity, nevertheless it was appropriate that the economy of salvation, which is ordered to participation in divine beatitude itself, should not only imitate the order of the Holy Trinity but also in some manner participate in that order. For this reason the very divine persons who from eternity proceed from the Father are also in time sent by the Father to initiate and strengthen new personal relations of reconciliation and love with human persons. In addition to this appropriateness is the fact that through the missions the divine persons are more clearly revealed, and each more ardently loved. (Fs)

497b Moreover, it was appropriate for one divine person to be sent visibly and the other invisibly. For a mission has a twofold end: a person is sent by a person to persons both so that a certain good might be accomplished and so that new personal relations might be initiated or strengthened. Now, since the cooperation among the divine persons is so perfect that there is one simple common operation of the Three, it follows that a divine person as divine can indeed enter into new personal relations but cannot perform works that are proper to himself. Since, therefore, the Son was sent to accomplish the work of mediator and redeemer, it was appropriate for him to assume, a human nature in accord with which he was able to do works proper to himself. But since the Holy Spirit is sent to confirm by uncreated gift the new relations initiated by the Son and to be a pledge of eternal life, it is appropriate that he dwells invisibly in our inmost hearts. (Fs)

499a To this appropriateness of the missions themselves many other instances of appropriateness can be added. It was appropriate for the Mediator that a divine person be in a human nature to teach human beings as a human being, to give them an example of the new life, and to lead them to reconciliation and love and eternal life. It was appropriate for the Redeemer that he was able to the for those whom he wished to the to themselves and live for God. It was appropriate for the Mediator and Redeemer to be the Son, who proceeds as truth from the Father and breathes as holiness that Love which is the Holy Spirit. It was appropriate for the one who proceeds from the Word spirating Love to be sent to us because of the Son. It was appropriate for the one who from eternity is Gift to be given to us as a guest and a pledge. It was likewise appropriate for us that we be drawn to the Father through the visible Son, and that we be drawn away from the realm of the senses, and that in the invisible Spirit we should desire and hope for everlasting life. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sendung: Sohn - Geist; sichtbar - unsichtbar; Vernunft - Wille

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 31 - Is the Son also sent invisibly and the Holy Spirit visibly? - ... inasmuch as the three divine persons produce in a creature those effects that regard the intellect, these are attributed to the Son by appropriation ... invisibly ...

Textausschnitt: 499b Our answer to this question is that some effects of grace regard more the intellect and others more the will. Those that regard the intellect express a certain likeness to the Son, who in God is the Word spirating Love.1 Those that regard the will bear a likeness to the Holy Spirit, who in God is proceeding Love. Therefore, inasmuch as the three divine persons produce in a creature those effects that regard the intellect, these are attributed to the Son by appropriation,2 while those that regard the will are attributed to the Holy Spirit by appropriation.3 In this sense the Son is said to be sent invisibly.4

499c Since, however, the Christian life, which the Holy Spirit interiorly directs, is 'hidden with Christ in God,'5 it was appropriate for the invisible mission of the Holy Spirit to be manifested sensibly by certain exterior signs.6 These manifestations in the form of a dove, of a bright cloud, of wind, and of tongues of fire, in which the Holy Spirit is symbolized in a sign,7 are said to be visible missions. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche Personen im Gerechten; Textstellen, Schrift; Gegenwart, Präsenz (verschieden Weisen); personale G. (Akt, Habitus);

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 32/1 - Is it by way of love that the divine persons are in the just and dwell in them? ... We understand personal presence, therefore, on the basis of acts, but in such a way that the acts have their foundation in habits.

Textausschnitt: 501a With regard to this question, two points must be considered, namely, the fact itself and the understanding of the fact. As to the fact itself, the teaching of the New Testament seems quite clear. (Fs)

1 John 4.16: 'God is love, and those who abide in love abide in God, and God abides in them.'
Ibid. v. 13: 'By this we know that we abide in him and he in us, because he has given us of his Spirit.' See Galatians 4.6; Romans 8.14-17. (Fs)

Ibid. v. 8: 'Whoever does not love does not know God, for God is love.'

John 15.4: 'Abide in me as I abide in you ...'; v. 5: 'I am the vine, you are the branches. Those who abide in me and I in them bear much fruit ...'; v. 9: 'As the Father has loved me, so I have loved you; abide in my love. If you keep my commandments, you will abide in my love, as I have kept my Father's commandments and abide in his love.'

John 14.15: 'If you love me, you will keep my commandments'; v. 16: 'I will ask the Father, and he will give you another Advocate, to be with you for ever. This is the Spirit of truth, whom the world cannot receive, because it neither sees him nor knows him'; v. 17: 'You know him, because he abides with you, and he will be in you'; v. 20: 'On that day you will know that I am in my Father, and you in me, and I in you'; v. 21: 'They who have my commandments and keep them are those who love me; and those who love me will be loved by my Father, and I will love them and reveal myself to them'; v. 23: 'Those who love me will keep my word, and my Father will love diem, and we will come to them and make our home with them.'

John 17.21: '... that they all may be one. As you, Father, are in me and I am in you, may they also be one in us, so that the world may believe that you have sent me'; v. 22: 'The glory that you have given me I have given them, so that they may be one as we are one, [v. 23] I in them and you in me, that they may become completely one, so that the world may know that you have sent me and have loved them as you have loved me'; v. 26: 'I made your name known to diem, and I will make it known, so that the love with which you have loved me may be in them, and I in them.'
Romans 7.17-18, 20: concerning sin as inhabiting and working [in us]. (Fs)

Romans 8.8-11. '... those who are in the flesh cannot please God.1' But you are not in the flesh; you are in the Spirit, since the Spirit of God dwells in you. Anyone who does not have the Spirit of Christ does not belong to him. But if Christ is in you, though the body is dead because of sin, the Spirit is life because of righteousness. If the Spirit of him who raised Jesus from the dead dwells in you, he who raised Christ from the dead will give life to your mortal bodies also through his Spirit that dwells in you.' See also 1 Corinthians 2.16-17, 6.15-20; 13; 2 Corinthians 5.14-21; 2 Timothy 1.13-14. (Fs)

503a From these and almost countless other texts,2 there is clearly a mutual 'being in' that implies not only the uncreated gift of God but also our acts, by which we habitually keep Christ's commandments through love. St Thomas interprets this indwelling, gift, possessing, and enjoying in accord with the fact that through the grace that renders us pleasing God is in the just as the known in the knower and the beloved in the lover.3 We must determine what this means by beginning from objects of sense and gradually proceeding to higher realities. (Fs) (notabene)

503b At first glance, then, presence would seem to be spatial proximity. But one stone can be close to another, and yet we do not think of stones being present to or absent from one another. (Fs)
Second, presence would seem to be a certain psychic adaptation resulting from spatial proximity. Thus, when one animal meets another we can conclude from external signs that a total internal sensitive adaptation has occurred. But if presence is seen as this sort of adaptation, then spatial proximity is only a condition for presence. (Fs)

503c Third, although other animals apparently form only those phantasms that are grounded in immediate sense experience, humans, since they proceed by intellect to the whole of being as the to-be-known, employ the utmost freedom of imagination.4 Therefore, even apart from the proximity of an object, they can be and generally are greatly moved merely by remembering the past or by imagining some future possibility. Hence, if presence consists in a certain psychic adaptation, we must distinguish two kinds of presence in humans, one that results from spatial proximity and another that is based upon the very freedom of human sensibility. (Fs)

505a Fourth, human beings are persons not because they are animals and use their senses, but because they have an intellectual nature and operate in accordance with it. If, therefore, we are speaking about the presence of one person to another, surely we must not leave out of the discussion the operations that are proper to persons. Besides, that which is known is in the knower with an intentional existence, and what is loved is joined and united to the lover, as the poet says about his friend being 'half of my soul.' Therefore the known in the knower and the beloved in the lover are also instances of presence; and since these operations of knowing and loving, insofar as they are performed in the intellectual part of our being, are proper to persons, this presence can be called personal presence. (Fs)

505b Further, only through many acts do we arrive at true knowledge of a person; and we do not acquire knowledge through many acts without thereby acquiring also a habit of knowing; and so it is a habit that provides the foundation of that knowledge by which a person who is truly known is in the knower. (Fs)

505c Again, although one or other act of the will can constitute an impulse towards union, still without a habit of love there will not be those acts of love that manifest the union of the lovers; and so it is a habit that provides the foundation of that love by which a person who is loved is in the lover as another self. (Fs)

505d We understand personal presence, therefore, on the basis of acts, but in such a way that the acts have their foundation in habits. But if we distinguish personal presence from obsession, we must also say that this presence requires not continuous acts but only that frequency that generally results from habits. Just as someone who lives in a house does not stay in the house all the time, so someone who has another person present to himself or herself still thinks about and wills and does many different things. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Göttliche Personen im Gerechten; Ordnungsgut - Gegenwart d. Person; Gott in sich = das Gewusste im Wissenden; Quasi-Identifikationen unter in Liebe verbundenen; Christus als Vermittler (Textstellen, Schrift)

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 32/1 - Is it by way of love that the divine persons are in the just and dwell in them? ... that the degree of perfection by which personal presence is achieved is the same as that by which the good of order is achieved.

Textausschnitt: notabene von: 511c From all of this we conclude that the divine persons themselves and the blessed in heaven and the just on this earth are in one another as those who are known are in those who know them and those who are loved are in those who love them.
---


505e For a better understanding of this, we return to the idea of the good of order. For as we said above,1 (1) persons, (2) interpersonal relationships, (3) cognitive and appetitive habits, (4) many coordinated operations among many persons, and (5) a succession and series of particular goods, are, as it were, organically interconnected. All these elements taken together constitute an intelligible good of order. But since these are the same elements that constitute personal presence, it must be said that the degree of perfection by which the good of order is achieved is the same as that by which personal presence is achieved, and similarly, that the degree of perfection by which personal presence is achieved is the same as that by which the good of order is achieved. (Fs) (notabene)

505f We have, then, distinguished several meanings of 'presence.' One sort of presence is a matter of spatial proximity, and on this basis one stone would be present to or absent from another. Another sort of presence has to do with the adaptation of sensibility resulting from spatial proximity. A third sort of presence, proper to rational animals, supposes only a remembrance of the past or the imagining of some future possibility. Finally, there is personal presence whereby persons, pursuing a common good of order, are mutually in one another as the known in the knower and the beloved in the lover. (Fs) (notabene)

507a From these considerations let us ascend to consider the triune God in order from there to strive for some understanding of the economy of salvation. (Fs)

First, then, God is in himself as the known in the knower and the beloved in the lover. For every mental word is, in the order of intelligible existence, the very thing that is known through that word. Now, God expresses himself through a word, and therefore that word is God in the order of intelligible existence. But in God to be is the same as to understand, and therefore God's natural existence is the same as God's intelligible existence. Hence, what is in God, in the way God the known is in God the knower, is God, not only in the order of intelligible existence but also in the order of natural existence. Thus, the Word of God is God. (Fs)

507b Further, by the very fact that a friend is loved there results a quasi-identification of the friend with the lover. Thus, a friend is said to be a second self, or as the poet says, 'half of my soul.' For friends who pursue a common good of order, work together in an orderly way, and enjoy a succession of particular goods, are so far from living each one for himself or herself that they may rather be said to have one life in common. Now, God loves himself. This divine love of God implies not only a quasi-identification, but even a total identity. For divine willing is God himself, and therefore the Holy Spirit, who proceeds in God as Love, is God. (Fs; tblVrw)

Moreover, God the Father is in the Son, and the Son is in the Father, both as the known in those who know them and the beloved in those who love them. '... and no one knows the Son except the Father, and no one knows the Father except the Son and anyone to whom the Son chooses to reveal him.'1 '... because you loved me before the foundation of the world.'2 '... just as I... abide in his love.'3 Those whose being and understanding and knowing and loving are one and the same and are indeed that which they themselves are, are in one another in the most perfect way. (Fs)

507c Besides, all other things apart from God are known and loved by God. These also are in God as the known in the knower and the beloved in the lover, not, of course, in the consubstantiality of the divine nature, but according to intentional existence and the quasi-identification of those in love. Still, God knows and loves others in accordance with what suits the perfection of their nature; but there are still others whom 'he foreknew [and] predestined to be conformed to the image of his Son, in order that he might be the firstborn among many brothers and sisters.'4 And those who are known and loved in this special way are also seen to be present in God in a special way as the known in the knower and the beloved in the lover. Therefore in a special way they are in the divine Word in which God the Father utters himself and all other things;5 and in a special way they are in the divine proceeding Love in which God the Father and God the Son love both themselves and all other things as well.6
509a Next, let us turn to the Lord and Mediator, the divine Word incarnate. He does not know all of those who cry, 'Lord, Lord,'7 but, 'I am the good shepherd. I know my own and my own know me.'8 Nor does he know his own without loving them; indeed, 'As the Father has loved me, so I have loved you';'9 and, 'No one has greater love than this, to lay down one's life for one's friends.'10 And the sheep do not know their shepherd without loving him. For, as the shepherd himself knew, 'And I, when I am lifted up from the earth, will draw all things to myself.'11 As also the apostle Paul exclaimed, 'For through the law I died to the law, so that I might live to God. I have been crucified with Christ; and it is no longer I who live, but it is Christ who lives in me. And the life I now live in the flesh I live by faith in the Son of God, who loved me and gave himself up for me.'12 And as the apostle prays for others, 'that, according to the riches of his glory, he may grant that you may be strengthened in your inner being with power through his Spirit, and that Christ may dwell in your hearts through faith, as you are being rooted and grounded in love. I pray that you may have the power to comprehend, with all the saints, what is the breadth and length and height and depth, and to know the love of Christ that surpasses knowledge, so that you may be filled with all the fullness of God.'13 And as the apostle concludes for others, 'For the love of Christ urges us on, because we are convinced that one has died for all; therefore all have died. And he died for all, so that those who live might live no longer for themselves, but for him who died and was raised for them. From now on, therefore, we regard no one from a human point of view; even though we once knew Christ from a human point of view, we know him no longer in that way. So if anyone is in Christ, there is a new creation: everything old has passed away; see, everything has become new!'14

511a Those, therefore, whom Christ the man knows and loves and who believe in Christ the man and love him, live not for themselves but for him, and Christ and they surely live and dwell in one another as those who are known are in those who know them and those who are loved are in those who love them. (Fs)

511b Third, as it was the function of the Mediator not to teach a doctrine of his own but that of the one who sent him, nor to seek his own will but that of the one who sent him, so also Christ does not unite the members of his body with himself without uniting them with God the Father. For the Father first loved us,15 and he was in Christ reconciling the world to himself.16 'Whoever has seen me has seen the Father';17 'those who love me will be loved by my Father';18 'you have loved them even as you have loved me.'19 'If you love me, ... he will give you another Advocate ... he abides with you, and he will be in you.'20 All of these are summed up in the words, '... as you, Father, are in me, and I am in you, may they also be one in us.'21 We surely do not arrive at this ultimate unity unless, by keeping Christ's commandments, we love one another as Christ has loved us. Indeed, one who loves one's neighbor, by that very fact loves Christ; and one who does not love one's neighbor who is hungry or thirsty or a stranger or naked or sick or in prison does not love Christ, as the futurejudge himself has testified.22

511c From all of this we conclude that the divine persons themselves and the blessed in heaven and the just on this earth are in one another as those who are known are in those who know them and those who are loved are in those who love them. This knowing and loving is directed both to the ultimate end, which is the good itself by essence, and to the proximate end, which is the general good of order, the kingdom of God, the body of Christ, the church. This consequent mutual 'being in,' however, differs according to each one's nature and status: the divine persons are in one another through consubstantiality; the just are in God and in one another by way of intentional existence and the quasi-identification of love. We are in the Word, however, as known and loved through both his divine and his human nature; and the Word is in us in order that in knowing and loving a visible human being we may arrive at knowing and loving God, who dwells in unapproachable light.23 And because this prior knowledge and love is easier for us, since it includes our sense memory of the past and our imagination of the future, we are led through it to that higher knowledge and love in which we no longer know Christ from a human point of view, but our inner word of the divine Word is spoken in us intelligently according to the emanation of truth, and our love of divine Love is spirated according to the emanation of holiness. For the divine persons are sent in accordance with their eternal processions, to encounter us and dwell in us in accordance with similar processions produced in us through grace. Those who proceed from and are sent by the Father do not come without the Father, to whom be all glory through the Son in the Spirit. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Einwohnung, Göttliche Personen im Gerechten - Akt, Stand der Gnade; Gnade: A liebt B (Gott liebt uns aufgrund des Sohnes)- A schenkt sich B (hieligmachende G.) - B Dankbarkeit, Bewusstsein (Habitus, Tugend)

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 18 - Although the indwelling of the divine persons exists more in acts and is better known in acts, still it is constituted through the state of grace.

Textausschnitt: 513a First, this indwelling is the fact that the divine persons and the just are in one another as the known are in those who know them and the beloved are in those who love them. We are not speaking here about the presence of a stone to stones but of a person to persons. (Fs)

515a Second, this indwelling exists more in acts and is better known in acts. The reason it exists more in acts is that the formality of knowledge and of love is verified more in act than in potency or habit. The indwelling is better known in acts, for each thing is known insofar as it is in act. (Fs)

515b Third, the discontinuity of acts does not automatically terminate or interrupt the indwelling. There is more than enough emphasis on this point from such words in scripture as 'abide,' 'live,' 'dwell in,' 'being in Christ,' 'being in the Spirit.' And there has never been any doubt about this on the part of theologians. (Fs)

515c Fourth, as a potency or a habit is known through act, so it is known in the very best way through the very best act. For although children and the sleeping and the sick and the insane and the moribund are really and truly human persons, still we do not go only or mainly to them in order to determine what human nature is. Similarly, although children or the sleeping or those who sin venially or those who are about to sin mortally can be in the state of grace, we must not consider only or mainly such persons in order to understand the nature of the indwelling. Hence, the nature of the indwelling can better be understood in each person the more he or she lives not for himself or herself but for Christ, abides in Christ, and is in the Spirit. Still, the fact of indwelling is not to be denied on the grounds that it is not seen by human eyes, because introspective analysis is very difficult, because there is no science in the strict sense about the interior supernatural life, and because it is not for its subject or for other persons to judge it, but for the Lord. (Fs)

515d Fifth, there is a distinction to be made among three things that are called 'grace.' They are (1) one person's favor toward another, (2) a gift given by the former to the latter, and (3) the gratitude felt by the latter.1 Therefore, with regard to divine grace we similarly distinguish (1) that the Father loves and gives to the just by the Holy Spirit because of his incarnate Son, (2) that there follows upon this love and giving sanctifying grace, which is an absolutely supernatural entitative habit received in the essence of the soul,2 and (3) that from this habit there flow, naturally as it were, virtues and gifts whereby the lower part of the soul is subordinated to reason and reason is subordinated to God, whereupon there results that inner rectitude and justice by which the just are readily moved by God towards eternal life, to which they are oriented.3 (Fs)

517a Still, these three are not to be so sharply distinguished as to be separated. For although love and uncreated gift, the habit of sanctifying grace, and the orientation of the justified soul are three realities, they are linked to one another in a single intelligible order. Since the love and giving are contingent, they require an appropriate external term as a consequent condition, and so the second follows the first. But since the virtues and the gifts flow from sanctifying grace as potencies flow from the essence of the soul, from the very fact that there is sanctifying grace there is also both the orientation of the justified soul and its readiness to act under divine influence. Thus, not only does the third follow the second, but also divine influence follows from the first in order to elicit actions that flow from the virtues and gifts. (Fs)

517b Sixth, a further distinction is to be made between the habit of grace and the state or situation of grace. The habit of grace is a physical accident received in the soul of the just. But the state or situation of grace refers to many distinct subjects together. Thus to constitute the state of grace there are required (1) the Father who loves, (2) the Son because of whom the Father loves, (3) the Holy Spirit by whom the Father loves and gives, and (4) the just, whom, because of the Son, the Father loves by the Holy Spirit, and to whom the Father gives by the Holy Spirit, and who consequently are endowed with sanctifying grace, whence flow the virtues and gifts, and who are thereby just and upright and ready to receive and elicit acts ordered towards eternal life.4

517c Seventh, through this state, therefore, there is constituted a divine-human interpersonal situation. In accordance with this state the divine persons and the just are in one another as those who are known are in those who know them and those who are loved are in those who love them.5 This state, of course, exists more in acts and is better known in acts, yet it does not cease to exist solely because of a temporary cessation of the acts. Moreover, what the nature of this state or situation is will emerge ever more clearly the more perfect the habits and acts are that are examined. (Fs)

519a In this state we are not our own, for we are temples of the Holy Spirit.6 In this state the Holy Spirit also is not his own, since he has been given to us.7 Similarly, in this state Christians live not for themselves but for him who died and was raised for them;8 therefore their lives are hidden with Christ in God.9 And who will separate them from the love of Christ?10 Their charity is not some blind psychic impulse, since they live by faith in the Son of God,11 and Christ dwells in their hearts through faith.12 Because of this they are not like those who have zeal for God but without sound knowledge.13 So, abiding in love, they abide in God and God in them,14 and they know this mutual abiding not because of their own charity but by the gift of the Spirit.15 For they did not first love God the Father, but he loved them first, and sent his Son as the atonement for their sins.16

519b In this state, therefore, the divine persons are in the just and the just are in the divine persons as the known are in those who know them and the beloved are in those who love them. On the part of the divine persons this state is always in second act, but on the part of the just it is always in first act so that under divine influence it may readily issue into second act, according to the degree of perfection of the just person.17 Hence, 'let one who is just be justified still,'18 according to the abundance of the life which that person lives in the Spirit through the Son to the glory of God the Father. For the glory of the Father is this, that just as he eternally speaks the Word in truth and through the Word breathes forth Love in holiness, so also in the fullness of time he sent his incarnate Son in truth so that by believing the Word we might speak and understand true inner words; and through the Word he sent the Spirit of the Word in holiness so that joined to the Spirit in love and made living members of the body of Christ we might cry out, 'Abba, Father!' (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Epilog, Zusammenfassung

Kurzinhalt: It enables us also to bring what we know about the Holy Trinity into an intelligible unity bodth with philosophical conclusions about God and with other theological treatises.

Textausschnitt: 523a We have been considering the part of trinitarian theology that aims at an understanding of truths that are certain. Thus, the order we have followed is not one that generates certainties but one that enlarges our understanding. (Fs)

Hence, we have presupposed as having been investigated, determined, and proven in the way of analysis, and needing no repetition here, whatever conclusions have been arrived at from the teaching of Christ and the church, from scripture, from the Fathers, and from the common opinion among theologians. Our task, therefore, has not been to establish that the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit are (1) really distinct from one another, (2) numerically one God and therefore (3) consubstantial, and (4) distinct from one another by their relations alone, which (5) are founded on origins or emanations (6) by generation, that is, in accordance with intellect, and (7) by spiration, in accordance with will. Nor has it been our procedure to follow the order that begins from the missions as related in the New Testament so as to arrive at the psychological analogy. We have had another objective, that is, taking for granted those doctrines that are not disputed among Catholics, to seek that fruitful understanding of them commended by the [First] Vatican Council, proceeding according to an order in which we deferred consideration of whatever would have required a prior understanding of something else. (Fs) (notabene)

523b If we wish now to view the work as a unified whole, we discover that there is one fundamental notion in virtually all of it. Just as in the material objects of sense perception there is a discernible order, so also there is an order within our intellectual and rational consciousness. After abstracting from it the imperfections of a finite nature and transferring it by analogy to God, this consciously rational order, in which volitional acts are ordered through intellectual judgments and these intellectual judgments are ordered through grasping the evidence for things, produces some understanding of the two processions in God and the four real relations, three of which are really distinct from one another. And if to this we add the fact that there is nothing real in God that is not God, it is clear that these relations are subsistent, and therefore that there are three divine persons, each of whom is conscious both of himself and of each of the others. Besides, since many things in an order constitute a unity and a good, we further conclude both to the perfection proper to the three divine persons and also to the perfection they communicate to us in that good of order which is the kingdom of God, the body of Christ, the church, and the economy of salvation. (Fs) (notabene)

525a This understanding, however imperfect, analogical, and obscure, is the principal fruit of the way of synthesis. Indeed, it enables us to hold the Catholic doctrine on the divine persons so firmly that we speak about these persons with alacrity, ease, and delight. It enables us also to bring what we know about the Holy Trinity into an intelligible unity bodth with philosophical conclusions about God and with other theological treatises. Moreover, it frees us from interposing the obstacle of subjective slow-wittedness when we are attempting to reach up to the mind of scripture, of the Fathers, and of theologians. Lastly it enables us, in judging contemporary intellectual movements, to detect more quickly what is false and apprehend more easily what is true. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Wortgebrauch (Thomas); energeia, poiesis - actio, operatio;

Kurzinhalt: The Greek words energeia, 'act,' and poiesis, 'making,' were both rendered into Latin by the words actio and operatio. Hence in reading St Thomas one must always determine from the context whether the word actio or the word operatio ...

Textausschnitt: 1 The Words 'Action' and 'Operation'

535a The Greek words energeia, 'act,' and poiesis, 'making,' were both rendered into Latin by the words actio and operatio. Hence in reading St Thomas one must always determine from the context whether the word actio or the word operatio refers to act or to an exercise of efficient causality. (Fs)
You will find a number of examples of this flexibility in usage in Theological Studies 8:3 (1947) 416-17, 434-37 [Verbum 119-21, 138-43]-

535b For example, 'operation' in this text means act: 'Every operation of the soul is the act of either an active or a passive potency' (In II De anima, lect. 6, §305). (Fs)

But, here 'operation' means to exercise efficient causality: 'The operation of some effect is attributed not to the movable thing but to the mover' (Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. m, a. 2 c). (Fs)

535c 'Action' in this case means act: 'Every action belongs either to an active potency or to a passive potency. But an object is to the act of a passive potency ... But (an object is) to the act of an active potency ...' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 77, a. 3 a). (Fs)

But 'action' means here to exercise efficient causality: 'In action there is implied a reference "as that from which there is movement in the movable thing ..."' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 28, a 3, ad im.)1

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt, Potenz (2 Proportionen: eg: A in A = B in BM; A als Zweck von A = B als Zweck von B); Beispiele: Hören, Ohr, Augen Sehen Sehvermögen; erster, zweiter A., erste, zweite Potenz; zweite Potenz = erster Akt

Kurzinhalt: 'One kind of proportion is that whereby we say that just as this is in this, so that is in that; as, for example ...

Textausschnitt: 2 The Two Proportions between Act and Potency1

535d There are two proportions according to which act and potency can especially be known. (Fs)

'One kind of proportion is that whereby we say that just as this is in this, so that is in that; as, for example, just as seeing is in the eye, so hearing is in the ear' (In IX Metaphys., lect. 5, § 1828). (Fs)

535e 'Another kind of proportion is that whereby we say that just as this is for this, so that is for that; as, for example, just as eyesight is for seeing, so the faculty of hearing is for hearing' (In IX Metaphys., lect. 5, §1829). (Fs)

537a Accordingly, there are two kinds of act and two kinds of potency. First act is form, for example, eyesight [the faculty of seeing] that is received in the eye, or the faculty of hearing that is received in the ear. Second act is operation, action, energeia, such as the act of seeing which perfects one's eyesight, and the act of hearing which perfects the faculty of hearing. First potency is like the eye, which needs to be perfected initially by form (eyesight) and then by second act (seeing). Second potency is the same as form or first act. See De potentia, q. I, a. I c. (Fs)

These two basic proportions are valid for both accidents and substances. (Fs)

'...just as the eye is made up of the pupil as its matter and sight as its form, so an animal is composed of a soul as form and a body as matter' (In II De anima, lect. 2, §241). (Fs)

'For just as existence follows upon form, so understanding follows upon an intelligible species' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 4 c). (Fs)

'... understanding, which is related to intellect in act in the same way that existence is related to being in act' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 34, a. 1, ad 2m). (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt, Potenz: A. dessen, was vollständig - unvollständig ist; unvollständiger Akt der Existenz, Bewegung

Kurzinhalt: ... the reality of things can either exceed the perfection of an essence or fall short of it ... Aristotle has shown that an act of the incomplete is present in every motion in the strict sense of the word.

Textausschnitt: 3 Act of What Is Complete and Act of What Is Incomplete

537b Every definition per se and directly regards an essence, either simply so called (substantial) or with some qualification (accidental). (Fs)

But the reality of things can either exceed the perfection of an essence or fall short of it. Thus, in the case of substances the act of existence adds a perfection beyond that of the essence. Likewise in the case of accidents there is a qualified essence inasmuch as the eye is informed by eyesight or the ear by the faculty of hearing or the intellect by a species or by a habit. But actual seeing is a further perfection added to the eye and eyesight; actual hearing is a further perfection added to the ear and the faculty of hearing; actual understanding is a further perfection added to the possible intellect and to a species or a habit. These added perfections are called acts of what is complete. (Fs)

537c On the other hand, the perfection of a thing can fall short of the perfection of an essence. You see this especially in the generation of living beings. The eye in a fetus cannot see but one day will be able to. In such an eye there is in addition to mere potency to vision an act and perfection which, however, still falls short of the perfection of vision. This act is called an act of what is incomplete. It is an act of what exists in potency insofar as it is in potency. It is an incomplete act of existence, that is, it possesses the reality of vision, not completely so as to be able to see, but incompletely in such a way that it will eventually be able to see. (Fs)

539a Aristotle has shown that an act of the incomplete is present in every motion in the strict sense of the word. See [St Thomas] In V Phys., lect. 2-4; In VI Phys., lect. 5, lect. 8, f 5, §1621, and lect. 12; In VIII Phys., lect. 4-6. Passages in St Thomas on these points will be found in Theological Studies 8:3 (1947) 408-13 [Verbum 110-16]. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Natur (Aristoteles, Thomas); N. - übernatüliche Wirklichkeit

Kurzinhalt: Aristode defines nature as the principle of motion and rest in that in which it exists primarily and per se and not by accident.

Textausschnitt: 4 Nature

539b Aristotle defines nature as the principle of motion and rest in that in which it exists primarily and per se and not by accident. Physics, 11, 1, 192b 21-32; In II Phys., lect. 1, ¶5, §289. In this sense, nature is not the thing itself but a principle of a thing, namely, either form or matter, and form more than matter. Ibid. lect. 2. (Fs) (notabene)

St Thomas uses the word 'nature' not only in the Aristotelian sense but also in the sense of essence or substance. Thus, supernatural realities are those that exceed the proportion of a nature, that is, the proportion of a finite substance or essence. See, for example, Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 110, a. 1 c. (Fs)

539c Concerning the relation of nature (in the Aristotelian sense) to supernatural realities, the following points should be noted. First, '[God] has infused some supernatural forms or qualities by means of which [we] might be gently and readily moved by him to attain eternal good.' Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. no, a. 2 c. Second, between a created intellect and the divine essence there exists a certain proportion of potency to act; thus, ibid. 1, q. 12, a. 1, ad 4m. Third, the nature of this proportion is a vexed question, especially with respect to obediential potency. But the way in which this obediential potency is to be understood depends to a considerable extent on the following notions of active and passive potency. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Thomas, Sprachgebrauch (Aristoteles, Avicenna): aktive - passive Potenz; Natur; Hervorgang einer Tätigkeit - processio operati


Kurzinhalt: Following Aristotle, he defines active potency as the principle of motion or change in another as other, and passive potency as the principle of motion or change by the other as other.

Textausschnitt: 5 Active and Passive Potency

539d St Thomas uses the words 'active' and 'passive' in two different ways. (Fs)

Following Aristotle, he defines active potency as the principle of motion or change in another as other, and passive potency as the principle of motion or change by the other as other. According to this terminology, then, nature, the principle of motion in that in which it is, is adequately distinguished from active and passive potency, the principle of motion from another or in another. (Fs)

539e But there is another usage derived, it seems, from Avicenna, according to which passive potency is first potency, potency simply so called, such as prime matter or the possible intellect, and active potency is form; thus, De potentia, q. 1, a. 1 c. According to this terminology, nature (in the Aristotelian sense) is the same as passive and active potency. (Fs)

541a Moreover, in the Avicennan terminology there are two aspects to active potency or form. As referring to second act (action, operation, energeia), form is called the principle of action or operation, or the formal principle of action or operation. As further referring to some other reality besides second act that is produced by means of this act, form is said to be the principle of the effect, or the principle of the product. (Fs)

541b Again, since form is both a principle of action and a principle of the effect, the distinction continually recurs between the twofold action, the twofold operation, the twofold motion, or between operation and motion, or action and production, where there is always a question of second act and of some further effect. See Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. I, ¶¶-6, §§853-55. (Fs)

541c From this same source arises the distinction between a procession of an operation and a processio operati (elsewhere, a process of an operation and a processus operati), as in De veritate, q. 4, a. 2, ad 7m. For the operator that is complete in first act through its form is a principle both of the further perfection which it receives, namely, operation, and of the further perfection which it produces, namely, the product or work.1

541d Note, however, that this double terminology did not at all lead St Thomas astray. In his Scriptum super Sententias and in the Quaestio disputata de potentia, the Avicennan terminology seems to prevail, while in the Summa contra Gentiles and in the Summa theologiae the Aristotelian terminology is more common. This is well illustrated if one compares De potentia, q. 1, a. 1, and Summa theologiae, 1, q. 25, a. 1: in the body of the article in De potentia he uses Avicenna's terminology, while in the objections he uses Aristotle's; contrariwise, in the body of the article in the Summa theologiae he uses Aristotelian terminology, and Avicenna's terminology comes up in the solutions to the objections. (Fs)

The relevant Thomistic passages and sources are indicated in Theological Studies 8:3 (1947) 418-29 [Verbum 121-33]; see also ibid. 437-41 [Verbum 143-48]. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Actio (poesis, factio); Aristotelels, Thomas: motivum, mobile (kineton), movens, motum, motus (kinesis); Tätigkeit mit/ohne Bewegung im engen Sinn

Kurzinhalt: For just as one and the same reality is the act both of the motor and of the movable, so also one and the same act is that of the sounding bell and of the one who hears it, and in general of the sensible and the sentient; for otherwise every mover ...

Textausschnitt: 7 Action (poiesis, factio)


543c Let us consider now that action which is not act (energeia) but the predicament or category of action, and perhaps, speaking more generally, the exercise of efficient causality. Here one must distinguish three things: (1) Aristotle's own terminology, (2) Aristotelian terminology as modified somewhat by St Thomas, and (3) another terminology found mostly in the Scriptum super Sententias and in the Quaestio disputata de potentia. (Fs)

543d First, then, Aristotle distinguished motive or motor (kinetikon/motivum), mobile or movable (kineton/mobile), mover (kinoun/movens), moved (kinoumenon/motum), and motion (kinesis/motus). The motive or motor is active potency, the motive force; mobile or movable is passive potency; and in one and the same act the motor becomes the mover, and the mobile or movable becomes the moved. This act is the motion, which is received in the movable but produced by the mover. Aristotle proves that nothing is received per se in the motor when it becomes an actual mover, because otherwise it would follow that every mover would itself be moved, which is impossible if there is any motion at all. (Fs) (notabene)

543e Now this one same act that is produced by the mover and received in the movable has a twofold relation, one to the mover from which it proceeds and the other to the moved in which it exists. Hence arise the definitions of action and passion. Action is the act of this as proceeding from this, that is, the act of the mover as from the mover, while passion is the act of this as being in this, that is, the act of the moved as present in the moved. See In III Phys., lect. 4 and 5. (Fs) (notabene)

543f Note1 that St Thomas makes use of this Aristotelian theorem in solving a famous difficulty in trinitarian theology. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 28, a. 3, ad 1m. (Fs) (notabene)

345a Note also that St Thomas does not restrict this Aristotelian analysis to material things or to motion in the strict sense of the word. For just as one and the same reality is the act both of the motor and of the movable, so also one and the same act is that of the sounding bell and of the one who hears it, and in general of the sensible and the sentient; for otherwise every mover would itself be moved. See In III De anima, lect. 2, §§592-93. (Fs) (notabene)

Quer zu oben: F1_028a3ad1

345b Second, this Aristotelian terminology is sometimes slightly modified by St Thomas. According to Aristotle, action and passion are identical with the motion itself. According to St Thomas's modification, action is the denomination of the agent from the patient or receiver, and passion is the denomination of the patient from the agent; see his commentary, In III Phys., lect. 5, ¶15, §614; see also ¶13, §612. Hence, it is possible that in creation, wherein there is no motion, there are nevertheless the relations of active and passive creation. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 45, a. 2, ad 2m; a. 3 c. (Fs) (notabene)

345c Third, there exists also another quite different terminology according to which action is conceived 'as being from the agent,' or 'as proceeding from the agent into the other.' That there is only a verbal and not a real difference between this terminology and the Aristotelian is clear from the following passage:

That which is attributed to something as proceeding from it to something else does not enter into composition with it, as neither does action [enter into composition] with the agent ... [In the case of a relation of one thing to another,] without any change in that which is related to another, a relation can cease to be through the mere change alone of the other; as also is clear about action, that there is no movement as regards action except metaphorically and improperly; as we say that one passing from leisure to act is changed; which would not be the case if relation or action signified something remaining in the subject. (De potentia, q. 7, a. 8 c; see also ibid. a. 9, ad 7m.)
See Theological Studies 3 (1942) 377-81 [Grace and Freedom 68-73].2

345d Finally, it is true that Aristotle in working out his theory of action is speaking diretly about motion in the strict sense. Now it is also true that St Thomas wrote, 'Action as a predicament, or category, refers to something flowing from an agent and with motion.' Super I Sententiarum, d. 8, q. 4, a. 3, ad 3m. But it is also true that St Thomas applied this analysis both to cognitive acts and to the gifts of divine grace, and used it to illustrate his teaching on both creation and the Trinity. As he knew perfectly well, action takes place with motion in the strict sense and also takes place without motion in the strict sense; and concerning this latter action without motion he writes: 'This is hard to understand for those who are unable to abstract their consideration from actions that take place with motion.' Quaestiones quodlibetales, 5, a. 9 c. See also Summa theologies, 1, q. 41, a. 1, ad 2m. (Fs)

547a Concerning the question of physical premotion, since it is not pertinent here, it will suffice to refer you to what I have written in Theological Studies 3 (1942) 381-402 [Grace and Freedom 73-93].3

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Vitaler Akt - Seele, Bewegung; Olivi, Scotus, Thomas (das Objekt verursacht einen Akt in der Seele), intellectus agens, possibilis, species; Wille - Selbstbewegung (S. th., De Malo); Natur

Kurzinhalt: There is no doubt that St Thomas held Aristotle's opinion. His teaching is that the object produces not only the prior disposition or species in the sense but also the very act of sensing.

Textausschnitt: 8 Vital Act

547b According to Aristotle, whatever is moved is moved by something else. According to the Platonic philosophers, however, the soul is generally defined as that which moves itself. (Fs)

Hence medieval Augustinian theologians, after they had been forced to admit the distinction between a soul and its potencies, taught that at least these potencies of the soul moved themselves. For just as a soul would not be alive if it did not move itself, so the acts of a soul would not be vital if they were not produced by those very potencies of the soul. (Fs) (notabene)

547c Peter John Olivi, O.F.M., was a most vigorous proponent of this doctrine. See his Quaestiones in secundum librum Sententiarum, vol. 2, Quaestiones 49-71, ed. Bernardus Jansen, s.i. (Ad Claras Aquas [Quaracchi]: Ex Typographia Collegii S. Bonaventurae, 1924) q. 58 c, pp. 409-14; ibid. ob. 13 and ad 13m, pp. 400-403, 437-61; ob. 14 and ad 14m, pp. 403-408, 461-515. (Fs)

547d Gonzalvus Hispanus, D.F.M. (Quaestiones disputatae et Quodlibet, ed. cura Leonis Amoros, O.F.M. [Ad Claras Aquas, Florentiae: Ex Typographia Collegii S. Bonaventurae, 1935] q. 3, pp. 27-49) mitigated Peter's opinion in this way, that the object would be not a mere condition of a vital act but would produce in a potency a certain disposition whereby that potency could perform a vital act. (Fs)

The Aristotelian side was upheld by Godfrey of Fontaines (in an exaggerated way), by Thomas Sutton, and by Nicholas Trivet. (Fs)

547e Scotus steered a middle course in maintaining that both the object and the potency were co-causes which came together to produce a vital act. (Fs)

549a There is no doubt that St Thomas held Aristotle's opinion. His teaching is that the object produces not only the prior disposition or species in the sense but also the very act of sensing. (Fs)

[The following passages express this doctrine.]

Super IV Sententiarum, d. 50, q. 1, a. 4 sol.: 'sense knowledge is completed in this, that the sense is moved by a sensible thing.'
Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 57, ¶8, §1333: 'Sensitive soul, therefore, does not function in sensing as mover and agent, but as that by which the receiver of an influence receives it.'
Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 76, ¶15, §1574: '[B]ut if the operation consists in receiving an influence, there is available to it a passive principle, as is evident for sensitive principles in animals.'
In II De anima, lect. 10, §350: 'sensing consists in being moved and receiving an influence.'
In II De anima, lect. 13, §393: 'sensing consists in a certain reception of an influence and undergoing change.'
Summa theologiae, 1, q. 17, a. 2, ad 1m: 'for a sense to be affected is the very sensing of the sense.'
Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 5 c: 'sensing is completed by the action of the sensible thing on the sense.'
Summa theologiae, 1, q. 85, a. 2, ad 3m: '... two operations. One consisting in alteration alone, and in this way the operation of a sense potency is achieved in this, that it is changed by the sensible thing.'
Quaestiones quodlibetales, 5, a. 9, ad 2m: 'knowledge in an external sense is constituted by this alone, that the sense is changed by the sensible thing.'

549b Furthermore, it is well known that the possible intellect is a passive potency and that to understand is a certain being-affected. However, since many are not convinced of this, it may help to add a few more detailed passages:

De veritate, q. 22, a. 5, ad 8m: '... the form received in something does not move the thing that receives it; but just as to have that form is itself to have been moved; but the thing is moved by an external agent; just as a body which is heated by fire is not moved by the heat it receives but by the fire. So too intellect is not moved by the species it has already received, nor by the truth which is the result of that species; but by some external thing which leaves an impression on the intellect, as the agent intellect, or phantasm, or something else of that nature.' (Fs) (notabene)

Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 26, a. 2 c: 'A natural agent produces two effects in the receiver. The first effect gives it a form, and the second effect gives it the movement that follows upon the form.' Therefore, if we may suppose a parity here, the agent intellect and the phantasm not only imprint the intelligible species (which is the form received in the possible intellect), but also produce the movement that follows upon that form (this movement is the act of understanding). But if there is no parity with a natural agent, it remains that the operation (the act of understanding) is more perfect than the form (the species) and therefore it cannot have in the species a proportionate mover. (Fs) (notabene)

551a
Super IV Sententiarum, d. 49, q. 3, a. 2 sol.: 'What is ultimate and most perfect in anything is its operation; wherefore every form inherent in a thing is to its operation somewhat as potency is to act; on this account form is called first act (for example, knowledge); and operation (for example, to consider) is called second act, as is evident in the second book of the De anima' (see lect. n, §§359-72). (Fs)

De potentia, q. 5, a. 5, ad 14m: '... that objection is based on second act, which is an operation remaining in the one operating, which is the end of the one operating, and consequently more excellent than the form of the one operating.' See also Super I Sententiarum, d. 35, q. 1, a. 5, ad 4m; De malo, q. 1, a. 5 c; Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 3, a. 2; q. 49, a. 3, ad im; 3, q. 9, a. 1 c; a. 4 c. Also, see the places cited in §2 above: 'The Two Proportions between Act and Potency.'

552a What St Thomas taught concerning the will is consistent with this doctrine. In his writings up to the first part of the Summa theologiae, there seems to be no mention about the will moving itself, but the Aristotelian principle holds, that 'the desirable when apprehended moves the appetite,' and freedom is based upon the fact that 'concerning contingent beings, reason is open to opposites' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 83, a. 1 a). Indeed, he writes that 'the free will is the cause of its movement because a human being through his or her free will moves himself or herself to act' (ibid, ad 3m). He also writes that the will of itself is moved (ibid. q. 105, a. 4, ad 2m and 3m). But the expression 'the will moves itself does not appear. See Theological Studies 3 (1942) 533-37 [Grace and Freedom 94-98]. (Fs)

552b Yet in De malo, q. 6, and in Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 9, a. 3 c, it is explicitly stated that the will moves itself, not, however, because in the will there is an active and a passive element as there is in the intellect (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 83, a. 4, ad 3m), but because the will when in act concerning the end brings itself from potency to act concerning the means. But the act concerning the end comes from an external source (ibid. 1-2, q. 9, a. 4), which source is God alone (ibid. a. 6), who moves human beings both to good in general and, through grace, to a particular good (ibid. a. 6, ad 3m). Clearly, then, the will is moved and does not move in the act whereby it wills the end; and this point is explicitly made concerning operative grace (ibid. q. in, a. 2 c). (Fs)

552c All this presents no difficulty so long as one does not impose upon St Thomas a doctrine that he never taught, that of vital act, to wit, that the potencies of living beings move themselves to all their acts. He had no need of such a notion to explain quite satisfactorily both life in general (Summa theologiae, I, q. 18, a. 2) and life in God (ibid. a. 3), who certainly is an unmoved mover. (Fs)

553a These apparent difficulties have two sources, the first of which is forgetting what nature means. According to Aristotle, the motor or mover per se is something extrinsic; for it is defined as the principle of motion or change in another as other. On the other hand, nature is defined as the principle of motion or rest in that being in which there is motion. And since all potencies are principles of motion in that being in which there is motion, it is clear that they all possess the formality of nature and that from an intrinsic principle and naturally they receive both forms and second acts. (Fs)

553b Another source of the apparent difficulties is Aquinas's frequent use of a non-Aristotelian terminology. The intellect when informed by a species or a habit is an active potency, a principle of action, a formal principle of action, and also a principle of an effect. All these belong to a terminology that seems to be derived from Avicenna and in no way contradict the rest of Thomist doctrine. As Aquinas expressly teaches, the procession of an operation perfects the operator and therefore it cannot be admitted that such a procession in God is real (De veritate, q. 4, a. 2, ad 7m). In fact, although in his earlier works using this terminology he spoke of the form of heaviness in heavy objects as being an active principle and an active potency, nevertheless he denied that this principle of movement was a motor. Relevant texts are listed in Theological Studies 8:3 (1947) 418 [Verbum 121, note 88]. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; die Gottesfrage; das virtuell Unbedingte

Kurzinhalt: Gibt es einen transzendenten, intelligenten Grund des Universums mit Notwendigkeit, oder gibt es ihn nicht?

Textausschnitt: 1. Die Gottesfrage

1/4 Die Tatsache von Gut und Böse, Fortschritt und Niedergang, rührt zu Fragen über die Eigenart unserer Welt. Solche Fragen wurden vielfach und auf sehr unterschiedliche Weise gestellt - die Antworten sind sogar noch zahlreicher. Doch hinter dieser Vielfalt gibt es eine grundlegende Einheit, die bei Anwendung der transzendentalen Methode zum Vorschein kommt. Wir können die Möglichkeit fruchtbarer Untersuchung untersuchen. Wir können das Wesen der Reflexion reflektieren. Wir können überlegen, ob unsere Überlegung zwecks einer Entscheidung der Mühe wert ist. In jedem dieser Fälle stellt sich die Frage nach Gott. (110; Fs)

2/4 Die Möglichkeit der Untersuchung liegt beim Subjekt in seiner Intelligenz, in seinem Drang, das Was, Warum und Wie zu wissen, sowie in seiner Fähigkeit, intellektuell befriedigende Anworten erreichen zu können. Aber warum sollten die Antworten, die die Intelligenz des Subjekts zufriedenstellen, mehr hergeben als eine nur subjektive Befriedigung? Warum sollte man vermuten, daß diese Antworten Bedeutung für die Erkenntnis des Universums haben? Mit Selbstverständlichkeit nehmen wir an, daß sie eine solche Relevanz haben. Wir können auf die Tatsache verweisen, daß unsere Annahme durch ihre Ergebnisse bestätigt wird. Damit geben wir einschlußweise zu, daß das Universum intelligibel ist, und hat man dies erst zugestanden, so erhebt sich die Frage, ob das Universum intelligibel sein könnte, wenn es keinen intelligenten Grund hätte. Das aber ist die Frage nach Gott. (110; Fs)

3/4 Über Reflexion zu reflektieren heißt fragen, was geschieht, wenn wir das Belegmaterial ordnen und abwägen, um zu behaupten, daß dies wahrscheinlich so und jenes wahrscheinlich nicht so ist. Worauf beziehen sich diese Metaphern des Ordnens und Abwägens? An anderer Stelle habe ich eine ausführliche Antwort auf diese Frage erarbeitet und kann hier meine Schlußfolgerung nur summarisch wiederholen.1 Das Urteil geht rational aus dem Erfassen eines virtuell Unbedingten hervor. Unter einem Unbedingten verstehe ich jedes X, das keine Bedingungen hat; unter einem virtuell Unbedingten jedes X, das keine unerfüllten Bedingungen hat. Mit anderen Worten ist ein virtuell Unbedingtes ein Bedingtes, dessen Bedingungen jedoch alle erfüllt sind. Das Belegmaterial zu ordnen heißt zu ermitteln, ob alle Bedingungen erfüllt sind. Das Belegmaterial abzuwägen heißt zu ermitteln, ob die Erfüllung der Bedingungen mit Sicherheit oder wahrscheinlich die Existenz oder das Geschehen des Bedingten einschließt. (110f; Fs) (notabene)

4/4 Diese Erklärung des Urteils enthält nun implizit ein weiteres Element. Wenn wir von einem virtuell Unbedingten zu sprechen haben, so müssen wir zuerst von einem Unbedingten sprechen. Das virtuell Unbedingte hat keine unerfüllten Bedingungen. Das Unbedingte im strengen Wortsinn hat überhaupt keine Bedingungen. Nach traditioneller Terminologie ist ersteres ein kontingentes und letzteres ein notwendiges Sein. In einer moderneren Terminologie: Das erstere gehört zu dieser Welt, zu der Welt möglicher Erfahrung, wogegen letzteres diese Welt in dem Sinne transzendiert, daß seine Wirklichkeit von völlig anderer Ordnung ist. In beiden Fällen aber stoßen wir auf die Gottesfrage. Existiert ein notwendiges Sein? Gibt es eine Wirklichkeit, die die Wirklichkeit dieser Welt übersteigt? (111; Fs) (notabene)

5/4 Etwas zu erwägen heißt fragen, ob dieses Etwas der Mühe wert ist. Das Erwägen selbst zu erwägen heißt fragen, ob jegliches Erwägen überhaupt der Mühe wert ist. Hat 'der-Mühe-wert-sein' irgendeine letzte Bedeutung? Ist die moralische Bemühung mit dieser Welt vereinbar? Wir loben das Subjekt, das sich entfaltet und immer fähiger wird zur Aufmerksamkeit, Einsicht, Vernünftigkeit und Verantwortlichkeit. Wir loben den Fortschritt und brandmarken alles, worin sich ein Niedergang manifestiert. Es fragt sich aber, ob das Universum auf unserer Seite ist oder ob wir nur Glücksspieler sind, und falls Spieler, ob nicht vielleicht auch Narren, insofern wir individuell um Authentizität ringen und gemeinsam versuchen, dem ständig wachsenden Wirrwarr des Niedergangs einen Fortschritt abzuzwingen. (111; Fs)

6/4 Diese Fragen stellen sich, und es wird deutlich, daß unsere Einstellung und Entschlossenheit zutiefst von den entsprechenden Antworten beeinflußt werden kann. Gibt es einen transzendenten, intelligenten Grund des Universums mit Notwendigkeit, oder gibt es ihn nicht? Ist dieser Grund die erste Instanz sittlichen Bewußtseins, oder sind wir es selbst? Sind Kosmogenese, biologische Evolution und der Geschichtsprozeß uns als moralischen Wesen grundlegend verwandt, oder sind sie indifferent und uns somit fremd? (111; Fs)

7/4 Solcherart ist die Gottesfrage. Sie ist keine Angelegenheit von bildhafter Vorstellung, von Gefühl, Begriff oder Urteil. Diese gehören zu Antworten; sie aber ist eine Frage. Sie erhebt sich aus unserer bewußten Intentionalität, aus jenem a priori strukturierten Impuls, der uns vom Erfahren zur Anstrengung des Verstehens führt, vom Verstehen zur Bemühung um das wahre Urteil und vom Urteilen zur Mühe des richtigen Wählens. In dem Maße, wie wir uns unserem eigenen Fragen zuwenden und dazu übergehen, es in Frage zu stellen, erhebt sich die Frage nach Gott. (111f; Fs) (notabene)

8/4 Sie ist eine Frage, die auf den verschiedenen Stufen der geschichtlichen Entwicklung des Menschen und in den zahlreichen Varianten seiner Kultur auf sehr unterschiedliche Weise zum Ausdruck kommt. Doch solche Unterschiede der Kundgabe und des Ausdrucks sind sekundär. Sie können fremde Elemente einführen, die die reine Frage überlagern, verdunkeln und verzerren: die Frage nämlich, die das Fragen selbst hinterfragt. Nichtsdestoweniger setzen auch ein Verdunkeln und Verzerren ebendas voraus, was sie verdunkeln und verzerren. Daraus folgt, daß - wie stark religiöse oder nicht-religiöse Antworten voneinander abweichen mögen, wie sehr auch die Fragen, die sie ausdrücklich stellen, differieren - dennoch in ihrer tiefsten Wurzel die gleiche transzendentale Tendenz des menschlichen Geistes vorhanden ist, jenes Geistes, der fragt, der ohne Einschränkungen fragt, der die Bedeutung seines eigenen Fragens in Frage stellt und so zur Gottesfrage vordringt. (112; Fs)

9/4 Die Gottesfrage liegt demnach im Horizont des Menschen. Die transzendentale Subjektivität des Menschen wird verstümmelt oder aufgegeben, wenn er sich nicht nach dem Intelligiblen, nach dem Unbedingten, nach dem Gut des Wertes ausstreckt. Die Reichweite, nicht seines Erreichens, sondern seines Intendierens ist unbegrenzt. Innerhalb seines Horizontes liegt ein Bereich für das Göttliche, ein Tempel für höchste Heiligkeit. Er ist nicht zu übersehen. Der Atheist mag ihn für leer halten; der Agnostiker kann betonen, seine Untersuchungen hätten zu keinem schlüssigen Ergebnis geführt, und der Humanist unserer Gegenwart wird sich weigern, diese Frage überhaupt zuzulassen. Doch all diese Negationen setzen den Funken in unserem Brandscheit voraus, unsere ursprüngliche Ausrichtung auf das Göttliche. (112; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; Selbst-Transzendenz - Authentizität

Kurzinhalt: Der Mensch erlangt Authentizität durch Selbst-Transzendenz. Man kann in eben dem Maß in einer Welt leben und einen Horizont haben, in dem man nicht in sich selbst verschlossen ist. Ein erster Schritt zu dieser Befreiung ...

Textausschnitt: 2. Selbst-Transzendenz

10/4 Der Mensch erlangt Authentizität durch Selbst-Transzendenz. Man kann in eben dem Maß in einer Welt leben und einen Horizont haben, in dem man nicht in sich selbst verschlossen ist. Ein erster Schritt zu dieser Befreiung ist die Sinnlichkeit, die wir mit den höheren Tieren gemeinsam haben. Diese aber sind in ihren Lebensraum eingeschlossen, während der Mensch in einem Universum lebt. Über die Sinneswahrnehmung hinaus stellt der Mensch Fragen, und sein Fragen ist unbegrenzt. (112f; Fs)

11/4 Da sind zuerst die Fragen nach Einsicht. Wir fragen 'Was, Warum, Wie und Wozu'. Unsere Antworten vereinigen, verbinden miteinander, klassifizieren, konstruieren, reihen ein und verallgemeinern. Von dem schmalen Raum-Zeit-Streifen, der unserer unmittelbaren Erfahrung zugänglich ist, kommen wir allmählich zum Aufbau einer Weltsicht und zur Erforschung dessen, was wir selbst sein sollten und tun könnten. (113; Fs)

12/4 Auf die Fragen nach Einsicht folgen Fragen nach Reflexion. Wir gehen über Vorstellung und Vermutung, über Idee und Hypothese, Theorie und System hinaus um zu fragen, ob dies tatsächlich so ist oder ob jenes wirklich sein könnte - oder nicht. Nun erhält die Selbst-Transzendenz eine neue Bedeutung. Sie geht nicht bloß über das Subjekt hinaus, sondern sucht auch das, was vom Subjekt unabhängig ist. Denn ein Urteil, daß dies oder jenes so ist, berichtet nicht, was mir erscheint, nicht was ich mir vorstelle, nicht was ich denke, nicht was ich wünsche, nicht was ich geneigt wäre zu sagen, und nicht was mir so scheint, sondern was so ist. (113; Fs)

13/4 Noch ist solche Selbst-Transzendenz nur kognitiv. Sie gehört nicht der Ordnung des Tuns, sondern nur der des Wissens an. Doch auf der endgültigen Ebene der Fragen nach Entscheidung wird die Selbst-Transzendenz moralisch. Wenn wir fragen, ob dieses oder jenes lohnt, ob es nicht nur scheinbar, sondern wahrhaft gut ist, suchen wir nicht das, was uns Vergnügen oder Schmerz, Behaglichkeit oder Unbehagen bereitet, auch nicht die spontane Empfindungsfähigkeit, weder den individuellen noch den Gruppen-Vorteil, sondern wir suchen den objektiven Wert. Weil wir solche Fragen stellen können, weil wir sie beantworten und gemäß den Antworten leben können, deshalb können wir in unserem Leben eine moralische Selbst-Transzendenz bewirken. Diese moralische Selbst-Transzendenz ist die Möglichkeit von Güte und Wohltätigkeit, von aufrichtiger Zusammenarbeit und wahrer Liebe, und sie ermöglicht uns, aus dem Lebensraum des Tieres völlig auszuscheren und Person in einer menschlichen Gesellschaft zu werden. (113; Fs)

14/4 Die transzendentalen Notionen - das sind unsere Fragen nach Verstand, nach Reflexion und Entscheidung - machen unsere Fähigkeit zur Selbst-Transzendenz aus. Diese Fähigkeit wird zur Tatsächlichkeit, wenn man zu lieben beginnt. Dann wird unser Sein ein In-Liebe-Sein. Solches In-Liebe-Sein hat seine Vorgeschichte, seine Gründe, Bedingungen und Anlässe. Doch ist es einmal erblüht, und solange es dauert, übernimmt es die Leitung. Es wird zum ersten Prinzip, aus dem alles hervorgeht: eigene Wünsche und Befürchtungen, Freuden und Leiden, Weiterkenntnisse, Entscheidungen und Taten. (113; Fs)

15/4 In-Liebe-Sein ist unterschiedlicher Art. Es gibt die Liebe der innigen Vertrautheit von Mann und Frau, von Eltern und Kindern. Es gibt die Nächstenliebe, die ihre Früchte trägt zum menschlichen Wohl. Es gibt die Liebe zu Gott aus 'ganzem Herzen und ganzer Seele, mit all deinen Gedanken und all deiner Kraft' (Mk 12,30). Die Liebe Gottes ist 'ausgegossen in unsere Herzen durch den Heiligen Geist, der uns gegeben ist' (Rom 5,5). Sie begründet die Überzeugung des hl. Paulus: 'Weder Tod noch Leben, weder Engel noch Mächte, weder Gegenwärtiges noch Zukünftiges, weder Gewalten der Höhe oder Tiefe noch irgendeine andere Kreatur können uns scheiden von der Liebe Gottes, die in Christus Jesus ist, unserem Herrn' (Röm 8,38f). (114; Fs)

16/4 Wie die Gottesfrage in all unserem Fragen eingeschlossen ist, so ist das mit Gott In-Liebe-Sein die grundlegende Erfüllung unserer bewußten Intentionalität. Diese Erfüllung führt zu einer tief verwurzelten Freude, die Demütigung, Versagen, Entbehrung, Leid, Treuebruch und Verlassenheit überdauern kann. Diese Erfüllung führt zu tiefstem Frieden, einem Frieden, den die Welt nicht geben kann. Diese Erfüllung trägt Früchte in der Nächstenliebe, die machtvoll danach strebt, das Gottesreich auf diese Erde zu bringen. Fehlt diese Erfüllung, so ist der Weg frei zur Banalisierung des menschlichen Lebens im Streben nach Vergnügungen, zur Härte des Lebens, die sich aus gnadenloser Machtausübung ergibt, zur Verzweiflung am Wohle des Menschen, die der Überzeugung entstammt, das Universum sei absurd. (114; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; religiöse Erfahrung; heiligmachende Gnade - Interiorität;

Kurzinhalt: Von heiligmachender Gnade zu sprechen gehört jenem Stadium der Bedeutung an, in dem die Welt der Theorie und die Welt des Allgemeinverstands zwar voneinander unterschieden, aber noch nicht ausdrücklich von der Welt der Interiorität unterschieden ...

Textausschnitt: 3. Religiöse Erfahrung

17/4 Mit Gott In-Liebe-Sein, als erlebt, heißt auf unbegrenzte Weise in Liebe zu sein. Jede Liebe ist Selbst-Hingabe, doch mit Gott in Liebe zu sein, ist ohne Einschränkungen oder Qualifikationen oder Bedingungen oder Vorbehalte In-Liebe-Sein. So wie unbegrenztes Fragen unsere Fähigkeit zur Selbst-Transzendenz ist, so ist mit Gott auf unbegrenzte Weise in Liebe zu sein die eigentliche Erfüllung dieser Fähigkeit. (114; Fs)

18/4 Diese Erfüllung ist nicht das Ergebnis unseres Wissens und unserer Wahl. Ganz im Gegenteil - sie läßt den Horizont, in dem sich unser Wissen und Wählen bisher abspielte, verschwinden und stellt einen neuen Horizont auf, in welchem die Liebe zu Gott unsere Werte umwertet und die Augen dieser Liebe unser Wissen verwandeln. (114; Fs) (notabene)

19/4 Obwohl diese Erfüllung nicht Ergebnis unseres Wissens und Wählens ist, ist sie doch ein bewußter und dynamischer Zustand von Liebe, Freude und Friede, der sich in Taten der Freundlichkeit, Güte, Treue, Sanftmut und Selbstbeherrschung zeigt (Gal 5,22). (114; Fs) (notabene)

20/4 Sagt man, dieser dynamische Zustand sei bewußt, so sagt man damit noch nicht, er sei auch erkannt. Denn Bewußtsein ist einfach Erfahrung, Wissen dagegen ist zusammengesetzt aus Erfahrung, Verstehen und Urteilen. Weil dieser dynamische Zustand bewußt ist, ohne jedoch erkannt zu sein, ist er eine Erfahrung des Geheimnisses. Weil es ein In-Liebe-Sein ist, ist das Geheimnis nicht nur anziehend, sondern geradezu faszinierend. Man gehört ihm, man wird von ihm besessen. Weil es eine unermeßliche Liebe ist, ruft das Geheimnis auch Ehrfurcht hervor. Daher ist das Geschenk der Liebe Gottes an sich, insofern es bewußt ist, ohne erkannt zu sein, eine Erfahrung des Heiligen, eine Erfahrung dessen, was Rudolf Otto mysterium fascinans et tremendum nannte.1 Paul Tillich nennt es 'Das, was uns unbedingt angeht'.2 Es entspricht dem, was Ignatius von Loyola als 'Trost' bezeichnet, der keine Ursache hat, wie Karl Rahner darlegte.3 (115; Fs)

21/4 Es ist auf der vierten Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins bewußt. Es ist nicht jenes Bewußtsein, das die Akte des Sehens, Hörens, Riechens, Schmeckens und Tastens begleitet; auch nicht das Bewußtsein, das die Akte des Untersuchens, des Einsehens, des Formulierens und Sprechens begleitet. Es ist auch nicht das Bewußtsein, das die Akte der Reflexion, des Ordnens und Abwägens des Belegmaterials, der Tatsachen- und Möglichkeitsurteile begleitet. Vielmehr geht es um jenes Bewußtsein, das überlegt, Werturteile fällt, entscheidet und handelt - verantwortlich und frei. Es ist aber dieses Bewußtsein, insofern es zur Erfüllung gebracht wurde, eine Bekehrung durchgemacht hat, eine Grundlage besitzt, die zwar ausgeweitet, vertieft, erhöht und bereichert, nicht aber ersetzt werden kann, und insofern es bereit ist zu überlegen, zu urteilen, zu entscheiden und zu handeln, und zwar mit der Leichtigkeit und Freiheit derer, die alles Gute tun, weil sie in Liebe sind. So durchdringt das Geschenk der Liebe Gottes den Wurzelgrund der vierten und höchsten Ebene des menschlich intentionalen Bewußtseins. Die Liebe herrscht über die 'Seelenspitze', den apex animae. (115; Fs)

22/4 Dieses Geschenk, das wir beschrieben haben, ist wirklich die heiligmachende Gnade, unterscheidet sich aber begrifflich von dieser. Die begriffliche Differenz ergibt sich aus unterschiedlichen Stadien der Bedeutung. Von heiligmachender Gnade zu sprechen gehört jenem Stadium der Bedeutung an, in dem die Welt der Theorie und die Welt des Allgemeinverstands zwar voneinander unterschieden, aber noch nicht ausdrücklich von der Welt der Interiorität unterschieden und in ihr fundiert sind. Vom dynamischen Zustand des mit Gott In-Liebe-Seins zu sprechen, gehört jenem Stadium der Bedeutung an, in dem die Welt der Interiorität explizit zur Grundlage der Welten der Theorie und des Allgemeinverstands gemacht worden ist. Daraus folgt, daß in diesem Stadium der Bedeutung das Geschenk der Gottesliebe zuerst als eine Erfahrung beschrieben und nur infolgedessen dann auch in theoretischen Kategorien objektiviert wird. (115f; Fs) (notabene)

23/4 Abschließend sei angemerkt, daß der dynamische Zustand an sich wirkende Gnade ist; der gleiche Zustand als Urgrund von Akten der Liebe, der Hoffnung, des Glaubens, der Reue und dergleichen aber mitwirkende Gnade. Man kann ergänzend sagen, daß damit die Bekehrung nicht als allzu gewaltsamer Wechsel oder als Bruch der psychologischen Kontinuität stattfindet und dem dynamischen Zustand recht ähnliche vorübergehende Dispositionen, die ebenso wirkend wie auch mitwirkend sind, vorangehen können. Ist der dynamische Zustand einmal hergestellt, wird er noch durch weitere zusätzliche Gnaden bereichert und entfaltet.4 (116; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; Ausdruck religiöser Erfahrung; Hierophanien; Friedrich Heiler

Kurzinhalt: Nun ist es nicht schwer einzusehen, so meine ich, wie diese sieben gemeinsamen Züge der Weltreligionen implizit in der Erfahrung eines uneingeschränkten In-Liebe-Seins enthalten sind.

Textausschnitt: 4. Ausdrucksweisen religiöser Erfahrung

24/4 Religiöse Erfahrung zeigt sich spontan in veränderten Einstellungen, in jener Ernte des Geistes: in Liebe, Freude und Friede, in Freundlichkeit, Güte, Treue, Sanftmut und Selbstbeherrschung. Sie ist aber auch mit ihrer Grundlage und ihrer Mitte im mysterium fascinans et tremendum befaßt, und der Ausdruck dieses Anliegens ändert sich sehr, wenn man von den früheren zu späteren Stadien der Bedeutung übergeht. (116; Fs)

25/4 Im frühesten Stadium ergibt sich der Ausdruck aus der Einsicht in wahrnehmbare Darstellungen und Vorstellungen. Da wird mit einer gewissen Leichtigkeit das Räumliche, nicht aber das Zeitliche herausgestellt, das Besondere, nicht aber die Gattung, das Äußere, nicht aber das Innere, das Menschliche, nicht aber das Göttliche. Nur insofern das Zeitliche, die Gattung, das Innere und das Göttliche auf irgendeine Weise mit dem Räumlichen, dem Besonderen, dem Äußeren und dem Menschlichen assoziiert oder - in der Sprache des naiven Realisten - darauf 'projiziert' werden kann, kommt eine Einsicht zustande und kann sich daher ein Ausdruck ergeben. So ergibt sich aus der assoziativen Verbindung religiöser Erfahrung mit ihrem äußeren Anlaß, daß die Erfahrung zum Ausdruck gebracht und dadurch für das menschliche Bewußtsein zu etwas Bestimmtem und Deutlichem wird. (116f; Fs) (notabene)

26/4 Solche äußeren Anlässe nennt man Hierophanien, und sie sind zahlreich. Wenn jede einzelne von den zahlreichen etwas Bestimmtes und zu den anderen nicht in Beziehung Stehendes ist, offenbaren die Hierophanien die sogenannten Götter des Augenblicks. Wenn sie zahlreich sind, aber als mit einer Familienähnlichkeit ausgestattet erkannt werden, dann hat man es mit einem lebendigen Polytheismus zu tun, wie er sich heute in den 800 000 Göttern des Shintoismus darstellt.1 Wenn bestimmte religiöse Erfahrungen mit einem einzigen Ort in Verbindung gebracht werden, so entsteht der Gott dieses oder jenes Ortes. Geht es um die Erfahrungen einer einzigen Person und sind die Erfahrungen in der Einheit dieser Person vereinigt, dann geht es um den Gott dieser Person, etwa um den Gott Jakobs oder den Gott Labans.2 Erfolgt aber die Vereinigung der Erfahrungen sozial, erstehen die Götter oder der Gott einer Gruppe. (117; Fs) (notabene)

27/4 Vermutlich gibt es kein eindeutiges Beweismaterial dafür, daß solche religiöse Erfahrung dem von mir aufgestellten Modell entspricht - abgesehen von jener vorgängigen Wahrscheinlichkeit, die auf der Tatsache beruht, daß Gott gut ist und allen Menschen hinreichend Gnade zu ihrem Heil gibt. Zumindest einen Gelehrten gibt es, bei dem man eine ausdrückliche Aussage über Gemeinsamkeiten der Weltreligionen - Christentum, Judentum, Islam, zoroastrischer Mazdaismus, Hinduismus, Buddhismus und Taoismus - findet. Friedrich Heiler hat sieben solcher Gemeinsamkeiten recht ausführlich beschrieben.3 Zwar kann ich hier nicht den ganzen Reichtum seines Denkens wiedergeben, wenigstens aber eine Liste der Themen aufstellen, die er behandelt: Es gibt eine transzendente Wirklichkeit; sie ist dem Menschenherzen immanent; sie ist höchste Schönheit, Wahrheit, Gerechtigkeit und Güte; sie ist Liebe, Barmherzigkeit, Mitleid; der Weg zu ihr ist Reue, Selbstverleugnung und Gebet; derselbe Weg ist Nächstenliebe, ja sogar Feindesliebe; der Weg ist Liebe zu Gott, so daß Seligkeit als Gotteserkenntnis, als Vereinigung mit ihm oder als Auflösung in ihm verstanden wird. (117; Fs)

28/4 Nun ist es nicht schwer einzusehen, so meine ich, wie diese sieben gemeinsamen Züge der Weltreligionen implizit in der Erfahrung eines uneingeschränkten In-Liebe-Seins enthalten sind. In-Liebe-Sein heißt mit jemanden in Liebe zu sein. Ohne Einschränkungen, Bedingungen, Vorbehalte oder Grenzen in Liebe zu sein heißt mit jemand in Liebe zu sein, der transzendent ist. Ist aber jemand, der transzendent ist, mein Geliebter, so ist er in meinem Herzen, so ist er für mich real von innen her. Wenn diese Liebe die Erfüllung meines grenzenlosen Drangs nach Selbst-Transzendenz durch Einsicht, Wahrheit und Verantwortlichkeit ist, so muß derjenige, der diesen Impuls an sein Ziel bringt und erfüllt, der Höchste an Intelligenz, Wahrheit und Güte sein. Da er zu mir kommen will durch das Geschenk der Liebe zu ihm, muß er selbst Liebe sein. Da ihn zu lieben mein Transzendieren meiner selbst ist, so ist es auch ein Verleugnen eben jenes Selbst, das zu transzendieren ist. Da ihn zu lieben heißt, ihm liebend Aufmerksamkeit zu schenken, ist diese Liebe Gebet, Meditation und Kontemplation. Da ihn zu lieben Früchte trägt, fließt diese Liebe über in die Liebe all derer, die er liebt oder lieben könnte. Aus einer Erfahrung der Liebe, die auf das Mysterium ausgerichtet ist, erfließt schließlich ein Verlangen nach Erkenntnis, während die Liebe selbst ein Verlangen nach Vereinigung ist; daher ist für den Liebenden, der den unbekannten Geliebten liebt, Inbegriff der Seligkeit, ihn zu erkennen und mit ihm vereint zu sein, wie immer dies zu erreichen sei. (118; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; Dialektik der religiösen Entwicklung; mit Gott In-Liebe-Sein; Gegensatz von Authentizität und Nicht-Authentizität

Kurzinhalt: ... diese Liebe ist das Äußerste an Selbst-Transzendenz, und die Selbst-Transzendenz des Menschen ist immer prekär ... Daher ist die menschliche Authentizität niemals ein reiner, friedlicher und sicherer Besitz.

Textausschnitt: 5. Die Dialektik der religiösen Entwicklung

29/4 Religiöse Entwicklung ist nicht einfach die Entfaltung des dynamischen Zustands uneingeschränkten In-Liebe-Seins mit all seinen Konsequenzen. Denn diese Liebe ist das Äußerste an Selbst-Transzendenz, und die Selbst-Transzendenz des Menschen ist immer prekär. Schon per se involviert Selbst-Transzendenz die Spannung zwischen dem transzendierenden und dem transzendierten Ich. Daher ist die menschliche Authentizität niemals ein reiner, friedlicher und sicherer Besitz. Sie ist immer nur ein Rückzug aus der Unechtheit, und jeder erfolgreiche Rückzug zeigt bloß die Notwendigkeit weiterer Rückzüge. Unser Fortschritt im Verstehen ist immer auch Beseitigung von Versehen und Mißverstehen. Unser Fortschritt in der Wahrheit ist immer auch eine Korrektur von Fehlern und Irrtümern. Unsere sittliche Entwicklung erfolgt auch durch Reue über unsere Sünden. Echte Religion wird entdeckt und verwirklicht durch eine Befreiung aus den zahlreichen Fallstricken religiöser Verirrung. So ist uns geboten zu wachen und zu beten und unseren Lebensweg in Furcht und Zittern zu gehen. Daher sind es gerade die größten Heiligen, die sich selbst für die größten Sünder halten, obwohl ihre Sünden den weniger heiligen Leuten, denen es an Unterscheidungsgabe und Liebe fehlt, wirklich leicht erscheinen. (118f; Fs)

30/4 Dieser dialektische Charakter religiöser Entwicklung impliziert, daß den oben genannten sieben gemeinsamen Bereichen oder Zügen in der Geschichte der Religionen auch deren Gegensätze entsprechen. In-Liebe-Sein heißt, wie wir sagten, mit jemanden in Liebe zu sein. Es hat eine personale Dimension. Dies aber kann in einer Schule des Gebets und der Aszetik, die die Ausrichtung der religiösen Erfahrung auf das transzendente Mysterium besonders betont, übersehen werden. Das Transzendente ist nichts in dieser Welt. Das Mysterium ist das Unbekannte. Ohne die transzendentale Notion des Seins als des Zu-Erkennenden kann man dazu kommen, das transzendente Geheimnis das Nichts schlechthin zu nennen.1 (119; Fs) (notabene)

31/4 In einem viel früheren Stadium kann die Transzendenz auch überbetont und die Immanenz übersehen werden: Dann wird Gott weit entfernt, bedeutungslos und fast vergessen.2 Umgekehrt kann die Immanenz überbetont und die Transzendenz übersehen werden. Dann beraubt der Bezugsverlust zum Transzendenten das Symbol, den Ritus und die Lesung ihres eigentlichen Sinngehalts und macht sie zum bloßen Idol, zur Magie und zum Mythos.3 Dann kann man das Göttliche auch mit dem Leben als universalem Prozeß identifizieren, von dem der einzelne und die Gruppe ein Teil sind und an dem sie teilhaben.4 (119; Fs)

32/4 Ich habe das mit Gott In-Liebe-Sein als letzte Erfüllung menschlicher Fähigkeit zur Selbst-Transzendenz aufgefaßt; diese Sicht der Religion wird gestützt, wenn Gott als die höchste Erfüllung der transzendentalen Notionen, als höchste Intelligenz, Wahrheit, Wirklichkeit, Gerechtigkeit und Güte aufgefaßt wird. Umgekehrt aber wird die Liebe zu Gott, wenn sie nicht streng mit der Selbst-Transzendenz in Verbindung gebracht wird, tatsächlich leicht durch das Erotische, Sexuelle und Orgiastische verstärkt.5 Andererseits ist die Liebe zu Gott auch von Ehrfurcht durchdrungen. Gottes Gedanken und Wege unterscheiden sich sehr von denen der Menschen, und durch diese Differenz wird Gott erschreckend. Wenn Religion nicht gänzlich auf das Gute ausgerichtet ist, auf echte Nächstenliebe und auf eine Selbstverleugnung, die einer umfassenderen Güte in sich selbst untergeordnet ist, dann kann der Kult eines Gottes, der schrecklich und erschreckend ist, ins Dämonische hinübergleiten, in eine jubelnde Destruktivität seiner selbst und der anderen.6 (119f; Fs)

33/4 Das also ist gemeint, wenn wir sagen, die religiöse Entwicklung sei dialektisch. Es geht hierbei nicht um den Kampf zwischen irgendwelchen Gegensätzen, sondern um den präzisen Gegensatz von Authentizität und Nicht-Authentizität, von transzendierendem und transzendiertem Ich. Es geht nicht bloß um einen Gegensatz zwischen konträren Aussagen, sondern um einen Widerstreit innerhalb der Realität menschlicher Individuen und Gruppen. Eine solch dialektische Entwicklung läßt sich nicht einfach durch eine apriorische Konstruktion von Kategorien definieren, sondern ist auch durch ein unterscheidungsfähiges Studium der Geschichte a posteriori zu entdecken. Sie ist nicht auf die von uns skizzierten Gegensätze beschränkt, sondern erstreckt sich durch die Jahrhunderte auf die endlose Vielfalt institutioneller, kultureller, personaler und religiöser Entwicklung, auf Niedergang und Wiederbelebung. Wir werden darauf zurückkommen, wenn wir als funktionale Spezialisierung die Dialektik behandeln. (120; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; Wort - Geschichte; das vorausgehende W. Gottes;

Kurzinhalt: Bevor die Religion in die durch Bedeutung vermittelte Welt eintritt, ist sie das voraufgehende Wort [sic], das Gott zu uns spricht, indem er unser Herz mit seiner Liebe überflutet. Dieses vorhergehende Wort gehört nicht zu der durch Bedeutung ...

Textausschnitt: 6. Das Wort

34/4 Unter Wort verstehen wir hier jeden Ausdruck religiösen Sinngehalts oder religiösen Wertes. Dessen Träger kann Intersubjektivität oder Kunst sein, Symbol oder Sprache, aber auch die erinnerten und aufgezeichneten Lebensläufe, Taten oder Leistungen von Individuen, Klassen oder Gruppen. Normalerweise kommen hierbei alle Ausdrucksweisen zur Anwendung; da aber die Sprache jenes Vehikel ist, durch das der Sinngehalt am umfassendsten artikuliert wird, ist das gesprochene und das geschriebene Wort für die Entwicklung und Klärung der Religion besonders wichtig. (120; Fs)

35/4 Durch ihr Wort tritt die Religion in jene Welt ein, die durch Bedeutung vermittelt und durch Werte geregelt wird. Sie beschenkt diese Welt mit ihrer tiefsten Bedeutung und mit ihrem höchsten Wert. Sie setzt sich in einen Kontext anderer Sinngehalte und anderer Werte. Innerhalb dieses Kontextes gelangt sie zu ihrem Selbstverständnis, setzt sich in Beziehung zu dem, was uns unbedingt angeht, und schöpft so von ihm die Kraft, um die Ziele, die uns als nächste angehen, um so angemessener und um so wirksamer anzustreben. (120; Fs)

36/4 Bevor die Religion in die durch Bedeutung vermittelte Welt eintritt, ist sie das voraufgehende Wort [sic], das Gott zu uns spricht, indem er unser Herz mit seiner Liebe überflutet. Dieses vorhergehende Wort gehört nicht zu der durch Bedeutung vermittelten Welt, sondern zur Welt der Unmittelbarkeit, zur unvermittelten Erfahrung des Mysteriums der Liebe und Ehrfurcht. Das äußerlich gesprochene Wort ist geschichtlich bedingt; seine Bedeutung hängt ab vom menschlichen Kontext, in dem es geäußert wird, und solche Kontexte ändern sich von Ort zu Ort und von einer Generation zur anderen. Doch das voraufgehende Wort in seiner Unmittelbarkeit entrückt den Menschen - obwohl es in seiner Intensität differiert, obwohl es bei unterschiedlichen Charakteren und auf verschiedenen religiösen Entwicklungsstufen recht unterschiedliche Resonanz hervorruft - aus der Mannigfaltigkeit der Geschichte, indem es aus der durch Bedeutung vermittelten Welt herausführt und hin zu einer Welt der Unmittelbarkeit, in der Bild und Symbol, Gedanke und Wort ihre Relevanz verlieren und sogar verschwinden. (121; Fs) (notabene)

37/4 Daraus sollte man nicht schließen, daß das äußere Wort etwas Nebensächliches sei, denn ihm kommt eine konstituierende Rolle zu. Wenn ein Mann und eine Frau einander lieben, ihre Liebe aber nicht bekennen, so sind sie noch nicht in der Liebe. Gerade ihr Schweigen bedeutet, daß ihre Liebe noch nicht den Punkt der Selbstaufgabe und Selbsthingabe erreicht hat. Erst die Liebe, die jeder freiwillig und völlig dem anderen bekundet, führt zur gänzlich neuen Situation des In-Liebe-Seins und ist der Anfang der Entfaltung ihrer lebenslangen Implikationen.1 (121; Fs)

38/4 Was für die Liebe von Mann und Frau gilt, gilt auf seine Weise auch für die Liebe von Gott und Mensch. Für gewöhnlich wird die Erfahrung des Mysteriums der Liebe und Ehrfurcht nicht objektiviert. Sie bleibt innerhalb der Subjektivität als ein Vektor, als ein Sog, als ein schicksalhafter Ruf zu einer gefürchteten Heiligkeit. Vielleicht verliert nach Jahren beständigen Gebetslebens und der Selbstverleugnung die Immersion in der durch Bedeutung vermittelten Welt ihren Totalitätscharakter und wird die Erfahrung des Mysteriums klar und deutlich genug, um Aufmerksamkeit, Staunen und Suche zu wecken. Selbst dann gibt es im individuellen Einzelfall keine sicheren Antworten. Das einzige, was man tun kann, ist sein lassen, was ohnehin ist, und geschehen lassen, was sich sowieso wiederholt. Dann aber braucht man, mehr denn je, das Wort - das Wort der Überlieferung, das religiöse Weisheit aufgespeichert hat, das Wort der Mitbrüderlichkeit, das jene vereint, die das Geschenk der Liebe Gottes teilen, das Wort des Evangeliums, das verkündet, daß Gott uns zuerst geliebt und in der Fülle der Zeit diese Liebe im gekreuzigten, gestorbenen und auferstandenen Christus uns geoffenbart hat. (121f; Fs)

39/4 Das Wort ist demnach personal. Cor ad cor loquitur: Liebe spricht zur Liebe, und ihre Sprache ist machtvoll. Der religiöse Führer, der Prophet, der Christus, der Apostel, der Priester, der Prediger - sie alle verkünden in Zeichen und Symbolen das, was mit dem Geschenk der Liebe, die Gott in uns wirkt, übereinstimmt. Das Wort ist aber auch sozial: Es bringt die versprengten Schafe, die zusammengehören, weil sie in der Tiefe ihres Herzens dem gleichen Mysterium der Liebe und Ehrfurcht antworten, in eine einzige Hürde [sic]. Schließlich ist das Wort auch geschichtlich. Es ist nach außen zum Ausdruck gebrachter Sinngehalt. Es muß seinen Ort im Kontext anderer, nicht-religiöser Sinngehalte finden. Es muß eine konkrete Sprache entlehnen und adaptieren, eine Sprache, die viel leichter über diese Welt als über die Transzendenz zu reden vermag. Doch solche Sprachen und Kontexte ändern sich je nach Zeit und Raum; sie geben den Worten wandelnde Bedeutungen und den Aussagen andere Implikationen. (122; Fs)

40/4 Daraus folgt, daß der religiöse Ausdruck durch die Stadien der Bedeutung hindurchgehen und in ihren verschiedenen Bereichen sprechen wird. Wenn man die Bereiche des Allgemeinverstands, der Theorie, der Interiorität und der Transzendenz unterscheidet und aufeinander bezieht, versteht man leicht die Vielfalt religiöser Äußerungen. Denn deren Quelle und Kern liegt in der Erfahrung des Mysteriums der Liebe und Ehrfurcht, und dies gehört zum Bereich der Transzendenz; die Grundlagen und Grundbegriffe religiöser Äußerungen, ihre Beziehungen und ihre Methode werden aus dem Bereich der Interiorität hergeleitet. Ihre technische Entfaltung finden sie im Bereich der Theorie; gepredigt und gelehrt werden sie im Bereich des Allgemeinverstands. (122; Fs) (notabene)

41/4 Hat man diese Bereiche einmal unterschieden und ihre Beziehungen verstanden, so ist es recht einfach, in groben Zügen frühere Stadien und verschiedenartige Entwicklungen zu verstehen. Fernöstliche Religion betonte besonders die religiöse Erfahrung. Semitische Religion betonte den prophetischen Monotheismus. Die Religion der westlichen Hemisphäre pflegte den Bereich der Transzendenz durch ihren Kirchbau und die Liturgie, durch ihren zölibatären Klerus sowie durch ihre religiösen Orden, Gemeinschaften und Bruderschaften. Sie zog ein in den Bereich der Theorie durch ihre Dogmen und ihre Theologie, durch ihre juridischen Strukturen und gesetzlichen Verfügungen. Sie hat die gemeinsame Grundlage von Theorie und Allgemeinverstand zu legen, die in der Interiorität zu finden ist, und sie muß sich dieser Grundlage bedienen, um die Erfahrung des Transzendenten mit der durch Bedeutung vermittelten Welt zu verbinden. (122f; Fs)

42/4 Rückschau zu halten ist leicht, doch Voraussicht ist recht schwierig. Wenn der Ausdruck auf den Bereich des Allgemeinverstands beschränkt ist, kann er nur gelingen, indem er sich der Kraft der Symbole und Gestalten bedient, um das, was nicht adäquat gesagt werden kann, anzudeuten oder zu evozieren. Wird der Bereich der Theorie expliziert, so kann auch die Religion von ihm profitieren, um eine klare und fest umrissene Skizze ihrer selbst, ihrer Aufgabenbereiche und Ziele aufzuzeichnen. Sofern es aber an intellektueller Bekehrung fehlt, entstehen Kontroversen. Selbst wo diese Bekehrung stattfindet, entsteht der merkwürdige Kontrast und die Spannung zwischen der alten Erfassungsweise, die von Gefühl durchtränkt ist, und der neuen theoretischen Erfassung, die frei von Gefühl ist, von Definitionen und Theoremen aber nur so strotzt. Daher wird der Gott Abrahams, Isaaks und Jakobs dem Gott der Philosophen und der Theologen gegenübergestellt. Die Anbetung der Dreifaltigkeit und das Gefühl der Reue werden der gelehrten Abhandlung über die Trinität und dem Definieren von Reue entgegengesetzt. Innerhalb der Bereiche des Allgemeinverstands und der Theorie läßt sich nun dieser Kontrast nicht verstehen und die Spannung nicht lösen. Man muß über sie hinausgehen und ins Reich der Interiorität vordringen. Denn nur im Bereich der Interiorität vermag sich das differenzierte Bewußtsein selbst zu verstehen und dadurch das Wesen und die komplementären Ziele der verschiedenen Schemata der Erkenntnistätigkeit zu erklären. (123; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; Glaube, Hoffnung; Pascal; Objektivierung der Gottesfrage

Kurzinhalt: Ohne den Glauben ist der Mensch selbst der Ursprungswert, und Zielwert ist das menschlich Gute, das der Mensch schafft. Im Licht des Glaubens aber ist der Ursprungswert das göttliche Licht und die göttliche Liebe, ...

Textausschnitt: 7. Glaube in der Religion

43/4 Glaube ist Erkenntnis, die aus religiöser Liebe geboren wird. Es gibt also erstens eine Erkenntnis, die aus der Liebe hervorgeht. Von ihr sprach Pascal in seiner Bemerkung, das Herz habe seine Gründe, die der Verstand nicht kennt. Unter 'Verstand' würde ich hier die Zusammensetzung der Aktivitäten auf den ersten drei Ebenen kognitiver Tätigkeit, nämlich des Erfahrens, Verstehens und Urteilens, verstehen. Unter den 'Gründen des Herzens' würde ich Gefühle verstehen, die intentionale Antworten auf Werte sind; und ich möchte die beiden Aspekte solcher Antworten in Erinnerung bringen: den absoluten Aspekt, der in der Anerkennung des Wertes besteht, und den relativen Aspekt, nämlich den Vorzug, den man einem bestimmten Wert vor einem anderen gibt. Und schließlich verstehe ich unter 'Herz' das Subjekt auf der vierten, existentiellen Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins und im dynamischen Zustand des In-Liebe-Seins. Demnach wäre der Sinn jener Bemerkung Pascals folgender: Neben dem Faktenwissen, das man durch Erfahren, Verstehen und Verifizieren erlangt, gibt es noch eine andere Art der Erkenntnis, die durch die Wertwahrnehmung und die Werturteile einer liebenden Person erreicht wird. (123f; Fs) (notabene)

44/4 Demzufolge ist der Glaube solch eine erweiterte Erkenntnis, wenn die Liebe Gottes Liebe ist, die unser Herz überflutet. Zu unserer Erfassung der vitalen, sozialen, kulturellen und personalen Werte kommt die Erfassung des transzendenten Wertes hinzu. Diese Erfassung besteht in der erfahrenen Erfüllung unseres unbegrenzten Dranges nach Selbst-Transzendenz, in unserer verwirklichten Ausrichtung auf das Mysterium der Liebe und Ehrfurcht. Da dieser ein Drang der Intelligenz nach dem Intelligiblen ist, ein Drang der Vernunft nach dem Wahren und dem Wirklichen, sowie der Freiheit und Verantwortlichkeit nach dem wahrhaft Guten, kann die erfahrene Erfüllung jenes Dranges in seiner Unbegrenztheit als eine verhüllte Offenbarung der absoluten Intelligenz und Intelligibilität, der absoluten Wahrheit und Wirklichkeit, der absoluten Güte und Heiligkeit objektiviert werden. (124; Fs) (notabene)

45/4 Mit dieser Objektivierung wiederholt sich die Gottesfrage in neuer Form. Denn jetzt ist sie in erster Linie eine Frage der Entscheidung. Werde ich Gott nun auch meinerseits lieben oder werde ich mich verweigern? Werde ich aus dem Geschenk seiner Liebe leben oder werde ich mich zurückhalten, abwenden und ganz entziehen? Hier erheben sich die Fragen nach Gottes Existenz und Wesen erst in zweiter Linie, und dann sind es entweder die Fragen eines Liebenden, der Gott zu erkennen sucht, oder Fragen eines Ungläubigen, der ihm entkommen möchte. Das ist die Grundoption des existentiellen Subjekts, sobald es einmal von Gott gerufen ist. (124; Fs) (notabene)

46/4 Wie andere Wertwahrnehmungen so hat auch der Glaube einen relativen und einen absoluten Aspekt. Er stellt alle anderen Werte in das Licht und in den Schatten des transzendenten Wertes. In den Schatten, weil der transzendente Wert der höchste und unvergleichliche Wert ist. In das Licht, weil sich der transzendente Wert mit allen anderen Werten verbindet, um sie zu verwandeln, groß zu machen und zu verherrlichen. Ohne den Glauben ist der Mensch selbst der Ursprungswert, und Zielwert ist das menschlich Gute, das der Mensch schafft. Im Licht des Glaubens aber ist der Ursprungswert das göttliche Licht und die göttliche Liebe, während der Zielwert das ganze Universum ist. Dadurch wird das menschlich Gute in ein allumfassend Gutes aufgenommen. (124; Fs)

47/4 Während zuvor eine Darstellung des menschlich Guten die Menschen aufeinander und auf die Natur bezog, reicht jetzt das Anliegen des Menschen über die Welt des Menschen hinaus bis zu Gott und seiner Welt. Menschen kommen zusammen, doch nicht nur um beieinander zu sein und menschliche Angelegenheiten zu regeln, sondern auch um anzubeten. Menschliche Entwicklung gibt es nicht nur bei Fertigkeiten und Tugenden, sondern auch in der Heiligkeit. Die Kraft der Gottesliebe bringt eine neue Energie und Wirksamkeit in alles Gutsein, und die menschliche Erwartung geht nun bis über das Grab hinaus. (124f; Fs)

48/4 Gott als Ursprungswert und die Welt als Zielwert zu verstehen schließt ein, daß auch Gott sich selbst transzendiert und die Welt die Frucht seiner Selbst-Transzendenz ist, Ausdruck und Kundgabe seiner Güte und Wohltätigkeit, ja seiner Herrlichkeit. Wie die Vortrefflichkeit des Sohnes die Ehre seines Vaters ist, so ist auch die Vortrefflichkeit der Menschheit die Ehre Gottes. Sagt man, Gott habe die Welt zu seiner Ehre geschaffen, so sagt man, daß er sie nicht um seinetwillen, sondern unseretwegen geschaffen hat.1 Er schuf uns nach seinem Bilde, denn unsere Authentizität besteht darin, ihm ähnlich zu sein, uns selbst zu transzendieren, Ursprung von Werten und in wahrer Liebe zu sein. (125; Fs) (notabene)

49/4 Ohne Glauben, ohne die Augen der Liebe ist die Welt zu böse, als daß Gott gut sein könnte, als daß ein guter Gott existierte. Der Glaube aber anerkennt, daß Gott dem Menschen seine Freiheit gewähret daß er ihn als Person will und nicht bloß als seinen Automaten, und daß er ihn zu jener höheren Authentizität beruft, die das Böse durch das Gute überwindet. So ist der Glaube mit dem menschlichen Fortschritt verbunden und muß der Herausforderung menschlichen Niedergangs begegnen. Denn Glaube und Fortschritt haben eine gemeinsame Wurzel in der kognitiven und moralischen Selbst-Transzendenz des Menschen. Wer eines von beiden fördert, der fördert indirekt auch das andere. (125; Fs) (notabene)

50/4 Der Glaube versetzt alle menschliche Bemühung in ein freundliches Universum; er enthüllt die letzte Bedeutung aller menschlichen Leistung und stärkt neue Unternehmungen mit Zuversicht. Umgekehrt verwirklicht der Fortschritt die Möglichkeiten von Mensch und Natur; er zeigt, daß der Mensch existiert, um in dieser Welt eine immer vollkommenere Leistung zu vollbringen, und daß diese Leistung, weil sie ein Gut des Menschen ist, auch der Ehre Gottes dient. Vor allem aber hat der Glaube die Kraft, den Niedergang rückgängig zu machen. Der Niedergang zerbricht eine Kultur mit widerstreitenden Ideologien. Er belastet die einzelnen mit sozialen, ökonomischen und psychologischen Zwängen, die angesichts der menschlichen Schwäche einem Determinismus gleichkommen. Er vervielfacht und häuft die Mißbräuche und Absurditäten, aus denen Empörung, Haß, Wut und Gewalt hervorgehen. Nicht durch Propaganda und nicht durch Argumente wird menschliche Vernunft aus ihren ideologischen Gefängnissen befreit, sondern durch religiösen Glauben. Nicht Versprechungen von Menschen, sondern die religiöse Hoffnung macht den Menschen fähig, den ungeheuren Zwängen des sozialen Verfalls zu widerstehen. (125f; Fs) (notabene)

51/4 Wenn Leidenschaften abklingen und Ungerechtigkeiten sich nicht verschlimmern sollen, wenn sie nicht ignoriert und nicht bloß bemäntelt werden dürfen, sondern zugegeben und beseitigt werden müssen, dann sind menschliche Besitzgier und menschlicher Stolz durch religiöse Nächstenliebe zu ersetzen, durch die Nächstenliebe des leidenden Gottesknechts, durch aufopfernde Liebe. Menschen sind Sünder. Wenn menschlicher Fortschritt nicht für immer entstellt und zerstört werden soll aus Unachtsamkeit, aus Mißverstehen und durch die Irrationalität und Verantwortungslosigkeit des Niedergangs, dann muß der Mensch an seine Sündhaftigkeit erinnert werden. Er muß seine wirkliche Schuld erkennen und eingestehen und muß sich bessern. Er muß in Demut lernen, daß sich die religiöse Entwicklung dialektisch vollzieht und daß die mühevolle Aufgabe der Reue und Umkehr ein Leben lang dauert. (126; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; religiöse Glaubensüberzeugung - communio, Gemeinschaft; Glaube (Lonergan: faith - belief);

Kurzinhalt: Wir können jedoch anmerken, daß wir durch die Unterscheidung von Glaube (faith) Glaubensüberzeugung (belief) eine Grundlage erhalten, die sowohl der ökumenischen Begegnung dient, wie auch einer Begegnung aller Religionen, die ein Fundament in der ...

Textausschnitt: 8. Religiöse Glaubensüberzeugung1

---
Fußnote zu oben:
Anm. des Herausgebers: G. Sala, S. J., verdanke ich folgende Präzisierung: Lonergan unterscheidet hier zwischen belief und faith. Von belief hat er schon in II, 5 gehandelt (wofür wir meistens den Terminus Glauben verwendet haben). Dort ging es um den Glauben im allgemeinen Sinn als das Sich-zu-eigen-Machen eines Etkenntnisinhaltes, zu dem das Subjekt nicht aufgrund eigenen immanent vollzogenen Erkenntnisprozesses gelangt. In diesem Sinne gehört der Glaube zum tatsächlichen Wissensbestand des Menschen, insofern er in einer Gesellschaft und in einer Kultur lebt. Die Wissenssoziologie geht genau auf diesen Vollzug der menschlichen Erkenntnis und auf diese Erkenntnisinhalte ein. Belief bezeichnet also im Phänomen des Glaubens seine allgemein menschliche Struktur und insbesondere seine Inhalte. Mit faith will jetzt Lonergan den Glauben als spezifisch und grundlegend religiöse Realität bezeichnen, die den verschiedenen lehrmäßigen Inhalten vorhergeht und sie begründet. Faith ist zwar den Inhalten gegenüber nicht gleichgültig, insofern der religiöse Glaube eines Menschen und einer Gemeinschaft auf konkrete und zwar möglichst formulierte Inhalte abzielt, identifiziert sich aber nicht ohne weiteres mit ihnen. Um beide Bedeutungen auch sprachlich zu unterscheiden, verwenden wir im gegenwärtigen Kontext den Terminus Glauben für faith und Glaubensüberzeugung für belief.
---

52/4 Unter den Werten, die der Glaube (faith) erkennt, ist der Wert, dem Wort der Religion zu glauben, sich die Tatsachen- und Werturteile, die die Religion vorlegt, zu eigen zu machen. Eine solche Glaubensüberzeugung (belief) und Annahme ist von gleicher Struktur wie andere Glaubensüberzeugung, die schon im zweiten Kapitel beschrieben wurde. Jetzt aber beruht die Struktur auf einer anderen Grundlage, und diese Grundlage ist der Glaube (faith). (126; Fs)
53/4 Religiöse Erfahrung mag noch so persönlich und innerlich sein, sie ist dennoch nicht einsam. Die gleiche Gabe kann vielen verliehen werden, und die vielen können untereinander eine gemeinsame Ausrichtung in ihrem Leben und Fühlen, in ihren Maßstäben und Zielen erkennen. Aus der gemeinsamen Communio mit Gott entsteht eine religiöse Kommunität, eine Gemeinschaft. (127; Fs) (notabene)

54/4 Gemeinschaft verlangt nach Ausdruck, und der Ausdruck kann verschieden sein. Er kann imperativ sein und gebieten, Gott über alles zu lieben, und seinen Nächsten wie sich selbst. Er kann narrativ sein und die Geschichte des Ursprungs und der Entwicklung der Gemeinschaft erzählen. Er kann asketisch und mystisch sein, den Weg zur völlig überweltlichen Liebe lehren und vor den Gefahren auf diesem Weg warnen. Er kann theoretisch sein und die Weisheit, die Güte und die Macht Gottes lehren und Gottes Absichten und Ziele kundtun. Er kann eine Verbindung aller vier Formen oder ein Verbund von zwei oder drei von ihnen sein. Das Zusammengesetzte kann die Komponenten zu einer einzigen ausgewogenen Synthese verschmelzen, oder es nimmt eine von ihnen als Grundlage und gebraucht diese, um die anderen Komponenten zu deuten und aufzuzeigen. Es kann über lange Zeiträume unverändert bleiben, kann sich aber auch periodisch den unterschiedlichen sozialen und kulturellen Bedingungen anpassen und weiterentwickeln. (127; Fs) (notabene)

55/4 Gemeinschaften überdauern die Zeit. Wenn neue Mitglieder an die Stelle der alten treten, wird der Ausdruck zur Tradition. Die Religion wird geschichtlich in jenem allgemeinen Sinne, daß sie die Zeit überdauert und Grundkomponenten beisteuert zum fortschreitenden Prozeß persönlicher Entwicklung, sozialer Organisation sowie kulturellen Sinngehalts und Wertes. (127; Fs)

55/4 Es gibt aber einen noch viel tieferen Sinn, in dem man eine Religion geschichtlich nennen darf. Der dynamische Zustand des In-Liebe-Seins trägt den Charakter einer Antwort. Er ist die Antwort auf eine göttliche Initiative. Die göttliche Initiative beschränkt sich nicht bloß auf die Schöpfung. Sie ist auch nicht nur das Gottesgeschenk seiner Liebe. Es gibt ein persönliches Eintreten Gottes in die Geschichte, eine Mitteilung Gottes an sein Volk, die Ankunft des Gotteswortes in der Welt des religiösen Ausdrucks. Von dieser Art war die Religion Israels. Von derselben Art ist das Christentum. (127f; Fs)

56/4 Deshalb kommt nicht nur das innere Wort, das die Gottesgabe seiner Liebe ist, sondern auch das äußere Wort der religiösen Überlieferung von Gott. Der Gottesgabe seiner Liebe entspricht sein Gebot, uneingeschränkt zu lieben mit ganzem Herzen und mit ganzer Seele, mit allen Gedanken und mit aller Kraft. Die Erzählung religiöser Ursprünge ist die Erzählung der Begegnung Gottes mit seinem Volk. Religiöses Streben nach Authentizität durch Gebet und Buße und religiöse Nächstenliebe, die sich in guten Taten zeigt, wird zum Apostolat, denn 'an ihren Früchten werdet ihr sie erkennen' (Mt 7,20). Und letztlich ist das Wort des religiösen Ausdrucks nicht bloß eine Objektivierung der Gottesgabe seiner Liebe; in einem Vorzugsbereich ist es auch die ganz besondere Bedeutung, eben das Wort Gottes selbst. (128; Fs)

57/4 Damit kommen wir zu Fragen, die nicht mehr methodologischer, sondern theologischer Art sind, Fragen hinsichtlich der Offenbarung und Inspiration, der Schrift und Tradition, der Entwicklung und Autorität, der Schismen und der Häresien. Diese Fragen müssen wir den Theologen überlassen, auch wenn wir in den späteren Kapiteln über 'Dialektik' und 'Fundamente' einiges zur Methode ihrer Lösung sagen werden. (128; Fs)

58/4 Wir können jedoch anmerken, daß wir durch die Unterscheidung von Glaube (faith) Glaubensüberzeugung (belief) eine Grundlage erhalten, die sowohl der ökumenischen Begegnung dient, wie auch einer Begegnung aller Religionen, die ein Fundament in der religiösen Erfahrung haben. Denn in dem Maße, wie jene Erfahrung echt ist, ist sie auf das Mysterium der Liebe und Ehrfurcht ausgerichtet; sie hat die Macht der unbegrenzten Liebe, alles, was wirklich gut ist, zu offenbaren und hochzuhalten; sie bleibt immer das Band, das die religiöse Gemeinschaft verbindet, das ihre gemeinsamen Urteile lenkt und ihre Glaubensüberzeugungen läutert. Überzeugungen weichen freilich voneinander ab, doch hinter dieser Abweichung liegt eine tiefere Einheit. Denn Glaubensüberzeugungen ergeben sich aus Werturteilen, und die für die religiöse Überzeugung maßgeblichen Werturteile stammen aus dem Glauben (faith), jenem Auge religiöser Liebe, das Gottes Selbsterschließungen erkennen kann. (128; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Religion; praktische Anmerkung; vier Sinnbereiche: Allgemeinverstand, Theorie, Interiorität und Transzendenz; heiligmachende Gnade: Metaphysik: Vernunft - Wille - Interiorität: Änderung auf er einen Ebne -> Änderungen auf allen anderen Ebenen

Kurzinhalt: Falls man diese Analyse auf metaphysische Begriffe übertragen möchte, dann sind die aktiven Vermögen die transzendentalen Notionen, die sich in Fragen nach Einsicht, in Fragen nach Reflexion ... zu erkennen geben. Die passiven Vermögen sind die ...

Textausschnitt: 9. Eine praktische Anmerkung

59/4 Während wir vier Sinnbereiche unterscheiden, nämlich Allgemeinverstand, Theorie, Interiorität und Transzendenz, unterschied eine ältere Theologie nur zwei: Allgemeinverstand und Theorie, und zwar unter der aristotelischen Bezeichnung der priora quoad nos und der priora quoad se. Daher sprach die ältere Theologie, wenn sie von innerer Erfahrung oder von Gott sprach, entweder innerhalb des Bereichs des Allgemeinverstands - dann war ihre Sprache bildhaft und mit Symbolen durchsetzt -oder im Theoriebereich - und dann war ihre Sprache grundlegend metaphysisch. Eine Folge dieses Unterschieds wurde bereits angemerkt. Die ältere Theologie verstand die heiligmachende Gnade als einen entitativen Habitus, der absolut übernatürlich und dem Wesen der Seele eingegossen ist. Wir dagegen können, weil wir die Interiorität als einen eigenen unterschiedenen Sinnbereich anerkennen, mit einer Beschreibung der religiösen Erfahrung beginnen, sodann einen dynamischen Zustand des In-Liebe-Seins ohne Einschränkungen anerkennen und dann erst diesen Zustand mit dem Zustand der heiligmachenden Gnade identifizierten. (128f; Fs) (notabene)

60/4 Es gibt aber auch noch andere Konsequenzen. Die ältere Theologie unterschied, weil ihre Darstellung der Interiorität grundlegend metaphysisch war, sinnliche und intellektuelle Vermögen, Erkenntnis- und Strebevermögen. Daraus ergaben sich verwickelte Fragen hinsichtlich ihrer gegenseitigen Interaktion. Es gab Debatten zur Priorität des Intellekts über den Willen, oder des Willens über den Intellekt, des spekulativen Intellekts über den praktischen, oder des praktischen Intellekts über den spekulativen. Im Gegensatz hierzu beschreiben wir die Interiorität als intentionale und bewußte Akte auf den vier Ebenen des Erfahrens, Verstehens, Urteilens und Entscheidens. Die niedrigeren Ebenen werden von den höheren vorausgesetzt und ergänzt. Die höheren Ebenen heben die niedrigeren auf. Falls man diese Analyse auf metaphysische Begriffe übertragen möchte, dann sind die aktiven Vermögen die transzendentalen Notionen, die sich in Fragen nach Einsicht, in Fragen nach Reflexion und in Fragen nach Entscheidung zu erkennen geben. Die passiven Vermögen sind die niedrigeren Ebenen, die von den höheren vorausgesetzt und ergänzt werden. Diese Beziehungen sind zwar festgelegt, doch entscheiden sie nicht Fragen der Initiative oder des Vorrangs. Eine bedeutsame Veränderung auf irgendeiner Ebene verlangt Anpassungen auf den anderen Ebenen, und die Reihenfolge, in der die Anpassungen stattfinden, hängt vor allem von der Bereitwilligkeit ab, mit der sie verwirklicht werden können. (129; Fs) (notabene)

61/4 Die vierte Ebene, die die anderen drei voraussetzt, ergänzt und aufhebt, ist die Ebene der Freiheit und Verantwortlichkeit, der moralischen Selbst-Transzendenz und in diesem Sinne der Existenz, der Selbst-Ausrichtung und Selbst-Kontrolle. Versagt ihre richtige Funktion, so zeigt sich dies im beunruhigten oder schlechten Gewissen. Ihr Erfolg aber zeigt sich im befriedigenden Gefühl, seine Pflicht getan zu haben. (129; Fs)

62/4 Da die vierte Ebene das Prinzip der Selbst-Kontrolle ist, ist sie für das rechte Funktionieren der drei anderen Ebenen verantwortlich. Sie erfüllt ihre Verantwortung oder versagt in dem Maße, wie wir im Erfahren aufmerksam oder unachtsam sind, wie wir uns in unseren Untersuchungen einsichtig oder unintelligent verhalten und in unseren Urteilen vernünftig oder unvernünftig sind. Damit verschwinden zwei Begriffe: zum einen der Begriff vom reinen Verstand oder von der reinen Vernunft, die eigenständig ohne Leitung und Kontrolle durch verantwortliche Entscheidung tätig sind; zum anderen der Begriff vom Willen als einer willkürlichen Kraft, die indifferent zwischen Gut und Böse wählt. (130; Fs) (notabene)

63/4 Das Auftauchen der vierten Ebene des Überlegens, Wertens und der Wahl ist ein langsamer Vorgang, der sich faktisch zwischen dem dritten und sechsten Lebensjahr vollzieht. In dieser Zeit wird die frühere affektive Symbiose des Kindes mit seiner Mutter durch Beziehungen zum Vater ergänzt, der in seinem Kind eine potentielle Person erkennt und ihm sagt, was es tun oder nicht tun soll, ihm ein Modell menschlichen Verhaltens vor Augen stellt und für gutes Benehmen die späteren Belohnungen des sich-selbst-bestimmenden Erwachsenen in Aussicht stellt. So tritt das Kind Schritt für Schritt in die durch Bedeutung vermittelte und durch Werte geregelte Welt ein, und im Alter von sieben Jahren hat es nach herrschender Meinung den Vernunftgebrauch erlangt.1 Dennoch ist dies erst der Anfang menschlicher Authentizität. Man muß erst die Unruhe der Pubertät gut hinter sich gebracht haben, ehe man nach dem Gesetz voll verantwortlich wird. Man muß erst selbst herausgefunden haben, daß man selber zu entscheiden hat, was man aus sich machen soll; man muß sich selbst beweisen, daß man diesem Augenblick existentieller Entscheidung gewachsen ist; und man muß dies in allen folgenden Entscheidungen weiterhin unter Beweis stellen, wenn man eine authentisch menschliche Person sein will. Dieses hochkomplizierte Geschäft von Authentizität und Unechtheit ist es, das den allzu einfachen Begriff vom Willen als einer willkürlichen Kraft ersetzen muß. Willkür ist nur ein anderes Wort für Unechtheit oder Nicht-Authentizität. Den Willen als willkürliche Kraft aufzufassen heißt anzunehmen, daß Authentizität nie existiert oder geschieht. (130; Fs)

64/4 Was wiederum den Begriff vom reinen Verstand oder reiner Vernunft naheliegend erscheinen läßt, ist das Faktum, daß kognitive Selbst-Transzendenz viel leichter zu erreichen ist als moralische Selbst-Transzendenz. Das heißt aber nicht, daß erkenntnismäßige Selbst-Transzendenz leicht sei. Urvölker leben unter der Herrschaft von Mythen und Magie. Nur langsam und widerstrebend meistern unsere jungen Menschen Grammatik, Logik und Methode. Erst nach wohlüberlegter Entscheidung widmen sich Menschen einem Leben der Gelehrsamkeit oder der naturwissenschaftlichen Forschung, und nur durch ständige Erneuerung dieser Hingabe erreichen sie die Ziele, die sie sich gestellt haben. Ein Leben des reinen Verstandes oder der reinen Vernunft wäre ohne die Kontrolle der Überlegung, der Wertung und der verantworteten Wahl etwas Geringeres als das Leben eines Psychopathen. (130f; Fs) (notabene)

65/4 Wenden wir uns nun einem weiteren Aspekt der Thematik zu. Man pflegte zu sagen: Nihil amatum nisi praecognitum - Erkenntnis geht der Liebe vorauf. Die Wahrheit dieser Redewendung liegt in der Tatsache, daß normalerweise Vollzüge auf der vierten Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins entsprechende Vollzüge auf den drei anderen Ebenen voraussetzen und ergänzen. Zu dieser Regel gibt es eine kleinere Ausnahme insofern, als Menschen sich verlieben, und dieses Sich-verlieben ist etwas, das in keinem Verhältnis zu seinen Ursachen, Bedingungen, Anlässen und Antezedentien steht. Denn Sich-verlieben ist ein neuer Anfang, ein Vollzug der vertikalen Freiheit, wodurch die eigene Welt einer Neuordnung unterzogen wird. Doch die wichtigere Ausnahme von der Regel dieser lateinischen Sentenz ist das Gottesgeschenk seiner Liebe, die unser Herz überströmt. Dann sind wir im dynamischen Zustand des In-Liebe-Seins.2 Doch wer es ist, den wir lieben, ist weder einfach gegeben noch bisher verstanden. Unsere Fähigkeit zu moralischer Selbst-Transzendenz hat eine Erfüllung gefunden, die tiefe Freude und vollkommenen Frieden bringt. Unsere Liebe offenbart uns Werte, die wir nicht zu schätzen wußten, Werte des Gebetes und der Anbetung, oder der Reue und der Glaubensüberzeugung. Wenn wir aber wissen möchten, was in uns vorgeht, und lernen, dies in unseren Lebensvollzug einzufügen, müssen wir fragen, nachforschen und Rat suchen. Daher kommt es, daß in religiösen Angelegenheiten die Liebe der Erkenntnis vorangeht; und weil diese Liebe eine Gabe Gottes ist, ist der eigentliche Anfang des Glaubens der Gnade Gottes zu verdanken. (131; Fs)

66/4 Nach dieser Darstellung ist nicht nur das alte Problem des Heils der Nicht-Christen stark reduziert, sondern auch das wahre Wesen der christlichen Apologetik geklärt. Aufgabe des Apologeten ist es weder, in anderen das Gottesgeschenk der Liebe hervorzurufen, noch, es für sie zu rechtfertigen. Nur Gott kann diese Gabe geben, und die Gabe rechtfertigt sich selbst. Menschen, die in Liebe sind, haben sich nicht durch Vernunftgründe zu ihrem In-Liebe-Sein gebracht. Aufgabe des Apologeten ist es, anderen zu helfen, das Gottesgeschenk dem ganzen Lebensvollzug einzufügen. Jedes bedeutsame Ereignis auf irgendeiner Bewußtseinsebene verlangt Anpassungen auf den anderen Ebenen. Religiöse Bekehrung ist ein außerordentlich bedeutsames Ereignis, und die Anpassungen, die sie verlangt, können groß und zahlreich sein. Wegen einiger wird man Freunde um Rat fragen; wegen anderer sucht man nach geistlicher Leitung. Zwecks allgemein benötigter Information oder Interpretation und zur Formulierung neuer und Überwindung falscher Tatsachen- und Weiturteile kann man die Apologeten lesen. Diese können zwar nicht direkt wirksam werden, weil sie ja nicht Gottes Gnade verleihen; sie müssen aber genau, erhellend und überzeugend argumentieren, sonst würden sie dem, der um Brot bittet, Steine geben, und eine Schlange dem, der nach Fisch verlangt. (131f; Fs) (notabene)

67/4 Hier noch eine Schlußbemerkung terminologischer Art: Wir haben zwischen Glaube und religiösen Glaubensüberzeugungen unterschieden. Wir haben dies in Konsequenz unserer Auffassung getan, daß es einen Bereich gibt, in dem die Liebe der Erkenntnis vorangeht. Wir haben es auch getan, weil diese Redeweise die ökumenische Diskussion erleichtert. Doch obwohl wir unsere Gründe für gültig und unsere Ziele für legitim erachten, müssen wir das Bestehen einer älteren und autoritativeren Überlieferung anerkennen, nach der Glaube und religiöse Glaubensüberzeugung gleichzusetzen sind. Wir machen dieses Eingeständnis um so bereitwilliger, als wir nicht von der älteren Lehre, sondern nur von der älteren Redeweise abweichen. Wir weichen nicht von der älteren Lehre ab, denn mit der Anerkennung religiöser Glaubensüberzeugungen anerkennen wir das, was man auch Glaube genannt hat, und mit der Anerkennung eines Glaubens, der die Glaubensüberzeugung fundiert, anerkennen wir das, was man früher als lumen gratiae oder lumen fidei oder auch als eingegossene Weisheit bezeichnet hat. Und als letztes sei angemerkt: Ein Vertreter der Klassik (classicist)3 würde darauf bestehen, daß man niemals von einer akzeptierten Terminologie abgehen sollte, wogegen ich behaupte, daß dieser Klassizismus nur die irrtümliche Vorstellung ist, die Kultur normativ aufzufassen, und daraus zu folgern, es gäbe nur eine einzige Kultur. Die Tatsachen heute zeigen, daß Kultur empirisch aufzufassen ist, daß es viele verschiedene Kulturen gibt und daß neue Distinktionen legitim sind, wenn die Gründe für sie dargelegt werden und die alten Wahrheiten gewahrt bleiben. (132f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz, Notion; Erkennen nach dem Modell des Sehens: Immanenz - Transzendenz; T. als Element der intentionalen Analyse (Übersteigen von Erfahren zum Erkennen usw.)

Kurzinhalt: Transzendenz bedeutet zu diesem Zeitpunkt also eine Entwicklung in der Erkenntnis des Menschen, die für die Entwicklung im Sein des Menschen relevant ist.

Textausschnitt: 1. Die Notion von Transzendenz


714c Für gewöhnlich wird Transzendenz als das Gegenteil von Immanenz aufgefaßt und deshalb ist der einfachste Weg, diesen Gegensatz zu verstehen, von der verbreiteten Sichtweise auszugehen, daß Erkennen im Anschauen bestehe. Denn für diese Sichtweise ist die Tatsache des Irrtums in gewisser Weise verwirrend: Entweder besteht der Irrtum im Sehen von etwas, das tatsächlich dort nicht vorhanden ist, oder er besteht darin, nicht zu sehen, was dort vorhanden ist. Wenn aber das erste Anschauen irrt, dann können auch das zweite, das dritte, das vierte oder w-te Anschauen in derselben oder einer anderen Weise irren. Welchem Anschauen sollen wir nun trauen? Können wir überhaupt irgendeinem trauen? Verlangt Gewißheit nicht die Möglichkeit eines Super-Anschauens, in welchem man das anzuschauende Objekt mit dem Objekt als gesehenes vergleichen kann? Und litte das Super-Anschauen nicht an derselben Schwierigkeit? Offensichtlich täte es das, und deshalb kommt man zu dem Schluß, Erkennen sei immanent, und zwar nicht nur im ontologischen (635) Sinne, daß das Erkennen im Erkennenden stattfindet, sondern auch im epistemologischen Sinne, daß nichts erkannt wird außer dem dem Erkenntnisakt immanenten Inhalt. (Fs)

715a Ein erster Schritt in Richtung Transzendenz ist also, die irrtümliche Annahme, daß Erkennen im Anschauen bestehe, zurückzuweisen. Ja, nicht einmal das oben erwähnte Argument für die Immanenz beruht auf einem Anschauen, sondern auf Verstehen und Urteilen, und deshalb würde sich jeder, der sich auf das oben erwähnte Argument bezieht, um die erkenntnistheoretische Immanenz zu behaupten, besser auf die Tatsache beziehen, daß er argumentiert, und würde damit zur Ablehnung des Obersatzes des Argumentes geführt. Die Gegenpositionen fordern ihre eigene Umkehrung heraus. (Fs)
715b In einem allgemeineren Sinne bedeutet Transzendenz "darüber hinausgehen". So geben Untersuchen, Einsehen und Formulieren nicht bloß den Inhalt der Sinneserfahrung wieder, sondern gehen über ihn hinaus. So geben sich Reflexion, Erfassen des Unbedingten und Urteil nicht mit bloßen Objekten des Annehmens, Definierens und Betrachtens zufrieden, sondern gehen über sie hinaus zum Universum der Tatsachen, des Seins, dessen, was als wahr bejaht wird und es wirklich ist. Ferner, man kann sich damit begnügen, die Dinge in bezug auf uns zu erkennen, oder man kann darüber hinausgehen und sich den Wissenschaftlern zugesellen, die nach der Erkenntnis der Dinge als aufeinander bezogen suchen. Man kann über den Common Sense und die gegenwärtige Wissenschaft hinausgehen, um die dynamische Struktur unseres rationalen Erkennens und Tuns zu erfassen und dann eine Metaphysik und eine Ethik formulieren. Man kann schließlich auch fragen, ob die menschliche Erkenntnis auf das Universum des proportionierten Seins beschränkt sei oder über dieses hinausgehe zum Bereich des transzendenten Seins; und dieser transzendente Bereich kann entweder relativ oder absolut aufgefaßt werden, entweder als über den Menschen hinausgehend oder als das schlechterdings Letzte im ganzen Prozeß des Darüber-Hinausgehens. (Fs)

715c Es ist klar, daß trotz dem imponierenden Namen die Transzendenz in der elementaren Sache des weiteren Fragenstellens besteht. So ist das vorliegende Werk von einem sich bewegenden Gesichtspunkt aus geschrieben worden. Es begann mit der Einsicht als einem interessanten Ereignis im menschlichen Bewußtsein. Es ging weiter zur Einsicht als zentralem Ereignis im Werdegang der mathematischen Erkenntnis. Es ging über die Mathematik hinaus, um die Rolle der Einsicht in den klassischen und in den statistischen Untersuchungen zu studieren. Es ging über die reproduzierbaren Einsichten der Wissenschaftler hinaus zum komplexeren Funktionieren der Intelligenz im Common Sense, in ihren Relationen zu ihrer psychoneuralen Basis und in ihrer historischen Erweiterung durch die Entwicklung von Technologie, Wirtschaftsordnungen und politischen Systemen. Es ging über all diese direkten und inversen Einsichten hinaus zum reflektierenden Einsehen, das das Urteil begründet. Es ging über alle Einsichten als Aktivitäten hinaus, um sie als Elemente in der Erkenntnis zu betrachten. Es ging über die tatsächliche Erkenntnis hinaus zu (636) ihrer beständigen dynamischen Struktur, um eine explizite Metaphysik zu konstruieren und die allgemeine Form einer Ethik anzufügen. Es hat gefunden, daß der Mensch einbegriffen und damit beschäftigt ist, sich zu entwickeln, über das hinauszugehen, was er de facto ist, und es ist konfrontiert worden mit der Unfähigkeit des Menschen zu anhaltender Entwicklung und mit seinem Bedürfnis, hinauszugehen über die bislang betrachteten Vorgehensweisen seiner Bemühung hinauszugehen. (Fs)

716a Transzendenz bedeutet zu diesem Zeitpunkt also eine Entwicklung in der Erkenntnis des Menschen, die für die Entwicklung im Sein des Menschen relevant ist. Bislang haben wir uns mit der Erkenntnis des proportionierten Seins zufriedengegeben. Der Mensch aber ist im Prozeß der Entwicklung begriffen. Insofern er intelligent und vernünftig, frei und verantwortlich ist, muß er seine eigene Entwicklung erfassen und bejahen, akzeptieren und zur Ausführung bringen. Aber kann er das? Seine eigene Entwicklung zu erfassen, bedeutet für den Menschen, sie zu verstehen, von seiner Vergangenheit durch die Gegenwart auf die alternativen Bereiche der Zukunft zu extrapolieren. Es bedeutet, nicht nur horizontal zu extrapolieren, sondern auch vertikal, nicht nur auf zukünftige Wiederholungen vergangener Ereignisse, sondern auch auf höhere Integrationen gegenwärtiger nichtsystematisierter Mengen. Noch grundlegender besteht es darin, die Prinzipien zu erfassen, welche mögliche Extrapolationen lenken; denn während die Möglichkeiten viele und schwer zu bestimmen sind, sind die Prinzipien wenige und ermittelbar. Ferner, weil die Finalität eine nach oben aber unbestimmt gerichtete Dynamik und weil der Mensch frei ist, liegt das wahre Problem nicht in den vielen Möglichkeiten, sondern in den wenigen Prinzipien, auf die der Mensch in der Ausarbeitung seines Geschicks sich verlassen kann. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; immanente Quelle der T.; Streben: unvoreingenommen, uneigennützig; unbeschränktes Streben - unbeschränktes Erkennen

Kurzinhalt: Zweitens, zu behaupten, daß das Streben unbeschränkt sei, bedeutet nicht zu behaupten, daß das Erreichen von Verstehen unbeschränkt sei.

Textausschnitt: 2. Die immanente Quelle der Transzendenz

717a Die immanente Quelle der Transzendenz im Menschen ist sein unvoreingenommenes, uneigennütziges und uneingeschränktes Erkenntnisstreben. Weil dieses der Ursprung all seiner Fragen ist, ist es der Ursprung der radikalen weiteren Fragen, die ihn über die genau festgelegten Grenzen einzelner Fragestellungen hinaustragen. Und es ist auch nicht bloß der Operator seiner kognitiven Entwicklung. Denn seine Unvoreingenommenheit und Uneigennützigkeit versetzen ihn in Opposition zu seiner voreingenommenen und eigennützigen Sinnlichkeit und Intersubjektivität; und die Erkenntnis, die es ermöglicht, verlangt von seinem Willen, daß er sich zur Willigkeit entwickle und so sein Tun zur Übereinstimmung mit seinem Erkennen bringe. (Fs) (notabene)

717b Wenn nun diese Spannung auch zu offenkundig ist, als daß die Existenz des reinen Erkenntnisstrebens bezweifelt werden könnte, scheint die Behauptung, es handle sich um ein unbeschränktes Streben, doch so extravagant, daß sie Zweifel auch bei jenen weckt, die schon all seine Implikationen akzeptieren. Es wird deshalb angebracht sein, diesen Punkt noch einmal zu klären, ehe wir in unserer Untersuchung weiter gehen. (Fs)

717c Das fragliche Streben ist also ein Streben nach korrektem Verstehen. Zu (637) behaupten, daß das Streben unbeschränkt ist, bedeutet nicht zu behaupten, das menschliche Verstehen sei unbeschränkt oder die Korrektheit seines Verstehens sei unbeschränkt. Das Streben geht ja dem Verstehen voraus und ist auch mit einem Nichtverstehen kompatibel. Wäre es dies nicht, so wären die Bemühung und der Prozeß der Untersuchung unmöglich; denn die Untersuchung ist die Äußerung eines Strebens nach Verstehen und tritt ein, ehe man versteht. (Fs)

717d Zweitens, zu behaupten, daß das Streben unbeschränkt sei, bedeutet nicht zu behaupten, daß das Erreichen von Verstehen unbeschränkt sei. Denn der Übergang vom Streben zum Erreichen hat Bedingungen, die vom Streben verschieden sind. Wissenschaftliche und philosophische Methoden existieren gerade, um diese Bedingungen zu erfüllen zu helfen. Ein unbeschränktes Streben zu behaupten, bedeutet also, die Erfüllung nur einer von vielen Bedingungen für das Erreichen des unbeschränkten Verstehens zu behaupten. Weit davon entfernt zu behaupten, daß die anderen Bedingungen erfüllt sein werden, versucht er nicht zu bestimmen, welches die anderen Bedingungen sein mögen. (Fs)

717e Drittens, die Behauptung der Unbeschränktheit des Strebens bedeutet nicht die Behauptung, daß in einem weise geordneten Universum das Erreichen von Verstehen unbeschränkt sein müsse. Eine solche Behauptung würde aus der Prämisse folgen: "In jedem weise geordneten Universum zieht das Streben nach Erreichung das Erfordernis der Erreichung nach sich." Die Prämisse ist aber offensichtlich falsch; ein Wunsch, einen Mord zu begehen, zieht nicht die Pflicht nach sich, den Mord zu begehen, und schon gar nicht in einem weise geordneten Universum. Man mag aber einwenden, daß die Prämisse richtig ist, wenn das Streben gut, naturhaft und spontan ist. Aber diese Behauptung hat ihre Voraussetzungen. In einem Universum statischer horizontaler Schichten, wie es von der autonomen abstrakten Physik, der autonomen abstrakten Chemie, der autonomen abstrakten Biologie usw. ins Auge gefaßt wird, würden die Tendenzen und Wünsche, die auf einer Ebene naturhaft und spontan sind, auf diese Ebene beschränkt bleiben müssen; weil sie auf ihre eigene Ebene beschränkt bleiben würden, könnten und würden sie auf ihrer Ebene erfüllt werden; und weil sie auf ihrer eigenen Ebene erfüllt werden könnten und würden, wäre es auch richtig zu behaupten, daß in einem weise geordneten Universum statischer horizontaler Schichten das Streben nach Erreichung das Erfordernis nach Erreichung nach sich zieht. Es müßte dann allerdings noch gezeigt werden, daß dieses Universum einem Satz abstrakter und unverbundener Wissenschaften entspricht und so in einem Satz statischer horizontaler Schichten besteht. Tatsache scheint es zu sein, daß dieses Universum konkret ist und daß logisch unverbundene Wissenschaften intelligent durch eine Reihenfolge höherer Gesichtspunkte miteinander verbunden sind. Neben den Tendenzen und Wünschen, die auf eine gegebene Ebene beschränkt sind, gibt es demnach die Tendenzen und Wünsche, die jede gegebene Ebene übersteigen; sie sind die Wirklichkeit der Finalität, die als aufwärts aber unbestimmt gerichtete Dynamik aufgefaßt wurde; und weil diese Dynamik der Finalität ihre aufeinanderfolgenden Ziele statistisch erreicht; weil die Wahrscheinlichkeiten abnehmen, wenn die Erreichung zunimmt, ist die Implikation einer unbeschränkten Erreichung im unbeschränkten Streben weder eine Notwendigkeit noch eine Erfordernis, sondern höchstens eine geringfügige Wahrscheinlichkeit. (Fs)

718a Wenn auch die Klärung dessen, was das uneingeschränkte Streben nicht ist, mit Mühe verbunden ist, ist es doch relativ einfach anzugeben, was es ist. Der Mensch sucht vollständig zu verstehen. Und wie der Verstehenswunsch das Gegenteil von Totalobskurantismus ist, so ist der unbeschränkte Verstehenswunsch das Gegenteil jedes auch nur teilweisen Obskurantismus, wie gering er auch sein mag. Die Zurückweisung des Totalobskurantismus bedeutet die Forderung, daß einigen Fragen zumindest nicht mit dem willkürlichen Aufruf "vergessen wir es doch!" zu begegnen ist. Die Ablehnung jedes einzelnen Teilobskurantismus bedeutet die Forderung, daß keine einzige Frage willkürlich angegangen werden darf, daß jede Frage dem Prozeß des intelligenten Erfassens und kritischen Reflektierens unterworfen werden muß. Das uneingeschränkte Streben schließt dann also negativ die unintelligente und unkritische Zurückweisung jeder Frage aus und verlangt positiv die intelligente und kritische Behandlung jeder Frage. (Fs)

719a Die Existenz dieses uneingeschränkten Strebens kann auch nicht bezweifelt werden. Weder jahrhundertelange Forschung noch enorme Bibliotheken voller Antworten lassen eine abnehmende Tendenz des Stroms weiterer Fragen erkennen. Philosophien und Gegenphilosophien haben sich vervielfacht, aber sie alle - seien sie intellektualistisch oder antiintellektualistisch, verkünden sie nun die Herrschaft der Vernunft oder treten für das Denken mit dem Blut ein - schließen kein Feld der Untersuchung aus, ohne erst zu beweisen, daß der Aufwand nutzlos oder entnervend oder irreführend oder illusorisch sei. Und in dieser Hinsicht können wir darauf vertrauen, daß die Zukunft der Vergangenheit ähnlich sein wird; denn außer wenn einer im Namen von Dummheit und Blödheit auftritt, wird er nicht in der Lage sein zu behaupten, daß einige spezifizierte oder unspezifizierte Fragen beiseite zu wischen sind, obwohl es keinen Grund dafür gibt. (Fs)

719b Die Analyse führt zu derselben Konklusion. Denn außer dem Sein gibt es nichts. Die Aussage ist analytisch; denn sie kann ohne inneren Widerspruch nicht verneint werden. Wenn es außer dem Sein etwas gäbe, dann würde dieses Etwas -sein; und wenn dieses Etwas wäre, wäre es ein anderer Fall von Sein und somit nicht außerhalb des Seins. Ferner, das Sein ist das Zielobjekt des unvoreingenommenen und uneingeschränkten Erkenntnisstrebens; dieses Streben begründet die Untersuchung und die Reflexion; die Untersuchung führt zum Verstehen, die Reflexion fuhrt zur Bejahung; und das Sein ist all das, was intelligent erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht werden kann. Das Sein aber ist unbeschränkt; denn außer ihm gibt 639 es nichts. Das Zielobjekt des unvoreingenommenen und uneigennützigen Strebens ist deshalb unbeschränkt. Ein Streben mit einem unbeschränkten Objekt aber ist ein unbeschränktes Streben, und damit ist das Erkenntnisstreben uneingeschränkt. (Fs)

719c Die introspektive Reflexion bringt uns nochmals zu derselben Behauptung. Denn was immer gelten mag für die kognitiven Bestrebungen anderer, könnte meine eigene nicht radikal beschränkt sein? Könnte nicht mein Wunsch nach korrektem Verstehen an einer immanenten und verborgenen Beschränktheit und Befangenheit kranken, so daß es reale Dinge geben könnte, die völlig jenseits seines äußersten Horizontes liegen? Könnte es nicht so sein? Und doch, wenn ich die Frage stelle, geschieht dies kraft meines Erkenntnisstrebens; und wie die Frage selbst offenbart, beschäftigt sich mein Erkenntnisstreben mit dem, was völlig jenseits eines vermuteten beschränkten Horizontes liegt. Selbst mein Streben scheint uneingeschränkt zu sein. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Notion der transzendenten Erkenntnis; Tatsache - Möglichkeit

Kurzinhalt: Sein ist das, was immer intelligent erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht werden kann. Das Sein ist proportioniert oder transzendent, je nachdem, ob es innerhalb oder außerhalb des Bereichs der äußeren und inneren Erfahrung des Menschen liegt.

Textausschnitt: 3. Die Notion der transzendenten Erkenntnis

720a Das unbeschränkte Erkenntnisstreben des Menschen ist mit einer beschränkten Fähigkeit zur Erreichung von Erkenntnis verbunden. Aus diesem Paradox folgen sowohl eine Tatsache wie auch eine Forderung. Die Tatsache ist, daß der Bereich der möglichen Fragen weitgehender ist als der Bereich der möglichen Antworten. Die Forderung ist die nach einer kritischen Prüfung der möglichen Fragen. Denn nur durch eine solche kritische Prüfung kann sich der Mensch intelligente und vernünftige Gründe verschaffen, die es ihm ermöglichen, nicht beantwortbare Fragen beiseite zu legen und seine Aufmerksamkeit auf jene Fragen zu beschränken, die beantwortbar sind. (Fs)

720b Dieses kritische Unternehmen ist nicht so einfach, wie angenommen worden ist. Denn während die Fragestellung in den Termini von Möglichkeit und Unmöglichkeit formuliert wird, kann sie nur in den Termini von Tatsachen beantwortet werden. Erstens ist die Frage nach der Möglichkeit regressiv. Wenn irgendeiner weniger allgemeinen Untersuchung eine kritische Untersuchung ihrer Möglichkeit vorausgehen muß, dann muß der kritischen Untersuchung eine vor-kritische Untersuchung über die Möglichkeit der kritischen Untersuchung vorausgehen, die vor-kritische Untersuchung wiederum benötigt eine vor-vor-kritische Untersuchung und so endlos weiter. Zweitens können Fragen nach Möglichkeit und Unmöglichkeit nur durch Bezugnahme auf Tatsachenurteile entschieden werden. Denn während es analytische Aussagen gibt und während diese ad libitum durch das Postulieren von syntaktischen Regeln und das Definieren von diesen Regeln unterworfenen Termini aufgestellt werden können, können analytische Prinzipien doch nur erhalten werden, indem die weitere Forderung erfüllt wird, daß sowohl die Termini wie auch die Relationen der analytischen Aussagen in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen. (Fs)

720c Das ausschlaggebende Element bei der Bestimmung der Möglichkeit von (640) Erkenntnis ist dann also immer die Tatsache der Erkenntnis. Das Argument wird immer sein, daß eine Erkenntnis möglich ist, wenn eine Erkenntnis dieser Art tatsächlich vorkommt. Es folgt, daß die kritische Fragestellung nur stückweise in Angriff genommen werden kann. Die Tatsachen müssen eine nach der anderen ermittelt werden, und die Antwort auf die kritische Fragestellung zeigt sich erst in der großangelegten Strategie, welche die reihenweise Anordnung der Tatsachen leitet. (Fs)

720d In unserem eigenen Vorgehen können vier Stadien unterschieden werden. Erstens, wir konzentrierten die Aufmerksamkeit auf die kognitive Aktivität als Aktivität und versuchten die Schlüsselereignisse im Erlernen der Mathematik, in der Beförderung der Wissenschaft, in der Entwicklung des Common Sense und im Bilden von Urteilen auf diesen Gebieten zu erfassen. Zweitens, wir wandten uns der kognitiven Aktivität als kognitiver zu und begannen bei dem besonderen Fall der Selbstbejahung, um zu zeigen, daß die Selbstbejahung vorkommt, daß es sich bei ihr um Erkenntnis handelt, wenn Erkennen das Erkennen von Sein bedeutet, und daß sie objektiv ist im Sinne gewisser bestimmbarer Bedeutungen des Terminus Objektivität. Drittens, wir wandten uns dem allgemeinen Fall der Erkenntnis von proportioniertem Sein zu und, weil die Selbstbejahung ein Schlüsselakt war, konnten wir ein allgemeines dialektisches Theorem aufstellen, das die Formulierungen der Entdeckungen menschlicher Intelligenz in Positionen und Gegenpositionen aufteilte und zeigte, daß die Positionen zu einer Entwicklung und die Gegenpositionen zu ihrer eigenen Umkehrung auffordern. Auf dieser Grundlage erwies es sich als möglich, eine Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins und eine entsprechende daraus folgende Ethik aufzustellen. (Fs)

721a Das vierte Stadium des Argumentes beschäftigt sich mit der menschlichen Erkenntnis des transzendenten Seins. Das Skelett des Verfahrens ist ziemlich einfach. Sein ist das, was immer intelligent erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht werden kann. Das Sein ist proportioniert oder transzendent, je nachdem, ob es innerhalb oder außerhalb des Bereichs der äußeren und inneren Erfahrung des Menschen liegt. Die Möglichkeit transzendenter Erkenntnis ist dann die Möglichkeit des intelligenten Erfassens und vernünftigen Bejahens eines transzendenten Seins. Und der Beweis für die Möglichkeit liegt in der Tatsache, daß ein solches intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen vorkommen. (Fs) (notabene)

721b Wie wir aber bemerkt haben, kann eine derart allgemeine Skizze nicht zeigen, ob das Verfahren kritische Bedeutung besitzt oder nicht. Denn diese Bedeutung liegt nicht im Beweis der Möglichkeit von der Tatsache her, sondern in der strategischen Wahl und reihenweisen Anordnung der Tatsachen. Im Moment ist alles, was über das vierte Stadium des Argumentes gesagt werden kann, daß es in dem Maße beitragen wird, die Macht und die Schranken des menschlichen Verstandes zu bestimmen, als das intelligente Erfassen und das vernünftige Bejahen des transzendenten Seins sich als den unvermeidlichen Höhepunkt unserer ganzen Darstellung von Verstehen und Urteil herausstellen. (Fs)

721c Zum Schluß wird es nicht fehl am Platze sein daraufhinzuweisen, daß dieser (641) Abschnitt über die Notion der transzendenten Erkenntnis keines Kommentars über die Ansichten von Kantianern und Positivisten bedarf. Denn wenn beide Gruppen auch lautstark die Möglichkeit transzendenter Erkenntnis bestreiten, hat uns ihre Unfähigkeit, eine adäquate Darstellung der proportionierten Erkenntnis herauszuarbeiten, schon auf einer elementareren Stufe des Argumentes dazu gezwungen, unsere Differenzen zu registrieren. Wenn man nicht Comtes mythische Religion der Humanität als etwas Positives betrachtet, hat der Positivismus den Gegenpositionen, so wie diese durch den Materialismus, Empirismus, Sensualismus, Phänomenalimus, Solipsismus, Pragmatismus, Modernismus und Existenzialismus veranschaulicht werden, nichts Positives hinzuzufügen. Im Gegensatz dazu ist Kants Denken reich und fruchtbar in den Problemen, die es aufwirft. Aber seine transzendentale Ästhetik ist von den jüngeren Arbeiten in Geometrie und Physik schwer beschädigt worden, und die transzendentale Logik krankt an einer Inkohärenz, die nicht zu beheben scheint. Denn die transzendentale Dialektik stellt ihre Behauptung einer transzendentalen Illusion auf die Grundlage, daß das Unbedingte nicht ein konstituierender Faktor im Urteil sei, sondern lediglich ein regulatives Ideal der reinen Vernunft. Indes liefert der Schematismus der Kategorien die Verbindung zwischen der Sinnlichkeit und den reinen Kategorien des Verstandes; eine derartige Verbindung geht dem Urteil voraus und ist ein konstituierender Faktor im Urteil als konkretem. Schließlich, während Kant nicht bemerkt, daß der Schematismus einfach eine Anwendung des virtuell Unbedingten ist (wenn z. B. die leere Form der Zeit gefüllt wird, so gibt es einen Fall von Realität; das Füllen findet statt; also gibt es einen Fall von Realität), bleibt doch die Tatsache, daß das Unbedingte den Schematismus begründet und so das konkrete Urteil nach Kants eigener Darstellung begründet. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; transzendente Idee; Extrapolation: von der Notion zur Idee des Seins

Kurzinhalt: Man kann unterscheiden zwischen (1) der reinen Notion des Seins, (2) der heuristischen Notion des Seins, (3) eingeschränkten Akten des Verstehens, der Begriffsbildung und der Bejahung von Sein und
(4) dem uneingeschränkten Akt des Verstehens von Sein.

Textausschnitt: 4. Vorbemerkungen zur Auffassung der transzendenten Idee

722a Die Erkenntnis des transzendenten Seins schließt sowohl intelligentes Erfassen wie auch vernünftiges Bejahen mit ein. Bevor wir aber vernünftig bejahen können, müssen wir intelligent erfassen; und bevor wir das transzendente Sein intelligent erfassen können, müssen wir vom proportionierten Sein aus extrapolieren. Der gegenwärtige Abschnitt befaßt sich also mit dieser Extrapolation. (Fs)

722b Die Natur der Extrapolation kann am besten dadurch erläutert werden, daß wir sie mit der Mathematik vergleichen. Denn der Mathematiker unterscheidet sich sowohl vom Logiker als auch vom Naturwissenschaftler. Er unterscheidet sich vom Logiker, insofern er nicht einräumen kann, daß alle die Termini und Relationen, die er verwendet, reine Gedankenobjekte sind. Er unterscheidet sich vom Wissenschaftler, insofern er nicht jedes Gedankenobjekt zurückweisen muß, dem die Verifikation abgeht. In etwas ähnlicher Weise beschäftigt sich der gegenwärtige Versuch, die transzendente Idee zu bilden, einfach mit Begriffen, mit Objekten des (642) Annehmens, Definierens, Betrachtens, und es stellt sich deshalb keine Frage nach Existieren oder Vorkommen. Trotzdem operiert die Extrapolation auf das Transzendente hin, wenn sie auch begrifflich ist, von der realen Grundlage des proportionierten Seins aus, so daß einige Elemente in der transzendenten Idee verifizierbar sein werden, so wie einige positive ganze Zahlen verifizierbar sind. (Fs)

723a Die Frage, die zur Extrapolation führt, wurde schon gestellt, aber noch nicht beantwortet. Wir haben ja das Wirkliche mit dem Sein identifiziert, aber nicht gewagt zu sagen, was denn das Sein ist. Was also ist das Sein?

Wir wollen uns erst orientieren. Man kann unterscheiden zwischen
(1) der reinen Notion des Seins,
(2) der heuristischen Notion des Seins,
(3) eingeschränkten Akten des Verstehens, der Begriffsbildung und der Bejahung von Sein und
(4) dem uneingeschränkten Akt des Verstehens von Sein. (Fs)

723b Die reine Notion des Seins ist das unvoreingenommene, uneigennützige und uneingeschränkte Erkenntnisstreben. Sie geht dem Verstehen und Bejahen voraus; aber sie zielt auf diese hin, weil sie der Grund der intelligenten Untersuchung und der vernünftigen Reflexion ist. Dieses Sich-Bewegen auf das Erkennen hin ist zudem selbst eine Notion; denn es zielt nicht unbewußt, wie der Samen auf die Pflanze hin, und auch nicht sinnesmäßig, wie der Hunger auf die Nahrung hin, sondern intelligent und vernünftig, wie die radikale noesis auf jedes noema hin, wie die grundlegende pensee pensante auf jede pensee pensee hin, wie die initiierende intentio intendens auf jede intentio intenta hin. (Fs)
723c Zweitens, weil die reine Notion des Seins sich durch das Verstehen und das Urteilen entfaltet, kann eine heuristische Notion des Seins formuliert werden als das, was immer intelligent zu erfassen und vernünftig zu bejahen ist. (Fs)

723d Drittens, wenn die reine Notion auch ein unbeschränktes Streben ist, ist sie doch ein intelligentes und vernünftiges Streben. Sie begnügt sich deshalb damit, sich vorläufig zu beschränken, eine Frage auf einmal zu stellen, von anderen Fragen abzusehen, während sie auf die Lösung der vorliegenden Fragestellung hinarbeitet. Aus diesem Absehen, welches komparative negative Urteile vorwegnimmt, so wie die Notion der Natur oder der Essenz oder des Allgemeinen den Inhalt der intelligenten Definition vorwegnimmt, folgen beschränkte Untersuchungen, beschränkte Verstehens- und Auffassensakte, Reflexion über solche Auffassungen und schließlich Urteile über einzelne Seiende und einzelne Bereiche des Seins. (Fs)

724a Viertens, keine der erwähnten Handlungen versetzt uns in die Lage, auf die Frage "Was ist das Sein?" zu antworten. Die reine Notion des Seins wirft alle Fragen auf, beantwortet aber keine. Die heuristische Notion faßt alle Antworten ins (643) Auge, bestimmt aber keine. Einzeluntersuchungen lösen einige Fragen, aber nicht alle. Nur ein uneingeschränkter Akt des Verstehens kann das Problem lösen. Denn das Sein ist völlig universal und völlig konkret; außer ihm gibt es nichts; und deshalb kann die Erkenntnis dessen, was das Sein ist, nicht in weniger als in einem Akt erzielt werden, der alles von allem versteht. In Korrelation zu einem unbeschränkten Streben nach Verstehen kann entweder ein unbegrenzter Prozeß der Entwicklung oder ein unbeschränkter Verstehensakt gesetzt werden. Der Inhalt des sich entwickelnden Verstehens ist aber nie die Idee von Sein; denn solange das Verstehen sich entwickelt, gibt es weitere Fragen, die zu beantworten sind. Nur der Inhalt des unbeschränkten Verstehensaktes kann die Idee des Seins sein, weil nur in der Annahme eines unbeschränkten Aktes alles über alles verstanden ist. (Fs)

724b Es folgt, daß die Idee des Seins absolut transzendent ist. Denn sie ist der Inhalt eines Aktes uneingeschränkten Verstehens. Ein solcher Akt bringt uns nun aber nicht nur über alle menschlichen Errungenschaften hinaus, sondern gibt auch die letzte Grenze des ganzen Prozesses des Darüber-Hinausgehens an. Einsichten und Gesichtspunkte können transzendiert werden, solange weitere Fragen gestellt werden können. Wenn aber alles von allem verstanden ist, so gibt es keinen Platz mehr für weitere Fragen. (Fs)

724c Wir haben von der Frage: "Was ist das Sein?" auf die absolut transzendente Idee des Seins extrapoliert, und da stellt sich selbstverständlich die kritische Frage. Weil das menschliche Erkenntnisstreben unbeschränkt ist, während seine Erkenntnisfähigkeit beschränkt ist, braucht man kein Narr zu sein, um mehr Fragen zu stellen, als ein Weiser beantworten kann. Gewiß fragen die Menschen "Was ist das Sein"? Seit wir das Reale mit dem Sein identifizierten, haben wir uns bemüht, diese Frage hinzuhalten, bis wir sie in angemessener Weise anpacken könnten. Doch wenn die Frage sich auch sehr natürlich stellt, folgt nicht, daß die natürlichen Anlagen des Menschen genügen, um sie zu beantworten. Der Mensch kann sie offensichtlich nicht dadurch beantworten, daß er über einen unbeschränkten Verstehensakt verfügt; denn dann wäre seine Erkenntnisfähigkeit nicht beschränkt und er würde keine kritischen Untersuchungen brauchen. Es scheint aber ebenfalls offensichtlich, daß der Mensch die Frage beantworten kann, indem er die Konklusion ausarbeitet, daß die Idee von Sein der Inhalt eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes ist. Die Tatsache erweist ja die Möglichkeit; und wir haben diese Konklusion erreicht. Außerdem, was wir bereits auf eine in hohem Maße allgemeine Weise bestimmt haben, kann nun noch detaillierter ausgearbeitet werden. Denn einerseits haben wir den Umriß einer Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins herausgearbeitet, und so steht uns zumindest ein Segment im Gesamtbereich der Idee des Seins zur Verfügung. Andererseits haben wir uns im ganzen vorliegenden Werk damit (644) beschäftigt, die Natur des Verstehens in der Mathematik, im Common Sense, in den Wissenschaften und in der Philosophie zu bestimmen; und deshalb steht uns nun eine Masse von Beweismaterial zur Verfugung, das einige Bestimmungen für die Notion eines unbeschränkten Verstehensaktes liefert. Demnach gelangen wir zu dem Schluß, daß der Mensch zwar sich keines unbeschränkten Verstehensaktes erfreut und so die Frage: "Was ist das Sein?" nicht beantworten kann; daß er aber doch eine Anzahl von Eigenschaften der Antwort bestimmen kann, indem er auf der Subjektseite vom beschränkten zum unbeschränkten Verstehen und auf der Objektseite von der Struktur des proportionierten Seins zur transzendenten Idee des Seins aufsteigt. (Fs)

725a In der Tat ist eine solche Vorgehensweise nicht nur möglich, sondern auch unumgänglich. Denn das reine Streben schließt nicht nur den Totalobskurantismus aus, der willkürlich jede intelligente und vernünftige Frage beseite wischt, sondern auch den Teilobskurantismus, der willkürlich diesen oder jenen Teil des Bereiches intelligenter und vernünftiger Fragen beiseite wischt, die genau bestimmte Antworten zulassen. So wie der Mathematiker legitimer- und fruchtbarerweise vom Existierenden aus auf Reihen des Nichtexistierenden extrapoliert, so wie der Physiker vom mathematischen Wissen profitiert und eigene Extrapolationen wie etwa den absoluten Nullpunkt der Temperatur hinzufügt, so ist eine Erforschung der Idee des Seins notwendig, wenn man die Macht und die Grenzen des menschlichen Verstandes ausmessen will. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Idee des Seins: Inhalt eines Verstehensaktes

Kurzinhalt: Das Sein ist das Zielobjekt des uneingeschränkten Erkenntnisstrebens. Die Idee des Seins ist deshalb der Inhalt eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes.

Textausschnitt: 5. Die Idee des Seins

725b Eine Idee ist der Inhalt eines Verstehensaktes. So wie ein Sinnesdatum der Inhalt eines Aktes der Sinne ist, so wie eine imaginative Vorstellung der Inhalt eines Vorstellensaktes der Einbildungskraft ist, so wie ein wahrgenommener Gegenstand der Inhalt eines Wahrnehmungsaktes ist, so wie ein Begriff der Inhalt eines Aktes des Konzipierens, Definierens, Annehmens, Betrachtens ist, so wie das Urteil der Inhalt eines Urteilsaktes ist, so ist eine Idee der Inhalt eines Verstehensaktes. (Fs) (notabene)

725c Das Sein ist das Zielobjekt des uneingeschränkten Erkenntnisstrebens. Die Idee des Seins ist deshalb der Inhalt eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes. (Fs)

726a Ferner, außer dem Sein gibt es nichts. Die Idee des Seins ist deshalb der Inhalt eines Verstehensaktes, der nichts zu verstehen übrig läßt, keine weitere Fragen zu stellen übrig läßt. Man kann aber nicht über einen Verstehensakt hinausgehen, der keine Fragen mehr übrig läßt, die noch zu stellen sind, und so ist die Idee des Seins absolut transzendent. (Fs)

726b Ferner, das Sein ist völlig universal und völlig konkret. Die Idee des Seins ist deshalb der Inhalt eines Verstehensaktes, der alles über alles erfaßt. Außerdem, (645) weil dieses Verstehen keine Fragen mehr übrig läßt, die noch zu stellen sind, kann kein Teil seines Inhalts implizit oder obskur oder undeutlich sein. (Fs)

Ferner, das Sein ist innerlich intelligibel. Die Idee des Seins ist deshalb die Idee des Gesamtbereichs der Intelligibilität. (Fs)

Ferner, das Gute ist mit dem Intelligiblen identisch. Die Idee des Seins ist deshalb die Idee des Guten. (Fs)

726c Ferner, der unbeschränkte Akt des Verstehens ist ein einziger Akt. Sonst wäre er ein Aggregat oder eine Reihenfolge von Akten. Wenn keiner dieser Akte das Verstehen von allem über alles wäre, dann bedeutete die Bestreitung der Einheit die Bestreitung des unbeschränkten Verstehens. Wenn einer dieser Akte das Verstehen von allem über alles wäre, dann wäre doch wenigstens dieser unbeschränkte Akt ein einziger Akt. (Fs)

Ferner, die Idee des Seins ist eine einzige Idee. Denn wären es viele, dann wären die vielen entweder intelligibel miteinander verbunden oder nicht. Wären sie intelligibel verbunden, dann wären die angeblich vielen intelligibel eine einzige, und deshalb gäbe es eine einzige Idee. Wären sie nicht intelligibel verbunden, dann gäbe es entweder nicht einen einzigen Akt, oder der einzige Akt wäre kein Akt des Verstehens. (Fs)

726d Ferner, die Idee des Seins ist eine, aber von vielen. In ähnlicher Weise ist sie immateriell, aber vom Materiellen; nicht-zeitlich, aber vom Zeitlichen; nicht-räumlich, aber vom Räumlichen. Es wurde ja gezeigt, daß die Idee eine ist; aber sie ist der Inhalt eines unbeschränkten Aktes, der zumindest die vielen Seienden versteht, die es gibt, in allen ihren Aspekten und Details. Ferner, sie ist der Inhalt eines Verstehensaktes, und es ist gezeigt worden, daß das Verstehen vom empirischen Residuum innerlich unabhängig ist; was aber innerlich vom empirischen Residuum unabhängig ist, kann weder materiell noch zeitlich noch räumlich sein; denn all diese hängen innerlich vom empirischen Residuum ab. Zugleich ist der zur Diskussion stehende Verstehensakt uneingeschränkt; er versteht vollständig alle die Seienden, die es gibt, und zumindest einige von diesen sind materiell, zeitlich und räumlich. (Fs)

727a Ferner, es ist kein Paradox zu behaupten, daß die Idee des Seins eine einzige, immateriell, nicht-zeitlich und nicht-räumlich ist, und doch von den vielen, den materiellen, den zeitlichen und den räumlichen. Denn was im Inhalt beschränkter Verstehensakte möglich ist, übersteigt nicht das, was das unbeschränkte Verstehen erreichen kann. Unser Verstehen ist nun eines und doch von vielen; denn wir verstehen in einem einzigen Akt die ganze Reihe der positiven ganzen Zahlen. Ähnlicherweise ist es ist immateriell, weil es vom empirischen Residuum abstrahiert, und doch vom materiellen, weil es im Verständnis des Universums voranschreitet. Ferner, es ist zwar in die Ordinalzeit eingebunden, weil es sich entwickelt; es ist aber nicht in die stetige Zeit der Ortsbewegung eingebunden, weil seine (646) Entwicklung nicht durch eine Reihenfolge nichtabzählbarer Stadien stattfindet. Schließlich, während es einem räumlich bedingten Subjekt zugehört, ist es doch nicht räumlich, weil es sich mit der nichtabzählbaren Vielfalt des Raumes durch Invariante beschäftigt, die von besonderen Raumstandorten unabhängig sind. (Fs)

727b Ferner, in der Idee des Seins ist eine Unterscheidung zu machen zwischen einer primären und einer sekundären Komponente. Denn das Eine ist nicht identisch mit den Vielen und das Immaterielle auch nicht mit dem Materiellen, noch das Nichtzeitliche mit dem Zeitlichen, noch das Nicht-räumliche mit dem Räumlichen. In der einen Idee aber sind viele Seiende zu erfassen; in der immateriellen, nicht-zeitlichen, nicht-räumlichen Idee werden das Materielle, das Zeitliche, das Räumliche erfaßt. Es muß deshalb eine primäre Komponente geben, die erfaßt wird, insofern es einen einzigen Verstehensakt gibt, und eine sekundäre Komponente, die verstanden wird, insofern die erste Komponente erfaßt wird. Denn so wie die unendliche Reihe der positiven ganzen Zahlen erfaßt wird, insofern das generative Prinzip der Reihe erfaßt wird, so wird auch der Gesamtbereich der Seienden erfaßt, insofern die eine Idee des Seins erfaßt wird. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Idee des Seins, primäre Komponente des Seinsidee: der Akt der sich selbst versteht; intelligigel (2 Weisen); Beispiel: Reihe positiver Zahlen; Notion des Geistigen

Kurzinhalt: Es wird folgen, daß, wie die Primärkomponente im uneingeschränkten Akt besteht, der sich selbst versteht, so die Sekundärkomponente im uneingeschränkten Akt besteht, der alles andere versteht, weil er sich selbst versteht.

Textausschnitt: 6. Die primäre Komponente in der Seinsidee

727c Die Idee des Seins ist definiert worden als der Inhalt eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes; und in diesem Inhalt ist eine Unterscheidung zwischen einer primären und einer sekundären Komponente erwiesen worden. Natürlich wird man fragen, was denn die Primärkomponente sei, und die Antwort wird sein, daß sie mit dem uneingeschränkten Akt identisch ist. Es wird folgen, daß, wie die Primärkomponente im uneingeschränkten Akt besteht, der sich selbst versteht, so die Sekundärkomponente im uneingeschränkten Akt besteht, der alles andere versteht, weil er sich selbst versteht. (Fs) (notabene)

728a Einige Klärungen müssen jedoch vorausgeschickt werden. Die Gegenposition vertritt eine schlechthin letzte Dualität zwischen Erkennendem und Erkanntem; denn die Objektivität wird in Analogie zur Extraversion aufgefaßt; und damit ist das Erkennen wesentlich ein Anschauen, Erblicken, Intuieren, Ansehen, während das Erkannte etwas anderes sein muß, das angeschaut, erblickt, intuiert, angesehen wird. Die Position lehnt eine solche Dualität ab; Erkennen ist das Sein erkennen; in jedem gegebenen Fall können das erkennende und das erkannte Seiende dasselbe oder verschieden sein; und ob sie dasselbe oder verschieden sind, muß durch die korrekten Urteile bestimmt werden. (Fs) (notabene)

728b Ferner, das Adjektiv intelligibel kann auf zwei ganz verschiedene Weisen (647a) verwendet werden. Normalerweise bezeichnet es das, was verstanden wird oder verstanden werden kann, und in diesem Sinne ist der Inhalt jedes Begriffes intelligibel. Tiefer noch bezeichnet es die Primärkomponente in einer Idee; es ist das, was erfaßt wird, insofern man versteht; es ist der intelligible Grund oder die Wurzel oder der Schlüssel, aus denen die Intelligibilität im normalen Sinne resultiert. Es gibt übrigens einen einfachen Test für die Unterscheidung zwischen dem normalen und dem tieferen Sinn des Terminus intelligibel. Denn das Intelligible im normalen Sinn kann verstanden werden ohne zu verstehen, was Verstehen bedeutet; das Intelligible im tieferen Sinn aber ist mit dem Verstehen identisch, und es kann deshalb nicht verstanden werden ohne zu verstehen, was das Verstehen ist. (Fs)

728c Die positiven ganzen Zahlen besipielsweise sind eine unendliche Reihe intelligibler in Beziehung stehender Termini. Sowohl die Termini wie auch die Relationen werden von jedem verstanden, der Arithmetik betreiben kann, und man kann Arithmetik betreiben, ohne zu verstehen, was Verstehen ist. Außer den Termini und ihren Relationen aber gibt es das generative Prinzip der Reihe; insofern dieses generative Prinzip erfaßt wird, erfaßt man den Grund für eine Unendlichkeit voneinander unterschiedener Begriffe. Was ist aber dieses generative Prinzip? Es ist intelligibel; denn es wird erfaßt, verstanden. Man kann aber keinen Begriff von ihm bilden, ohne den Begriff dessen zu bilden, was eine Einsicht ist; denn das eigentliche generative Prinzip der Reihe ist die Einsicht. Nur wer bereit ist, über die Einsicht zu sprechen, ist auch fähig, die Frage: "Wie erkennt man den unendlichen Rest der positiven ganzen Zahlen, der durch das 'und so weiter' bezeichnet wird?" zu stellen und zu beantworten. (Fs) (notabene)

728d Es folgt eine nötige Klärung der Notion des Geistigen. Es ist unterschieden worden zwischen dem Intelligiblen, das auch intelligent ist, und dem Intelligiblen, welches es nicht ist. Es wurde weiter unterschieden zwischen dem, was innerlich vom empirischen Residuum unabhängig ist, und dem, was innerlich nicht unabhängig vom empirischen Residuum ist. Das Geistige wurde identifiziert sowohl mit dem Intelligiblen, das auch intelligent ist, als auch mit dem, was innerlich unabhängig ist vom empirischen Residuum. Eine Schwierigkeit tritt nun auf, wenn gefragt wird, ob eine Essenz als in einem Begriff erfaßt geistig sei oder nicht. Denn eine Essenz als im Begriff erfaßt abstrahiert vom empirischen Residuum; aber sie ist nicht intelligent und versteht nicht. Eine Lösung kann erreicht werden, indem man sich auf die zwei Bedeutungen des Terminus intelligibel beruft. Wenn es ein Intelligibles im tieferen Sinn gibt, gibt es auch einen Verstehensakt, mit dem es identisch ist; und dann ist das Intelligible geistig sowohl in dem Sinne, daß es mit dem Verstehen identisch ist, als auch in dem Sinn, daß es vom empirischen Residuum innerlich unabhängig ist. Wenn es andererseits ein Intelligibles im geläufigen Sinn gibt, dann ist es nicht mit einem Verstehensakt identisch; aber es kann vom (648) empirischen Residuum insofern abstrahieren, als es aus einem geistigen Akte resultiert; und so sind die Essenzen als in Begriffen erfaßt geistig in dem Sinne, daß sie Produkte des Geistes sind; aber nicht in dem Sinne, daß sie intelligente Intelligible sind. (Fs) (notabene)

729a Nach diesen Klärungen können wir nun zu unserem Problem zurückkehren. Die Idee des Seins ist der Inhalt eines unbeschränkten Verstehensaktes, und dieser Inhalt teilt sich unerbittlich in eine Primärkomponente, welche eine einzige, immateriell, nicht-zeitlich und nicht-räumlich ist, und in eine Sekundärkomponente, die aus Vielen besteht und die das Materielle, das Zeitliche und das Räumliche einbegreift. Was ist nun die Primärkomponente? Sie ist der uneingeschränkte Verstehensakt. (Fs)

729b Denn wenn ein Verstehensakt unbeschränkt ist, versteht er das Verstehen; er versteht nicht bloß eingeschränkte Akte, sondern auch den uneingeschränkten Akt; wenn er den uneingeschränkten Akt versteht, muß er dessen Inhalt verstehen, weil sonst das Verstehen des uneingeschränkten Aktes beschränkt wäre; der Inhalt des uneingeschränkten Aktes aber ist die Idee des Seins, und wenn so der uneingeschränkte Akt sich selbst versteht, versteht er damit auch alles andere. (Fs)

729c Es folgt, daß der uneingeschränkte Verstehensakt selbst die Primärkomponente in der Idee des Seins ist. Denn die Primärkomponente ist die immaterielle, nichtzeitliche, nicht-räumliche Einheit derart, daß, wenn sie erfaßt wird, alles über alles andere erfaßt wird. Aber der unbeschränkte Akt genügt dieser Definition. Denn er ist ein einziger Akt, er ist geistig, und deshalb ist er immateriell, nicht-zeitlich und nicht-räumlich; und es wurde soeben gezeigt, daß, wenn er erfaßt wird, alles über alles andere auch erfaßt wird. (Fs)

730a Anstatt von Primär- und Sekundärkomponente in der Seinsidee zu sprechen, können wir demnach zwischen einem Primärintelligiblen und Sekundärintelligiblen unterscheiden. Das Primärintelligible ist identisch mit dem unbeschränkten Verstehensakt. Es ist intelligibel im tieferen Sinn; denn es ist ein Intelligibles, das mit Intelligenz im Akt identisch ist. Es ist ein einzigartiges Intelligibles; denn es ist mit dem einzigartigen Akt des unbeschränkten Verstehens identisch. Andererseits sind die Sekundärintelligiblen das, was auch insofern erfaßt wird, als der unbeschränkte Akt sich selbst versteht. Sie sind intelligibel im gewöhnlichen Sinn; denn sie werden verstanden; sie sind aber nicht intelligibel im tieferen Sinn, weil der unbeschränkte Akt ein Verstehen vieler Intelligibler ist, und allein das einzigartige Primärintelligible ist mit dem unbeschränkten Akt identisch. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Idee des Seins, sekundäre Komponente des Seinsidee; Notion des Nicht-systematischen;

Kurzinhalt: Es scheint zu folgen, daß die nicht-systematische Komponente im tatsächlichen Universum und in anderen möglichen und noch wahrscheinlicheren Universen die Möglichkeit eines unbeschränkten Aktes, der alles von allem versteht, ausschließt.

Textausschnitt: 7. Die Sekundärkomponente in der Idee des Seins (649)

730b Weil er sich selbst versteht, versteht der uneingeschränkte Verstehensakt konsequenterweise alles über alles andere. Ist diese Konsequenz aber möglich? Schließlich haben wir ja entdeckt, daß das existierende Universum des Seins eine nichtsystematische Komponente einbegreift. Zudem gibt es zu jedem Zeitpunkt in der Entfaltung dieses Universums eine Anzahl wahrscheinlicher Alternativen und eine noch viel größere Anzahl möglicher Alternativen. Es gibt dann also ein enormes Aggregat ähnlicher möglicher Universen, und in jedem von ihnen gäbe es eine ähnliche nicht-systematische Komponente. Das Nicht-systematische ist nun der Mangel einer intelligiblen Regel oder eines intelligiblen Gesetzes; die Elemente sind bestimmt; die Relationen zwischen den Elementen sind bestimmt; aber es gibt keine Möglichkeit einer einzigen Formel, der durch die Reihenfolge der bestimmten Relationen Genüge geleistet wird. Es scheint zu folgen, daß die nicht-systematische Komponente im tatsächlichen Universum und in anderen möglichen und noch wahrscheinlicheren Universen die Möglichkeit eines unbeschränkten Aktes, der alles von allem versteht, ausschließt. (Fs)
730c Dies ist das Problem der Sekundärintelligiblen in der Idee des Seins, und unsere Lösung wird darin bestehen, daß das Nicht-systematische vom Gesichtspunkt des unbeschränkten Verstehens verschwindet. Zuerst aber soll in Erinnerung gerufen werden, wie die Notion des Nicht-systematischen entsteht; denn sonst können ihre exakten Implikationen nicht bestimmt werden. (Fs)

730d Unsere Analyse gestand die Möglichkeit einer vollständigen Erkenntnis aller Systeme von Gesetzen zu, hielt aber dafür, daß diese Systeme abstrakt sind und deshalb weiterer Bestimmungen bedürfen, wenn sie auf das Konkrete angewendet werden sollten. Sie folgerte, daß derartige weitere Bestimmungen nicht systematisch miteinander verbunden sein könnten, weil eine vollständige Erkenntnis aller Gesetze eine vollständige Erkenntnis aller systematischen Relationen einschließen würde. Sie bestritt aber nicht, daß die weiteren Bestimmungen intelligibel aufeinander bezogen sind. Sie anerkannte im Gegenteil die Existenz rekursiver Schemata, in welchen eine glückliche Kombination abstrakter Gesetze und konkreter Umstände typische weitere Bestimmungen wiederkehrend macht und sie so unter die Herrschaft der Intelligenz bringt. Ferner, sie anerkannte, daß konkrete Schemata divergierender Reihen von Bedingungen intelligibel sind. Wenn sowohl die benötigte Information als auch die Meisterung der systematischen Gesetze gegeben sind, ist es prinzipiell möglich, sich von einem gegebenen Ereignis Z durch so viele vorhergehende Stadien seiner divergierenden und verstreuten Bedingungen zurückzuarbeiten, wie man will; und es ist diese Intelligibilität konkreter Schemata, welche die Überzeugung der Deterministen wie etwa A. Einstein begründet, daß die (650) statistischen Gesetze dem, was es zu erkennen gibt, nicht gerecht werden. (Fs)

731a Indes stimmen wir mit den Indeterministen soweit überein, als sie die Möglichkeit von Deduktion und Voraussagen als allgemeinen Fall bestreiten. Denn wenn auch jedes konkrete Muster divergierender Bedingungen intelligibel ist, liegt seine Intelligibilität doch nicht auf der Ebene des abstrakten Verstehens, welches Systeme von Gesetzen erfaßt, sondern auf der Ebene des konkreten Verstehens, das sich mit einzelnen Situationen befaßt. Außerdem bilden solche konkrete Muster eine enorme Menge, die durch die abstrakte systematisierende Intelligenz aus dem triftigen Grund nicht behandelt werden kann, daß ihre Intelligibilität in jedem Einzelfall konkret ist. Es ergibt sich der spezifische Typ von Unmöglichkeit, die aus einem gegenseitigen Sich-Bedingen hervorgeht. Wenn man eine vollständige Information über eine Totalität von Ereignissen einräumen würde, könnte man von der Erkenntnis aller Gesetze her das konkrete Muster herausarbeiten, in welchem die Gesetze die Ereignisse in der Totalität in Beziehung setzten. Ferner, wenn man die Erkenntnis des konkreten Musters einräumen würde, könnte man sie als Leitfaden benutzen, um eine Information über eine Totalität relevanter Ereignisse zu erhalten. Nun aber ist die Bedingung der ersten Aussage die Konklusion der zweiten; die Bedingung der zweiten Aussage ist die Konklusion der ersten; und so bleiben beide Konklusionen lediglich theoretische Möglichkeiten. Denn die konkreten Muster bilden ein nicht-systematisches Aggregat, und so lassen sich die korrekten Muster nur durch Bezugnahme auf die Totalität der relevanten Ereignisse auswählen; andererseits ist die relevante Totalität der Ereignisse zerstreut, und sie können deshalb nur ausgewählt werden, um betrachtet und gemessen zu werden, wenn das relevante Muster schon bekannt ist. (Fs)

732a Wenn es aber einen unbeschränkten Verstehensakt gibt, dann wird er alles über alles verstehen ohne weitere Fragen, die noch zu stellen sind. Die konkreten Muster divergierender Reihen zerstreuter Bedingungen sind nun aber alle intelligibel, und so wird ein unbeschränkter Akt jedes von ihnen verstehen. Ferner, das Verstehen jedes einzelnen konkreten Musters bringt die Erkenntnis der Totalität der für jedes Muster relevanten Ereignisse mit sich; denn das konkrete Muster schließt alle Bestimmungen und Umstände jedes einzelnen Ereignisses ein. Und diese Konklusion widerspricht auch nicht unserer früheren Konklusion. Denn der unbeschränkte Verstehensakt geht nicht aus einem Erfassen abstrakter Systeme von Gesetzen hervor, sondern aus einem Erfassen seiner selbst; er macht sich nicht an die unmögliche Aufgabe, durch ein abstraktes System die konkreten Muster in Beziehung zu setzen, sondern erfaßt sie alle in einer einzigen Sicht, insofern er sich selbst versteht. Er bietet nicht an, Ereignisse abzuleiten oder vorauszusagen; denn er braucht keine Deduktion oder Voraussage und er kann mit ihnen auch nichts anfangen, weil er in einer einzigen Sicht die Totalität konkreter Muster erfaßt, und in jedem Muster die Totalität seiner relevanten Ereignisse. (Fs)

732b Um das Argument zusammenzufassen, sind Deduktion und Voraussage im allgemeinen Falle unmöglich. Sie sind unmöglich für das beschränkte Verstehen des Menschen, weil das beschränkte Verstehen die Menge der konkreten Muster divergierender Reihen zerstreuter Bedingungen nur dann meistern könnte, wenn diese Menge systematisiert werden könnte; und sie kann nicht systematisiert werden. Andererseits sind Deduktion und Voraussage, allerdings aus einem anderen Grunde, auch unmöglich für den unbeschränkten Verstehensakt; denn dieser könnte nur deduzieren, wenn er im Erkennen Fortschritte machen würde, entweder indem er eine abstrakte Prämisse in eine andere transformierte, oder indem er abstrakte Prämissen mit konkreter Information kombinierte. Das unbeschränkte Verstehen macht aber keine Fortschritte im Erkennen, weil es schon alles weiß. Ferner, das unbeschränkte Verstehen könnte nur dann Voraussagen machen, wenn einige Ereignisse relativ zu ihm gegenwärtig und andere Ereignisse relativ zu ihm zukünftig wären. Das unbeschränkte Verstehen aber ist nicht-zeitlich; es ist sozusagen außerhalb der Totalität der zeitlichen Reihenfolgen; denn diese Totalität ist ein Teil des "alles über alles andere", welches es erfaßt, wenn es sich selbst versteht; und wie es alles über alles andere in einer einzigen Sicht erfaßt, so erfaßt es die Totalität der zeitlichen Reihenfolgen in einer einzigen Sicht. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Kausalität; Unmgöglichkeit der reinen Tatsache; Positivismus, Gegenpositionen; jedes de facto Bedingtes verlangt ein Unbedingtes

Kurzinhalt: Im allgemeinen bezeichnet Kausalität das objektive und reale Gegenstück der Fragen und weiteren Fragen ... Daraus folgt, daß von reinen Tatsachen zu sprechen, die keinerlei Erklärung zulassen, von nichts zu sprechen ist.

Textausschnitt: 8. Kausalität

733a Indem wir fragten, was das Sein sei, wurden wir dazu geführt, den Begriff eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes zu bilden. Wenn wir nun fragen, was Kausalität sei, werden wir dazu geführt, die Existenz eines uneingeschränkten Aktes zu bejahen. (Fs) (notabene)

733b Im allgemeinen bezeichnet Kausalität das objektive und reale Gegenstück der Fragen und weiteren Fragen, die durch das unvoreingenommene, uneigennützige und uneingeschränkte Erkenntnisstreben gestellt werden. Weil diese Fragen verschiedener Arten sind, müssen Unterscheidungen zwischen verschiedenen Typen von Ursachen gemacht werden. (Fs)

733c Die Grundunterscheidung ist die zwischen äußeren und inneren Ursachen. Innere Ursachen sind die zentralen und konjugaten: Potenz, Form, Akt, die schon untersucht wurden. Äußere Ursachen sind die Wirkursache, die Zielursache und die Exemplarursache, und sie können auf drei Weisen in Betracht gezogen werden, nämlich in konkreten Fällen, im Prinzip und in der Fülle, die aus der Anwendung der Prinzipien herrührt. So kann in einem konkreten Fall eine Gemeinde durch einen Fluß geteilt sein und in einer Brücke die Lösung für viele ihrer Probleme sehen. Ein Ingenieur wird den Baugrund prüfen und eine entsprechende Struktur entwerfen; Bauunternehmer werden schließlich Bauarbeiterund Materialien zusammenbringen, um die Brücke zu bauen. Die Zielursache wird in diesem Fall die Verwendung sein, für welche die Gemeinde die Brücke vorgesehen hat; die Wirkursache wird die Bauarbeit sein; die Exemplarursache wird der Bauplan sein, wie er vom Ingenieur verstanden und konzipiert wurde. Nun wird man nicht ohne (652) weiteres annehmen, daß das Universum wie eine Brücke sei, und wenn man also behaupten will, Wirk-, Ziel- und Exemplarursache seien allgemein gültige Prinzipien, muß man diesen Notionen auf den Grund gehen und ermitteln, ob sie nun Allgemeingültigkeit haben oder nicht. Schließlich, wenn eine solche Allgemeingültigkeit behauptet wird, wird man, weil Wirk-, Ziel- und Exemplarursache äußere Ursachen sind, früher oder später dazu gebracht werden, einen ersten Wirkenden, ein letztes Ziel und ein Primärexemplar des Universums des proportionierten Seins aufzufassen und zu bejahen, und dann wird das Kausalitätsprinzip eine Bedeutung und Fülle annehmen, die es nicht besaß, solange seine konkreten Implikationen nicht ermittelt wurden. (Fs)

733d Unsere erste Aufgabe wird folglich darin bestehen, den Übergang von den vertrauten aber anthropomorphen Notionen der äußeren Kausalität zu ihrer Wurzel in einem allgemein anwendbaren Prinzip zu untersuchen. Wir nehmen an, daß die Exemplarursächlichkeit eine Wirklichkeit ist, wie sie durch Erfindungen veranschaulicht wird; daß die Wirkursächlichkeit eine Wirklichkeit ist, wie sie durch die Industrie veranschaulicht wird, und daß die Zielursächlichkeit eine Wirklichkeit ist, wie sie durch die Verwendung der Produkte von Erfindung und Industrie veranschaulicht wird. Wir fragen, ob solche Wirklichkeiten Fälle eines Prinzips sind, das fähig ist, die menschliche Erkenntnis vom Bereich des proportionierten Seins in den Bereich des transzendenten Seins zu führen. Unsere Antwort wird affirmativ ausfallen, und die Gründe dafür sind die folgenden. (Fs)

734a Erstens, das Sein ist intelligibel. Es ist weder jenseits noch außerhalb noch verschieden vom Intelligiblen. Es ist das, was durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen zu erkennen ist. Es ist das Zielobjekt des unvoreingenommenenen und uneigennützigen Strebens, intelligent zu fragen und kritisch zu reflektieren; und dieses Streben ist uneingeschränkt. Andererseits ist das, was außerhalb des Seins ist, nichts, und deshalb ist das, was außerhalb des Intelligiblen ist, nichts. Daraus folgt, daß von reinen Tatsachen zu sprechen, die keinerlei Erklärung zulassen, von nichts zu sprechen ist. Wenn die Existenz eine reine Tatsache ist, ist sie nichts. Wenn das Vorkommen eine reine Tatsache ist, ist es nichts. Wenn es eine reine Tatsche ist, daß wir erkennen, und daß klassische und statistische Gesetze, genetische Operatoren und ihre dialektischen Störungen, erklärende Gattungen und Arten, emergente Wahrscheinlichkeit und aufwärts zielgerichtete Dynamik erkannt werden können, dann sind sowohl das Erkennen wie auch das Erkannte nichts. Dies ist eine rüde und schroffe Behauptung, und man könnte versucht sein, sich in die Gegenpositionen zu flüchten, die Identität des Realen mit dem Sein abzulehnen, Objektivität mit Extraversion zu verwechseln und bloße Erfahrung für menschliche Erkenntnis fälschlich zu halten. Jede derartige Flucht ist aber nur vorläufig. Trotz ihrer wuchernden Vielfalt und beständigen Vitalität rufen die Gegenpositionen ihre eigene Umkehrung in dem Augenblick herbei, da sie beanspruchen, intelligent (653) erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht zu sein. Weil dieser Anspruch von einem intelligenten und vernünftigen Subjekt nicht vermieden werden kann, kann die Umkehrung nicht vermieden werden; und weil die Umkehrung nicht vermieden werden kann, wird man schließlich darauf zurückgezwungen sein zu bejahen, daß das Sein intelligibel ist, und daß die reine Tatsache ohne Erklärung außerhalb des Seins steht. (Fs) (notabene)

734b Zweitens, die menschliche Erkenntnis kann nicht auf den Bereich des proportionierten Seins beschränkt werden, ohne daß man sie zu reinen Tatsachen ohne Erklärung verurteilt, und sie so der Erkenntnis nicht nur des transzendenten, sondern auch des proportionierten Seins beraubt. Mit anderen Worten, jeder Positivismus ist wesentlich in die Gegenpositionen verwickelt. (Fs) (notabene)

735a Denn wir erkennen nicht, ehe wir urteilen; unsere Urteile beruhen auf einem Erfassen des virtuell Unbedingten; und das virtuell Unbedingte ist ein Bedingtes, dessen Bedingungen de facto erfüllt sind. Deshalb wirft jedes Urteil eine weitere Frage auf; es offenbart, daß ein Bedingtes ein virtuell Unbedingtes ist, und damit offenbart es Bedingungen, die de facto erfüllt sind. Dies "de facto" ist eine Tatsache, und wenn es nicht eine reine Tatsache ohne Erklärung bleiben soll, stellt sich eine weitere Frage. (Fs) (notabene)

735b Das proprotionierte Sein ist aber unserer Erkenntnis proportioniert. Wie unsere Urteile auf einem Erfassen des virtuell Unbedingten beruhen, so ist jedes proportionierte Sein in all seinen Aspekten ein virtuell Unbedingtes. Als eine Tatsache ist es, und damit ist es unbedingt. Es ist aber unbedingt nicht formal in dem Sinn, daß es keinerlei Bedingungen hat, sondern nur virtuell in dem Sinn, daß seine Bedingungen de facto erfüllt sind. Dieses "de facto" als letzthinnig anzusehen, bedeutet, eine reine Tatsache ohne Erklärung zu behaupten. Ein "de facto" durch die Berufung auf ein weiteres zu erklären bedeutet, das Thema zu wechseln, ohne das Problem zu lösen; denn wenn das andere "de facto" wiederum als reine Tatsache ohne Erklärung betrachtet wird, dann ist es entweder kein Sein, oder aber ist das Sein nicht das Intelligible. (Fs) (notabene)

735c Dies ist der springende Punkt des Argumentes; es kann auf so viele Weisen angewendet werden, wie es verschiedene Aspekte des proportionierten Seins gibt. (Fs)

735d Wenn nichts existierte, gäbe es niemanden, der Fragen stellen könnte und nichts, wonach zu fragen wäre. Die grundlegendste aller Fragen fragt demnach nach der Existenz; aber weder die empirische Wissenschaft noch eine methodisch eingeschränkte Philosophie können eine adäquate Antwort geben. Statistische Gesetze geben die Häufigkeiten an, mit denen die Dinge existieren, und die Erklärung der statistischen Gesetze wird die jeweilige Anzahl der verschiedenen Arten von Dingen begründen. Die Anzahl der existierenden Dinge ist nun aber eine Sache, und ihre Existenz eine ganz andere. Ferner, in Einzelfällen kann der Naturwissenschaftler ein existierendes Ding aus einem anderen herleiten; aber nicht einmal im Einzelfall kann er die Existenz der anderen begründen, auf die er sich als seine (654) Prämissen beruft. Soweit es die empirische Wissenschaft betrifft, ist die Existenz nur eben eine bloße Tatsache. Und der methodischen beschränkten Philosophie geht es auch nicht gerade besser. Weit davon entfernt, die Existenz begründen zu können, kann der Philosoph zeigen, daß sie innerhalb der Grenzen des proportionierten Seins nicht begründbar ist. Denn jedes proportionierte Seiende, das existiert, existiert bedingt; es existiert, insofern die Bedingungen seiner Existenz de facto erfüllt sind; und die Kontingenz dieses "de facto" kann nicht eliminiert werden, indem man sich auf ein anderes "de facto" beruft, das ebenfalls kontingent ist. (Fs)

736a Was für die Existenz gilt, gilt nicht minder für das Vorkommen. Sowohl Fragen wie auch Antworten kommen vor, und so gäbe es ohne das Vorkommen weder Fragen noch Antworten. Statistische Gesetze geben die jeweilige Anzahl der verschiedenen Arten von Ereignissen an; doch ist die Zahl eine Sache und das Vorkommen eine ganz andere. In Einzelfällen kann der Wissenschaftler einige Vorkommnisse aus anderen herleiten; aber die anderen sind nicht weniger bedingt als diejenigen, die hergeleitet worden sind. Ohne Anfangsprämissen gibt es keine Deduktion; und ohne Bedingungen, die de facto erfüllt sind, gibt es keine ersten Prämissen. Soweit es um die empirische Wissenschaft geht, ist das Vorkommen einfach eine reine Tatsache, und eine methodisch eingeschränkte Philosophie kann das Argument über die Existenz wiederholen, um zu zeigen, daß auch das Vorkommen als eine bloße Tatsache zu betrachten ist, solange man innerhalb des Bereiches des proportionierten Seins verharrt. (Fs)

736b Ferner, alles, was durch die empirische Wissenschaft und die eingeschränkte Philosophie erkannt werden kann, ist durchdrungen von der Kontingenz der Existenz und des Vorkommens. Klassische Gesetze sind nicht, was sein muß; sie sind empirisch, sie sind, was tatsächlich so ist. Genetische Operatoren erfreuen sich sowohl einer minderen wie auch einer größeren Flexibilität, und somit ist der Operator in jedem konkreten Fall das, was er tatsächlich ist. Erklärende Gattungen und Arten sind nicht Avataras von Platos ewigen Ideen; sie sind mehr oder weniger erfolgreiche Lösungen für kontingente Probleme, die durch kontingente Situationen aufgegeben werden. Der tatsächliche Verlauf der verallgemeinerten emergenten Wahrscheinlichkeit ist nur einer unter einer großen Zahl anderer wahrscheinlicher Verläufe, und die wahrscheinlichen Verläufe wiederum sind eine Minderheit unter den möglichen Verläufen; der tatsächliche Verlauf ist dann also das, was tatsächlich ist. Weit davon entfernt, derartige Kontingenz zu eliminieren, ist der Wissenschaftler durch seine Methode darauf festgelegt, zu ermitteln, welches in der Tat die klassischen Gesetze und die genetischen Operatoren sind; welches in der Tat die erklärenden Gattungen und Arten sind; welches in der Tat der tatsächliche Verlauf der verallgemeinerten emergenten Wahrscheinlichkeit ist. Und ein Philosoph, der auf das proportionierte Sein beschränkt ist, kann ebenfalls nicht mehr als eine Darstellung dessen bieten, was die Struktur dieses Universums in der Tat ist, (655) und er kann diese Darstellung auch nicht auf mehr basieren, als auf das, was die Struktur der menschlichen Erkenntnis in der Tat ist. (Fs)

736c Unser erster Schritt bestand darin, die Intelligibilität des Seins und die Nichtigkeit der reinen Tatsache zu behaupten, die keine Erklärung zuläßt. Unser zweiter Schritt bestand darin zu behaupten, daß man sich - wenn man innerhalb der Grenzen des proportionierten Seins verbleibt - dauernd mit reinen Tatsachen ohne mögliche Erklärung konfrontiert sieht. Es folgt sofort die negative Konklusion, daß die Erkenntnis des transzendenten Seins nicht ausgeschlossen werden kann, wenn es proportioniertes Sein gibt und das Sein intelligibel ist. Und diese Konklusion wirft die weitere Frage auf, worin denn unsere Erkenntnis des transzendenten Seins besteht. (Fs) (notabene)

737a Drittens, ein transzendentes Sein, das für unser Problem relevant ist, muß zwei Grundattribute besitzen. Einerseits darf es in keiner Hinsicht kontingent sein; denn wenn es dies wäre, wären wir wiederum mit der bloßen Tatsache konfrontiert, die wir ja vermeiden müssen. Andererseits muß das transzendente Sein nicht nur selbst-erklärend, sondern auch fähig sein, die Erklärung von allem über alles andere zu begründen; denn ohne dieses zweite Attribut ließe das transzendente Sein unser Problem der Kontingenz im proportionierten Sein ungelöst. (Fs)

737b Die genannten Anforderungen können noch anders ausgedrückt werden. Jedes proportionierte Seiende ist ein Bedingtes, dessen Bedingungen de facto erfüllt sind. Das Sein aber ist intelligibel, und deshalb gibt es kein reines Vorkommen, keine Kontingenz, die das Letzte schlechthin wären. Das proportionierte Sein jedoch existiert und existiert kontingent; also ist es nicht das Letzte schlechthin; also ist ein anderes Sein das Letzte schlechthin; und dieses ist nicht kontingent. Ferner, das letzthinnige Sein muß nicht nur selbst selbst-erklärend sein, sondern auch imstande, alles andere zu erklären; denn sonst bliebe das proportionierte Sein ein Bedingtes, dessen Bedingungen bloß de facto erfüllt worden sind; es wäre in jeder Hinsicht bloß eine Tatsache; und weil eine reine Tatsache nichts ist, wäre es nichts. (Fs)

737c Um dasselbe noch etwas anders auszudrücken, muß man nur die schon anerkannten Tatsachen der Ziel-, Exemplar- und Wirksursächlichkeit korrekt formulieren. (Fs)

737d Denn man verkennt das Entscheidende hinsichtlich der Wirkursächlichkeit, wenn man meint, diese bestehe einfach in der Notwendigkeit, daß das bedingt Seiende nur dann virtuell unbedingt wird, wenn seine Bedingungen erfüllt werden. Dieser Formulierung zufolge würde der Wirkursächlichkeit Genüge getan werden durch einen unendlichen Regreß, in welchem jedes Bedingte seine Bedingungen durch ein vorhergehendes Bedingtes erfüllt bekommt, oder - vielleicht realistischer (656) - durch einen Kreis, wie er durch das Schema der Rekursivität veranschaulicht wird. Indes ist die eigentliche Forderung, daß das bedingte Sein, wenn es Sein ist, intelligibel sein muß; es kann nicht existieren oder vorkommen als reine Tatsache, für die keine Erklärung verlangt oder erwartet werden soll; denn das Nicht-Intelligible liegt außerhalb des Seins. Nun sind sowohl der unendliche Regreß wie auch der Kreis einfach Aggregate reiner Tatsachen; sie sind nicht imstande, für die Intelligibilität des bedingten Seins zu sorgen; und deshalb gelingt es ihnen auch nicht, eine Wirkursache für das Sein, das intelligibel und doch bedingt ist, anzugeben. (Fs)

738a Noch kann eine Wirkursache angegeben werden, ehe man ein Sein behauptet, das sowohl selbst ohne Bedingungen ist, als auch die Erfüllung der Bedingungen für alles andere, das sein kann, begründet. (Fs)

738b Ferner, wenn es bedingte Seiende gibt, gibt es auch die Erfüllung ihrer Bedingungen; und wenn es keine bloßen Tatsachen gibt, die letztlich unerklärt bleiben, dann werden keine Bedingungen einfach zufällig erfüllt. Wenn aber keine Bedingungen einfach aufs Geratewohl erfüllt werden, dann werden alle in Übereinstimmung mit einem Exemplar erfüllt; und deshalb muß es eine Exemplarursache geben, welche die Intelligibilität des Schemas begründen kann, in welchem alle Bedingungen erfüllt sind oder erfüllt würden, die erfüllt sind oder erfüllt werden. (Fs)

738c Ferner, weil das Sein intelligibel ist, ist es auch gut. Als potentiell intelligibel ist es ein Mannigfaltiges, und dieses Mannigfaltige ist gut, insofern es unter dem formalen Gut der Ordnung stehen kann. Mögliche Ordnungen gibt es aber viele; sie schließen inkompatible Alternativen ein; sie entwickeln sich, aber sie tun es flexibel auf viele verschiedene Weisen; in jedem Stadium können sie auf viele verschiedene Weisen versagen, um dann ihre dialektische Korrektur hervorzubringen. Wenn es also in einem Universum eine tatsächliche Ordnung gibt, wenn diese tatsächliche Ordnung innerhalb des Seins liegt und somit keine bloße Tatsache ist, dann muß diese Ordnung ein Wert sein und ihre Auswahl infolge einer rationalen Wahl stattgefunden haben. Ähnlich, wenn in jedem möglichen Universum das Sein intelligibel ist und das Intelligible gut ist, dann ist die Möglichkeit jedes Universums die Möglichkeit seines Ausgewählt-Werdens durch eine schlechthin letzte rationale Wahl. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Kausalität 2: Zusammenfassung

Kurzinhalt: Erstens, das Universum des proportionierten Seins ist von Kontingenz durchzogen. Zweitens, reine Kontingenz liegt außerhalb des Seins, und deshalb muß es einen letzten Grund für das Universum geben ...

Textausschnitt: 738d Es mag scheinen, daß dies alles zu schnell gegangen ist, und deshalb wird es angebracht sein, das Argument nochmals im ganzen zu betrachten. Erstens, das Universum des proportionierten Seins ist von Kontingenz durchzogen. Zweitens, reine Kontingenz liegt außerhalb des Seins, und deshalb muß es einen letzten Grund für das Universum geben, und dieser Grund kann nicht kontingent sein. Drittens, der notwendige letzte Grund kann nicht genötigt sein, ein kontingentes Universum zu begründen, und er kann nicht willkürlich sein im Gründen eines intelligiblen und guten Universums. Er kann nicht genötigt sein; denn was aus dem Notwendigen notwendig folgt, ist gleichfalls notwendig. Er kann nicht willkürlich 657 sein; denn was willkürlich aus dem Notwendigen resultiert, resultiert als eine reine Tatsache ohne mögliche Erklärung. Was aber weder notwendig noch willkürlich und doch intelligibel und ein Wert ist, ist das, was frei aus der vernünftigen Wahl eines rationalen Bewußtseins hervorgeht. (Fs)

738e Die Zielursache ist also der Grund des Wertes, und sie ist die schlechthin letzte Ursache der Ursachen; denn sie überwindet die Kontingenz auf ihrer tiefsten Ebene. Das Sein kann nicht willkürlich sein, und das kontingente Sein kann nicht notwendig sein. Es folgt, daß das kontingente Sein eine vernünftig realisierte Möglichkeit sein muß. Seine Möglichkeit ist in der Exemplarursache begründet, seine Realisierung in der Wirkursache, seine Vernünftigkeit aber in der Zielursache. Ohne diese Vernünftigkeit wäre es willkürlich und damit außerhalb des Seins; was aber außerhalb des Seins ist, ist nicht möglich; und was nicht möglich ist, kann nicht verwirklicht werden. (Fs)

739a Solcherart ist also der Übergang von Wirk-, Exemplar- und Zielursache als Tatsachen innerhalb des Bereichs des proportionierten Seins zu den universellen Prinzipien, die unsere Erkenntnis in den Bereich des transzendenten Seins führen. (Fs)

739b Der Leser wird möglicherweise der Meinung sein, daß der Übergang diese Notionen der Ursächlichkeit nicht von ihrer anthropomorphen Qualität zu befreien vermochte. Denn weit entfernt davon, vom Menschen wegzukommen, führen sie recht offensichtlich zur Bejahung eines unbedingten intelligenten und rationalen Bewußtseins, welches das Universum frei in einer Weise begründet, die sehr ähnlich ist der Weise, wie das bedingte intelligente und vernünftige Bewußtsein des Menschen frei seine eigenen Handlungen und Produkte begründet. Unsere Antwort ist eine doppelte. Einerseits ist das spezifisch Menschliche, das Anthropomorphe, nicht ein rein intelligentes und rationales Bewußtsein, sondern ein in Spannung zwischen dem reinen Streben und anderen Streben begriffenes Bewußtsein. Andererseits kann man nicht umhin, insofern man im Menschen nur sein intelligentes und rationales Bewußtsein betrachtet, sich mit dem zu befassen, was auf das Universum und seinen letzten Grund innerst bezogen ist. Denn was anderes ist das Universum und sein Grund als das Zielobjekt des unvoreingenommenen, uneigennützigen und unbeschränkten Erkenntnisstrebens?

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Notion von Gott 1 (18 Bestimmungen);

Kurzinhalt: Erstens, wenn es einen uneingeschränkten Verstehensakt gibt, gibt es ein Primärintelligibles, das mit ihm identisch ist. Denn der uneingeschränkte Akt versteht sich selbst.

Textausschnitt: 9. Die Notion von Gott

739c Wenn Gott ein Seiendes ist, muß er durch ein intelligentes Erfassen und ein vernünftiges Bejahen erkannt werden. Es stellen sich dementsprechend zwei Fragen: Was Gott ist und ob Gott ist. Indem wir aber fragten, was das Sein ist, wurden wir schon zur Konklusion geführt, daß die Idee des Seins der Inhalt eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes sein würde, der sich primär selbst versteht und infolgedessen jede andere Intelligibilität erfaßt. Wie sich nun zeigen wird, hat unser Begriff eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes mehrere Implikationen, und wenn diese einmal ausgearbeitet sind, wird es offenkundig, daß es dasselbe ist, zu (658) verstehen, was das Sein ist, und zu verstehen, was Gott ist. Der vorliegende Abschnitt beschäftigt sich demnach ausschließlich mit der Formulierung der Notion Gottes; ob diese Notion sich auf eine existierende Realität bezieht, ist eine weitere Frage, die im folgenden Abschnitt über die Bejahung Gottes betrachtet werden soll. (Fs) (notabene)

740a Erstens, wenn es einen uneingeschränkten Verstehensakt gibt, gibt es ein Primärintelligibles, das mit ihm identisch ist. Denn der uneingeschränkte Akt versteht sich selbst. (Fs)

740b Zweitens, weil der Akt uneingeschränkt ist, gäbe es keine Möglichkeit der Korrektur, der Revision, oder der Verbesserung, und damit wäre der uneingeschränkte Akt als Verstehen unanfechtbar. Weil er sich selbst erkennen würde, würde er zudem erkennen, daß er uneingeschränkt und damit unanfechtbar ist. Demnach wäre er mit einem reflektierenden Verstehensakt identisch, der sich selbst als unbedingt und deshalb als korrekt und wahr erfaßt; und damit wäre das Primä-rintelligible auch mit der Primärwahrheit identisch. (Fs)

740c Drittens, das, was durch korrektes und wahres Verstehen erkannt wird, ist das Sein; das Primärintelligible wäre also auch das Primärseiende; und das Primärseiende wäre geistig im vollen Sinne der Identität des Intelligenten und Intelligiblen. (Fs)

740d Viertens, das Primärseiende würde weder Defekt noch Mangel noch Unvollkommenheit aufweisen. Denn gäbe es Defekt, Mangel oder Unvollkommenheit, würde das uneingeschränkte Verstehen zumindest erfassen, was fehlt. Die Konsequenz ist aber unmöglich, und so muß das Antezedens falsch sein. Das Primärseiende ist ja identisch mit dem uneingeschränkten Akt, und ein Erfassen des Fehlenden im Primärseienden wäre somit das Erfassen einer Beschränkung im unbeschränkten Akt. (Fs)

740e Fünftens, das Gute ist mit dem intelligiblen Sein identisch, und so ist das Primärintelligible und vollständig vollkommene Primärseiende auch das Primärgute. (Fs)

740f Sechstens, wie die Vollkommenheit des Geistigen verlangt, daß das Intelligible auch intelligent sein soll, so verlangt sie auch, daß die bejahbare Wahrheit bejaht und das liebenswürdige Gute geliebt werde. Das Primärintelligible ist nun aber auch die Primärwahrheit und das Primärgute; und damit ist in einem vollständig vollkommenen geistigen Seienden das Primärintelligible nicht nur mit einem uneingeschränkten Verstehensakt identisch, sondern auch mit einem vollständig vollkommenen Akt der Bejahung der Primärwahrheit und einem vollständig vollkommenen Akt des Liebens des Primärguten. Außerdem ist der Akt der Bejahung nicht ein zweiter Akt, der vom unbeschränkten Verstehensakt verschieden ist, und der Akt der Liebe auch nicht ein dritter Akt, der vom Verstehen und dem Bejahen ver-659 schieden ist. Denn wären sie dies, wäre das Primärseiende unvollständig und unvollkommen und bedürfte der weiteren Akte des Bejahens und Liebens, um vervollkommnet und vervollständigt zu werden. Daher ist eine und dieselbe Realität zugleich uneingeschränktes Verstehen und das Primärintelligible, reflektierendes Verstehen und das Unbedingte, vollkommenes Bejahen und die Primärwahrheit, vollkommenes Lieben und das Primärgute. (Fs)

741a Siebtens, das Primärintelligible ist selbst-erklärend. Denn wäre es dies nicht, wäre es in seiner Intelligibilität unvollständig; und wir haben schon gezeigt, daß jeder Defekt oder Mangel und jede Unvollkommenheit inkompatibel mit dem uneingeschränkten Verstehen ist. (Fs)

741b Achtens, das Primärseiende ist unbedingt. Das Primärseiende ist ja identisch mit dem Primärintelligiblen; und das Primärintelligible muß unbedingt sein; denn hinge es von irgendetwas sonst ab, wäre es nicht selbst-erklärend. Schließlich ist es unmöglich, daß das Primärintelligible vollkommen unabhängig ist und daß das Primärseiende, das mit ihm identisch ist, von sonst etwas abhängig ist. (Fs)

741c Neuntens, das Primärseiende ist entweder notwendig oder unmöglich. Es kann nämlich nicht kontingent sein, weil das Kontingente nicht selbst-erklärend ist. Wenn es also existiert, existiert es aus Notwendigkeit und ohne Bedingungen; und wenn es nicht existiert, ist es unmöglich; denn dann gibt es keine Bedingung, aus der es resultieren könnte. Ob es aber existiert oder nicht, ist eine Frage, die die Idee des Seins oder die Notion Gottes nicht betrifft. (Fs)

741d Zehntens, es gibt nur ein Primärseiendes. Denn entia non sunt multiplicanda praeter neccessitatem, und es gibt keine Notwendigkeit für mehr als eines. Ferner, wenn es mehr als ein Primärseiendes gäbe, dann wäre jedes identisch oder nicht identisch mit dem uneingeschränkten Verstehensakt. Wenn sie es nicht sind, so wären die mit beschränkten Verstehensakten identischen Intelligiblen keine Primärseiende. Wenn sie es sind, so gäbe es verschiedene in allen Hinsichten gleiche Primärseiende; denn unbeschränkte Akte können nicht verschiedene Objekte erfassen, ohne daß einer oder mehrere nicht erfassen, was ein anderer erfaßt und damit aufhören, ein unbeschränkter Akt zu sein. Es kann aber nicht mehrere in allen Hinsichten gleiche Primärseiende geben; denn dann wären sie bloß empirisch verschieden; und das bloß Empirische ist nicht selbst-erklärend. Demnach kann es nur ein Primärseiendes geben. (Fs)

741e Elftens, das Primärseiende ist einfach. Denn das Primärseiende ist ein einziger Akt, der zugleich unbeschränktes Verstehen, vollkommenes Bejahen und vollkommenes Lieben ist; und es ist identisch mit dem Primärintelligiblen und der Primärwahrheit und dem Primärguten. (Fs)

741f Es läßt die Zusammensetzung von zentralen und konjugaten Formen nicht zu. Denn es gibt keine weiteren Seiende derselben Ordnung, mit denen es (660) konjugat sein könnte; und weil es nur ein Einzelakt ist, bedarf es keiner vereinheitlichenden zentralen Form. (Fs)

742a Es läßt auch die Zusammensetzung von Potenz und Form nicht zu. Denn es ist ein geistiges Seiendes jenseits aller Entwicklung, und die Potenz ist identifiziert worden mit entweder einer Fähigkeit zur Entwicklung oder mit dem empirischen Residuum und der Materialität. (Fs)

742b Es läßt auch nicht die Zusammensetzung von Form und Akt als voneinander verschieden zu. Denn wenn es existiert, existiert es notwendig. Ferner, wenn das Primärintelligible und Primärseiende und Primärgute Form oder Essenz genannt werden, und der unbeschränkte Verstehens-, Bejahens-, Liebensakt Akt oder Existenz oder Vorkommen genannt werden, sind sie doch nicht voneinander unterschieden, sondern identisch. (Fs)

742c Zwölftens, das Primärseiende ist zeitlos. Es ist ohne stetige Zeit, weil es geistig ist, während die stetige Zeit das empirische Residuum und die Materialität voraussetzt. Und es ist ohne Ordnungszeit, weil es sich nicht entwickelt. (Fs)

742d Dreizehntens, wenn das Primärseiende existiert, ist es ewig. Denn es ist zeitlos, und die Ewigkeit ist zeitlose Existenz. (Fs)

Neben dem Primärintelligiblen müssen allerdings die Sekundärintelligiblen in Betracht gezogen werden; denn der uneingeschränkte Verstehensakt erfaßt auch alles über alles andere, insofern er sich selbst versteht. (Fs)

742e Vierzehntens, die Sekundärintelligiblen sind bedingt. Sie sind ja das, was zu verstehen ist, wenn das Primärintelligible verstanden wird. (Fs)

Es folgt, daß sie vom Primärintelligiblen verschieden sind; denn sie sind bedingt, und dieses ist unbedingt. (Fs)

742f Wenn auch die Sekundärintelligiblen vom Primären verschieden sind, brauchen sie doch nicht verschiedene Realitäten zu sein. Denn Erkennen besteht nicht im Anschauen von etwas anderem, und wenn die Sekundärintelligiblen auch erkannt werden, brauchen sie doch deshalb nicht etwas anderes zu sein, das angeschaut werden kann. Außerdem ist das Primärseiende ohne Mangel, Defekt oder Unvollkommenheit; es wäre aber unvollkommen, wenn der unbeschränkte Verstehensakt weiterer Realitäten bedürfte, um unbeschränkt zu sein. (Fs)

742g Schließlich, die Sekunduarintelligiblen können reine Gedankenobjekte sein. Denn sie werden als verschieden vom Primärintelligiblen erfaßt, doch brauchen sie nicht verschiedene Realitäten zu sein. So wird die Unendlichkeit der positiven ganzen Zahlen von uns in der Einsicht erfaßt, die das generative Prinzip der Relationen und der Termini der Reihe ist. (Fs)

742h Fünfzehntens, (661) das Primärseiende ist die allmächtige Wirkursache. Das Primärseiende wäre ja unvollkommen, wenn es alle möglichen Universen als Gedankenobjekte aber nicht als Realitäten begründen könnte. Ähnlich wäre das Primärgute unvollkommen, wenn es zwar in sich selbst gut, aber nicht die Quelle anderer Fälle des Guten wäre. Das Primärseiende und Primärgute ist aber ohne Unvollkommenkeit; und so kann es jedes mögliche Universum begründen und jeden anderen Fall des Guten hervorbringen. (Fs)

743a Sechzehntens, das Primärseiende ist die allwissende Exemplarursache. Denn es ist die Idee des Seins und erfaßt in sich selbst die intelligible Ordnung jedes möglichen Universums von Seienden in allen Komponenten, Aspekten und Details. (Fs)

743b Siebzehntens, das Primärseiende ist frei. Denn die Sekundärintelligiblen sind kontingent: Sie brauchen nicht eigenständige Realitäten zu sein; sie können reine Gedankenobjekte sein; sie sind nicht unbedingt, weder in ihrer Intelligibilität noch in ihrer Gutheit, und damit sind sie nicht unbedingt im Sein, wobei das Sein nicht außerhalb der Intelligibilität und der Gutheit steht. Das kontingente Sein kann aber als kontingentes nicht notwendig und als Sein nicht willkürlich sein; es folgt, daß kontingente Seiende, wenn es sie gibt, kraft der Freiheit des unbeschränkten Ver-stehens und vollkommenen Bejahens und vollkommenen Liebens existieren. (Fs)

743c Achzehntens, weil der Mensch sich entwickelt, ist jedes zusätzliche Element des Verstehens und Bejahens und Wollens ein weiterer Akt und eine weitere Realität in ihm. Das vollkommene Primärseiende hingegen entwickelt sich nicht; denn es ist ohne Defekt oder Mangel oder Unvollkommenheit; und so versteht und bejaht und will der unbeschränkte Art, daß kontingente Seiende existieren, ohne irgendeinen Zuwachs oder eine Veränderung in seiner eigenen Realität. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Notion von Gott 2; Korollarien (25 Bestimmungen)

Kurzinhalt: Es folgen eine Anzahl Konklusionen von beträchtlicher Wichtigkeit. Obwohl man sie oft für extrem schwierig hält, liegt die einzige Schwierigkeit darin, die Unterschiede zu erfassen, die Grammatik, Logik und Metaphysik trennen.

Textausschnitt: 743d Es folgen eine Anzahl Konklusionen von beträchtlicher Wichtigkeit. Obwohl man sie oft für extrem schwierig hält, liegt die einzige Schwierigkeit darin, die Unterschiede zu erfassen, die Grammatik, Logik und Metaphysik trennen. Die Grammatik beschäftigt sich mit Wörtern und Sätzen; die Logik beschäftigt sich mit Begriffen und Urteilen; die Metaphysik aber beschäftigt sich mit der Auflistung der notwendigen und hinreichenden Realitäten unter der Voraussetzung, daß Urteile wahr sind. (Fs)

743e Das erste Korollarium besagt, daß jede kontingente Aussage über Gott zugleich eine äußere Benennung ist. Mit anderen Worten, Gott bleibt innerlich derselbe, ob er nun versteht, bejaht, will verursacht oder nicht, daß dieses oder jenes Universum ist. Wenn er es nicht tut, dann existiert Gott und nichts anderes existiert. Wenn er es tut, existiert Gott und zugleich existiert das in Frage stehende Universum; diese beiden Existenzen genügen für die Wahrheit der Urteile, daß Gott das Universum versteht, bejaht, will, bewirkt; denn Gott ist in seiner Vollkommenheit (662) uneingeschränkt, und was in seiner Vollkommenheit uneingeschränkt ist, muß alles andere, was ist, verstehen, bejahen, wollen, bewirken. (Fs)

744a Das zweite Korollarium besagt, daß, obwohl die äußere Benennung zeitlich ist, die kontingente Aussage bezüglich Gott ewig sein kann. Denn ein ewiger Akt ist zeitlos; in ihm sind alle Augenblicke ein und derselbe Augenblick; und deshalb ist das, was in einem Augenblick wahr ist, in allen Augenblicken wahr. Wenn es nun in einem Augenblick wahr ist, daß Gott die Existenz von Alexanders Pferd Buke-phalus versteht, bejaht und will, dann sind die metaphysischen Bedingungen dieser Wahrheit die Existenz von Gott und die Existenz von Bukephalus; ferner, wenn Bukephalus auch nur während einer kurzen Zeit existiert, versteht, bejaht und will Gott doch ewig, daß Bukephalus für diese kurze Zeit existiert. (Fs)

744b Ein drittes Korollarium ist die göttliche Wirksamkeit. Es ist unmöglich für sie, daß es wahr ist, daß Gott die Existenz oder das Vorkommen von irgend etwas versteht, bejaht, will und bewirkt, ohne daß es wahr ist, daß das Ding existiert oder das Ereignis vorkommt, und zwar genau so, wie Gott es versteht, bejaht oder will. Denn eine und dieselbe metaphysische Bedingung ist notwendig für die Wahrheit beider Aussagen, nämlich das einschlägige kontingente Existieren oder Vorkommen. (Fs)
744c Das vierte Korollarium ist umgekehrt zum dritten und besagt, daß die göttliche Wirksamkeit ihren Folgen keine Notwendigkeit auferlegt. Im Lichte der göttlichen Wirksamkeit ist es durchaus wahr, daß es unmöglich ist, daß dieses oder jenes nicht existiert oder nicht vorkommt, wenn Gott die Existenz oder das Vorkommen von diesem oder jenem versteht oder bejaht oder will oder bewirkt. Die Existenz oder dieses Vorkommen ist aber eine metaphysische Bedingung der Wahrheit des Antezendens, und somit sagt die Konsequenz eigentlich nur das Prinzip der Identität aus, daß es nämlich die Existenz oder das Vorkommen gibt, wenn es die Existenz oder das Vorkommen gibt. Thomas' oft wiederholte Illustration dazu lautet bekanntlich: Socrates, dum sedet, necessario sedet, necessitate tamen non absoluta sed conditionata. (Fs)

744d Das fünfte Korollarium betrifft die scientia media. Weil der göttliche Verstehensakt uneingeschränkt und wahr ist, erfaßt er nicht allein jede mögliche Weltordnung, sondern auch die eben dargelegten vier Korollarien. Deshalb erkennt Gott unabhängig von jeder freien Entscheidung (in signo antecedente omnem actum voluntatis), daß, wenn er irgendeine Weltordnung wollte, diese Ordnung in jedem Aspekt und Detail realisiert würde; jede Weltordnung ist aber ein einzelnes, intel-ligibles Muster vollständig bestimmter Existierender und Ereignisse; und damit erkennt Gott exakt, völlig unabhängig von jeder göttlichen Entscheidung, was jeder freie Wille in jeder aufeinanderfolgenden Menge von Umständen, die in jeder möglichen Weltordnung enthalten sind, wählen würde. (Fs)

745a Die vorerwähnte scientia media schließt Molinas Notion der göttlichen (663) Weisheit ein, welche die Ordnung jedes möglichen Universums erfaßt; aber sie schließt Molinas Tendenz nicht ein, von den bedingten Futurabilien als Entitäten zu sprechen, die Gott zu seiner Orientierung anschaut. Ferner, sie beruht weder auf Molinas Super-Erfassung des menschlichen Willens, noch auf Suarez' unerklärter objektiver Wahrheit, sondern auf Thomas' bekannten Behauptungen zur Unveränderlichkeit Gottes und zur bedingten Notwendigkeit dessen, was Gott erkennt oder will oder verursacht. Sie steht schließlich in radikalem Gegensatz zum Scotistischen Voluntarismus und zu den voluntaristischen decreta hypotheticepraedeterminantia. (Fs)

745b Neunzehntens, Gott wäre der Schöpfer. Denn wenn Gottes Wirkursächlichkeit die Existenz irgendeiner Materie voraussetzte und auf das Gestalten und Ordnen derselben beschränkt wäre, dann bliebe die Existenz dieser Materie unerklärt; was aber letztlich unerklärt ist, gehört nicht zum Sein; und damit erwiese sich die angebliche Materie als Nichts. (Fs)

745c Es kann behauptet werden, daß es in diesem Universum tatsächlich ein rein empirisches Residuum gibt, das unerklärt ist. Man kann dagegen antworten, daß das empirische Residuum der Individualität, des Kontinuums, der einzelnen Orte und Zeiten und der nichtsystematischen Divergenz der tatsächlichen Häufigkeiten zwar durch die Einzelwissenschaften unerklärt bleibt, jedoch in der Erkenntnistheorie und der Metaphysik teilweise verstanden und letztlich durch Gottes schöpferische Entscheidung erklärt wird. Denn die erste Potenz der Individualität ist die Bedingung der Möglichkeit der allgemeinen Erkenntnis und der allgemeinen Naturen; die erste Potenz des Raum-Zeit-Kontinuums ist die Bedingung der Möglichkeit von abstrakten und invarianten Gesetzen, von konreten Wahrscheinlichkeiten und ihrer Anhäufung in einer Weltordnung der emergenten Wahrscheinlichkeit; das Nicht-systematische schließlich wird durch einen unbeschränkten Verstehensakt transzendiert. Ferner, das empirische Residuum begründet das Mannigfaltige des potentiell Guten, und insofern es unter der Weltordnung steht, besitzt es den Wert, der dem Kontingenten durch die Vernünftigkeit der Freiheit eines vollständig weisen und guten Seienden erwächst. (Fs)

745d Zwanzigstem, Gott wäre der Erhalter. Seine Wirkursächlichkeitwürde nicht ein Universum schaffen und es dann sich selbst überlassen, sondern im Gegenteil ausgeübt werden, solange das Universum oder irgendwelche Teile desselben existieren. Denn die metaphysische Bedingung für die Wahrheit der Aussage, daß A B verursacht, ist die Realität einer Abhängigkeitsrelation (ut a quo) in B in bezug auf A. Sie ist nicht, wie die Gegenpositionen behaupten würden, ein in der Einbildungskraft vorstellbarer "Einfluß", der den zwischen A und B liegenden Raum besetzt hielte. Sie ist nicht eine Veränderung in A\ denn das Feuer verändert sich nicht, wenn es aufhört, die Kartoffeln zu kochen, und beginnt, das Steak zu braten. Sie (664) ist B, insofern es in intelligibler Abhängigkeit von A entsteht oder existiert oder vorkommt. Nun ist aber kein kontingent Seiendes selbst-erklärend, und damit befindet sich jedes kontingent Seiende, so lang es ist, in intelligibler Abhängigkeit vom selbst-erklärenden Sein. (Fs)

746a Einundzwanzigstens, Gott wäre der erste Urheber jedes Ereignisses, jeder Entwicklung, jeder Emergenz. Denn jedes dieser Vorkommnisse ist bedingt, und entweder divergieren die Bedingungen und zerstreuen sich durch das Universum, oder sie bilden ein rekursives Schema, das allerdings nur aufgrund von Bedingungen entsteht und überlebt, die divergieren und sich durch das Universum zerstreuen. Es folgt, daß allein die Ursache der Weltordnung der zureichende Grund für das Vorkommen jedes Ereignisses sein kann. Ferner, weil jede Entwicklung und jede Emergenz von einem Komplex von Ereignissen abhängt, kann allein der Grund der Weltordnung der zureichende Grund für jegliche Entwicklung oder Emergenz sein. (Fs)

746b Es folgt weiter, daß Gott jede kontingente Ursache zu ihrem Handeln bringt. Denn die Wirkursache handelt in Übereinstimmung mit dem Muster der Weltordnung, wenn die Bedingungen des Handelns erfüllt sind; die Bedingungen sind aber erfüllt, wenn andere Ereignisse vorkommen; und Gott ist je erste Wirkursache jedes dieser Vorkommnisse. Zudem folgt, daß jede geschaffene Wirkursache ein Instrument in der Ausführung des göttlichen Plans ist; ihre Handlung ist ja die Erfüllung einer Bedingung für andere Ereignisse; und damit wird sie von einer höheren Wirkursache zu einem weiteren Ziel verwendet. Schließlich folgt, daß Gott durch seine Intelligenz alle Dinge auf ihre passenden Zwecke hinbewegt; denn Gott verursacht jedes Ereignis, bringt jedes Handeln zu seinem Handeln und verwendet jede Handlung, insofern er die Ursache der Ordnung des Universums ist. (Fs)

746c Es soll bemerkt werden, daß sich diese Erklärung der göttlichen Kontrolle über die Ereignisse von den Erklärungen von Baflez und Molina unterscheidet. Sie schreiben nämlich die göttliche Kontrolle aller Ereignisse der Tatsache zu, daß Gott durch eine spezielle Aktivität jedes Ereignis kontrolliert. Nach der obigen Analyse hingegen kontrolliert Gott jedes Ereignis, weil er alle kontrolliert, und er kontrolliert alle, weil er allein die Ursache der Ordnung des Universums sein kann, von der jedes Ereignis abhängt. Außerdem, obwohl unsere Analyse in zeitgenössischen Termini formuliert worden ist, braucht man nur die moderne Physik durch die Aristotelische zu ersetzen, um zum Denken und zur Sprache des Thomas von Aquin zu gelangen1. (Fs)

747a Zweiundzwanzigstens, Gott wäre die schlechthin letzthe Zielursache jedes Universums, der Grund seines Wertes und das schlechthin letze Zielobjekt allen zielgerichteten Strebens. Denn, wie wir gesehen haben, wäre das Primärintelligible unvollständig, wenn in ihm nicht jedes andere Intelligible erfaßt werden könnte; das Primärseiende wäre unvollkommen in seinem Sein, wenn es nicht andere Seiende (665) hervorbringen könnte; und das Primärgute wäre in seiner Gutheit mangelhaft, wenn es steril wäre und nicht die Quelle anderer Fälle des Guten sein könnte. Umgekehrt sind dann die Sekundärintelligiblen intelligibel wegen der Vollständigkeit des Primärintelligiblen; die kontingent Seienden wegen der Vollkommenheit des Primärseienden möglich; und andere Fälle des Guten können wegen der Exzellenz des Primärguten entstehen. Was aber wegen der Vollkommenheit und Exzellenz eines anderen möglich ist, wird auch wegen dieser Vollkommenheit und Exzellenz wirklich sein; und deshalb muß Gottes Vollkommenheit und Exzellenz die Zweckursache alles anderen sein. (Fs)
747b Außerdem, ein Wert ist das Objekt einer vernünftigen Wahl, und der Grund des Wertes ist so der Grund der Möglichkeit in den Objekten und der Vernünftigkeit im Wählen. Jede mögliche Weltordnung wird nun aber im Primärintelligiblen erfaßt und aus ihm abgeleitet; und jede aktuelle Weltordnung wird von einem Wollen gewählt, das nicht nur mit einem unbeschränkten Verstehen übereinstimmt, sondern auch mit ihm identisch ist. Gott wäre damit der Grund des Wertes jeglicher Weltordnung und in der Tat ein Grund, der mit dem Maßstab dessen, was wahrer Wert ist, identisch ist. (Fs)

747c Weiter, wir haben gesehen, daß die immanente Ordnung dieser Welt eine zusammengesetzte bedingte Reihe von Dingen und rekursiven Schemata ist, die in Übereinstimmung mit aufeinanderfolgenden Wahrscheinlichkeitstabellen realisiert werden; und es wurde hinzugefügt, daß vom Gesichtspunkt des unbeschränkten Verstehens her das Nicht-systematische verschwindet, um einem völlig bestimmten und absolut wirksamen Plan und einer entsprechenden Intention Platz zu machen. Es folgt, daß die Finalität noch genauer aufgefaßt werden muß. Anstelle einer aufwärts aber unbestimmt gerichteten Dynamik gibt es die beabsichtigte Zuordnung jeder Potenz zur Form, welche sie erhält, jeder Form zum Akt, welchen sie erhält, jeder Menge niedriger Akte zu den höheren Einheiten und Integrationen, unter denen sie subsumiert werden. So kommt es, daß jede Tendenz und Kraft, jede Bewegung und Veränderung, jeder Wunsch und jedes Streben dazu bestimmt ist, die Ordnung des Universums herbeizuführen, und dies in der Art und Weise, in der sie zu diesem Ziel beitragen; und weil die Ordnung selbst des Universums - wie gezeigt worden ist - wegen der Vollkommenheit und Exzellenz des Primärseienden und Primärguten existiert, so zielt alles, was für die Ordnung des Universums ist, letztlich auf die Vollkommenheit und Exzellenz hin, welche ihre Primärquelle und ihr Primärgrund ist. (Fs)

748a Dreiundzwanzigstens, es folgt eine Transformation der Metaphysik, wie wir sie aufgefaßt haben. Denn die Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins wird zu einem untergeordneten Teil einer allgemeineren Metaphysik, welche die transzendente Idee des Seins in Betracht zieht. (Fs)

748b Vierundzwanzigstens, (666) es folgt eine Transformation der auf die beschränkte Metaphysik aufgebauten Ethik. Diese Ethik beschäftigte sich ja mit der Übereinstimmung von Erkennen und Tun im rationalen Selbstbewußtsein des Individuums. Jetzt ist es aber klar geworden, daß wahre Erkenntnis nicht bloß wahr ist, sondern auch ein Erfassen der göttlich bestellten Ordnung des Universums, und daß das mit dem Erkennen übereinstimmende Tun nicht bloß mit dem Erkennen übereinstimmt, sondern auch die Zusammenarbeit des Menschen mit Gott in der Realisierung der Ordnung des Universums darstellt. Umgekehrt erweist sich der Irrtum als eine Abweichung nicht nur von der Wahrheit, sondern auch von Gott, und falsches Tun nimmt den Charakter der Sünde gegen Gott an. (Fs)
748c Fünfundzwanzigstens, etwas muß über das Böse und die Sünde gesagt werden. Es scheint ja, daß Gott, weil er die wirksame Ursache von allem im Universum ist, der Autor aller seiner Übel und verantwortlich für all seine Sünden sein muß. Bevor wir aber zu dieser Konklusion springen, wollen wir zwischen dem physischen Übel, dem moralischen Übel und der Grundsünde unterscheiden. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Notion von Gott 3; Unterschied; physisches, moralisches Übel (Folge der Grundsünde), Sünde; Grundsünde (Wurzel des Irrationalen im rationalen Selbstbewusstsein); Kausalität; Trichotomie (Satz vom Widerspruch)

Kurzinhalt: Unter Grundsünde werde ich das Versagen des freien Willens verstehen, einen moralisch verpflichtenden Handlungsverlauf zu wählen, oder sein Versagen, einen moralisch verwerflichen Handlungsverlauf abzulehnen.

Textausschnitt: 748c Fünfundzwanzigstens, etwas muß über das Böse und die Sünde gesagt werden. Es scheint ja, daß Gott, weil er die wirksame Ursache von allem im Universum ist, der Autor aller seiner Übel und verantwortlich für all seine Sünden sein muß. Bevor wir aber zu dieser Konklusion springen, wollen wir zwischen dem physischen Übel, dem moralischen Übel und der Grundsünde unterscheiden. (Fs)


748d Unter Grundsünde werde ich das Versagen des freien Willens verstehen, einen moralisch verpflichtenden Handlungsverlauf zu wählen, oder sein Versagen, einen moralisch verwerflichen Handlungsverlauf abzulehnen. Die Grundsünde ist damit die Wurzel des Irrationalen im menschlichen rationalen Selbstbewußtsein. Als intelligent und rational bewußter erfaßt und bejaht der Mensch, was er tun soll und was er nicht tun soll. Wissen ist nun aber eine Sache und Tun eine ganz andere. Wenn er will, tut er, was er soll; wenn er will, wendet er seine Aufmerksamkeit von den Plänen ab, das zu tun, was er nicht tun soll; wenn er aber zu wollen versagt, dann wird der verpflichtende Handlungsverlauf nicht ausgeführt; wiederum, wenn er zu wollen versagt, verweilt seine Aufmerksamkeit bei den unerlaubten Absichten; die Unvollständigkeit ihrer Intelligibilität und die Inkohärenz ihrer scheinbaren Vernünftigkeit werden ignoriert; und in dieser Verengung des Bewußtseins, welche die Grundsünde ist, geschieht dann die falsche Handlung, die zwar auffallender, in Wirklichkeit aber abgeleitet ist. (Fs)

749a Zweitens, unter moralischen Übeln werde ich die Folgerungen der Grundsünde verstehen. Aus der Grundsünde, nicht zu wollen, was man wollen sollte, folgen moralische Übel der Auslassung und eine Erhöhung der Versuchung in sich selbst oder in anderen zu weiteren Grundsünden. Aus der Grundsünde, unerlaubte Absichten nicht beiseite zu setzen, folgt ihre Ausführung und eine positivere Erhöhung der Spannung und der Versuchung in sich selbst und in seinem sozialen Milieu. (Fs)

749b Schließlich, unter physischen Übeln werde ich alle die Unzulänglichkeiten einer Weltordnung verstehen, die - so weit wir sie verstehen - in einer verallgemeinerten emergenten Wahrscheinlichkeit besteht. Denn in einer solchen Ordnung geht die ungeordnete Menge dem formalen Gut höherer Einheiten und höherer Ordnungen (667) voraus; das Unentwickelte geht dem Entwickelten voraus; es gibt Fehlstarts, Zusammenbrüche, Versagen; Fortschritt geschieht um den Preis des Risikos; Sicherheit paart sich mit Sterilität; und das Leben des Menschen wird von einer Intelligenz gelenkt, die entwickelt, und von einer Willigkeit, die erworben werden muß. (Fs)

749c Die Relevanz dieser dreifachen Unterscheidung für unser Problem dürfte nicht schwierig zu erkennen sein. Ein Problem ist ja eine Frage nach Einsicht; es definiert eine zu erfassende Intelligibilität; und die Intelligenz kann offenkundig nicht Grundsünden, moralische Übel und physische Übel zusammenwerfen. (Fs)

749d Erstens, alles, was die Intelligenz in bezug auf die Grundsünden erfassen kann, ist daß es keine zu erfassende Intelligibilität gibt. Was ist die Grundsünde? Sie ist das Irrationale. Warum kommt sie vor? Gäbe es einen Grund, wäre es keine Sünde. Es mag Entschuldigungen geben; es mag mildernde Umstände geben; aber es kann keinen Grund geben; denn die Grundsünde besteht nicht darin, daß man sich Gründen und Vernunft unterwirft, sondern darin, daß man versagt, sich ihnen zu unterwerfen; sie besteht nicht in einem unaufmerksamen Versagen, sondern in Beachtung und im Wissen um die Verpflichtung, der, nichtsdestoweniger, nicht durch eine vernünftige Antwort gefolgt wird. (Fs)

749e Wenn nun die Grundsünde einfach irrational ist, wenn sie zu verstehen im Erfassen besteht, daß sie keine Intelligibilität hat, dann kann sie evidentermaßen nicht auf intelligible Weise von irgendetwas anderem abhängen. Was aber nicht in einem intelligiblen Abhängigkeitsverhältnis zu irgendetwas anderem stehen kann, kann keine Ursache haben; denn die Ursache ist korrelativ zu einer Wirkung; und eine Wirkung ist das, was in intelligibler Abhängigkeit von etwas anderem steht. Schließlich, wenn die Grundsünden keine Ursache haben können, kann Gott nicht ihre Ursache sein. Und diese Konklusion widerspricht auch nicht unserer früheren Behauptung, daß jedes Ereignis von Gott verursacht wird. Denn die Grunsünde ist kein Ereignis; sie ist nicht etwas, das positiv vorkommt; im Gegenteil, sie besteht in der Versäumnis eines Vorkommnisses, in der Abwesenheit im Willen einer vernünftigen Antwort auf ein verpflichtendes Motiv. (Fs)

750a Ferner, wenn ein Problem das Irrationale in sich enthält, kann es nur in einer hoch komplexen und kritischen Weise korrekt angegangen werden. Wenn der Mathematiker den imaginären Zahlen genau dieselben Eigenschaften zuschreiben würde, die er in den reellen Zahlen findet, würde er gewiß einen Schnitzer machen. Ein gravierender und nicht weniger unvermeidlicher Mißgriff wartet auf jeden, der die durch die Irrationalität der Grundsünde erforderten Unterscheidungen zu machen und den entsprechenden Regeln zu folgen versäumt. Denn die bekannte Disjunktion des Prinzips des ausgeschlossenen Dritten (entweder A oder nicht-A) muß durch eine Trichotomie ersetzt werden. Neben dem, was positiv ist, und dem, was einfach nicht ist, gibt es das Irrationale, das in dem besteht, was sein könnte und (668) sollte, aber nicht ist. Außer dem Sein, das Gott verursacht, und dem Nicht-Sein, das Gott nicht verursacht, gibt es das Irrationale, das Gott weder verursacht noch nicht verursacht, sondern von dem er zuläßt, daß andere es begehen. Außer dem tatsächlichen Guten, das Gott will, und dem nicht verwirklichten Guten, das Gott nicht will, gibt es die Grundsünden, die er weder will, noch nicht will, sondern verbietet. (Fs)

750b Nun ist es bestimmt nicht schlecht, sondern gut, ein derart vorzügliches Seiendes zu erschaffen, das rationales Selbstbewußtsein besitzt, aus dem Freiheit auf natürliche Weise folgt. Es ist nicht schlecht, sondern gut, diese Freiheit unangetastet zu lassen, zwar das Gute zu befehlen und das Böse zu verbieten, aber sich einer Einmischung zu enthalten, die die Freiheit auf einen illusorischen Schein reduzieren würde. Infolgedessen ist es nicht schlecht, sondern gut, eine Weltordnung zu entwerfen, wählen und bewirken, auch wenn Grundsünden auftreten können und werden. Es bedeutet nämlich einen Fehlschluß, wenn argumentiert wird, daß Grundsünden entweder Entitäten oder Nicht-Entitäten sind, und daß sie, wenn sie Entitäten sind, auf die universelle Ursächlichkeit Gottes zurückzuführen sind, wenn sie aber Nicht-Entitäten sind, auf Gottes Unwilligkeit, die gegenteiligen Entitäten zu bewirken, zurückzuführen sind. (Fs)

750c Es bleiben die physischen und die moralischen Übel. Wenn nun das Kriterium des Guten und Bösen Lust und Schmerz sind, dann sind physische und moralische Übel evidentermaßen letztlich ein Übel. Das angemessene Kriterium für das Gute aber ist die Intelligibilität, und alles außer der Grundsünde kann in diesem Universum verstanden werden und ist deshalb gut. Denn die Unvollkommenheit des Niedrigeren ist die Potentialität für das Höhere; das Unentwickelte ist für das Entwickelte; und sogar die moralischen Übel zielen durch die dialektische Spannung, die sie herbeiführen, entweder auf ihre eigene Aufhebung oder auf eine Verstärkung des moralisch Guten ab. Auf diese Weise kann eine verallgemeinerte emergente Wahrscheinlichkeit selbst von unserem limitierten Verstand als eine immanente und hoch intelligible Ordnung erfaßt werden, die alles in unserem Universum umfaßt. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Notion von Gott 4; Gott ist Person; personalistische Sicht der Ordnung des Universums

Kurzinhalt: ... eine Intelligibilität, die nur verstanden werden kann, indem man klassische und statistische, genetische und dialektische Methoden verbindet, die Gebote und Verbote enthält, die den Willen eines Einzelnen über den Willen der anderen zum Ausdruck ...

Textausschnitt: 751a Sechsundzwanzigstens, Gott ist Person. Obwohl wir mit der höchst unpersönlichen Frage: Was ist das Sein? begannen, obwohl wir die Implikationen eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes in sich selbst und in seinen Beziehungen zum Universum herausgearbeitet haben, obwohl wir von einem Gedankenobjekt gesprochen haben, das, wenn es existiert, als ein Objekt der Bejahung im objektiven Bereich des Seins erkannt werden wird, ist doch die Notion, zu der wir gelangten, die Notion eines personal Seienden. Wie der Mensch, so ist Gott ein rationales Selbstbewußtsein; denn der Mensch wurde nach Abbild und Ähnlichkeit Gottes geschaffen. Was der Mensch aber durch ein uneingeschränktes Streben und ein begrenztes Erreichen ist, ist Gott als uneingeschränkter Akt. Ein uneingeschränkter Akt rationalen Bewußtseins tut aber offenkundig allem Genüge, was mit dem Subjekt, der Person, dem mit einer eigenen Intelligenz und einer eigenen Vernunft und einem (669) eigenen Willen ausgestatteten anderen gemeint ist, wie objektiv und unpersönlich dieser Akt auch aufgefaßt worden ist. (Fs)

751b Ferner, wie die Idee des Seins die Notion eines personalen Gottes ist, so impliziert sie auch eine personalistische Sicht der Ordnung des Universums. Diese Ordnung ist ja nicht ein Plan, wie ein Architekt ihn für ein Gebäude zeichnen könnte, und sie ist auch nicht ein Plan, wie er von einer Regierung, die sich der sozialen Manipulation verschrieben hat, auferlegt werden könnte, sondern eine Intelligibilität, die nur verstanden werden kann, indem man klassische und statistische, genetische und dialektische Methoden verbindet, die Gebote und Verbote enthält, die den Willen eines Einzelnen über den Willen der anderen zum Ausdruck bringen, die Raum hat für das Abstehen von der Erzwingung, mit dem selbst der allmächtige Wille es ablehnt, sich dem Willen anderer Personen in den Weg zu stellen, die die scheinbare Anomalie der Trichotomie enthält, welche über das Prinzip des ausgeschlossenen Dritten hinausgeht, um dem Irrationalen der Grundsünde Raum zu geben. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Bejahung Gottes 1; ontologisches Argument (Anselm, Descartes, Leibniz);

Kurzinhalt:
... zu behaupten, daß Gott existiert, bedeutet nicht, ihm die Existenz oder das subtil gezeichnete Dasein des existentialistischen Denkens zuzuschreiben. Denn eine solche Existenz ist die Existenz des Menschen ...

Textausschnitt: 10. Die Bejahung Gottes

752a Unsere Erkenntnis vom Sein geschieht durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen. Indem wir fragten, was das Sein sei, sind wir zum Erfassen und Konzipieren dessen gelangt, was Gott ist. Weil wir gezeigt haben, daß das Sein der Kern aller Bedeutung ist, folgt, daß unser Erfassen und Konzipieren der Notion Gottes das bedeutungsvollste aller möglichen Objekte unseres Denkens ist. Nun wirft aber jedes Gedankenobjekt eine weitere Frage auf; denn wenn die Aktivität des intelligenten Bewußtseins einmal vollendet ist, setzt die Aktivität des reflektierenden Bewußtseins ein. Ist Gott denn ein reines Gedankenobjekt? Oder ist Gott wirklich? Ist er ein Objekt vernünftigen Bejahens? Existiert er?

752b Diese vier Fragen sind eigentlich ein und dieselbe. Denn das Reale ist das Sein, und außerhalb des Seins gibt es nichts. Das Sein wird nicht ohne vernünftiges Bejahen erkannt, und die Existenz ist der Aspekt, unter dem das Sein erkannt wird, genau insofern es vernünftig bejaht wird. Es ist also ein und dasselbe zu sagen, Gott sei real, er sei ein Objekt einer vernünftigen Bejahung und er existiere. (Fs)

752c Wiederum, zu behaupten, daß Gott existiert, bedeutet nicht, ihm die Existenz oder das subtil gezeichnete Dasein des existentialistischen Denkens zuzuschreiben. Denn eine solche Existenz ist die Existenz des Menschen, nicht als intelligent erfaßter und vernünftig bejahter, sondern als erfahrender, untersuchender und reflektierender, aber keine definitiven Antworten auf seine Fragen über sich selbst erhaltender. (Fs)

Kommentar (16.04.10) zu oben: die menschliche Existenz ist immer eine de facto Existenz.

752d Ferner, während sowohl die Existenz eines proportionierten Seienden und die Existenz Gottes durch ein rational gefälltes "Ja" erkannt werden, folgt nicht, daß (670) beide Existenzen gleich wären. Denn die Bedeutung des "Ja" ändert sich mit der Frage, die es beantwortet. Wenn gefragt wird, ob ein kontingent Seiendes existiert, bedeutet eine bejahende Antwort ein kontingent Seiendes. Wird aber gefragt, ob ein selbst-erklärendes Seiendes existiert, bedeutet eine bejahende Antwort eine selbst-erklärende Existenz. (Fs) (notabene)

752e Ferner, in der Selbsterkenntnis eines selbsterklärenden Seienden würde es für es selbst dasselbe sein, zu erkennen, was es ist und ob es ist. Denn seine Erkenntnis dessen, was es ist, würde in einem Verstehen des formell Unbedingten bestehen, und wie das Verstehen die Frage: "was?" beantwortet, so beantwortet das Unbedingte die Frage: "ob?"

752f Es folgt aber nicht, daß die beiden Fragen in unserer Erkenntnis eine einzige Antwort haben. Denn wenn wir erfassen, was Gott ist, ist unser Erfassen nicht ein unbeschränkter Verstehensakt, sondern ein beschränktes Verstehen, das von sich selbst auf einen unbeschränkten Akt extrapoliert, und indem es immer weitere Fragen stellt, zu einer Liste von Attributen des unbeschränkten Aktes gelangt. Was also erfaßt wird, ist nicht der unbeschränkte Akt, sondern die Extrapolation, die aus den Eigenschaften eines beschränkten Aktes zu den Eigenschaften eines unbeschränkten Aktes fortschreitet. Wenn die Extrapolation abgeschlossen ist, bleibt deshalb die weitere Frage, ob der unbeschränkte Akt ein Gedankenobjekt oder eine Realität ist. (Fs)

753a Es folgt, daß alle Formen des ontologischen Argumentes falsch sind. Denn sie argumentieren vom Begriff Gottes auf dessen Existenz. Nun aber ergeben unsere Konzeptionen nicht mehr als analytische Aussagen. Und wie wir gesehen haben, läßt sich der Übergang von den analytischen Aussagen zu den analytischen Prinzipien nur insofern bewerkstelligen, als die Termini und Relationen der Aussage in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen. Wenn es also nicht schwierig ist, Gott so aufzufassen, daß die Verneinung seiner Existenz eine contradictio in terminis bedeutete, ergibt diese Auffassung doch nicht mehr als eine analytische Aussage; und die fragliche Aussage kann nur dann zu einem analytischen Prinzip werden, wenn wir in einem konkreten Tatsachenurteil behaupten können, daß Gott existiert. (Fs) (notabene)

753b Dem Argument Anselms muß deshalb durch eine Unterscheidung der Prämisse, Deus est quo maius cogitari nequit, begegnet werden. Man räumt ein, daß sie durch geeignete Definitionen und syntaktische Regeln zu einer analytischen Aussage gemacht werden kann. Aber man fragt nach dem Beweis, daß die Termini, so wie sie definiert sind, in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vorkommen. (Fs)
753c Das Cartesische Argument scheint vom Begriff auf die Existenz eines vollkommenen Seienden zu schließen. Dies wäre dann gültig, wenn Konzipieren Anschauen wäre und Anschauen Erkennen. Diese Auffassung enthält aber die Gegenpositionen; und wenn man zu den Positionen wechselt, findet man, daß Begriffe nur (671) durch das reflektierende Erfassen des Unbedingten zu Erkenntnissen werden. (Fs)

753d Leibniz argumentiert von der Möglichkeit auf die Wirklichkeit Gottes. Wie wir gesehen haben, ist Gott entweder notwendig oder unmöglich. Er ist aber nicht unmöglich, weil die Notion Gottes keinen Widerspruch in terminis enthält. Also existiert er notwendig. Der Obersatz ist nun bloß eine analytische Aussage, und deshalb kann die Konklusion nicht mehr sein als eine analytische Aussage. Außerdem verlangt der für den Untersatz angegebene Grund eine Unterscheidung. Wenn es einen allmächtigen Gott gibt und wenn die Allmacht im Vermögen besteht, alles hervorzubringen, was nicht einen inneren Widerspruch einschließt, dann beweist die Abwesenheit eines inneren Widerspruchs die Möglichkeit. Wenn wir aber die Existenz der göttlichen Allmacht nicht voraussetzen, dann beweist die Abwesenheit eines inneren Widerspruchs nicht mehr als die Kohärenz eines Gedankenobjekts. (Fs)

754a Wenn das ontologische Argument aber als trügerisch angesehen werden muß, gibt es scheinbar keine Möglichkeit, die Existenz Gottes rational zu behaupten. Denn unsere Unterscheidung zwischen analytischen Aussagen und analytischen Prinzipien entspricht dem Verifikationsprinzip der logischen Positivisten. Es scheint aber keine Möglichkeit zu geben, einen unbeschränkten Verstehensakt entweder in unserer äußeren oder in unserer inneren Erfahrung zu verifizieren. Und selbst wenn diese Erfahrung möglich wäre, bedürfte es erst der Tatsache, ehe die Existenz Gottes vernünftig bejaht werden könnte. (Fs)

754b Dieser Einwand beruht allerdings auf einer Gleichsetzung der Notionen von Verifikation und von Erfahrung. Wenn das Fallgesetz nun aber verifiziert wird, wird es offensichtlich nicht erfahren. Was erfahren wird, ist ein breites Aggregat von Inhalten von Beobachtungsakten. Nicht die Erfahrung, sondern das Verstehen bringt das Aggregat zusammen, indem es diese Inhalte auf ein hypothetisches Gesetz der fallenden Körper bezieht. Nicht die Erfahrung, sondern die kritische Reflexion fragt, ob die Daten mit dem Gesetz übereinstimmen und ob die Übereinstimmung genügt für die Bejahung des Gesetzes. Nicht die Erfahrung, sondern ein reflektierendes Erfassen der Erfüllung der Bedingungen einer wahrscheinlichen Bejahung macht den einzigen Verifikationsakt aus, den es für das Gesetz der fallenden Körper gibt; und ähnlich ist es ein reflektierendes Erfassen des Unbedingten, das jedes andere Urteil begründet. (Fs)

754c Außerdem, bei der Forderung nach einem Übergang von den analytischen Aussagen zu den analytischen Urteilen geht es primär um eine Unterscheidung zwischen verschiedenen Typen des Unbedingten, und nur sekundär schließt diese Forderung eine Ähnlichkeit mit dem Verifikationsprinzip ein. Es gibt ein virtuell Unbedingtes, dessen Bedingungen sich schon durch Akte des Definierens und Postulierens erfüllen lassen; dies ist die analytische Aussage. Zu diesem virtuell Unbedingten kann eine weitere Erfüllung hinzukommen, insofern das, was die analytische Aussage definiert und was sie postuliert, sich ebenfalls als virtuell unbedingt herausstellt; solcherart ist das analytische Prinzip. Diese weitere Erfüllung kommt in konkreten Tatsachenurteilen vor, wie sie im Verifikationsprozeß stattfinden; und in dieser Hinsicht ist unsere Position der der logischen Positivisten ähnlich. Ähnlichkeit braucht aber nicht Identität zu sein. Denn wir unterscheiden uns von den logischen Positivisten darin, daß wir uns von der Illusion völlig befreit haben, das Reale zu erkennen sei, irgendwie das anzuschauen, was jetzt schon da draußen ist. Im Gegensatz zu ihnen haben wir viel über das Unbedingte zu sagen, und wir siedeln gerade im Unbedingten die ganze Bedeutung und Kraft der Verifikation an. (Fs)

755a Einerseits muß also das ontologische Argument zurückgewiesen werden, weil der Begriff allein eine unzureichende Grundlage für das Urteil darstellt. Andererseits ist das, was dem bloßen Begriff hinzugefügt werden muß, nicht eine Gotteserfahrung, sondern ein Erfassen des Unbedingten. Bejahen ist ein innerlich rationaler Akt; es geht mit rationaler Notwendigkeit aus dem Erfassen des Unbedingten hervor; und das zu erfassende Unbedingte ist nicht das formell Unbedingte, das Gott ist und das vom uneingeschränkten Verstehen erfaßt wird, sondern das virtuell Unbedingte, das darin besteht, Gottes Existenz aus Prämissen herzuleiten, die wahr sind. Es bleibt nur noch eine Vorbemerkung. Wir haben es schon bemerkt, aber wir müssen nochmals daraufhinweisen, daß ein Beweis kein automatischer Prozeß ist, der ein Urteil zum Resultat hat, so wie das Einnehmen eines Aspirins vom Kopfschmerz befreit oder das Einschalten den Computer auf seinen unfehlbaren Weg schickt. Alles, was auf diesen Seiten niedergelegt werden kann, ist eine Anzahl von Zeichen. Die Zeichen können ein relevantes virtuell Unbedingtes darstellen. Aber es zu erfassen und das daraus folgende Urteil zu fällen, ist ein immanenter Akt des rationalen Bewußtseins, den jeder für sich selbst zu vollziehen hat und den niemand sonst für ihn vollziehen kann. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Bejahung Gottes 2; Gottesbeweis 1; Sein - vollständig intelligibel; Identität: das Reale - Sein -> Gott; Gegenpositionen: Atheismus, Agnostizismus

Kurzinhalt: Wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, existiert Gott. Das Reale ist aber vollständig intelligibel. Also existiert Gott.

Textausschnitt: 755b Die Existenz Gottes wird also als die Konklusion eines Argumentes erkannt, und während solche Argumente viele sind, sind sie alle m. E. in die folgende allgemeine Form einbegriffen. (Fs)

Wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, existiert Gott. Das Reale ist aber vollständig intelligibel. Also existiert Gott. (Fs)

Um beim Untersatz zu beginnen, wird also argumentiert, daß das Sein vollständig intelligibel ist; daß das Reale das Sein ist; und daß deshalb das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist. (Fs)

755c Das Sein ist nun vollständig intelligibel. Denn das Sein ist das Zielobjekt des unvoreingenommenen, uneigennützigen und unbeschränkten Erkenntnisstrebens; dieses Streben besteht im intelligenten Untersuchen und kritischen Reflektieren; es (673) hat eine Teilerkenntnis zum Resultat, insofern die intelligente Untersuchung ein Verstehen ergibt und die kritische Reflexion das Verstehen als korrekt erfaßt; es erreicht aber sein Zielobjekt, das Sein, nur, wenn auf jede intelligente Frage eine intelligente Antwort gegeben worden ist und sich diese Antwort als korrekt herausgestellt hat. Das Sein ist also intelligibel; denn es ist das, was durch ein korrektes Verstehen erkannt wird; und es ist vollständig intelligibel, weil das Sein nur dann vollständig erkannt wird, wenn alle intelligenten Fragen korrekt beantwortet worden sind. (Fs)

755d Ferner, das Reale ist das Sein. Das Reale ist ja das, was mit dem Terminus "Reales" gemeint wird. Alles, was gemeint wird, ist aber entweder ein bloßes Gedankenobjekt oder sowohl ein Objekt des Denkens als auch ein Objekt des Bejahens. Das Reale ist nicht bloß ein Objekt des Denkens; deshalb ist es sowohl ein Objekt des Denkens als auch ein Objekt des Bejahens. Das Reale ist auch nicht bloß einige der Objekte des Denkens und des Bejahens, sondern deren alle. Und ähnlich ist das Sein alles, was durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen erkannt werden kann. (Fs)

756a Wenn dieses Zusammenfallen des Realen mit dem Sein ein Akzeptieren der Positionen und eine Ablehnung der Gegenpositionen voraussetzt, wird doch der Leser auf diesem Stadium de Beweisführung kaum eine Wiederholung der Hauptpunkte erwarten, die immer wieder auf den vorhergehenden Seiten dieses Werkes erörtert worden sind. Die Positionen zu akzeptieren bedeutet, die eigene Intelligenz und Vernunft zu akzeptieren und zu dieser Akzeptanz zu stehen. Die Gegenpositionen zurückzuweisen bedeutet, das Sich-Einmischen anderer Wünsche in das richtige Funktionieren des unvoreingenommenen, uneigennützigen und unbeschränkten Erkenntnisstrebens zurückzuweisen. Folglich führt jede Gegenposition zu ihrer eigenen Umkehrung; denn sie verwickelt sich in Inkohärenz, sobald behauptet wird, daß sie intelligent erfaßt und vernünftig bejaht wird; und ein intelligentes und vernünftiges Subjekt kann nicht vermeiden, diese Behauptung zu machen. (Fs)

756b Es bleibt der Obersatz, nämlich: Wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, existiert Gott. Das Argument kann in folgenden Schritten dargelegt werden. (Fs)

Wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, dann existiert die vollständige Intel-ligibilität. Wenn die vollständige Intelligibilität existiert, existiert die Idee des Seins. Wenn die Idee des Seins existiert, existiert Gott. Wenn also das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, existiert Gott. (Fs)

756b Es bleibt der Obersatz, nämlich: Wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, existiert Gott. Das Argument kann in folgenden Schritten dargelegt werden. (Fs)

Wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, dann existiert die vollständige Intelligibilität. Wenn die vollständige Intelligibilität existiert, existiert die Idee des Seins. Wenn die Idee des Seins existiert, existiert Gott. Wenn also das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, existiert Gott. (Fs)

756c Wir wollen jede dieser Prämissen der Reihe nach kommentieren. (Fs)

Erstens, wenn das Reale vollständig intelligibel ist, dann existiert die vollständige Intelligibilität. Denn gerade so, wie das Reale nicht intelligibel sein könnte, wenn die Intelligibilität nicht existierte, könnte das Reale nicht vollständig intelligibel sein, wenn die vollständige Intelligibilität nicht existierte. Mit anderen (647) Worten, die vollständige Intelligibilität des Realen zu bejahen bedeutet, die vollständige Intelligibilität all dessen, was behauptet werden kann, zu behaupten. Man kann nun aber nicht die vollständige Intelligibilität all dessen bejahen, das bejaht werden soll, ohne die vollständige Intelligibilität zu bejahen. Und die vollständige Intelligibilität zu bejahen bedeutet, ihre Existenz zu erkennen. (Fs)

756d Zweitens, wenn die vollständige Intelligibilität existiert, dann existiert die Idee des Seins. Denn die Intelligibilität ist entweder materiell oder geistig oder abstrakt. Sie ist materiell in den Objekten der Physik, Chemie, Biologie und Sinnespsychologie; sie ist geistig, wenn sie mit dem Verstehen identisch ist; und sie ist abstrakt in den Begriffen von Einheiten, Gesetzen, idealen Häufigkeiten, genetischen Operatoren, dialektischen Spannungen und Konflikten. Die abstrakte Intelligibilität ist aber notwendigerweise unvollständig; denn sie entsteht nur dadurch, daß die geistige Intelligibilität sich selbst zum Ausdruck bringt. Wiederum, die geistige Intelligibilität ist unvollständig, solange sie untersuchen kann. Schließlich, die materielle Intelligibilität ist notwendigerweise unvollständig, weil sie in ihrer Existenz und in ihren Ereignissen, in ihren Gattungen und Arten, in ihren klassischen und statistischen Gesetzen, in ihren genetischen Operatoren und im tatsächlichen Lauf ihrer emergenten Wahrscheinlichkeit kontingent ist. Außerdem, sie schließt ein rein empirisches Residuum der Individualität, der nichtzählbaren Unendlichkeiten, der einzelnen Orte und Zeiten ein, und für die systematische Erkenntnis eine nichtsystematische Abweichung. Es folgt, daß die einzige Möglichkeit einer vollständigen Intelligibilität in einer geistigen Intelligibilität liegt, die nicht untersuchen kann, weil sie alles über alles versteht. Und ein solches unbeschränktes Verstehen ist die Idee des Seins. (Fs)

757a Drittens, wenn die Idee des Seins existiert, existiert Gott. Denn wenn die Idee des Seins existiert, existiert zumindest ihre primäre Komponente. Die Primärkomponente besitzt aber, wie wir gezeigt haben, alle Attribute Gottes. Wenn also die Idee des Seins existiert, existiert Gott. (Fs)

757b Derartig ist also der Beweisgang. Als eine Gesamtheit von Zeichen in einem Buch kann es nur die Materialien für ein reflektierendes Erfassen des virtuell Unbedingten angeben. Einen solchen Akt hervorzubringen ist die Arbeit, die der Leser selbst zu vollbringen hat. Ferner, insofern ein Leser wohl von der weit verbreiteten zeitgenössischen Ansicht beeindruckt worden ist, derzufolge die Existenz Gottes nicht bewiesen werden kann, wird er sich nun wundern, wo der Fehlschluß liegt, wann genau der ungerechtfertigte Schritt in diesem Versuch, das angeblich Unmögliche zu vollbringen, gemacht wurde. Wir wollen ihn auf seinem Reflexionsweg begleiten. (Fs)

757c Gewiß müßte es im Argument einen Fehlschluß geben, wenn es nicht einen vollständigen Bruch mit den verschiedenen Strömungen des modernen Denkens voraussetzte, die auf dem Atheismus oder dem Agnostizismus bestehen. Ein solcher vollständiger Bruch existiert aber in der völligen Ablehnung der Gegenpositionen und in einer ebenfalls vollständigen Annahme der Positionen. Zugegeben, daß das (675) Reale das Sein ist; zugegeben, daß das Sein durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen erkannt wird; dann ist Gott eine Realität, wenn er ein Seiendes ist, und er ist ein Seiendes, wenn ein intelligentes Erfassen ihn konzipiert und die Vernunft bejaht, was die Intelligenz konzipiert. Wiederum, die Ausschließung jedes Obskurantismus zugegeben, ist die Intelligenz der Bemühung verpflichtet, eine Notion Gottes zu bilden; denn wenn das Reale das Sein ist, hat man sich der Frage: "Was ist das Sein?" zu stellen, und wie wir gesehen haben, schließt die Antwort auf diese Frage die Antwort auf die Frage "Was ist Gott?" mit ein. Die Antwort auf eine Frage nach Einsicht wirft aber notwendigerweise die entsprechende Frage nach Reflexion auf, und die Ausschließung des Obskurantismus verpflichtet uns erneut zur Bemühung um eine Antwort. Wenn die Antwort negativ ist, ist der Atheismus korrekt. Wenn keine Antwort möglich ist, ist der Agnostizismus korrekt. Wenn die Antwort affirmativ ist, ist der Theismus korrekt. Es geht also nur darum zu entscheiden, welche von den dreien die Antwort ist, die von der Einheit des empirischen, intelligenten und rationalen Bewußtseins, das ich selbst de facto bin, zu geben ist. Schließlich, wenn ich im intellektuellen Erfahrungsmuster operiere, wenn ich in meinem Akzeptieren der Herrschaft des unvoreingenommenen, uneigennützigen und unbeschränkten Strebens nach intelligenter Untersuchung und vernünftiger Reflexion echt bin, dann habe ich keinen Grund überrascht zu sein, wenn ich es unmöglich finde zu verneinen, daß es eine Realität gibt oder daß die Realität das Sein ist oder daß das Sein vollständig intelligibel ist oder daß die vollständige Intelligibilität ein unbeschränktes Verstehen ist oder daß das unbeschränkte Verstehen Gott ist. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz; Bejahung Gottes 3; Gottesbeweis 2; Verbindung: Existenz aus Selbstbejahung - Sein = Realität

Kurzinhalt: ... muß unterschieden werden zwischen: (1) der Behauptung einer Verbindung zwischen einer anderen Existenz und Gottes Existenz und (2) der Behauptung der anderen Existenz, die mit Gottes Existenz verbunden ist. (Fs)

Textausschnitt: 758a Eine Konklusion kann nun aber nicht mehr enthalten als ihre Prämissen. Wenn wir am Anfang nicht wissen, ob Gott existiert, dann muß zumindest dieses Wissen im Prozeß aufkommen, wenn es am Ende desselben präsent sein soll. Wo also tritt denn Gottes Existenz implizit in den Prozeß ein?

758b Dies ist eine gute Frage; aber um sie zu beantworten, muß unterschieden werden zwischen
(1) der Behauptung einer Verbindung zwischen einer anderen Existenz und Gottes Existenz und
(2) der Behauptung der anderen Existenz, die mit Gottes Existenz verbunden ist. (Fs)

758c Das zweite Element liegt in der Behauptung irgendeiner Realität: Es fand im Kapitel über Selbstbejahung statt und wurde in den nachfolgenden Kapiteln zum Universum des proportionierten Seins erweitert. Das erste Element ist der Prozeß, der das Wirkliche mit dem Sein identifiziert, dann das Sein mit der vollständigen Intelligibilität identifiziert und schließlich die vollständige Intelligibilität mit dem unbeschränkten Verstehensakt identifiziert, der die Eigenschaften Gottes besitzt und alles andere erklärt. In diesem Prozeß ist das ausdehnungsfähige Moment das erste: (676) Denn wenn das Reale das Sein ist, ist das Reale das Zielobjekt eines unbeschränkten Strebens nach korrektem Verstehen; um ein solches Zielobjekt zu sein, muß das Reale vollständig intelligibel sein; denn was nicht intelligibel ist, ist nicht Zielobjekt eines Strebens nach Verstehen; und was nicht vollständig intelligibel ist, ist das Zielobjekt nicht eines unbeschränkten Strebens nach korrektem Verstehen, sondern eines solchen umsichtig mit einer obskurantistischen Verstehensverweigerung vermischten Strebens. Wenn dieses ausdehnungsfähige Moment einmal erreicht ist, folgt der Rest. Das Reale kann nicht vollständig intelligibel sein, wenn die vollständige Intelligibilität nicht real ist. Und die vollständige Intelligibilität kann nicht real sein, wenn der unbeschränkte Verstehensakt bloß ein Gedankenobjekt ist. Denn die Intelligibilität dessen, was bloß Inhalt eines Begriffes ist, ist nicht real; die Intelligibilität der materiellen Realität hängt von einem rein empirischen Residuum ab und ist somit unvollständig; die Intelligibilität der fragenden und sich entwickelnden Intelligenz sucht ihre eigene Vervollständigung und gibt damit ihre eigene Unvollständigkeit kund; und deshalb ist die einzige Möglichkeit einer Intelligibilität, die zugleich vollständig und real ist, der uneingeschränkte Verstehensakt. (Fs)

759a Wer sind wir aber, daß wir Anspruch auf die Erkenntnis jeder Möglichkeit erheben? Könnte es nicht irgendeine weitere Alternative geben? Könnte die Intelligibilität nicht in einer anderen Weise real und vollständig sein, die jenseits der engen Grenzen unseres Verstehens liegt? Es könnte dies geben, wenn wir bereit wären, bei den Gegenpositionen Zuflucht zu nehmen oder unseren eigenen Tendenzen zum Obskurantismus den Weg frei zu geben. Wir gehen aber davon aus, daß wir das nicht sind. Und wenn wir das nicht sind, so ist das Mögliche mögliches Sein, das Sein innerlich intelligibel, und das Intelligible entweder identisch mit dem Verstehen oder auf es bezogen als etwas, das verstanden werden kann. Aber die Intelligibilität der letzteren Art ist unvollständig, weil sie in ihrer Intelligibilität selbst durch ihre Relation auf etwas anderes bedingt ist. Und auch das untersuchende und sich entwickelnde Verstehen ist nicht vollständig. Dann bleibt nur der unbeschränkte Verstehensakt übrig. Und es liegt in unserer Behauptung, alle möglichen Alternativen berücksichtigt zu haben, auch kein Paradox; denn wenn wir wissen können, daß das von uns Erreichte sehr beschränkt ist, können wir dies, weil unsere Erkenntnis einem unbeschränkten Streben nach korrektem Verstehen entspringt; und so ist es ein und dasselbe unbeschränkte Streben, das uns einerseits den unermeßlichen Bereich der Möglichkeiten offenbart und zugleich die Grundbedingungen festlegt, denen jede Möglichkeit zu genügen hat. (Fs)

759b Schließlich könnte eingewendet werden, daß ein unbeschränkter Akt des Verstehens, soviel wir wissen, einen Widerspruch in terminis darstellt. Aber zumindest ein unbeschränktes Streben danach, korrekt zu verstehen, ist kein Widerspruch; denn es ist eine Tatsache. Und der Widerspruch hat auch keinen anderen Ursprung (677) als die Existenz verschiedener Verstehensakte in bezug auf dasselbe Objekt. Und der Widerspruch impliziert auch keine Unmöglichkeit, außer wenn die Realität vollständig intelligibel ist. Der uneingeschränkte Verstehensakt ist aber ein einzelner Akt, so daß kein Widerspruch aus ihm hervorgehen kann; und allein weil der uneingeschränkte Akt alles begründet, was ist, und alles begründen würde, was sein könnte, ist es wahr, daß das Widersprüchliche nicht sein kann. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz, Metaphysik; Vergleiche und Kontrast 1; Aristoteles: enoEsis noEseOs - Plato; Thomas (Gottesbeweis, fünf Wege); Schleiermacher


Kurzinhalt: ... die fünf Wege, auf denen Thomas die Existenz Gottes beweist, sind ebensoviele Einzelfälle der allgemeinen Behauptung, daß das proportionierte Universum unvollständig intelligibel ist und daß vollständige Intelligibilität verlangt wird.

Textausschnitt: 11. Vergleiche und Kontraste

760a Es wurde bewiesen, daß unsere Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins einen universalen Gesichtspunkt liefert, und jetzt, da die Metaphysik transformiert wurde, so daß sie auch das transzendente Sein einschließt, müssen wir fragen, ob der Universalgesichtspunkt beibehalten wird. (Fs)

760b Erstens, unsere Auffassung von Gott als dem unbeschränkten Verstehensakt deckt sich mit Aristoteles' Auffassung des unbewegten Bewegers als noEsis noEseOs, wenn noEsis dieselbe Bedeutung hat wie noein in der berühmten Aussage in De Anima, daß nämlich die Formen vom Verstand in den Bildern erfaßt werden. Und diese Interpretation hat auch nichts Phantastisches in sich. Wie Aristoteles' Metaphysik von Materie und Form einer Psychologie von Sinnlichkeit und Einsicht entspricht, so sind Aristoteles' getrennte Formen nicht platonische Ideen ohne Intelligenz, sondern Identitäten der Intelligibilität im Akt mit Intelligenz im Akt. (Fs) (notabene)

760c Zweitens, die Reihe der Attribute, die wir im unbeschränkten Verstehensakt aufgefunden haben, offenbart die Identität unserer Auffassung mit Thomas' Auffassung von Gott als ipsum intelligere, ipsum esse, summum bonum, das Urbild, die Wirkursache, der erste Urheber und der letzte Zweck von allem, was sonst ist oder sein könnte. Unter Thomisten besteht allerdings ein Streit darüber, ob das ipsum intelligere oder das ipsum esse subsistens unter den Attributen logisch an erster Stelle stehe. Wie wir im Abschnitt über die Notion Gottes gesehen haben, folgen alle anderen göttlichen Attribute aus der Notion eines uneingeschränkten Verstehensaktes. Weil wir außerdem das Sein durch seine Relation zur Intelligenz definieren, ist unser schlechthin Letztes notwendigerweise nicht das Sein, sondern die Intelligenz. (Fs; tblVrw: Relationen) (notabene)

760d Drittens, wie Thomas, so haben auch wir das ontologische Argument abgelehnt und jede andere Behauptung einer unmittelbaren Erkenntnis Gottes. Wie wir aber mittelbar von der Realität der Geschöpfe auf die Realität Gottes argumentiert haben, so haben wir die Implikation dieser Vorgehensweise explizit gemacht, indem wir zwei Ebenen in der Metaphysik unterschieden. Denn wenn die Geschöpfe von uns erkannt werden, ehe Gott erkannt ist, so gibt es in unserer Erkenntnis eine Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins, die tatsächlich wahr ist und die tatsächlich die ontologische Struktur des proportionierten Seins offenbart. Reine Tatsachen (678) können aber für die Intelligenz nicht das Letzte sein, und deshalb werden wir von der proportionierten Metaphysik her, nämlich von der Kontingenz durch Kausalität zum Sein geführt, das zugleich transzendente Idee und transzendente Realität ist. (Fs) (notabene)

761a Viertens, die fünf Wege, auf denen Thomas die Existenz Gottes beweist, sind ebensoviele Einzelfälle der allgemeinen Behauptung, daß das proportionierte Universum unvollständig intelligibel ist und daß vollständige Intelligibilität verlangt wird. Es gibt dann also ein Argument aus der Bewegung, weil der Übergang von der Potenz zum Akt bedingt ist und ein uneingeschränktes Aggregat bedingter Übergänge nicht zur vollständigen Intelligibilität beiträgt. Es gibt ein Argument aus der Wirkursächlichkeit; denn die intelligible Abhängigkeit der Wirkung von der Ursache wird nur dann vollständig intelligibel, wenn es eine Ursache gibt, die intelligibel ist ohne abhängig zu sein. Es gibt ein Argument aus der Kontingenz; denn die Kontingenz ist eine Tatsache, und die Tatsache ist nicht vollständig intelligibel. Es gibt ein Argument aus den verschiedenen Seinsebenen; denn die Vielen können nur dann vollständig intelligibel sein, wenn sie auf das Eine und Einzige bezogen werden. Es gibt ein Argument aus der Ordnung des Universums, weil die Intelligibilität der Ordnung in ihrer Intelligibilität durch ihre Relationen zu einer Intelligenz bedingt ist. (Fs) (notabene)

761b Fünftens, außer den fünf Wegen von Thomas gibt es soviele andere Beweise für die Existenz Gottes, wie es Aspekte der unvollständigen Intelligibilität im Universum des proportionierten Seins gibt. Insbesondere muß die Aufmerksamkeit auf das epistemologische Problem gerichtet werden. Denn so wie nichts im proportionierten Universum eine vollständige Intelligibilität ist, ist es auch unser Erkennen nicht. Umgekehrt, wenn wir irgendeine Realität nicht erkennen, gibt es keine Möglichkeit, die Existenz Gottes abzuleiten. Es folgt, daß wir zuerst erweisen müssen, daß wir tatsächlich erkennen und daß es tatsächlich eine Wirklichkeit gibt, die unserem Erkennen proportioniert ist. Denn erst wenn die Tatsachen bekannt sind, können wir hoffen, eine Erklärung der Möglichkeit einer Übereinstimmung zwischen unserem Untersuchen und Verstehen, unserem Reflektieren und Urteilen, und andererseits dem Wirklichen wie es wirklich ist, zu erreichen. (Fs)

761c Infolgedessen sind wir gezwungen, dem nicht zuzustimmen, was anscheinend das Verfahren Schleiermachers war. Er hielt korrekterweise dafür, daß unser Erkennen nur möglich ist, wenn es eine letzte Identität von Denken und Sein gibt. Es folgt daraus aber nicht, daß eine derartige Identität in unserem Erkennen genetisch an erster Stelle kommen muß. Und so folgt nicht, daß das Ganze unseres Erkennens auf einem durch ein religiöses Gefühl hervorgerufenen Glauben an diese letzte Identität beruht. Wie wir gesehen haben, definiert unser eigenes unbeschränktes (679) Erkenntnisstreben für uns, was wir verstehen müssen, wenn wir vom Sein sprechen. Im Lichte dieser Notion können wir durch intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen ermitteln, was in der Tat ist und was in der Tat nicht ist; und während dieses Verfahren nicht erklärt, warum jede mögliche und aktuelle Realität intelligibel sein muß, legt es doch fest, was in der Tat schon als wahr erkannt worden ist und wirft zugleich die weitere Frage auf, die nach vollständiger Erklärung und vollständiger Intelligibilität fragt. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz, Metaphysik; Vergleiche und Kontrast 2; Isomorphie: proportioniertes Sein - kontingentes Subjekt = Sein - transzendentes Subj.; Korollarium: mögliche Wwelten

Kurzinhalt: ... wie die Struktur des proportionierten Seins aus der Struktur des kontingenten Subjektes abgeleitet werden kann, so können gewisse allgemeine Eigenschaften jedes möglichen Universums aus den Attributen des transzendenten Subjektes abgeleitet werden.

Textausschnitt: 762a Sechstens, wie die Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins auf der Isomorphie des proportionierten Erkannten zum Erkennenden beruht, so wird der Übergang zum Transzendenten dadurch bewerkstelligt, daß man vom unbeschränkten Erkenntnisstreben des kontingenten Subjektes zum unbeschränkten Verstehensakt des transzendenten Subjektes fortschreitet. Weiter, wie die Struktur des proportionierten Seins aus der Struktur des kontingenten Subjektes abgeleitet werden kann, so können gewisse allgemeine Eigenschaften jedes möglichen Universums aus den Attributen des transzendenten Subjektes abgeleitet werden. Während aber die Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins durch Bezugnahme auf den Common Sense und die empirischen Wissenschaften entwickelt werden kann, müssen die allgemeinen Eigenschaften jedes möglichen Universums in unserer Erkenntnis Allgemeinheiten bleiben, weil wir keine empirische Erkenntnis von Universen haben außer dem Universum, in welchem wir existieren. (Fs) (notabene)

762b Es folgt ein Korollarium von beachtlicher theologischer Wichtigkeit, nämlich daß unsere Erkenntnis möglicher Welten im allgemeinen nicht mehr als eine Ableitung aus unserer Gotteserkenntnis ist. So z.B. können wir, weil Gott allmächtig ist, ableiten, daß jede nichtwidersprüchliche Aussage in irgendeiner möglichen Welt wahr wäre. Weil die göttliche Weisheit der göttlichen Macht gleichkommt, können wir sagen, daß jede mögliche Welt gemäß der unendlichen Weisheit geordnet wäre. Weil die göttliche Güte mit der göttlichen Weisheit übereinstimmt, können wir sagen, daß jede mögliche Welt der unendlichen Güte würdig wäre. Weil unser Verstehen aber nicht der unbeschränkte Akt ist, können wir dies nicht im Detail ausführen. Kurzum, wir sind auf die Nüchternheit von Thomas in der fünfundzwanzigsten Quaestio des ersten Teils der Summa Theologiae verpflichtet, und sind veranlaßt, die Scotistische Sichtweise, daß eine Frage erst dann wissenschaftlich wird, wenn sie im Hinblick auf alle möglichen Welten gestellt wird, als methodologisch falsch abzulehnen. Tatsache ist, daß eine Frage dann meist unbestimmbar wird, und die Sterilität der Spätscholastik scheint zu nicht geringem Teil ihren irrtümlichen Auffassungen von der Natur der wissenschaftlichen Erkenntnis zuzuschreiben sein. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz, Metaphysik; Vergleiche und Kontrast 3; Positionen (primär, sekundär) - Gegenpositionen; Bewußtsein polymorph: Variablen, Philosophie; veritas est una et error multiplex

Kurzinhalt: In dem Maße, als die primäre und die sekundäre Entwicklung nicht stattgefunden haben oder man sie sich nicht angeeignet hat, ist nicht nur das menschliche Bewußtsein polymorph, sondern auch seine verschiedenen Komponenten nicht analysiert.

Textausschnitt: 763a Siebtens, wenn unsere Darstellung der Notion und Bejahung Gottes auch in die Aristotelische und Thomistische Tradition gestellt werden kann, genügt sie auch der Forderung, die Existenz anderer Sichtweisen zu erklären. Denn obwohl wir (680) über die Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins zur transzendenten Idee und zur transzendenten Realität des Seins hinausgegangen sind, ist unsere Operationsbasis doch dieselbe geblieben. Wir stellten die Frage nach der Notion Gottes, indem wir fragten, was das Sein ist. Wir beantworteten die Frage, ob Gott existiert, indem wir behaupteten, daß das Reale das Sein ist, und daß das Sein das vollständig intelligible Zielobjekt eines unbeschränkten Strebens nach korrektem Verstehen ist. Es war auch an keinem entscheidenden Punkt im Prozeß verborgen, daß wir unsere Antworten dadurch erreichen, daß wir den Positionen treu bleiben und die Gegenpositionen ablehnen. Die Polymorphie des menschlichen Bewußtseins wird aber durch die reine Tatsache nicht ausgeschaltet, daß ein Mensch fragt, was und ob Gott ist. Folglich, wie unsere Notion und Bejahung Gottes aus den Positionen resultieren, so können andere Auffassungen von der Gottheit erreicht werden, indem man verschiedene Stufen in der Entwicklung der Positionen und im Irrgang der Gegenpositionen annimmt. (Fs)

763b Es folgt, daß der Universalgesichtspunkt der proportionierten Metaphysik bewahrt, aber erweitert wurde. Denn ein Gesichtspunkt ist universell in dem Maße, als er
(1) einer und kohärent ist;

(2) Fragen aufwirft, die zu grundsätzlich sind, als daß sie übergangen werden könnten und
(3) seine Analyse des Beweises soweit auf den Grund geht, daß sie die Existenz jeder anderen Ansicht erklären und zugleich die eigene begründen kann. (Fs)

763c Notion und Bejahung Gottes ist aber eine; denn Gott ist einer; sie ist kohärent; denn Kohärenz resultiert aus der Einheit eines einzelnen Verstehensaktes, und Gott ist ein einzelner, unbeschränkter Verstehensakt. Ferner, zu fragen, was das Sein ist, und zu fragen, ob das Reale Sein ist, bedeutet Fragen aufzuwerfen, die zu grundlegend sind, als daß sie übergangen werden könnten. Schließlich, so wie unsere Antwort aus den Positionen in ihrer gegenwärtigen Entwicklungsphase resultiert, so können andere Antworten (zumindest wenn wir einstweilen von der mystischen Behauptung des Unaussprechlichen und der gläubigen Behauptung einer göttlichen Offenbarung absehen) abgeleitet werden, indem den Variablen im polymorphen Bewußtsein des Menschen verschiedene Werte zugewiesen werden. (Fs)

764a Um diese Konklusion kurz zu erläutern, entwickeln sich die Positionen primär, insofern die Sinneswahrnehmung vom Verstehen unterschieden wird und beide, Sinneswahrnehmung und Verstehen, vom Urteil unterschieden werden, und sie entwickeln sich sekundär, insofern die Positionen scharf und wirksam von den Gegenpositionen unterschieden werden. Pythagoras und Parmenides, Plato und Aristoteles, Augustinus und Thomas sind die großen Namen im primären Prozeß, (681) während der Zusammenbruch der mittelalterlichen Scholastik und die methodologischen Bemühungen der modernen Philosophie das Problem der sekundären Entwicklung aufwerfen, und der Fortschritt von Mathematik und empirischer Wissenschaft die präzise Auskunft liefert, die nötig ist, um diese Entwicklung herbeizuführen. (Fs)

764b In dem Maße, als die primäre und die sekundäre Entwicklung nicht stattgefunden haben oder man sie sich nicht angeeignet hat, ist nicht nur das menschliche Bewußtsein polymorph, sondern auch seine verschiedenen Komponenten nicht analysiert. Der Mensch bejaht das Göttliche, und dunkel weiß er, was er meint. So gut er kann, sucht er seinem Sinngehalt Ausdruck zu verleihen, aber die Mittel, um ihn auszudrücken, sind dieser Aufgabe nicht gewachsen. Er kann Gott einen Namen geben; doch gibt es viele Zungen, und so gibt es viele Namen. Er kann durch Analogie die göttlichen Attribute angeben; aber er kann die Analogien, die er verwendet, nicht von ihren Unvollkommenheiten trennen. Gott zu einer Ursache zu machen, bedeutet auch, ihn in die Vergangenheit zu verweisen; ihn zu einem Ziel zu machen, bedeutet, ihn in die Zukunft hinauszuschieben; auf seiner Unmittelbarkeit und Relevanz für die Welt und das menschliche Leben zu bestehen, bedeutet, ihn in Heim und Familie einzubeziehen, in die Verherrlichung der patriarchalen und matriarchalen Einrichtungen, in die Angelegenheit der Jäger und Fischer, der Ackerbauer, Handwerker und Nomaden, in die Interessen von Besitztum und Staat, in die Beschäftigungen von Krieg und Frieden. Die vierfache Befangenheit des dramatischen und praktischen Subjektes des Common Sense taucht wieder auf in der Auffassung des Göttlichen, und sie zielt durch diese Verstärkung und Sanktion zuerst auf eine immer größere Erweiterung hin, aber letztlich auf ihre eigene Umkehrung. So sammelten die Imperien des Mittelmeerraumes die Götter ihrer Völker in Pantheons; die Synkretisten reduzierten deren Anzahl; die Allegoristen gaben ihren Taten neue Sinngehalte; und die Philosophen entdeckten und predigten den Primat des Intelligiblen und des Einen. (Fs)

765a Aber die Entstehung der Philosophie als eines eigenständigen Forschungsgebietes verlegt bloß das Problem. Die vielen Götter weichen den vielen Philosophien. Dem Intellektualismus eines Plato und eines Aristoteles steht der Atomismus eines Leukipp und Demokrit entgegen. Die Zeit trennt die alten, mittleren und neueren Akademien. Das Lykeion verläßt die fünfzig sonderbaren unbewegten Beweger der Aristotelischen Kosmologie, um sich der empirischen Forschung zu widmen. Die Philosophie selbst wird im primär ethischen Interesse der Kyniker und Kyrenaiker, der Epikuräer und Stoiker praktisch; und die geistreiche Spekulation eines Plotin endet in den wirksameren Sonderbarkeiten eines Proclus und Jamblichus. (Fs)

765b Ferner, wenn behauptet werden kann, daß der anhaltende Monotheismus der hebräischen und christlichen Traditionen und einiger ihrer Ableger eine historische Einmaligkeit darstellt, kann doch nicht gesagt werden, sie hätten die Polymorphie (682) des menschlichen Bewußtseins exorziert. Neben den Rechtgläubigen gab es die Häretiker. Die scheinbar monolithische Front der mittelalterlichen Scholastik zerbricht bei näherer Betrachtung in Schulen und innerhalb der Schulen streiten sich die Menschen um ihre besondere Rechtgläubigkeit. Hinter den Gewißheiten eines gemeinsamen Glaubens entstehen Zweifel und Verneinungen hinsichtlich des unabhängigen Bereiches und Wertes der menschlichen Vernunft. Der Cartesischen Wiedergeburt folgte der Gegensatz von Rationalismus und Empirismus. Der Kantische Kompromiß wurde aufgegeben, einerseits zugunsten des Idealismus und andererseits zugunsten des Irrationalismus. Um das zunehmende Vakuum zu füllen, wird die Wissenschaft zum Szientismus und verkündet, die Erde sei nur einer der Planeten, wie der Mensch nur eines unter den Tieren sei, Gott sei nur eine Projektion aus den Tiefen der Psyche, und Religion bloß eine Fassade für wirtschaftliche und soziale Interessen. (Fs) (notabene)

765c Wenn nun die Notion und Bejahung Gottes zu den Positionen gehören, und zwar nicht auf zufällige Weise, sondern als notwendige Antworten auf die unvermeidlichen Fragen nach der Idee des Seins und der Identität von Sein und Wirklichem, dann folgt, daß die Gegenpositionen, die stets durch die Polymorphie des menschlichen Bewußtseins unterstützt werden, vorphilosophische Notionen des Göttlichen ins Mythische verwickeln, gegenphilosophische falsche Auffassungen, Zweifel und Abstreitungen erzeugen und dazu tendieren werden, sogar korrekte Notionen und Behauptungen zu korrumpieren, wenn diese nicht durch eine wirksame Kritik der Einflüsse unterstützt werden, die aus dem Unbewußten in die menschliche Sinnlichkeit und Intersubjektivität aufsteigen und in den Bereich des Wahren eindringen, wenn tribale, nationale, wirtschaftliche und politische Notwendigkeit und Nützlichkeit es fordern. (Fs)

766a Wenn das Verfahren des vorliegenden Kapitels in der Konzeption der Natur und in der Behauptung der Existenz Gottes übermäßig mühsam, verwickelt und schwierig zu sein scheint, wäre es unfair, die Tatsache zu übersehen, daß es unser Anliegen gewesen ist, nicht den leichtesten Zugang zur Notion Gottes zu wählen, nicht den einfachsten Beweis seiner Existenz zu liefern, sondern so vom proportionierten zum transzendenten Sein fortzuschreiten, daß der Universalgesichtspunkt, den wir in den früheren Stadien der Argumentation erreichten, sowohl beibehalten als auch erweitert werden könne. Ein alter Spruch lautet: veritas est una et error multiplex; aber auch die Wahrheit verändert ihr Aussehen, während das menschliche Verstehen sich entwickelt, und es ist kein geringfügiger Vorteil, wenn man von einer einzigen Grundlage her imstande ist, nicht nur das sich verändernde Aussehen der Wahrheit, nicht nur die Vielfalt des Irrtums, sondern auch den schlimmsten aller Feinde zu erklären, nämlich den in des Menschen Haushalt, der (683) so spontan und so natürlich dazu tendiert, die Wahrheit, die man kennt, anzupassen und zu färben je nach den Forderungen des eigenen soziokulturellen Milieus und dem Farbton des eigenen Temperaments. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz, Metaphysik; Vergleiche und Kontrast 4; Unterschied: Erkennen - Erkennen des Erkennenes : Gott erkennen - G. erkennen als unbeschränkten Verstehensakt

Kurzinhalt: Achtens, weil es schwierig ist zu erkennen, worin unser Erkennen besteht, ist es auch schwierig zu erkennen, was unser Erkennen von Gott ist.

Textausschnitt: 766b Achtens, weil es schwierig ist zu erkennen, worin unser Erkennen besteht, ist es auch schwierig zu erkennen, was unser Erkennen von Gott ist. So wie aber unser Erkennen einer Analyse der Erkenntnis vorausgeht und viel leichter als diese ist, so ist auch unsere Erkenntnis Gottes leichter und früher als jeder Versuch, ihr einen formalen Ausdruck zu verleihen. Denn ohne explizite Formulierung der Notion des Seins, verwenden wir diese, wann immer wir untersuchen und verstehen, reflektieren und urteilen. Ohne explizite Ablehnung des Obskurantismus stellen wir auf unserer Suche nach dem Intelligiblen und Unbedingten Fragen und weitere Fragen. Alles aber, was wir über uns selbst und die Welt um uns herum erkennen und erkennen können, wirft ein und dieselbe weitere Frage auf; denn es wird durch ein reflektierendes Erfassen des virtuell Unbedingten als bloße Tatsache erkannt; und die allgegenwärtige und unaufhörliche weitere Frage läßt nur eine Antwort zu, nämlich, eine Intelligibilität, die formell unbedingt ist. Deshalb ist es so, daß alle Menschen zwar verstehen, was sie unter der "Natur von ..." meinen, aber in Verlegenheit sind, wenn sie aussagen, was sie damit meinen, und ähnlich verstehen sie alle, was sie unter Gott meinen, obwohl sie in Verlegenheit sind, wenn sie gefragt werden, eine derart grundlegende und vertraute Notion zu erklären. Ferner, so wie jeder Forscher etwas weiß, wenn er weiß, daß es eine zu erkennende Natur gibt, wenn er auch noch zu entdecken hat, worin diese Natur besteht, so weiß jedermann etwas, wenn er weiß, daß es einen Gott gibt, auch wenn er nicht hoffen kann, je einen unbeschränkten Verstehensakt zu erreichen und so zu erkennen, was Gott ist. (Fs) (notabene)

767a Ferner, so wie die Notion der Natur vom Gnostiker und Magier mißbraucht werden kann, liefert sie doch, wenn richtig verwendet, die dynamische Basis, worauf das Ganze der wissenschaftlichen Erkenntnis aufgerichtet wird, so kann auch die Notion Gottes vom mythischen Bewußtsein korrumpiert und von einer falsch angebrachten Praxisorientiertheit entstellt werden; doch liefert sie, wenn richtig verwendet, die dynamische Basis, woraus nicht nur das Ganze der intelligenten und rationalen Erkenntnis, sondern auch das Ganze des intelligenten und rationalen Lebens entsteht. Schließlich, wie der Mißbrauch der Notion der Natur diese in den Augen jener, die am meisten begierig sind zu erkennen, was durch das Verstehen erkannt werden kann, lächerlich macht, so führt auch eine falsche Auffassung und der Mißbrauch der Notion Gottes zu ihrer Ablehnung gerade durch jene Menschen, die am meisten darauf bestehen, den Obskurantismus zu brandmarken; zu fordern, daß die Urteile auf dem Unbedingten beruhen; und Übereinstimmung zwischen Erkennen und Tun zu verlangen. Wenn einer aber begierig ist zu erkennen, was durch das Verstehen erkannt werden kann, kann er die Notion der Natur nur deshalb der Lächerlichkeit preisgeben, weil er nicht weiß, was dieser Terminus bedeutet; und wenn einem echt an der Brandmarkung des Obskurantismus und der Forderung (684) nach dem Unbedingten gelegen ist, dann verehrt er entweder schon Gott, ohne ihn zu nennen, oder aber muß nicht weit gehen, um ihm zu begegnen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Transzendenz, Metaphysik; Vergleiche und Kontrast 5; Zusammenfassung; Flucht, Scotosis; kritische Methode

Kurzinhalt: Ähnlich bestand die Methode der Metaphysik darin, klassische und statistische, genetische und dialektische Methoden zu einem Ganzen zusammenzufassen und umzusetzen. Die kritische Methode unterscheidet sich von den anderen Methoden allein in ihrem ...

Textausschnitt: 767b Neuntens, wir haben zugegeben, daß es ein kritisches Problem gibt, weil das unbeschränkte Streben des Menschen mehr Fragen stellt, als die begrenzte Fähigkeit des Menschen beantworten kann; wir haben die Ansicht geäußert, daß eine Lösung des Problems stückweise erfolgen muß, weil die Fragen nach der Möglichkeit nur durch Bezugnahme auf Tatsachen entschieden werden können; und wir haben betont, daß die stückweise Lösung in dem Maße methodisch wird, als sie eine umfassende und wirksame Strategie zur Anwendung bringt, wenn sie die Tatsachen auswählt, auf die sie sich nach und nach beruft. Frühere Elemente in der Strategie, die wir befolgt haben, sind dem Leser schon vertraut; es bleibt aber zu zeigen, daß die Tatsache, daß wir Gott als die transzendente Idee auffassen und ihn als die transzendente Realität des Seins behaupten können, nicht nur mit all dem Vorhergehenden in Kontinuität steht, sondern auch dessen Höhepunkt darstellt. (Fs)

767c Unser Thema ist der Akt der Einsicht oder des Verstehens gewesen, und Gott ist der uneingeschränkte Akt des Verstehens, die ewige Verzückung, die in jedem archimedischen Eureka-Schrei schimmerte. Verstehen begegnet Fragen nach Einsicht und Fragen nach Reflexion. Der uneingeschränkte Akt begegnet allen zugleich; denn er versteht das Verstehen und alle Intelligibilität, die auf ihm beruht; und er versteht sein eigenes Verstehen als uneingeschränktes, unanfechtbares und wahres. Was durch wahres Verstehen erkannt wird, ist Sein, und das Sein, das durch die Selbsterkenntnis des uneingeschränkten Verstehens erkannt wird, ist das Primärseiende, selbsterklärend, unbedingt, notwendig ohne jeden Mangel oder Makel. Das Gute ist das Intelligible, und somit ist das Primärseiende auch das Primärgute. So wie Intelligibilität ohne Intelligenz mangelhaft wäre, so wäre auch die Wahrheit ohne Bejahung, oder das Gute ohne Liebe mangelhaft. Gott aber ist ohne Fehler; nicht weil der Verstehensakt durch weitere Akte vervollständigt würde, sondern durch einen einzigen Akt, der zugleich verstehend und intelligibel, Wahrheit und Bejahung, Gutheit und Liebe, Sein und Allmacht ist. (Fs)

768a Unser Thema war das Verstehen in seinem Werdegang. Es entsteht im intelligenten und rationalen Bewußtsein; aber ehe es entsteht, wird es vorweggenommen, und diese Vorwegnahme ist der spontane Grund, der durch Reflexion herausgeschält zu den Methoden der Wissenschaft und zur vollständigen heuristischen Struktur wird, die in der Metaphysik des proportionierten Seins umgesetzt wird. Die grundlegende Vorwegnahme aber ist das unvoreingenommene, uneigennützige und uneingeschränkte Streben nach korrektem Erkennen; die grundlegende Annahme ist, daß das Reale mit der begründeten Intelligibilität zusammenfällt, die durch (685) korrektes Verstehen erkannt werden soll; die grundlegende reflektierende Herausschälung aller intelligenten und rationalen Vorwegnahme und Annahme besteht darin, die Idee des Seins und damit die Notion Gottes zu konzipieren und zu behaupten, daß das Reale das Sein ist, und damit die Realität Gottes zu behaupten. (Fs) (notabene)

768b Unser Thema ist die Flucht vor dem Verstehen in der Scotosis des dramatischen Subjektes, in der dreifachen Befangenheit des Common Sense, in der Dunkelheit des mythischen Bewußtseins, in den Irrgängen der Gegenphilosophien gewesen. Es ist aber nicht der Forschungsgeist, der sich weigert zu fragen, was das Sein ist, und auch nicht die kritische Reflexion, die die Frage ignoriert, ob das Sein und nur das Sein das Reale sei. Es ist nicht die Flucht vor dem Verstehen, die die Notion eines unbeschränkten Verstehensaktes bildet, und auch nicht die Forderung des rationalen Bewußtseins nach dem Unbedingten, die sich alarmiert zurückzieht, wenn eine Forderung nach dem formell Unbedingten aufkommt. Es ist kraft der Positionen, daß die Notion von Gott entwickelt und die Bejahung Gottes aufrecht erhalten wird, und es ist wegen der Gegenpositionen, daß die Probleme falsch aufgefaßt und verworren werden. (Fs)

768b Kant sprach von einer tranzendentalen Illusion, und wenn auch gezeigt worden ist, daß das von ihm Gemeinte falsch ist, überlebt doch der Ausdruck und stiftet Mißtrauen. Es ist aber nicht das unvoreingenommene und uneigennützige Streben nach korrektem Verstehen, das eine Illusion genannt werden kann; denn es ist die Einmischung in dieses Streben, die an der Wurzel allen Irrtums liegt. Auch kann das unbeschränkte Streben nicht als transzendentale Illusion bezeichnet werden; denn es muß eine Illusion geben, ehe sie immanent oder transzendental sein kann. Und man kann auch nicht sagen, es gebe das reine Streben, es sei nicht illusorisch, aber in der Tat nicht uneingeschränkt. Schließlich stehen Kantianer und Positivisten nicht unter einer Illusion, sondern sie irren sich einfach, wenn sie sich bemühen, die menschliche Untersuchung innerhalb jener Grenzen einzuschränken, die jedermann natürlich und spontan überschreitet. (Fs)

769a Was ist denn die kritische Methode? Sie ist eine Methode im Hinblick auf das schlechterdings Letzte, eine Methode als auf die grundlegendesten Fragen angewandte. Wie wir nun gesehen haben, beruht die Methode der empirischen Wissenschaften auf der heuristischen Struktur des menschlichen Strebens und Vermögens, Daten richtig zu verstehen. Ähnlich bestand die Methode der Metaphysik darin, klassische und statistische, genetische und dialektische Methoden zu einem Ganzen zusammenzufassen und umzusetzen. Die kritische Methode unterscheidet sich von den anderen Methoden allein in ihrem Gegenstand. So wie diese, stützt sie sich auf das unvoreingenommene, uneigennützige und uneingeschränkte Streben nach korrektem Verstehen. So wie diese, erfaßt und bejaht sie ein Objekt, das korrelativ zum Streben ist. So wie diese, besteht sie darauf, daß sich allgemeine Aussagen über das Objekt machen lassen, ehe es tatsächlich verstanden wird, und daß solche Aussagen, wenn sie auch gültig und wahr und nützlich sind, hinter dem zurückbleiben, das erkannt wird, wenn das Verstehen einmal erreicht ist. Kurzum, die kritische Methode besteht nicht und kann auch nicht im sanften Verfahren (686) bestehen, transzendentale Fragen der Vergessenheit anheimfallen zu lassen. So wie die wissenschaftliche Methode die Notion der Natur nicht zurückweist, sondern sie als die unbestimmte Funktion, die bestimmt werden soll, als die ideale Häufigkeit, von der die tatsächlichen Häufigkeiten nicht systematisch abweichen können, als den genetischen Operator, als die dialektische Spannung und Opposition zwischen dem reinen Streben und der menschlichen Sinnlichkeit expliziert und präzisiert, so weist die kritische Methode die Notion Gottes nicht zurück, sondern formuliert sie als den unbeschränkten Verstehensakt und arbeitet ihre allgemeinen Attribute aus. So wie die wissenschaftliche Methode nicht die Erkenntnis der Methode mit ihren Früchten verwechselt, so verwechselt die kritische Methode nicht unsere Formulierung des unbeschränkten Verstehens mit einer Behauptung, daß wir alles über alles verstehen. So wie der Wissenschaftler bereit ist, jede wissenschaftliche Hypothese und Theorie aufzugeben, ohne das Vertrauen in die Korrektheit der wissenschaftlichen Methode zu verlieren, so behauptet der Metaphysiker die Realität dessen, was der Wissenschaftler zu erkennen sucht, und der kritische Denker läßt es nicht zu, daß Entwicklungen in der Notion Gottes irgendwelchen Zweifel daran hervorrufen, daß es ein und dasselbe Seiende ist, auf das sich alle Menschen beziehen, ob sie nun mehr oder weniger erfolgreich sind im Begriff, den sie sich von ihm bilden, ob sie seine Existenz nun korrekt bejahen oder irrtümlich verneinen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Verstehen, Akt des Verstehens = AV (operatio, energeia); AV zu Intellekt im Akt wie Existenz zu Sein im Akt; processio: operationis - operati; Aristoteles - Avicenna (Nautur - aktive Potenz); intellectus possibilis - agens

Kurzinhalt: But the agent intellect acts and the possible intellect is acted upon inasmuch as a phantasm is the instrument by which the agent intellect impresses an intelligible species upon the possible intellect.

Textausschnitt: 9 Application to the Act of Understanding

553c We can resolve what we have said into some unity if we apply it to the act of understanding. (Fs)

To understand, then, is a perfection, a second act, an act of what is complete, a motion in the broad sense. It is called an action or operation, not in the sense of a production, poiesis, but in the sense of an act, energeia. (Fs) (notabene)

It is either an infinite or a finite act. If it is infinite, it is the very act of understanding itself and is simply identical with the very act of existence itself. Also, when predicated equally of the Father, of the Son, and of the Holy Spirit it is an essential, not a notional, act. (Fs)

553d But if it is a finite act, it is an accident, and is to the intellect in act as existence is to being in act. Besides, just as the act of existence follows upon substantial form, so does the act of understanding follow upon the intelligible species. But the intelligible species is in the category of quality. Therefore, just as existence is resolved into the category of substance, so understanding is resolved into the category of quality. Finally, every finite being is from another as from its efficient cause, and therefore finite understanding is from another and is a being-changed, a reception, that is to say, a pati not in the proper sense but in the general sense [see §6 above]. Hence, the possible intellect also is a passive potency. (Fs) (notabene)

555a In the terminology apparently derived from Avicenna, the possible intellect, informed by an impressed species, is a principle of action or operation, and indeed the formal principle of action or operation. This action or operation is the act of understanding. And although in this terminology the possible intellect informed by a species is an active potency with respect to the act, the action, the operation, of understanding, nevertheless the process from this active potency to the act of understanding is not a processio operati but a procession of an operation [see §5 above]. For understanding is related to the intellect informed by a species not as an effect to its efficient cause but as a perfection to a perfectible. On the other hand, the word that is the term of the action, the operation, the act of understanding, and is produced by this action, operation, act, is a product or effect; hence, in relation to the word, the intellect informed by a species is the principle of an effect or the principle of a product, and the procession of the word is said to be aprocessio operati. (Fs)

555b In the Aristotelian terminology, both the possible intellect and the species by which the intellect is informed are principles of the act of understanding. These principles, however, since they produce the act in that being in which the act is, are referred to not as passive potency or active potency but as nature. For a passive potency is the principle of motion or change from another as from that other; active potency is the principle of motion or change in another as in that other. Accordingly, the possible intellect is a passive potency in comparison with the agent intellect, and the agent intellect is an active potency in comparison with the possible intellect. But the agent intellect acts and the possible intellect is acted upon inasmuch as a phantasm is the instrument by which the agent intellect impresses an intelligible species upon the possible intellect. Moreover, just as whatever has produced a heavy or a light object also moves it locally, so in general an agent gives something not only a form but also the motion that is consequent upon the form. In this way the agent intellect is a mover whenever an act of understanding follows upon an intelligible species. (Fs) (notabene)

555c Beware of the common error of thinking that the mover [movens] is the sole principle of an act. For a mover as such is something extrinsic, and the more it contributes to an act the less perfect is the subject. Thus, if one is moving towards an act of understanding through one's possible intellect alone as the natural principle of this act, both the agent intellect and the teacher have the most work to do. But if one is moving towards the act not by one's possible intellect alone but also by an intelligible species as by the natural principles [of the act of understanding], then that person has no need of a teacher and operates whenever he or she wishes. And the larger a collection of well-ordered species one possesses (which is an intellectual habit), the more does one tend to understand, and the more easily does one understand and add new insights to what one has already understood. (Fs) (notabene)

557a It was for this reason that St Thomas in investigating the essential notion of life made a distinction between life itself and the external sign of life. 'For the use of the word "life" is based upon an external feature of the [living] thing, the fact that it moves itself; but this word does not signify this feature but rather the substance to which self-movement belongs by its nature or to move itself to operation in any way at all' (Summa theologiae, i, q. 18, a. 2 c). Then, when he was treating the question of the degrees of perfection among living things, he did not consider those beings to be more alive in which more principles of motion and mobility were to be found, but stated this rule: 'Since things are said to be alive insofar as they operate by themselves and not as if moved by something else, it follows that the more this feature belongs to a thing, the higher is the degree of perfection of the life to be found in it' [ibid. a. 3, c]. Accordingly, proceeding through all the levels of life, and excluding the very lowest level as that which is moved to something by something else, St Thomas arrived at that being 'whose act of understanding is its very nature, and which, in what it naturally possesses, is not determined by another' [ibid.]. This act of understanding fits the definition of life, that is, to move oneself to operation in any way at all. For understanding is an operation and a motion in the broad sense; but God understands himself, and 'that which understands itself is said to move itself [ibid, ad im], Yet, it must not be understood from this that there is any, even a minimal, duality in God; for God's existence and understanding are so much one that in God truth is present not according to a conformity (which supposes duality) but through the absence of dissimilarity (ibid. q. 16, a. 5, ad 2m). Hence, it follows that the processions in God cannot be proved from the fact that God is alive and that a living thing moves and is moved. For the most perfect life is pure act without the least admixture of potentiality. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Akt des Verstehens - Wort; Erfassen des Vor-Begrifflich (preconceptual); Thomas - Scotus; Bildund des Wortes ohne Verstehen: Verunmöglichung des analogen Verstehens der Trinität

Kurzinhalt: It remains, therefore, that our intellect grasps not only conceptual objects but preconceptual objects as well. Otherwise we would not form conceptions because we understand, but rather, as the Scotists teach, ...

Textausschnitt: The Act of Understanding1

599a For an inner word or concept to emanate intellectually, it is absolutely necessary that we understand before we form within ourselves a word or concept. We certainly understand something in this prior act, but the object of this act cannot be a word that has not yet been formed. It remains, therefore, that our intellect grasps not only conceptual objects but preconceptual objects as well. Otherwise we would not form conceptions because we understand, but rather, as the Scotists teach, we are able to understand because in some unconscious manner conceptions have been formed.2 (Fs) (notabene)

561a Therefore, we must now explain briefly what St Thomas thought regarding this question. No one can be unaware of the great importance of this question, since the unconscious formation of the word would destroy that intellectual emanation which we have considered to be the psychological analogy of the Holy Trinity. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Akt des Verstehens 2 - Notion des Objekts; Objekt: aktive - passive Potenz

Kurzinhalt: Therefore an object can be either a mover that brings about an act in a potency, or a term produced by an act, or the end to which a potency tends through acts.

Textausschnitt: 1 The Notion of Object

561b Object is defined by St Thomas in terms of a causal relation to potency and to act. Therefore an object can be either a mover that brings about an act in a potency, or a term produced by an act, or the end to which a potency tends through acts. (Fs)

Summa theologiae, 1, q. 77, a. 3 c: 'Every action belongs either to an active potency or to a passive potency. But an object is to the act of a passive potency as principle and moving cause; for color is the principle of vision insofar as it moves the faculty of sight. But an object is to the act of an active potency as term and end; as the object of the faculty of growth is achieving its due quantity, which is the end of growth.' (notabene)

See also De veritate, q. 16, a. 1, ad 13m; In II De anima, lect. 6, §305; Quaestiones disputatae De anima, a. 13 c; Summa tkeologiae, 1-2, q. 18, a. 2, ad 3m; Theological Studies 8:3 (1947) 433-37 [Verbum 138-43]. (Fs)
561c It follows, then, that the notion of object is not a primitive notion but is reducible to the notions of potency, act, mover, and end or term. Therefore, do not talk about attaining an object without having thought about which clearly defined relation you are referring to. (Fs)

561c It follows, then, that the notion of object is not a primitive notion but is reducible to the notions of potency, act, mover, and end or term. Therefore, do not talk about attaining an object without having thought about which clearly defined relation you are referring to. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Akt des Verstehens 3 - das Objekt des Intellekts als Term (inneres Wort) und Endziel (Sein); Wort: inneres - äußeres; Unterschied: Akt (d. Verstehens, Denkens, Vermutens usw.) - inneres Wort

Kurzinhalt: The object of the intellect as its end is being, in the widest sense of the word ... But the object of the intellect as the term produced within the intellect itself is the 'word of the heart' or 'inner word.'

Textausschnitt: 2 The Object of the Intellect as End and Term

563a The object of the intellect as its end is being, in the widest sense of the word. For the intellect is that which can make and become all things, and 'all' is not restricted to any genus. Summa theologiae, 1, q. 79, a. 7 c. (Fs)

But the object of the intellect as the term produced within the intellect itself is the 'word of the heart' or 'inner word.' And since there are two intellectual operations, there are also two terms produced immanently, namely, the simple word or definition and the compound word or proposition,1 that is, the true or the false. De veritate, q. 4, a. 2; q. 3, a. 2; De potentia, q. 8, a. 1; q. 9, a. 5; Quaestiones quodlibetales, 5, a. 9; Super loannem, c. 1, lect. 1. (Fs)

563b The existence of these inner words is proven from the meaning of outer words. We speak of 'man' or 'triangle,' and we surely mean something by these words. Unless, therefore, you believe that universals subsist as real entities, you will necessarily conclude that universals are conceived in the mind and signified directly and immediately by external words. Again, human speech states what is true and what is false. What, then, is signified directly and immediately by a false statement? Unless along with the neo-positivists you maintain that false statements signify nothing, you will necessarily acknowledge a compound word formed inwardly in the mind and signified directly and immediately in an external statement. Finally, we all hold that human speech also signifies things, and yet we do not accept anything unless it is true. But the true and the false are in the mind; truth, in fact, is formally only in a judgment. Again, therefore, one must conclude that outer words signify things, not immediately, of course, but through the medium of inner words that are true. (Fs)

563c Hence, primarily and per se outer words, whether spoken or written or present in the imagination, signify and are not signified. Things, on the other hand, are signified, but primarily and per se do not signify. Inner words, however, both signify and are signified: they are signified by outer words, and signify things themselves. (Fs) (notabene)

563d For this reason one must be careful not to confuse inner words either with the act of understanding or with thinking, defining, supposing, considering, affirming, or denying. An inner word is that which is understood, is thought, is defined, is supposed, is considered, is affirmed, is denied-not, of course, according to its natural existence but according to its intentional existence. Intentional existence is the medium in which a thing is known. (Fs) (notabene)

565a Furthermore, an inner word is not noesis but a noema, not la pensée pensante but la pensée pensée, not an intending intention but an intended intention, not the intention of the one understanding, but the intention understood.2

For the relevant texts, see Theological Studies 7:3 (1946) 351-59 [Verbum 14-24]. On the discrepancy between the Scriptum super Sententias and Aquinas's other writings beginning from De veritate, q. 3, a. 2, see Theological Studies 7:3 (1946) 360, note 51 [Verbum 25, note 52]. (Fs)

565b With regard to the minor work, De natura verbi intellectus, the following observations will suffice. (1) Fr Mandonnet has judged it to be spurious; (2) the criteria proposed by Mandonnet on the value of the catalogues have long since been rejected by experts; (3) from external criteria Msgr Grabmann judged as more probably authentic a series of minor works, including the De natura verbi intellectus; (4) more recendy Fr Pelster, among others, has agreed with Grabmann, holding that external criteria make for probability while internal criteria make for certitude ('Die Thomas von Aquin zugeschriebenen Opuscula De instantibus, De natura verbi intellectus, De principio individuationis, De genere, De natura acci-dentis, De natura materiae, De quatuor oppositis und ihr Verfasser,' Gregorianum 36 [1955] 21-49); (5) it seems to me better for the time being to omit diese testimonies from this treatise. For the argument from internal criteria, even if it had been peremptory on all points (which Fr Pelster did not claim it to be), is better suited to determine chronology than to evince authenticity. Then again, authenticity is by no means a univocal concept: there are some works written by St Thomas and edited by him, there are others written by him and reported by someone else, and there are still others that can in some sense be called authentic, which have come from him in some way or other. This being the case, I have deemed it safer and more useful to eschew needless questions and explain the teaching that is found in works of certain authenticity. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Akt des Verstehens 4 - das den Intellekt bewegende Objekt: einfaches, zusammengesetztes Wort (incomplexum, complexum, 3 Elemente; Beispiel Kreis, Nacht, Licht; intellectus agens - phantasma; forma, species; Formalursache

Kurzinhalt: Since the intellect has two operations, it has likewise two objects that move it. In order that the intellect be able to speak either a simple or a compound word, it must first understand; ... Sufficient evidence itself, insofar as it can move any ...

Textausschnitt: 567a Since the intellect has two operations, it has likewise two objects that move it. In order that the intellect be able to speak either a simple or a compound word, it must first understand; but since it is a passive potency, in order to understand it must be moved to an act of understanding. Nothing is moved from potency to act unless it has something to move it; and this, as capable of moving something, is called a motive or motor, and as actually moving something is called a mover.1

567b In the case of the second intellectual operation, this is very obvious. Take, for example, the spoken judgment, 'I am reading a book.' Why do I utter this judgment? Because I have grasped sufficient evidence as being sufficient. So there are three elements here: the sufficient evidence itself, the grasp of the sufficient evidence as sufficient, and the judgment uttered on the grounds of the sufficiency of the evidence. Now, a judgment is a compound word. Grasping the sufficiency of evidence is a reflective act of understanding whence there is spoken a compound word. Sufficient evidence itself, insofar as it can move any intellect to grasp its sufficiency, is a motive, and insofar as it actually moves an intellect, it is the object moving it. (Fs)

567c But this same analysis holds in the case of the first operation of the intellect. One who first discovers the definition of something or one who learns it is not impelled by some blind spontaneity but by his mental acuity and quickness to understand. Here, for example, is the definition of a circle: 'a locus of coplanar points equidistant from a center.' Why is it so defined? Because it is obvious that a line must necessarily be perfectly round if all the radii are equal, and also that it cannot be round if any radii are unequal. But where is this obvious? Is it in grasping a nexus between abstract concepts? Certainly not, for there is only one abstract radius and only one abstract point, whereas the definition involves an infinity of radii and points. Besides, that necessary roundness which grounds and explains the definition of a circle is grasped in those equal radii themselves. Here too are three distinct elements: the equal radii represented in the imagination, the grasp of the necessary roundness in these equal radii, and the definition of a circle that proceeds from the grasp of this roundness. Now, a definition is a simple word. Grasping the necessary roundness is a direct act of understanding. The equal radii, represented in the imagination and illumined by the light of the agent intellect, as being capable of moving any intellect to understand the nature of a circle, are the motive, and as actually moving this or that particular intellect, are the object moving it. (Fs) (notabene)

569a This needs further clarification. Equal radii are easy to imagine, but the necessity of roundness cannot at all be imagined. Necessity and possibility can only be apprehended intellectually. Nevertheless, without a multiplicity of radii in a visible continuum the necessity of roundness would never be grasped; and unless we grasp this necessity, we cannot arrive at the definition of a circle, except, perhaps, like children who memorize words without understanding what they refer to. (Fs) (notabene)

569b For this reason we must distinguish between the intelligible in potency and the intelligible in act. Just as at night colors are potentially visible while in the daytime they are actually visible, so the phantasms in themselves are actually sensible but potentially intelligible. Through the illumination of the agent intellect they become actually intelligible, and then not only do we imagine equal radii but also we understand the necessity of roundness in those imagined radii.1 Upon grasping this necessity, we speak inwardly the simple word that is the definition of a circle. (Fs) (notabene)

569c We must further distinguish between the proper object of our intellect in our present state of existence, its object as the term of the first intellectual operation, and its indirect object. In seeing with our eyes or in imagining equal radii, we first and directly understand through our intellect the necessity of roundness, the form or species or quiddity or nature or formal cause2 of a circle. All of these words refer to one thing, namely, the actually intelligible as luminous in the phantasm and directly discerned by the intellect. This is the nature of the proper object of our intellect in our present state of existence in which our soul is joined to our body; and since this proper object cannot be had without a phantasm, we cannot understand anything unless our intellect turns its attention to phantasms. And then, as it now grasps the necessity of roundness in the equal radii, we form the definition of a circle and thus produce the object that is the term of this first operation. Finally, in order to know intellectually a singular thing already known by our senses and imagination, we add particular knowledge indirectly to our already acquired universal knowledge by reflecting upon the phantasm in which the species shines forth. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Akt des Verstehens 5 - Quidditas, Washeit; Form, species, morphe; quod quid est, quod quid erat esse; Imagination - Verstehen : Materie - Form; 3 Objekte: Imagination, Verstehen, Definieren; Aristoteles: 4 Grundfragen (Reduktion auf 2)

Kurzinhalt: Thus there are three objects: the object of the imagination (equal radii), the object of the understanding (the necessity of roundness), and the object of the interior utterance (the definition of a circle).

Textausschnitt: 5 Quiddity

577b St Thomas time and again repeats that the proper object of the human intellect in its present state is quod quid est, 'what a thing is,' or quidditas, 'whatness' or 'quiddity.' Now we must ask, What is this 'what a thing is'?

Aristotle recognized two realities and made a certain distinction between them, namely, to ti esti and to ti en einai. Moreover, he used a more nuanced expression, to ti en einai tini, that is, to ti en einai toi toioidi somati (De anima, ii, 1, 412b 11), and even more briefly, einai with the dative case, as pelekei einai, megethei einai, sarki einai, euthei einai. (Fs)

For these expressions the medieval translators wrote, respectively, quod quid est, quod quid erat esse, quod quidem est esse eiusmodi corporis (sic, the Pirotta edition, Marietti, p. 63), dolabrae esse, magnitudini esse, carni esse, recto esse. (Fs)

577c In addition to these, the word quidditas is found in the writings of St Thomas, which had the advantage of being able to be declined through the various cases. (Fs)

On the use of these terms, see Theological Studies 7:3 (1946) 364-72 [Verbum 29-38]; 10:1 (1949) 18-25 [Verbum 168-75]. (Fs)

577d With regard to their meaning and signification, we have already made a distinction between the imagined equal radii, the understood necessity of roundness, and, finally, the spoken or uttered definition of a circle. Now, anyone can imagine equal radii. It is a matter of intelligence to grasp the necessity of roundness in that equality of radii. Finally, the act of defining is a matter of attributing to a circle and only to a circle that series or locus of points which lie in die same plane surface equidistant from a center. Thus there are three objects: the object of the imagination (equal radii), the object of the understanding (the necessity of roundness), and the object of the interior utterance (the definition of a circle). These are not only distinct but are also interrelated. The object of the imagination is to the object of understanding as matter to intelligible form, and the object of understanding is to the object of an interior utterance or word as its reason or cause or 'because of which' (propter quid). (Fs) (notabene; tblStw: Relationen)

577e That the object of the imagination stands as matter is stated in Summa theologiae, 1, q. 84, a. 6 c: 'Sense knowledge cannot be said to be the total and complete cause of intellectual knowledge, but rather, as it were, the matter of the cause.'1

579a That the object of understanding is as an intelligible form can be seen from its ordinary name. In Greek the word 'form' is either morphe or eidos; eidos is generally translated into Latin as species; and the intellect not only abstracts intelligible species from phantasms but also understands them in the phantasms (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 85, a. 1, ad im). (Fs)

579b That the object of an interior utterance has its reason and cause and its 'because of which' in the object of understanding is clear both from our intellectual experience - we are able to define a thing because we have understood it - and also on the authority of St Thomas: 'Whenever we understand, by the mere fact that we do understand, something proceeds within us, which is the conception of the thing understood, issuing from our intellectual power and proceeding from its knowledge. A spoken word signifies this conception; and this conception is called "the word of the heart," signified by the spoken word.' '... according to intellectual emanation, such as that of the intelligible word from the speaker, which remains within the speaker. Thus does the Catholic faith affirm procession in God' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 1 a). (Fs) (notabene)

579c If you have understood this, you will now be able to go on to consider the Aristotelian and Thomistic way of speaking. In Posterior Analytics, II, 1 and 2, Aristotle states that all questions can be reduced to four types: Whether there is an A? What is an A? Whether A is B? Why A is B? And these four can be further reduced to two; for the first and the third are about existence, while the second and the fourth are about 'why,' 'because of what.' (Fs) (notabene; TblVrw)

579d This is easy to see in the case of the first, third, and fourth questions. The first asks about the existence of some A, the third asks about the existence of a property B in a subject A, and the fourth deals expressly with why A is B. But it seems odd, perhaps, that the question, What is an A? is regarded as asking about a why. For it expressly asks What? rather than Why?

579e Yet, as Aristotle remarked, the question What? very often without any difficulty changes into Why? If I ask, for example, 'What is a lunar eclipse?' the question really means, 'Why is the moon covered over like this?' And in fact, whether I understand what an eclipse is, or whether I understand why the moon is covered over, I am understanding the same thing, namely, that the earth moves in between the moon and the sun, thus preventing the moon from being illuminated. (Fs)

581a In certain cases, however, it is not easy to show that a person who asks What? is really asking Why? In Posterior Analytics Aristotle left this problem unsolved, but took it up again in the Metaphysics. There he concluded that the questions What is a man? and What is a house? are really asking, Why is this (pointing to a man) a man? and Why is this (pointing to a house) a house? (Metaphysics, VII, 17, 1041a 6 to 1041b 32; In VII Metaphys., lect. 17, §§1648-80.)'1

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Der Akt des Verstehens 6 - Quidditas, Washeit; Aristoteles: Demonstrativpronomen in Grundfragen (2 Bedeutungen); quod quid erat esse (Formalprinzip); Mittelterm (propter quid ) zw. Verstehen und Wort; Hylemorphismus

Kurzinhalt: 'This' can stand for sensible or material things, and then one must say that the form or cause of being of the thing is that because of which 'this' pertains to the being of a man or to the being of a house. But again, 'this' can stand for a supposit ...

Textausschnitt: Vorher:
581a In certain cases, however, it is not easy to show that a person who asks What? is really asking Why? In Posterior Analytics Aristotle left this problem unsolved, but took it up again in the Metaphysics. There he concluded that the questions What is a man? and What is a house? are really asking, Why is this (pointing to a man) a man? and Why is this (pointing to a house) a house?

581b In these reformulated questions, however, there is an ambiguity in the word 'this.' 'This' can stand for sensible or material things, and then one must say that the form or cause of being of the thing is that because of which 'this' pertains to the being of a man or to the being of a house. But again, 'this' can stand for a supposit, and then one must say that the quiddity is that because of which this is a man or that is a house; for this is a man because of humanity, which is the quiddity of man, and that is a house because of the quiddity of house. Hence St Thomas writes in his commentary:

Similarly, when we ask, 'What is a man?' it is the same as if we were to ask why this being, namely Socrates, is a man, the answer being that there is in him the quiddity of a man. And it is also the same as if we were to ask why a certain organic body is a man. For this is the matter of a man, as stones and bricks are the matter of a house. Thus it is clear that in such questions we are asking about 'the cause of the matter,' that is, why the matter pertains to the nature of that which is being defined. What we are looking for in asking about the cause of the matter is the species, that is, the form by which something is. But this is substance, that is, that substance which is quod quid erat esse. (In VII Metaphys., lect. 17, §§1667-68)1

581c About this quod quid erat esse, note that in its primary meaning it is 'neither genus nor species nor an individual, but the formal principle of all of these' (In VII Metaphys., lect. 2, §1275). But whether it is a form or a quiddity is not clearly determined on account of the ambiguity we mentioned. For matter pertains to the existence of a man because of a human-soul, which is his form, while the supposit pertains to him because of his humanity, which is the quiddity of man. One can only marvel at Aristotle's subtlety. It is commonly said that he transposed Plato's Ideas from some noetic heaven into material things. But the Platonic Ideas were universals, and Aristotle did not at all think that there are universals in material things, since he taught that this individual man was composed of this matter and this form. (Fs)

583a One can only marvel at the acuity of his mind. Kant thought that it was not possible for anyone to penetrate to the very generative principles of intellectual knowledge from conceptual categories. But Aristotle did. On the one hand, he located the beginning of all knowledge and philosophy in that wonder that asks questions, and since all questions can be reduced to two types, he concluded to two intellectual operations. On the other hand, since it is clear from logic that all teaching and learning consists in finding and verifying a middle term, he sought the middle term that would bring together sense data and primary concepts. For just as in an explanatory syllogism the middle term is the reason why a predicate is added to a subject, similarly in the genesis of primary concepts, which are not predicated of anything else, a middle term is the form or the cause of being or the quiddity because of which the existence of such a substance is attributed to this particular matter. (Fs)

583b One can only marvel at his discovery of rational psychology. Understanding is our soul's 'proper act, perfectly demonstrating its power and its nature' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 88, a. 2, ad 3m). But acts of the soul are known only through their objects (ibid. q. 87, a. 3 a), and the object proper to the act of understanding is the 'because of which' that is discerned in the phantasm and grounds a concept. (Fs)

583c One can only marvel at his discovery of hylomorphism. Just as the intelligible species is to the phantasm in which it shines forth, so is substantial form to prime matter. Aristotle did not state that all material things were composed of form and matter because he had perceived a form or quiddity in each and every sensible object; rather, because he had thoroughly understood the nature of human inquiry and intelligence, he came to the conclusion that material things were humanly knowable insofar as they consisted of two elements, one material, known by the senses, and the other formal, known through the intellect. For this reason, no matter how much human knowledge advances, it will always progress by means of sense and intellect and therefore always know a thing constituted by matter and form. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Species (eidos) 1: forma, universale; sp.: impressa, expressa; Akt d. Vestehens folgt auf die Form, kommt aber nicht von ihr -> intellectus agens + phantasma = esse sequitur forma, aber Seinsakt (eg: forma dat esse)

Kurzinhalt: Therefore, just as a finite act of existence does not come from the form which limits it but from something else, similarly a finite act of understanding comes not from the form which it follows but from something else, namely, the agent intellect and ...

Textausschnitt: 587c The Latin for the Greek word eidos is species, whose two principal meanings are 'form' and 'universal.' 'It must be noted, however, that no matter, whether common or individual, in itself pertains to "species" taken as form. But insofar as "species" is taken as the universal - for example, as when we say that 'man' is a species - the common matter pertains per se to the species, but not the individual matter in which the nature of the species is received' (In VII Metaphys., lect. 9, § 1473).

587d There is a well-known distinction between the impressed and the expressed intelligible species which, though not explicitly made by St Thomas, nevertheless is based on his writings. (Fs)

587e In Summa theologiae, 1, q. 84, aa. 3, 4, and 7, and q. 85, a. 2, he is referring to the impressed species. This is the species that is received and conserved in the possible intellect. It is received from the phantasm as an instrument of the agent intellect, and once received is the form according to which the intellect understands. Hence, in Avicenna's terminology it has the nature of an active potency and is a principle of action (understanding) and also a principle of the product or effect or term (inner word). But this does not in the least prevent this same species from being, according to Aristotelian terminology, a nature and first act and passive potency to receive the second act (understanding); and this reception of second act is also a passion, not in the proper sense but in a general sense.1 Thus, '... as existence follows upon form, so understanding follows upon an intelligible species' (ibid. q. 14, a. 4 c). '... understanding, which is related to intellect in act in the same way that existence (esse) is related to being in act' (ibid. q. 34, a. 1, ad 2m). Therefore, just as a finite act of existence does not come from the form which limits it but from something else, similarly a finite act of understanding comes not from the form which it follows but from something else, namely, the agent intellect and phantasm. Finally, this impressed and conserved species is not that which is understood, except when the intellect reflects upon itself and its act (ibid. q. 85, a. 2; see also q. 87). (Fs; tblStw: Relationen) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt des Verstehens 6 - Quidditas, Washeit; Universalien (2 Arten: Verstand - Sinnesvermögen); getrennte Substanzen: Form ohne Materie; visio beata

Kurzinhalt: Further, just as a separate substance is known differently from the way a man is known, it also knows in a different way. For since it is not sensible, it cannot have either senses or phantasms or an understanding of species shining in phantasms.

Textausschnitt: 583d Finally, one must marvel at the way he conceived the notion of separate substances. He recognized that the nature of separate substances and the nature of man were two quite different questions. The quiddity of man is that because of which 'this' pertains to the existence of a man, where 'this' denotes either the sensible properties of a man or something manifested through them. But such a 'this' cannot be found in a separate substance, since a separate substance is neither sensible nor material (In VII Metaphys., lect. 17, §1669). And since he had already proven that nothing universal subsists, he concluded that a separate substance was a form without matter. Further, just as a separate substance is known differently from the way a man is known, it also knows in a different way. For since it is not sensible, it cannot have either senses or phantasms or an understanding of species shining in phantasms. Therefore, in immaterial beings the understander and the understood are one and the same, and their act of understanding is an understanding of understanding (In XII Metaphys., lect. 11, §§2613, 2617, 2620). (Fs) (notabene)

585a But beware of an illusion. Not without a lengthy inquiry and wearisome labor do we come to know the quiddity of a thing. For it is not by some marvelous intuition but by thinking and reasoning that we arrive at understanding and uttering an inner word. Thus St. Thomas:

... when I want to conceive the intelligibility of a stone, it is necessary that I come to it by a process of reasoning; and so it is in all other things that are understood by us, except perhaps in the case of first principles, which, since they are known simply, are known at once without any discursive reasoning process. Therefore as long as the intellect is thrown this way and that in a process of reasoning, its formation is not yet finished, not until it conceives the intelligibility of the thing perfectly; and only then does it have the intelligibility of the complete thing, and only then does it have the intelligibility of the word. And that is why in our soul we have thinking, by which is meant the discursive process of inquiry, and we have a word, which is now formed according to the perfect contemplation of the truth.. [Super Ioannem, c. 1, lect. 1)

585b We certainly do not know by what sort of reasoning St Thomas arrived at the understanding of stone. But he spoke in the same way about the difficulty of understanding the nature of the human soul (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 87, a. 1 c), and it is evident from Summa contra Gentiles, 2, cc. 46-90, how he labored to come to know its quiddity. Also, how highly he valued a definition is clear from the following texts. (Fs)

De veritate, q. 2, a. 7, ad 5m: '... whoever knows a definition knows potentially the statements that are demonstrated through the definition.'

Ibid. q. 20, a. 5 c: 'Any given thing is understood when its definition is known ... However, the definition of any power is taken from those things to which this power extends itself. Thus, if the soul of Christ knew everything to which the power of God extended itself, he would comprehend completely the power of God; and this is quite impossible.'

585b From this you can understand why St Thomas identified the beatific vision with knowing God's essence (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12), and how he was able to conclude that man has a natural desire for the beatific vision because he naturally seeks to know what God is (ibid. 1-2, q. 3, a. 8 c). (Fs) (notabene)

587a What leads many astray is the opinion of those who hold that universals are known only through the intellect, and therefore whenever they come to know a universal, they immediately think they have understood something. But there are two universals: one is that which is uttered because a 'why' has been grasped; the other is the universal in a particular individual, which is apprehended by some sensory faculty:

It is clear that the singular is sensed properly and per se, but sense is in a certain way also of the universal. For it knows Callias, not only as Callias, but also as this man; and similarly it knows Socrates as this man. And so it is that given such preceding sense knowledge, the intellective soul can consider man in each of them. But if it were the case that sense apprehends only what pertains to particularity and that it in no way along with this apprehends the universal in the particular, it would not be possible that from sense apprehension there would be caused in us a knowledge of universals (In II Post, anal, lect. 20; see also Summa theologiae, 1, q. 78, a. 4 c, where the evaluative ability in animals is compared to the cogitative power in a human being.)

587b Those, therefore, who claim to understand because somehow or other they perceive a universal are absolutely wrong. Take, for example, the case of the circle: those who know perfectly well the external shape, the Gestalt, of a circle yet have never thought about why a circle is necessarily round have really not progressed beyond the operations of their senses. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Species expressa: Wort, conceptio, Definition, intentio intellecta, ratio, Idee

Kurzinhalt: It is 'word' inasmuch as it is directly signified by outer words ... It is called 'conception,' 'concept,' 'conceived' inasmuch as it originates from the act of understanding... 'Idea': What the meaning (ratio) is in speculative matters, the idea is ...

Textausschnitt: 589a What later authors termed 'expressed species' St Thomas calls (1) word, (2) concept, (3) definition or proposition, (4) the intention understood, (5) meaning, what is meant (ratio),1 (6) idea, (7) form arrived at and conceived and formulated2 by an act of understanding. (Fs)

589b It is 'word' inasmuch as it is directly signified by outer words, as in Summa thologiae, 1, q. 34, a. 1 and passim, although outer words derive their ability to signify from inner words (De veritate, q. 4, a. 1, ad 7m). (Fs)

591a It is called 'conception,' 'concept,' 'conceived' inasmuch as it originates from the act of understanding. 'It is of the essence of the concept of the heart that it proceed from another, that is, from the knowledge of the one conceiving' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 34, a. 1 c). '[T]he conception is the effect of the act of understanding ... something expressed by the knowledge of the mind' (De veritate, q. 4, a. 2 c). 'But neither does the word arise from our intellect except insofar as it exists in act; but as soon as intellect exists in act, the word is conceived in it' (Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 14, ¶3, §3499). 'For this intelligible reality [God] is the same reality as the understanding intellect, an emanation of which is the conceived Word' (ibid. 4, c. 11, ¶14, §3474); and in other places. (Fs)

591b 'Definition' and 'proposition'3 refer to the division of both words (De veritate, q. 3, a. 2; q. 4, a. 2; De potentia, q. 8, a. 1; q. 9, a. 5; Quaestiones quodlibetales, 5, a. 9; Super Ioannem, c. 1, lect. 1) and conceptions (for example, De veritate, q. 11, a. 1 c: '... the first conceptions of intellect, which are known immediately by the light of agent intellect ... whether they be compound, as first principles, or simple, such as the concept of being ...'). (Fs)

591c The intention understood is distinguished from the thing understood (Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 11, ¶6, §3466). A word is 'that which is understood,' 'interiorly understood,' 'that which is actually considered by intellect' (De veritate, q. 4, a. 1), 'that at which the operation of our intellect terminates, which is what is understood, what is called the conception of the intellect' (ibid. a. 2), '... the product of the intellect, but through it the intellect comes to knowledge of the external thing' (ibid. q. 3, a. 2 a). 'This is what is first and per se understood, namely, what the intellect conceives within itself concerning the thing it has understood, whether that concept be a definition or a proposition ..." (Depotentia, q. 9, a. 5). '... the reason that the intellect forms in itself the conception of the thing is this, that it might know the thing understood' (ibid. q. 8, a. 1 a). '... the intellect ... forms a word for this purpose, that it might understand the thing' (Quaestiones quodlibetales, 5, a. 9, ad im). ' ... in [the word] expressed and formed it sees the nature of the understood thing' (Super Ioannem, c. 1, lect. 1); and in other places. (Fs)

591d 'Meaning, what is meant' (ratio): 'The meaning that a noun signifies is the definition of the thing' (In IV Metaphys., lect. 16, §733). 'White and black are outside the mind; but what is meant by these terms is only in the mind' (In IV Metaphys., lect. 4, § 1230). 'There are two ways in which scientific knowledge is of something. In the first and principal way scientific knowledge is of universals upon which it is established. In another, secondary way, and, as it were, by a kind of reflection, scientific knowledge is of those things to which these meanings belong ... (Fs)

593a For a knower uses a universal meaning both as a thing known and as a medium of knowing' (In Boet. De Trin., q. 5, a. 2, ad 4m; or lect. 2, q. 1, a. 2 ad 4m).1 (Fs)

593b 'Idea': What the meaning (ratio) is in speculative matters, the idea is in practical matters. 'The idea of the thing done is in the mind of the doer as that which is understood; but not as the species by which it is understood, which is the form bringing the intellect to act' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 15, a. 2 c). See the next paragraph, which is also about ideas. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Form: (auf 2 Weisen im Intellekt): Prinzip - Term des Verstehens; species - phantasma - intellectus (Beispiel: Farbe, Sehen - phantasma, Intellekt); species im phantasma (Warnung); Unfehlbarkeit des Intellekts; Wende zum - Reflexion über phantasma

Kurzinhalt: ... no intelligible species, as strictly spiritual, is or can be formally in a phantasm. But a species can be said to be in a phantasm virtually, both inasmuch as a phantasm is an instrument by which a species is impressed upon the possible intellect ...

Textausschnitt: 593c 'Form': 'There are two ways in which form can be in the intellect. In the first way, it is that which is the principle of the act of understanding, as the form of the one understanding inasmuch as he understands; this is the likeness of the thing understood in the one understanding. In the second way, it is the term of the act of understanding, as an architect through understanding devises the form of a house. And since this form is devised through an act of understanding and is, as it were, produced through that act, it cannot be a principle of the act of understanding as something pre-existing by which understanding takes place, but is rather that by which, when it is understood, the one understanding operates' (De veritate, q. 3, a. 2). (Fs; tblStw: Form) (notabene)

593f To understand this, consider the relation that exists between a phantasm that is properly disposed and an intelligible species. A phantasm is to the species not as its total and complete cause but rather, in a way, as the matter of the cause (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 84, a. 6 a). On the other hand, the species is to a phantasm as cause of the matter, that is, just as the form or the quod quid erat esse by which the matter comes to be something or to be a substance (In VII Metaphys., lect. 17, §1668). Therefore, just as natural dispositions induce a natural form in the matter, so the dispositions represented in a phantasm in the order of intentional existence are as instruments in the production of the intelligible species in the possible intellect. Moreover, just as from a consideration of the dispositions that emerge in matter a person can understand the form induced from those dispositions, so in like manner one can understand in one's duly disposed phantasm the species of a thing similar to the species for whose production the phantasm is disposed. (Fs) (notabene)

595a This virtual, dispositive presence of a species in the phantasm is entirely sufficient. First of all, it is sufficient that the phantasm be an instrument in the production of the species, for an instrument is such that it produces an effect beyond its proper proportion. Also, it is sufficient that the phantasm be the ground in which the species shines forth and is understood; for 'intellect' is from intus legere, 'to gather inwardly,' that is, to grasp the inner form and essence of a thing in externals apprehended by the senses. This can be illustrated in another way. Just as colors on a wall that are actually being seen are identical with the faculty of sight rendered in act and yet are not seen in one's eyes but on the wall, so in a similar way species that are actually understood are one with the possible intellect rendered in act and yet are understood not in the intellect but in the phantasm. See In IIIDe anima, lect. 2, §§592-93, 595; Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 59, ¶[14, §1366. (Fs; tblStw: Beispiel)

595b With regard to the above, three points should be noted. (Fs)

First, do not confuse this understanding of the species in the phantasm with knowing the species received and conserved in the possible intellect. For the species shining in the phantasm, the intelligible in the sensible, the quiddity existing in corporeal matter, is the proper object of our intellect, and therefore our intellect understands nothing whatever unless it turns to the phantasm. But the species received in the possible intellect is not known except when the intellect reflects upon itself (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 85, a. 2 c.) and in its inquiry proceeds from its object to its act, from acts to habits, from habits to potencies, and from potencies to the essence of the soul (ibid. q. 87). (Fs) (notabene)

595c Second, note that the intellect is infallible primarily and per se with respect to a quiddity or species, and secondarily with respect to other things as more or less closely related to a quiddity (Aristotle, De anima, III, 6, 430a 26 - 430b 30; In III De anima, lect. II, §§746-63). For what is understood in the phantasm is indivisible and simple, and therefore it is either truly understood or not at all, as is the case with separate substances (In III De anima, lect. II, §763; In IX Metaphys., lect. 11, §§1904-09). From this infallibility there follows infallibility (1) in defining, as long as the concept really proceeds from the understanding, (2) in predicating, as long as what are imagined accord with what are sensed, and (3) in understanding primary principles, as long as two intelligibles that have been separately understood coalesce into one intelligible likewise understood in the sensible (see Theological Studies 8:1 [1947] 36-46 [Verbum 61-71]; P. Hoenen, 'De origine primorum principiorum scientiae,' Gregorianum 14 [1933] 153-84). (Fs) (notabene)

595d Third, one must avoid the common error of confusing the intellect's turning to the phantasm with its reflection upon the phantasm. Turning to the phantasm is necessary for it to know its proper object, the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter (Summa theologiae, i, q. 84, a. 7 a). But reflection upon the phantasm is done in order to know the indirect object of the intellect, which is the singular already known through sense and imagination but not known by the intellect except indirectly and by this sort of reflection (ibid. q. 86, a. 1 a). The possibility and basis for this indirect reflective knowledge lies in the fact that the intelligible species is linked to and has a certain continuity with the singular phantasm, since the species itself is understood in the phantasm. Accordingly, the intellect understands directly the species illuminated in the phantasm, while indirectly it knows the singular represented through the phantasm. (See Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, 1, q. 86, a. 1; Aristotle, De anima, in, 4, 429b 10-21; Aquinas, In IIIDe anima, lect. 8, §§705-18; Theological Studies 10:1 [1949] 20-23 [Verbum 169-73].)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt d. Vestehens; Notwendigkeit des Wortes 1; erstes Objekt d. Intellekt: Natur eines materiellen Seins (nicht species im intellectus possibilis); erstrebtes Objekt d. Intellekt.: Sein (per se gewusst); Erkenntnis von Prinzipien

Kurzinhalt: Note here that this first object is not the species received in the possible intellect ... nor the act of understanding, nor a definition or inner word, but an external reality, the nature of some material thing ...

Textausschnitt: 597a There is one object that activates our intellect in this present state of existence and another more extensive object to which our intellect tends, and this is why it is necessary for us to form inner words. (Fs)

598b That which moves our intellect in the present state is its proper object, the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 84, a. 7 c), which is known primarily and per se (ibid. q. 85, a. 8 a), which is known first (ibid. q. 87, a. 3 c), and is the first thing understood by us in our present state (ibid. q. 88, a. 3 c). (Fs)

598c Note here that this first object is not the species received in the possible intellect (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 85, a. 2 c), nor the act of understanding, nor a definition or inner word, but an external reality, the nature of some material thing (ibid. q. 87, a. 3 c). And since this object moving [the intellect] is restricted to that to which the phantasm stands as the matter of the cause, therefore 'in this present state of life, neither through the possible intellect nor through the agent intellect can we understand immaterial substances in themselves' (ibid. q. 88, a. 1 c.) and 'much less can [the human intellect] understand the essence of the uncreated substance' (ibid. a. 3 c). (Fs) (notabene)

598d But the object to which the intellect tends as to its end is not any genus of things but is being in its widest extension. The intellect is that which can become all things, and 'all' is unrestricted (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 79, a. 7 a). This object, since it is founded upon the very nature of the intellect, is known by us naturally and per se (Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 83, ¶31, §1678) and cannot be unknown to us (De veritate, q. 11, a. 1, ad 3m), but is known immediately by the light of the agent intellect (ibid. c). (Fs)

599a We can come to understand the meaning of 'known naturally' both from principles that are known naturally and from our own experience. For principles that are known naturally are grounded upon the meaning of being (Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 83, ¶31, §1678; Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 66, a. 5, ad 4m); a habit regarding them 'is, in a way, innate in our minds by the light of the agent intellect' (Super II Sententiarum, d. 24, q. 2, a. 3 sol; De veritate, q. 8, a. 15 c.) and is more comparable to an infused than to an acquired habit (Super III Sententiarum, d. 23, q. 3, a. 2, ad im). This is confirmed by experience. Children are neither taught nor do they learn to ask, Is it? and Why? about everything; when they do so, they are asking about being with respect to its existence and its essence. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt d. Vestehens; Notwendigkeit des Wortes 2; Objekt als Beweger - als Ziel: vierfache Notwendigkeit d. Wortes (weil das Ziel d. Intellekts weiter ist als das O. als Beweger); Unmöglichkeit des Beweises d. Wortes in Gott

Kurzinhalt: For we have established the necessity of a word in us because of the fact that the object of our intellect as its end is broader than the object that moves it.

Textausschnitt: 7 The Necessity for the Word

597a There is one object that activates our intellect in this present state of existence and another more extensive object to which our intellect tends, and this is why it is necessary for us to form inner words. (Fs)

598b That which moves our intellect in the present state is its proper object, the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 84, a. 7 c), which is known primarily and per se (ibid. q. 85, a. 8 a), which is known first (ibid. q. 87, a. 3 c), and is the first thing understood by us in our present state (ibid. q. 88, a. 3 c). (Fs)

598c Note here that this first object is not the species received in the possible intellect (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 85, a. 2 c), nor the act of understanding, nor a definition or inner word, but an external reality, the nature of some material thing (ibid. q. 87, a. 3 c). And since this object moving [the intellect] is restricted to that to which the phantasm stands as the matter of the cause, therefore 'in this present state of life, neither through the possible intellect nor through the agent intellect can we understand immaterial substances in themselves' (ibid. q. 88, a. 1 c.) and 'much less can [the human intellect] understand the essence of the uncreated substance' (ibid. a. 3 c). (Fs) (notabene)
598d But the object to which the intellect tends as to its end is not any genus of things but is being in its widest extension. The intellect is that which can become all things, and 'all' is unrestricted (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 79, a. 7 a). This object, since it is founded upon the very nature of the intellect, is known by us naturally and per se (Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 83, ¶31, §1678) and cannot be unknown to us (De veritate, q. 11, a. 1, ad 3m), but is known immediately by the light of the agent intellect (ibid. c). (Fs)

599a We can come to understand the meaning of 'known naturally' both from principles that are known naturally and from our own experience. For principles that are known naturally are grounded upon the meaning of being (Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 83, ¶31, §1678; Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 66, a. 5, ad 4m); a habit regarding them 'is, in a way, innate in our minds by the light of the agent intellect' (Super II Sententiarum, d. 24, q. 2, a. 3 sol; De veritate, q. 8, a. 15 c.) and is more comparable to an infused than to an acquired habit (Super III Sententiarum, d. 23, q. 3, a. 2, ad im). This is confirmed by experience. Children are neither taught nor do they learn to ask, Is it? and Why? about everything; when they do so, they are asking about being with respect to its existence and its essence. (Fs) (notabene)

599b From this difference between the object moving the intellect and the object as its end, a fourfold necessity for the word becomes clear. (Fs)

First, since both God and separate substances fall within being taken in its broadest extent and yet do not move our intellect in our present state of life, we need inner words as means in which to know them analogically. Hence, we do know God in this life inasmuch as from his effects we know 'that this statement which we form about God when we say, "God exists," is true' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 3, a. 4, ad 2m). (Fs) (notabene)

599b Second, it is proper to the intellect to apprehend many things as a unity. But a multitude of material objects cannot be represented simultaneously in a phantasm, and therefore in order to achieve a philosophic or scientific synthesis we need inner words to express many things together. (Fs) (notabene)

599c Third, material things consist not only of form or essence or quiddity but also of another principle called esse or existence. This principle is known in the second intellectual operation when we answer the question, Is it? But the question, Is it? is not properly put unless we first define what it is we are asking about, and therefore the forming of inner words is necessary for us to know material things as to their quiddity and their existence. (Fs) (notabene)

599d Fourth, the proper object of our intellect is the quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter. But unless we form an inner word, only the quiddity or nature will be known to us directly through our intellect, and only the corporeal matter through our senses or through a phantasm. But the requirement is that a thing, a unity in itself, become known through one intellectual knowing, and for this the forming of a word is necessary. St Thomas indicates this: 'Therefore what is primarily and per se understood is that which the intellect conceives within itself about the object understood, that is, either a definition or a proposition ...' (De potentia, q. 9, a. 5 c.) (Fs) (notabene)

599e From all that we have been saying, it is immediately evident that by the light of reason alone we cannot demonstrate the existence of the Word in God. For we have established the necessity of a word in us because of the fact that the object of our intellect as its end is broader than the object that moves it. But God is neither moved by anything nor tends to an end. He himself is by identity both existence itself and understanding itself. And because he perfectly understands himself, he perfectly understands both his power and all that lies within the scope of his power. Nor is there within him any discursive reasoning, but in one act and one intuition he comprehends both himself and all other things (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14). For this reason, then, we say that only by faith do we hold that there is a Word in God (De veritate, q. 4, a. 2, ad 5m; De potentia, q. 8, a. 1, ad 12m; Summa theologiae, 1, q. 32, a. 1, ad 2m). (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt d. Verstehens, inneres Wort 1; Illumination, phantasma -> Verstehen; 1., 2. Tätigkeit d. Intellekts: verschiedene Objekte; Beispiele: Mondfinsternis, animal rationale; Verstehen, actus perfecti, energeia (wie: Hören, Sehen, Wollen)

Kurzinhalt: ... it may perhaps not be so easy to see why the same intellectual operation, whether the first or the second, has two different objects, the object of the act of understanding and the object of an act of uttering an inner word.

Textausschnitt: 17 The Act of Understanding and the Uttering of an Inner Word

603a The operations of the soul are distinguished by their respective objects (De anima, II, 4, 415a 14-22; In II De anima, lect. 6, §§304-308; Summa theologiae, 1, q. 77, a. 3 c; q. 87, a. 3 c). Accordingly, the act of understanding, or insight (intelligere), and the uttering of an inner word (dicere) are different from each other inasmuch as their objects are different. (Fs)

603b An object can be either that which moves something else, or an immanently produced term, or an end or goal. (Fs)

603c There are two objects that move us. We are moved to eliciting a direct act of understanding by the illumination of a phantasm, and in that phantasm we grasp a species that shines forth, or a cause of being, or a quiddity, as we explained above in appendix 2, §3. We are moved to eliciting a reflective act of understanding by sufficient evidence as sufficient; and we arrive at this act when we have resolved what we have conceived to its principles, namely, sense, self-evident principles, and the light of the intellect itself (see Theological Studies 8:1 (1947) 36-52 [Verbum 61-78]).1 (Fs) (notabene)

605a Again, there are two terms that are produced immanently. When we have directly grasped a species or cause of being or quiddity, we inwardly conceive, or utter, the definition, the meaning [ratio], of a thing; and when we have by reflection grasped the sufficiency of evidence as such, we inwardly conceive or utter a proposition.2

605b Finally, since we define in order to judge and judge in order to know truth and being, the end of our entire intellectual operation is being, the formal object of the intellect. (Fs)

605c With regard to the distinction of these objects, some things are quite clear while others need some explanation. The distinction between the first operation, which has to do with the question, What is it? and the second operation, which answers the question, Is it? is quite clear. Also quite clear is the distinction between terms that are immanently produced and the end for which they are produced; for we inwardly formulate definitions and propositions in order that through them, as means-in-which, we may come to know being. But it may perhaps not be so easy to see why the same intellectual operation, whether the first or the second, has two different objects, the object of the act of understanding and the object of an act of uttering an inner word. (Fs)

605d The difference between these two is that the object of an act of understanding is that from which and because of which the object of the act of uttering emerges. In the case of the second intellectual operation this is easy to see. Why do we judge? Because we grasp that there is sufficient evidence to make such a judgment. We surely grasp the sufficiency of the evidence before we make our judgment. But the sufficient evidence that is grasped is certainly different from the judgment that the sufficiency of evidence enables us to make. (Fs) (notabene)

605e But the reason is exactly the same in the case of the first intellectual operation. What is a lunar eclipse? It is the darkening of the moon caused by the shadow of the earth, which has come between the light of the sun and the moon which it illumines. But the interiorly conceived and uttered definition of an eclipse is surely not the same as the realization by the intellect that the moon will necessarily be darkened if its light from the sun is blocked. What is man? A rational animal. But why do we say 'rational animal'? Granted that animal is something we see and hear; rational, however, is something that is neither seen nor heard. But what we cannot know by our senses we could never express by an inner word unless we somehow grasped it by our intellect; and what this grasp is, we have sufficiently explained. Present in the sensible data through which we come to know man there are indications of rationality. These indications are the matter of the cause, while the rationality which they point to is the cause of the matter, that is, the formal principle by reason of which these sensible data are the sensible data of a human being, and the cause of being by virtue of which this particular matter comes to exist as human. And yet it is one thing to discern rationality in external indications, and quite another to say 'rational animal'; and again, it is one thing to understand an intellectual soul being in such a body, and quite another to define or utter that composite of soul and body. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Akt d. Verstehens, inneres Wort 2; Unterschied in Terminologie: Avicenna, Aristoteles; Sein als bewegendes Objekt?; visio beata: esse als Beweger und Ziel d. Intellekts

Kurzinhalt: Now, certainly I would by no means deny that what moves the senses or the intellect is being. But the being that moves a sense faculty is not being in its full extension but only a certain kind of being, such as color or sound ...

Textausschnitt: 607a There is, however, another difficulty, one that is metaphysical rather than psychological, in fact, more semantic than metaphysical. For understanding is an act or operation in one sense, whereas defining or uttering an inner word is an act or operation in another sense. Understanding is an act, second act, an act of what is complete (actus perfecti), energeia, like seeing and hearing and willing. But defining is a kind of making; when we utter interiorly we form and produce an inner word, either a simple inner word, such as a definition, or a compound inner word, a proposition. In Avicenna's terminology the intelligible species received in the possible intellect is to the act of understanding as the principle of an action, the formal principle of action; and the same species is to the uttered word as the principle of something done [principium operati), the principle of an effect. But in Aristotle's terminology active potency is not contrary to act but rather is grounded in it (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 25, a. 1, ad im); hence, the potency to utter an inner word is not contrary to the act of understanding but is grounded in it. Besides, in the same terminology, since a making is the effect produced considered as being from the maker, whereas a passion is this effect considered as being in the product, it follows that uttering is the inner word itself considered as being from the act of understanding, and being uttered is that word considered as being in the possible intellect. Moreover, according to Aristotle's terminology as slightly modified by St Thomas, to utter would regard the act of understanding itself as related to the word produced, while being uttered would regard the inner word inasmuch as the word results from the act of understanding. Finally, in Avicenna's terminology the relationship between understanding and the inner word is that the word is the term of the action of understanding.1

609a Here one might raise the objection that the formal object of the intellect is being, and that since there is motion from being, therefore being is a motive object and not an object as an end. (Fs)

609b Now, certainly I would by no means deny that what moves the senses or the intellect is being. But the being that moves a sense faculty is not being in its full extension but only a certain kind of being, such as color or sound or flavor, and the like. Likewise, the being which moves our intellect in its present state of union with a body is not being in its full extension but only corporeal being; hence, we cannot know separate substances except by way of certain analogies (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 88), and the proper object of our intellect is defined as a quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter (ibid. q. 84, a. 7 c). Still, those who reach the beatific vision behold the very act of existence itself and in it all other things, according to the degree of perfection of their vision; then, perhaps, it could be said that being in its full extension is not only the end but also the mover of the created intellect. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Intellektuelle, materielle Emanation; "intelligibile" (2 Bedeutungen); Gott -> Sohn -> Geist (eine Realität; Ggs: Hitze als Ursache - Erhitztes als Wirkung); Verstehen -> inneres Wort -> Urteil -> Wille (Bejahung des Guten)

Kurzinhalt: ... in the same way the act of understanding is really different from the proceeding inner word. Besides, if this duality between the principle and the resultant did not exist, the principle could not be a cause and the resultant could not be an effect..

Textausschnitt: 18 Intellectual Emanation

609c There are two points that should be especially noted with regard to intellectual emanation: first, the fact that 'the higher a particular nature is, the more that which emanates from it will be intimately (one) with it' (Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 11, ¶1, §3461), so that if there is an emanation in God, that which emanates would be consubstantial with that from which it emanates; second, that although the one who emanates and the one from whom he emanates are one and the same substance, nevertheless there is still an emanation in the true and proper sense. (Fs)

609d The first point is made by St Thomas in the passage just quoted (Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 11, ¶1, §3461; see also Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 1, ad 2m). The second will become clear insofar as the difference between intellectual emanation and material or sensible emanation is understood; so our task now is to try to acquire that understanding.1 (Fs)

611a Note, first, that the Latin word 'intelligibile' can be taken in two ways: in the first way, even material and sensible realities are in some way considered intelligible, inasmuch as they are produced by God's knowledge (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 8 c.) and are known by us through understanding; in the second way, intelligible realities (intelligibilia) are contradistinguished from material and sensible things. It is in this latter sense that 'the human intellect is in the order of intelligible things (intelligibilium) as a being that is only in potency, just as prime matter is in the order of sensible things' (ibid. q. 87, a. 1 c). It is in this exclusive sense that we speak of an emanation as 'intellectual' (Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 11, ¶8, §3468) or (in Latin) 'intelligibilis' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 1 c), since the image of God is in a human being only with respect to the mind (ibid. q. 93, a. 6).2 (Fs)
611b Next we must distinguish between what among created things is common to both intellectual emanation and material or sensible emanation and, on the other hand, what is proper to intellectual emanation alone. (Fs)

611c Now, in created things, an element common to all emanation is that the originating principle of emanation is really different from that which emanates from it. The heat of a heater is really different from the heat of that which is heated; in the same way the act of understanding is really different from the proceeding inner word. Besides, if this duality between the principle and the resultant did not exist, the principle could not be a cause and the resultant could not be an effect; for since nothing can be a cause of itself, no causality in the proper sense exists without duality. Hence, if we are to get some understanding of the divine processions we shall have to go to something other than causality; for although in God the Son proceeds from the Father and the Spirit proceeds from both, the three Persons are one God, one substance, one reality. (Fs) (notabene)

611d Note, therefore, that it is proper to an intellectual emanation that the inner word is not only an effect produced by the act of understanding but also that it can only result and does only result insofar as the reason why it should be produced is grasped in an act of understanding.3 We can only conceive a definition and only do actually conceive it insofar as we understand the because of, the why, of the thing to be defined. Again, we can only affirm or deny that something is inasmuch as we grasp that there is sufficient evidence for that affirmation or negation; there is no other way to make a rational judgment. Finally, since the will is defined as a rational or intellectual appetite, we can similarly in no way will something unless we affirm the reason why we are willing it, namely, goodness. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Emanation; Unterschied: intellektuelle - materielle E. (intelligibile: in potencia - in actu usw.); geschaffener Intellekt: Teilhabe am ungeschaffenen Licht: potens omnia facere et fieri; Norm: Intelligibilität: Wort -> Urteil -> Liebe, Wille; Licht

Kurzinhalt: 'The higher a particular nature is, the more that which emanates from it will be intimately (one) with it.' Think of a nature that is most perfect in every way and you will come to the conclusion that in it the principle of emanation and that which ...

Textausschnitt: 613a The disparity between these intellectual emanations and the other material or sensible emanations can be seen in the nature and manner of their emanating. Every created being is an outward imitation of divine perfection. Other created things manifest some particular aspect of the divine excellence and operate of their own accord according to particular laws that are appropriate to each. But the created intellect is a participated likeness of uncreated Light. Since this uncreated Light is the source and origin of all natures and all laws, even the created intellect has a certain omnipotence about it, whence it is said to be potens omnia facere et fieri - able to make and to become all things. Nor is the operation of the created intellect controlled by any particular law, whether implanted in it by its very nature or imposed upon it from without: the intellect itself is, as it were, a transcendental law unto itself. What are generally regarded as laws of the intellect, such as the principles of identity, of noncontradiction, of the excluded middle, or of sufficient reason, express no rule, whether particular or specific or generic, but rather state the conditions of possibility of any rule or law. But although the created intellect is in some sense capable of everything, and although it is not controlled by any determinate law, nevertheless it does not operate by whim or by chance. Its supreme norm is that it operate only in accordance with an intelligibility that it has grasped; indeed, the whole force and efficacy of intellectual operation and emanation lies in this, that it is from this apprehended intelligibility and in accordance with it that both words in the intellect and acts of the will proceed. An inner word proceeds from grasping a quiddity; a judgment proceeds from grasping the evidence; an act of love proceeds from grasping goodness. (Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (11/10/10): Hier also: Akt der Liebe = Akt des Willens. Der Willen geht hervor im Erfassen der Gutheit.

613b These relations between principle and resultant are of an altogether different nature from the relations between a material cause and a material effect. These latter relations can be understood, and so are said to be intelligible in potency; the former, however, belong to one who understands precisely as understanding, and so are by their very nature intelligible in act. The latter are understood according to a particular law; the former emerge as the primary principle of all law. The latter are verified in material or sensible realities, not because these realities themselves understand anything but because they were made by some intelligence; the former, on the other hand, come into being because their principle actually understands. (Fs) (notabene)

615a Let us now press on to our goal! 'The higher a particular nature is, the more that which emanates from it will be intimately (one) with it.' Think of a nature that is most perfect in every way and you will come to the conclusion that in it the principle of emanation and that which emanates are really identical. And from this identity you may further conclude that that emanation does not take place in the manner of efficient causality, since this supposes and requires a cause and an effect that are really distinct. Your final conclusion will be that it can be said truly and properly to be an emanation provided it is intellectual. For although the real identity here between the word and the principle of the word rules out efficient causality, one cannot argue that it denies that the inner word exists because of the act of understanding on the part of its principle. Likewise, although the real identity between the word that spirates love and that proceeding love itself rules out efficient causality, it cannot be demonstrated that it denies that that love exists because of the apprehended goodness of its principle. (Fs)

615b Now if all this is more or less understood, it is clear why human beings are said to be in the image of the Holy Trinity precisely wim respect to their minds. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Hauchung (spiration), Wort; Testsammlung: Thomas von Aquin

Kurzinhalt: There are many texts in which Aquinas states that love proceeds from a mental word... '... it belongs to the very essence of love that it does not proceed except from a conception of the intellect.'

Textausschnitt: 19 Spiration

614c There are many texts in which Aquinas states that love proceeds from a mental word. (Fs)
Super I Sententiarum, d. 11, q. 1, a. 1, ad 4m: '... the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Word the way love proceeds from a mental word.'

Super I Sententiarum, d. 27, q. 2, a. 1, sol.:'... since there can be two apprehensions, either of truth by itself or of truth as expanded to take in the good and the fitting - and this latter is a complete apprehension - hence there are two words, namely, of something pleasing that is set forth, a word that spirates love - and this is a complete word - and the word of something also that displeases ... or does not please.' See In III de anima, lect. 4, §§634-35. (Fs)

Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 24, ¶12, §3617: 'For love proceeds from a word, inasmuch as we cannot love anything unless we conceive it in a word of the heart.'

Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c.19, ¶8, §3564: 'But that something is in the will as what is loved is in the lover (means that) it has a certain relation to the conception by which intellect conceives it ... for nothing would be loved unless it were in some way known.'

614d De potentia, q. 9, a. 9, ad 3m (2nd ser.): '... for nothing can be loved whose word is not first conceived in the intellect; hence, the one who proceeds by way of the will must be from the one who proceeds by way of the intellect, and consequently is distinguished from that one.' See ibid. q. 10, a. 2 c; ad 2m; ad 7m; a. 4 c. (Fs)

617a De potentia, q. 10, a. 5 c: 'For it cannot be, nor can it be understood, that there is a love for something that has not first been conceived by the intellect; therefore, every love is from some word, when one is speaking of love in an intellectual nature.'
Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 3, ad 3m: '... it belongs to the very essence of love that it does not proceed except from a conception of the intellect.'

Summa theologiae, 1, q. 36, a. 2 c: 'It is necessary that love proceed from a word; for we do not love anything except inasmuch as we apprehend it in a mental conception. Accordingly, from this too it is clear that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Son.'

Compendium theologiae, c. 49: 'Similarly too, what is loved is in the one loving inasmuch as it is actually being loved. The fact that an object is actually loved proceeds from the lover's capacity to love, and also from the lovable good actually understood. Accordingly, the fact that the beloved is in the one loving proceeds from two principles: from the loving principle, and from an apprehended intelligible, which is the word that has been conceived concerning the lovable.'

De rationibus fidei ad Cantorem Antiochenum, c. 4: 'It is clear that we are able to love nothing with an intellectual and holy love that we do not actually conceive by means of the intellect. But the conception of the intellect is the word; hence, it is necessary that love come forth from the word. Now, we say that the Word of God is the Son; it is clear, then, that the Holy Spirit is from the Son.'

617b Here, then, is the clear teaching of St Thomas, from his Commentary on the Sentences to his Compendium of Theology. In agreement with this teaching are Augustine (in the passage referred to in the textbook, p. 112),1 Anselm, Godfrey of Fontaines, John of Naples (see Theological Studies 10 [1949] 379 [Verbum 212]), Cajetan (In Sum. theol. 1, q. 27, a. 3, §§IX-XI; Leonine edition, vol. iv, 312). Scotus in fact, having applied his doctrine of concurrent coordinate causes to the will, stated this conclusion: if the object conceived is related to love only as a necessary condition, then the Word is related to the Holy Spirit only as a necessary condition (Theological Studies 10 [1949] 379 [Verbum 212-13]). (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Hauchung, Wort; Unterschied: processio operati (Akt von Akt) - processio operationis (aus Potenz zu Akt); Akt d. Wortes -> Akt d. Willens (p. operati); Wille: 2 Beweger;

Kurzinhalt: ... whether the procession of love from a word is a processio operati. To this the answer would seem to be in the affirmative... that the apprehended object of desire moves the appetite, and that this apprehended object is an unmoved mover while ...

Textausschnitt: 617c One may ask, however, whether the procession of love from a word is a processio operati. To this the answer would seem to be in the affirmative. The distinction made in De veritate, q. 4, a. 2, ad 7m, consists in this, that a procession of an operation (processio operationis) is a procession of a perfection from or in that which is perfectible, while a processio operati is a procession of a perfection from a perfection. Again, a procession of an operation is a procession of an act from a potency, which cannot be admitted in God, but a processio operati is a procession of an act from an act, and it is at least not so clear that this is to be excluded from God. Therefore, if an act of willing comes either from the potency of willing or from a potency that has been disposed or informed by a habit, the procession is that of an operation; if, on the other hand, the act of willing comes from another second act, namely a word, the procession is a processio operati, for it is the procession of a perfection from a perfection, of an act from an act. (Fs) (notabene)

619a As to the manner in which love proceeds from a word, there is considerable confusion, since some assign the influence of the apprehended object of desire upon the appetite to final causality while others assign it to efficient causality. Cajetan (In Sum. theol, 1, q. 27, a. 3, §§IX-XI; Leonine edition, vol. IV, 312) holds this influence to be by way of efficient causality and refers to Averroes. John of St Thomas states, 'Final causality is real, as the real is contradistinguished from a conceptual being [ens rationis], not as the real is contradistinguished from the intentional ... which is an intentional motion, but which nevertheless truly exists in reality and produces a true effect in the will ..." (Joannis a Sancto Thoma Naturalis Philosophiae, 1, q. 13, a. 2, ad 3m [ed. Beato Reiser] Taurini [Turin]: Marietti, 1933, vol. 2, p. 281). Aristotle in De generations et corruptione (1, 7, 324b 14-15) distinguishes between an end and an agent (poietikon) and says that an end is an agent in a metaphorical sense only; hence his well-known statement about metaphorical motion from an apprehended object of desire. The significance of this statement may be gathered from the fact that it is this motion that is the effect of Aristotle's prime mover. (See In XII Metaphys., lect. 7, §§2519-22; Summa contra Gentiles, 1, c. 13, ¶29,. §108.) And if this motion is reduced to a mere metaphor, it needs nothing more than a metaphorical prime mover. (Fs)

619b As Aristotle distinguished between an end and a maker, so also Aquinas, along the same lines it seems, recognizes two influences upon the will, one by way of an agent and one by way of an end. The influence by way of an agent is exerted by God alone: it belongs to the creator of the will to impress forms upon the will, to infuse virtues in it, to change its dispositions, and to bring about an exercise of its act (Summa contra Gentiles, 3, c. 88, ¶5, §2641; De veritate, q. 22, a. 8; Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 9, a. 6; q. in, a. 2. See also Theological Studies 3/4 [1942] 537-41 [Grace and Freedom 98-104]). The influence by way of an end is exerted by the apprehended object of desire, which moves the appetite to a specification of its act by presenting an object to the will. (See, for example, Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 9, a. 1 c.)

621a It is abundantly clear that an apprehended object of desire is a true cause and not a mere condition. (Fs)

The only reason for hesitation on this point is Augustine's opinion that all the powers of the soul move themselves to all of their acts, an opinion which, as we have seen [appendix i, §8], has been wrongly foisted upon St Thomas. (Fs)

621b Aquinas constantly repeats Aristotle's doctrine that the apprehended object of desire moves the appetite, and that this apprehended object is an unmoved mover while the will is a moved mover. (Fs)

Nowhere in the writings of St Thomas will you find any other cause for the specification of the act of the will than the apprehended object of desire. (Fs)

621c What causes the specification of an act is not to be disregarded as being unimportant. For among the powers of the soul, only the will causes the exercise of both its own act and that of the other powers {Sutnma theologiae, 1-2, q. 17, a. 1; see also 1, q. 82, a. 4). (Fs)

Moreover, an end is in the highest degree a cause, and the first of causes; and yet, 'an end is not a cause except insofar as it moves an agent to act' (De potentia, q. 5, a. 1 c). (Fs)

621d For our present purpose, however, concerning the manner in which love proceeds from a word, the most important point to be attended to is intellectual emanation. The will is a rational, an intellectual, appetite. But love is good on account of the goodness of the object apprehended by the intellect. This dependence upon the intellect is more than just the relation between a material cause and a material or sensible effect; and it is not at all clear that there is no such dependence when the Love is so intimately related to the Speaker and the Word as to be in reality absolutely the same act with them. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: The Hervorgang (processio) der Liebe; Akt d. Verstehens -> term: inneres Wort; Akt d. Willens -> term: der Geliebte im Liebenden (John of St Thomas, aber nicht Thomas v. Aquin); Textstellen (bei Thomas)

Kurzinhalt: [Thomas] ... he neither explicitly nor implicitly holds that the beloved is in the lover because from the act of loving there proceeds a term that is distinct from that love itself.

Textausschnitt: 20 The Procession of Love

621e The procession of love can be understood in two ways: (1) love proceeds from the spirating inner word; (2) from the act of loving, from love, something else proceeds. (Fs) (notabene)
In the preceding section, the procession of love is understood in the first sense both by Cajetan [In Sum. theol, 1, q. 27, a. 3, §§ix-xiii, Leonine edition, vol. xv, 312-13) and by Ferrariensis (In C. Gent., 4, c.19, ¶¶iv-x, Leonine edition, vol. xv, (76-79)

621f The procession of love is understood in the second sense by John of St Thomas, who says, 'It is the express opinion of St Thomas that through an act of the will a term is produced by which the object loved is said to be in the will not as a likeness but as a pull or inclination' (Cursus theologicus, In Sum. theol, 1, q. 27; Disp. xii, a. 7, §4 [Ed. Ludovicus Vives; Parisiis, 1884], vol. iv, 142). John's point is that just as in the intellect the act of understanding produces a term, namely the inner word, so in the will the act of loving produces a term, namely the beloved in the lover. I find this opinion to be without foundation in the works of St Thomas and quite useless in elucidating his doctrine on the divine processions. (Fs) (notabene)

623a Although St Thomas clearly and expressly teaches that the object known is in the knower and the beloved is in the lover, he neither explicitly nor implicitly holds that the beloved is in the lover because from the act of loving there proceeds a term that is distinct from that love itself. Not explicitly, for there is no passage in which this is stated; nor implicitly, because he often implies that it is through love itself that the beloved is in the lover. (Fs)

623b Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 19, ¶7, §3563: 'But what is loved is within the one loving inasmuch as it is loved; love is an act of will; God's act of willing is God's own act of existence ... God's act of existence (esse), therefore, [is] in God's will through love.' In this passage the whole deduction proceeds without any mention of a distinct term produced by the act of loving. (Fs)

De malo, q. 6, a. 1, ad 13m: 'Love is said to transform the one loving into the beloved inasmuch as the one loving is moved by love toward the very thing that is loved.'

Compendium theologiae, c. 49: 'Similarly too, what is loved is in the one loving inasmuch as it is actually being loved. The fact that an object is actually loved proceeds from the lover's capacity to love, and also from the lovable good actually understood. Accordingly, the fact that the beloved is within the one loving proceeds from two principles: from the loving principle, and from an apprehended intelligible, which is the word that has been conceived concerning the lovable.' Once again the deduction proceeds without any mention and indeed with an implicit exclusion of any term produced by an act of loving. (Fs)

623c Besides, John's basic point is explicitly ruled out by St Thomas. John's point was that just as in the intellect there is a processio operati, there is likewise one within the will. Aquinas, however, wrote: 'There is this difference between intellect and will: the operation of the will terminates at things, in which there is good and evil; but the operation of the intellect terminates in the mind, in which there is the true and the false, as is said in Metaphysics vi [lect. 4, §1240]. Consequently, the will does not have anything going forth from itself, except what is in it after the manner of an operation; but the intellect has in itself something that goes forth from itself, not only after the manner of an operation, but also after the manner of a reality that is the term of the operation' (De veritate, q. 4, a. 2, ad 7m). (Fs) (notabene)

625a Note that it is wrong to leave out the word 'except' in this passage, although this is done in several editions; see Irénée Chevalier, 'Notule de critique textuelle thomiste: De veritate, Q. iv, Art. 11, Ad 7,' Divus Thomas (Piacenza) 41 (1938) 63-68; J.-A. Robilliard, review of Penido, 'Gloses sur la procession ...' Bulletin thomiste 5 (1937-39) 135 39.

625b Finally, John's opinion is not at all helpful for elucidating St Thomas's teaching on the procession of the Holy Spirit. For according to that opinion, the Holy Spirit would not be proceeding Love itself but rather a term proceeding from love. But St Thomas clearly teaches that the Holy Spirit is proceeding Love. (Fs)

625c Summa theologiae, 1, q. 37, a. 1, sed contra: 'The Holy Spirit himself is Love.'

Summa theologiae, 1, q. 37, a. 1 c, ad fin.: 'Insofar as we use these words (amor, dilectio) to express the relationship to its own principle of that reality which proceeds after the manner of love, and vice versa, so that by "love" [amor], proceeding love is understood ..., and so Love is the name of a person.' See ibid, ad 3m and ad 4m. (Fs)

Summa theologiae, 1, q. 37, a. 2 c, ad fin.: 'The Father and the Son are said to be loving through the Holy Spirit or through proceeding Love.' See ad 3m. (Fs)

Summa theologiae, 1, q. 38, a. 1 c: '... partaker of the divine Word and of proceeding Love.'
Summa theologiae, 1, q. 38, a. 2 c: '... since the Holy Spirit proceeds as Love ...'
Summa theologiae, 1, q. 38, a. 2, ad im: 'The Holy Spirit because he proceeds as Love from the Father ...'

625c Here we must not fail to point out that a processio operati does not of itself suffice for there to be an analogy to the divine processions. A phantasm proceeds from the imagination by way of a processio operati (Quaestiones quodlibetales, 5, a. 9, ad 2m), but the image of God is to be found not in the procession of the phantasm but only in a rational creature with respect to its intellect (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 93, a. 6). The reason for this is that an analogy to the divine processions can be had only in that processio operati that is an intellectual emanation. The procession of love from an inner word is such a procession, but not the procession of that strange and unknown term which John of St Thomas defends. (Fs)

625d For a fuller exposition on the beloved being in the lover, see Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 19, and Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 28, a. 2. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Sein (esse) - Intellekt; Unterschied: Vernunft (reason) - Intellekt; göttlicher Intellekt: Akt allen Seins

Kurzinhalt: But when reasoning has finished, the intellect begins its work and attempts to apprehend in a single intuitive grasp effects in their causes, conclusions in their principles, and quiddities in their sensible data.

Textausschnitt: 21 The Analogy of Intellect

627b Before going on to consider the mysterious analogies of word and of love, it seems necessary to have a clear and distinct concept of the analogy of intellect itself. (Fs)
627c This analogy, then, is a comparison that is drawn between being and different grades of intellect. St Thomas arrives at a threefold conclusion: the divine intellect is to the totality of being as act; the angelic intellect is to the totality of being as form; the human intellect is to the totality of being as potency. (Fs; tblStw: Relationen)

627d This conclusion is explicitly set forth in Summa theologiae, 1, q. 79, a. 2, and is sufficiently indicated in Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 98, ¶9, §1835; but it implicitly contains within itself the whole theory of intellect, and so it will be useful in this connection to read Summa contra Gentiles, 1, cc. 44-71; 2, cc. 46-101; 3, cc. 25-63; Summa theologiae, 1, qq. 14-15, 54-58, 79, 84-89; 1-2, q. 3; 3, qq. 9-12; De veritate, qq. 1-4, 8-12, 14-20; and so forth. (Fs)

629a For an understanding of this, the two most important things to consider are intellect and being. (Fs)

629b As to the intellect, note that the analogy begins from the human intellect with respect to its principal intellectual act. Consequently, that metaphorical conception which regards the human intellect as a kind of spiritual eye will not do. Nor does it help to consider its derived acts, that is, concepts or inner words; all this leads to is a Platonic analogy of intellect which proceeds from universals in our mind to universals that are eternal and subsistent. Nor will it help to go to the origin of the act of understanding, since that origin is called reason rather than intellect.1 But one should attend as carefully as possible to the term of any process of reasoning, when inquiry and discursive reasoning have ceased and the intellect comprehends many things as a unity. For it is the function of reason (1) to inquire into sensible data in order to come to know quiddities; (2) to work from quiddities that are understood separately in order to formulate general principles; (3) to proceed discursively from principles to conclusions; and (4) to argue from cause to effect. (See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 7.) But when reasoning has finished, the intellect begins its work and attempts to apprehend in a single intuitive grasp effects in their causes, conclusions in their principles, and quiddities in their sensible data. And the more powerful the intellect, the more things it comprehends in fewer and more synthetic acts. (Ibid. q. 55, a. 3.)

Fußnote zu oben:
2 [See Lonergan, Verbum. 66-68. '... reason is to understanding as motion is to rest. Reason is not one potency, and understanding another potency; on the level of potency the two are identical; they differ only as process to a term differs from achievement in the term.' Ibid. 66.]

629c Now as to being, here we must appeal to that wisdom which makes judgments about primary notions (Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 66, a. 5, ad 4m). For what is in question here is not being as a common name, as Henry of Ghent supposed. Nor is it being as a kind of univocal idea, having maximum extension but minimum content, meaning 'not nothing,' as Scotus conceived it. Nor is it being as an analogous concept, that is, a known proportion between some unknown essence and its equally unknown act of existence (esse). Although this notion of being is true, it does not suffice for understanding the analogy of intellect. The question here is rather about being taken quidditatively. It is about being that is properly understood when the question, What is being? is satisfactorily answered. It is about the why of being; it is about that by which, when understood, all being is comprehended; it is about the object of every intellect as that object is properly understood. There now, we have expressed the very same thing in five different ways!

631a Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 98, ¶9, §1835: 'Intelligible being is the proper object of intellect: that which embraces all differences and all possible kinds of being; for whatever can be, can be understood. Since, however, all knowledge is by way of similitude, an intellect cannot know its object in its totality unless it has within itself a similitude of all being and of all its differences. Such a similitude of the totality of being can only be an infinite nature, one which is not delimited to any species or genus of being, but is the universal principle and active power of all being ... It remains therefore that only God knows all things through his essence.' (Fs)

631b Summa theologiae, 1, q. 79, a. 2 c: 'For there is an intellect which is to universal being as the act of all being; this is the divine intellect, which is God's essence, in which originally and virtually all being preexists as in its first cause ... No created intellect can be as act with respect to the totality of being, for if it were it would have to be infinite being. Hence every created intellect, by the very fact that it is, is not the act of all intelligible realities, but is to those intelligibles as potency is to act.' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Analogie, Gott; Sein (esse) - Intellekt; Platon - Aristoteles (noesis noeseos); Wissen - Identität (Textstellen bei Thomas v. A.); intelligibile in act est intellectus in actu; Thomas: Unterschied im Intellekt (Gott, Engel, Mensch)

Kurzinhalt: Aristotle ... drew the analogy from the act of understanding itself, and accordingly from our intellect that is moved by a phantasm he concluded to the existence of a separate intellect that cannot be moved by anything.

Textausschnitt: 631c From its implications we may clearly see how profound is this analogy of intellect. First of all, it is an analogy that accords with the thought of Aristotle. Plato went from universal concepts to subsistent universals, or Ideas; hence, the Platonists placed the Intelligences in a second order, lest the Ideas be eternally unknown (see De substantiis separatis, c. 4). Aristotle, on the other hand, drew the analogy from the act of understanding itself, and accordingly from our intellect that is moved by a phantasm he concluded to the existence of a separate intellect that cannot be moved by anything. And since in us the intellect in act is the intelligible in act, 'in non-material beings,' he said, 'understanding and the understood are identical'. Therefore, he declared the act of understanding of a separate substance to be noesis noeseos, a phrase which, in my opinion, was more accurately translated by medieval philosophers as 'understanding understanding' than as 'thinking about thinking,' as some moderns have rendered it. (Fs) (notabene)

631d Second, we reject the Platonic principle that knowledge necessarily and by its very nature supposes duality, and accept the Aristotelian principle that knowledge is rooted in identity. This principle is of such paramount importance in our present study that we must now quote St Thomas's explicit teaching on this point. (Fs) (notabene)

633a Summa theologiae, 1, q.14, a. 2 c: '... the sensible in act is the sense in act, and the intelligible in act is the intellect in act ... And it is only because of the fact that both are in potency that a sense or intellect is really different from a sensible or an intelligible object. Since, therefore, God has no potency but is pure act, it necessarily follows that in God intellect and what is understood are one and the same in every way.' See the definition of 'object' in appendix 2, §1, above. (Fs)

633b Hence for St Thomas God's essence and existence and intellect and the species by which God understands and the divine act of understanding are absolutely one and the same (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 4). Indeed, he does not find the formality of truth in God to lie in a conformity between the divine intellect and the divine existence, for conformity supposes duality, but rather in the absence of any dissimilarity whatsoever (ibid. q. 16, a. 5, ad 2m). Finally, it follows from this identity between the understander and the intelligible that since the Word of God is the intelligible act of existence of God, the Word of God is God (ibid. q. 27, a. 2; q. 34, a. 2, ad 4m; Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 11, ¶[11, §3471). (Fs)

633c This theorem destroys the very roots of the opinions of its adversaries: (1) J.-P. Sartre, who uses a distinction between en-soi and pour-soi to declare 'God-simple-and-conscious-of-himself to be a contradiction; (2) Günther, who supposes the distinctions between subject, object, and the act of knowing to be necessary (see László Orbán, Theologia Guntheriana et Concilium Vaticanum. Analecta Gregoriana, vol. 28 [Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1942J 98-110.); (3) Rosmini, who deduces from a knowing God the Father a second subsistent as known (see Francesco Bruno, 'Le dimostrazioni trinitarie di Antonio Rosmini,' Divas Thomas [Piacenza] 55 [1952] 183-85); (4) Scotus, who if you concede to him that an object is at least conceptually prior to the act of the knower, proves his formal distinction a parte rei (In I Sent., d. 2, q. 7; d. 8, q. 4; Rep. Par., In I Sent., d. 45, q. 2; see B. Jansen, 'Beiträge zur geschichtlichen Entwicklung der Distinctio formalis,' Zeitschrift zur katholische Theologie 53 (1929) 317- 44, 517-44; see also §25, below). (Fs) (notabene)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Analogie, Gott; Thomas: über Aristoteles hinaus (Seinsweisen: Mensch, Engel, Gott - erstes Objekt d. Intellekts); das Eine - Viele (Plotinus, Rosmini); Thomas: viele Ideen (rationes) in Gott - aber: virtuell, emminenter, formal; Quelle d. Einheit

Kurzinhalt: Thus, the primary object of the divine intellect is 'the universal principle and active power of all being,' that is, 'Being itself (ipsum esse); its secondary object is everything to which the divine power extends. The angelic intellect, however ...

Textausschnitt: 633d Third, Thomas's analogy goes far beyond that of Aristotle. (1) Aristotle's 'understanding understanding' is itself scarcely understandable (Summa contra Gentiles, 3, c. 26, ¶10, §2080); (2) one cannot derive from it the knowledge God has of other things and God's providence over them; (3) it does not furnish a basis for distinguishing between the divine intellect and an angelic intellect. These very serious obstacles are removed by St Thomas by his comparison between different intellects and being quidditatively, or comprehensively, understood. Thus, the primary object of the divine intellect is 'the universal principle and active power of all being,' that is, 'Being itself (ipsum esse); its secondary object is everything to which the divine power extends. The angelic intellect, however, has as its primary object the essence of the angel itself. (Fs) (notabene)

635a Fourth, this knowledge that God has of other things must be very carefully understood. When Plotinus was unable to reconcile the one and the many in one simple reality, he first posited the One and then Intelligence, or Mind (Nous). Clement of Alexandria erroneously distinguishes between Father and Son as if the Father were the One as the One and the Son were the One as the All. (For the text, see R. Arnou, De 'Platonismo' Patrum: Textus et collegit et notis illustravit. Series theologica 21 [Rome: Gregorian University Press, 1935] 19, where other passages are referred to; see also pp. 8, 40-41). Rosmini tried to demonstrate some multiplicity in God, namely, the Trinity, on the basis of multiplicity in things (see Francesco Bruno, 'Le dimostrazioni trinitarie di Antonio Rosmini.' Divus Thomas [Piacenza] 55 [1952] 181-83). (Fs)

635b Now Thomas clearly taught that there are many ideas in God (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 15, a. 2), which in [God's] speculative knowledge are called 'ideas' (rationes) and in [God's] practical knowledge are called 'exemplars' (ibid. a. 3). This multitude is contained virtually (i.e., as in its cause) in the divine power, eminently in the divine essence as being in a multitude of ways outwardly imitable, and formally in the divine intellect. (Fs)

635c Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 5 c: '... the very act of existence of the first efficient cause, which is God, is his act of understanding. Thus, whatever effects preexist in God as in their first cause must be in his act of understanding, and all that are in it must be there in an intelligible manner; for whatever is in something else is in it in the manner of that in which it is.'

635d But God does not behold the many ideas in themselves, since ideas do not subsist, but sees them in himself (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 5 a). Nor are they species by which God understands, for the species by which God understands is unique and is God's essence itself (ibid. q. 15, a. 2). Nor are they many words uttered by God, since in God there is but one unique Word (ibid. q. 34, a. 3, ad 4m). Nor are they conceptual beings (entia rationes) except according to our way of thinking, for God truly knows many ideas which, if they were in God as conceptual beings, would also be [inner] words. But they are secondary objects of the divine act of understanding itself, for they are 'as that which is understood'; 'there are many ideas in the divine mind as things understood by him' (ibid. q. 15, a. 2 a); 'many ideas are in his intellect as understood' (ibid, ad 2m) as its secondary object, which does not specify its act (ibid. q. 14, a. 5, ad 3m). (Fs)

635e Therefore, the first source of multiplicity is the divine intelligence. For it is of the nature of its act to understand in such a way that many other things are understood in one understood content. And since the very act of existence is the universal principle of all being, it is quite impossible for God to know himself without formally knowing many things through the same act of understanding, without any multiplication of reality. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 5; see also a. 6 and q. 15, a. 2. (Fs)
637a You may interject here that God's essence or his power is the ultimate origin of multiplicity. But the multitude is in his essence eminently, not formally, and in his power virtually, not.formally; whereas in the act of understanding himself, God clearly and distinctly and properly understands many, indeed an infinity, of things. (Fs)

637b You may further object that there cannot be a clear and distinct understanding of many things unless many inner words are formed. Our answer to this is that every inner word proceeds from the knowledge of the one who understands and therefore an understanding of many things is a prerequisite for the formation of many words. Now in us, to be sure, such an understanding occurs only through many acts of understanding and the formation of many words; but in God's case, as he comprehends all things in a single act of understanding, so does he utter all things in a single word (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 34, a. 3). Besides, there is no legitimate argument to prove the existence of the divine word from the fact that we, with our weak intellects, need many acts of understanding and many words. See appendix 2, §7, above, on the necessity of the word in us, and §25, below. (Fs)

637c Fifth, let it be clearly understood that God is of an intellectual nature. No divine perfection is unknown to God, and all knowledge is rooted in identity. In God's self-knowledge, therefore, the one who understands and the act of understanding and what is understood are one and the same, so that all divine perfection is identical with his act of understanding. Since, however, knowledge is rooted only in identity, to the primary object is added a secondary object whereby God in the one and the same unique act of understanding clearly, distinctly, and properly knows all other things to be contained eminently in his essence and virtually in his power. Note here that in God 'to be understood as a secondary object' and 'to be understood in his essence' and 'to be understood in his power' and 'to be contained eminently in his essence' and 'to be contained virtually in his power' are all the same. That which in God is one, in us is conceived in many different ways according to various analogous concepts of the same reality.1 (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Analogie, Mensch 1; gött. Intellekt zu Sein - Akt des Seins; menschl. Intellekt zu Sein - Potenz; Potenzen: akzidentell, essentiell, obediential (potentia obedientialis)

Kurzinhalt: A third kind of potency is that of one who possesses neither a form nor a habit and cannot be brought to becoming informed through any created agency. This is obediential potency, which only the power of God can actuate ...

Textausschnitt: 23 Implications of the Analogy with Respect to Man

637d Let us go now to another part of the analogy. As the divine intellect is to being as the act of all being, so the created intellect is to all being as potency. But there are several different kinds of potency. (Fs; tblStw: Potenz)

639a One kind of potency is the potency of that which already possesses a form or a habit so that, whenever it wills, it can immediately go into operation. This potency, which is called second or accidental potency, is found both in human beings who have acquired some knowledge and in angelic beings inasmuch as through species connatural to them they can know other angels and material reality as well. (Fs) (notabene)

639b A second kind of potency is that of one who does not possess a form or habit but yet can receive such a form through some created agent. This potency, which is called first or essential potency, is found in persons who have not yet acquired knowledge but are capable of doing so. (Fs) (notabene)

639c A third kind of potency is that of one who possesses neither a form nor a habit and cannot be brought to becoming informed through any created agency. This is obediential potency, which only the power of God can actuate (Summa theologiae, 3, q. 11, a. 1 c), and is found in all created intellects with respect to knowing all being (ibid. q. 9, a. 2, ad 3m). For the totality of being is known by an intellect only if God is known by his essence; but God is known by his essence only if God himself unites with a created intellect as an intelligible species (ibid. 1, q. 12, aa. 4 and 5). This, of course, is a gift of God that exceeds the scope or proportion of any finite substance and so is absolutely supernatural. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Analogie, Mensch 2; Potenzen: entsprechende Erfordernisse (exigencies, exigentia); intellektuelles Verlangen (desire, appetitio) - Wesen Gottes: potentia obedientialis; Sein - Analogie (dem Umfang nach, quiddidativ); Erkenntnis Gottes - die Seligen

Kurzinhalt: First there is a determinate exigency, and, since every determination comes from a form ... so the created intellect is to the totality of being as potency. Now this potency is not second or accidental potency ... It is, rather, obediential potency


Textausschnitt: 639d Further, as we have distinguished between different potencies, so we must carefully examine the matter of exigencies. First there is a determinate exigency, and, since every determination comes from a form, only second or accidental potency can exert a determinate exigency; thus, whatever does not have a human form cannot have a determinate exigency to perform human activities. A second kind of exigency is an indeterminate exigency, which is found in first or essential potency; thus, prime matter calls for any kind of informing, though matter that is not properly disposed cannot require that it be informed by a human soul. Finally, with obediential potency no exigency of any kind, determinate or indeterminate, can exist or even be thought of. For God does not exist for the sake of order in the universe, but the order of the universe exists for God. And the order of the universe does not exist for the sake of intellectual creatures, but intellectual creatures exist for the sake of the order of the universe (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 103, a. 2 c. and ad 3m; Summa contra Gentiles, 3, c. 112, ¶¶8-10, §§2863-65), an order which God has chosen in an utterly free decision (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 19, a. 3; q. 21, a.1, ad 3m). (Fs) (notabene)

639e Second, St Thomas did acknowledge a true and real relationship of the created intellect to the totality of being. For the intellect is really and truly related not only to what it does know or can know naturally but also to what it desires to know. So, having learned about the existence of a first cause, we automatically wonder what that cause is; and as the fact of questioning manifests intellectual desire, so the question itself determines the object of that desire, since one who asks the question What? desires to understand the essence of the thing in question. Intellectual desire, therefore, is such that it does not rest until it knows God by his essence (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12, a. 1; 1-2, q. 3, a. 8; Summa contra Gentiles, 3, c. 50; for the systematic character of this doctrine, see ibid. cc. 25-63. Aquinas immediately goes on to note the supernaturality of this vision, Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12, aa. 4 and 5; 1-2, q. 5, a. 5; Summa contra Gentiles, 3, c. 52; we have pointed out the confusions to be avoided in this matter in a section appended to this section: see §24, below). (Fs)

641a From the foregoing we conclude that as the divine intellect is to the totality of being as act, so the created intellect is to the totality of being as potency. Now this potency is not second or accidental potency, for it is not founded upon a form or habit, since one who asks a question has not yet received the intellectual form or habit. Nor is it first or essential potency, which can receive its form through a created agent; only God is equal to uniting the divine essence to a created intellect. It is, rather, obediential potency, which is founded upon the perfectibility of the intellect, and, indeed, on a perfectibility which only the omnipotence of God can perfect. (Fs) (notabene)

641b Third, we conclude that only the blessed understand what God is; for to understand what a thing is is the same as to know it by its essence (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 1, a. 7, ad im; q. 12, a. 12, ad im; a. 13, ad im; 1-2, q. 3, a. 8). (Fs)

641c We may further conclude to the difference between being taken analogously and being taken quidditatively. (Fs)

For in both cases we use the word 'being,' and in the same respect in both according to its extension, what it denotes on the part of the object, namely: all things that are, whether existing necessarily as God or contingently as creatures, both with respect to their total actual reality past, present, or future, and even with respect to all that lies within the power of a creature or in the power of God himself. (Fs)

641c But when we add 'analogously' or 'quidditatively' we do so with respect to the manner in which the totality of being is apprehended. For it belongs to the intellect to apprehend many realities in one. But if that 'one' is the very essence of God, which is the universal principle of all being and, in a way, the 'because of which' (propter quid) of the existence of God and of every possible being, then we are considering being quidditatively.1 If, however, that 'one' is some created being, or a species or genus of created beings, then we have, it is true, the beginning of and basis for knowing something about all beings; but, since all creatures fall short of the infinite perfection of the divine essence, we have neither the beginning of nor the basis for being able to understand the total reality of all being. Therefore, whenever the divine essence is not apprehended through itself, it is impossible to know all beings except according to an imperfect analogy - by way of analogy, because by reason of a certain proportion among them, we can go from knowing created things to knowing all being; by way of an imperfect analogy, because created being is an imperfect basis for knowing all being. See, for example, Summa theologiae, 1, q. 88. (Fs)

643a Fourth, we draw these further conclusions: (1) God knows himself comprehensively (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 14, a. 3); (2) the blessed see God in his essence but do not know God comprehensively (ibid. q. 12, a. 7); (3) there are truths so deeply hidden in God that not even the blessed know them; (4) there are truths so deeply hidden in God that they can never be known through analogical knowledge; (5) from the fact of revelation there are truths hidden in God which can be revealed to us by God and in fact have been revealed; (6) through revelation and faith it is certain that these revealed matters are true; (7) through reason enlightened by faith an analogical understanding of mysteries is possible (db 1796, ds 3016, nd 131); (8) this understanding, fruitful though it is, is attained only through analogies that are imperfect; (9) these limitations cannot be removed while we are walking by faith and not by vision; for concerning the mysteries, faith teaches us how to answer the question, Is it so? but only the vision of God provides us with the grounds for understanding what God is. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Analogie, Mensch 3; Sein (esse): 2 Fehlschlüsse (Parmenides, Rosmini): Erkenntnis von esse durch das Wesen d. Existenz, Intuition v. Sein;

Kurzinhalt: ... our intellect is related to all being not through some intuition but only through the desire for an intuition; and this desire is neither a concept nor a knowledge of being, nor does it contain anything by way of an object, but is totally on the ...

Textausschnitt: 643b With all this well understood, there are two fallacies to advert to concerning being. Having discovered the essences of some things and being able to demonstrate their properties from these essences, it is possible for us to make the mistake of thinking that we know being through the essence of existence itself and so ought to be able to demonstrate the properties of all being as if from the known essence of being. Thus did Parmenides reason about being the way we legitimately reason about a circle or about man.1 So also did A. Rosmini hold that there is within us a certain intuition of being and tried to demonstrate the Trinity from three forms of being (DB 1916, DS 3226). (Fs) (notabene)

645a Now with regard to the intuition of being, we may grant that there is in us something potential, indeterminate, and most fundamental that has to do with all being. For there is within us an intellect that is able to make and become all things, and is a created participation of uncreated Light. But our intellect is related to all being not through some intuition but only through the desire for an intuition; and this desire is neither a concept nor a knowledge of being, nor does it contain anything by way of an object, but is totally on the side of the subject inasmuch as it docs not know and yet desires to know. (Fs) (notabene)

645b Accordingly, the removal of such an intuition also radically eliminates any process of reasoning that would argue from being to the properties or forms of existence itself. For when an essence is unknown, one cannot deduce properties from it. But if one cannot deduce the properties of something from its essence, there is no other way of knowing them except through some imperfect analogies, either ones that are certain, as in natural theology, or ones that are probable or fitting, as in dogmatic theology, or ones that are erroneous, as in the case of Rosmini with his 'three forms.' God has but one essence or form, and this essence is the form of existence itself. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das natürliches Verlangen d. Intellekts (Thomas v. Aquin, desiderio intellectus, appetitus): Bestimmungen 1-6; Unterschied: intellektuelles - willentliches Verlangen

Kurzinhalt: Second, in this psychological fact can be discerned a natural desire. For what is desired is intellectual knowledge; and since this desiring results neither from sense knowledge nor from intellectual knowledge, it is said to be natural ..

Textausschnitt: 24 Excursus: The Natural Desire of the Intellect

645c Since St Thomas's doctrine is so coherent that it cannot be understood by one who would syncretistically accept one part while rejecting another, it would seem desirable at this point to inquire whether he contradicted himself in teaching that man desires the vision of God naturally yet obtains it supernaturally. (Fs)

645d We shall not treat this question in its full extent, since it appears likely that the mind of Aquinas on this matter underwent development; we shall restrict ourselves to certain definite passages, namely, Summa contra Gentiles, 3, cc. 50 and 52; Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12, aa. 1 and 4; 1-2, q. 3, a. 8 and q. 5, a. 5; 3, q. 9, a. 2, ad 3m. For it is in these four passages from his most systematic works that the apparent contradiction is to be found. (Fs)

645e For the thought of the medieval theologians (all of them, it seems), see Victorinus Doucet, 'De naturali seu innato supernaturalis beatitudinis desiderio iuxta theologos a saeculo XIII usque ad XX,' Antonianum 4 (1929) 167-208; E. Elter, 'De naturali hominis beatitudine ad mentem Scholae antiquioris,' Gregorianum 9 (1928) 269-306. The following observations have to do only with an understanding of this matter. (Fs)

647a First, then, there is the psychological fact that man has an innate tendency to wonder, which (1) precedes intellectual knowledge and leads to it, (2) is not constituted but is manifested by the questions, Is it? and What is it? (3) is so far-ranging that it does not rest until it sees God by his essence, and thus (4) contains implicitly in itself that drive towards the vision of God which Aquinas briefly explains in the Summa contra Gentiles and in the Prima pars and the Prima secundae of the Summa theologiae, in the passages referred to above. (Fs)

647b Second, in this psychological fact can be discerned a natural desire. For what is desired is intellectual knowledge; and since this desiring results neither from sense knowledge nor from intellectual knowledge, it is said to be natural (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 80, a. 1 a). (Fs) (notabene)

647c Third, this natural desire is also a 'nature' in the Aristotelian sense of the word (see above, appendix 1, §4). For it is a principle of motion and rest in that in which it primarily and per se resides. It is through this desire, which is in the intellect, that we primarily and per se desire to understand and, once we have understood, rest in that understanding. (Fs) (notabene)

647d Hence this desire, which is in the intellect as its subject and leads it towards understanding, is totally different from that other natural appetite which is in the will and in an indeterminate way tends towards beatitude (Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 1, a. 7). In Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 3, a. 8, Aquinas argues from this natural desire of the intellect to determine the object of perfect beatitude. (Fs) (notabene)

647e Fourth, the principle, intrinsic to the intellect, by which we desire to understand, is not an acquired habit but is innate within us and spontaneously manifests itself. Wearing their parents out with a virtually endless stream of questions is something that children neither are taught nor learn. (Fs)

647f Fifth, much less is this principle intrinsic to the intellect a supernaturally infused habit. For without it all questioning would cease and we should not acquire even natural knowledge. (Fs)

647g There are, therefore, three ways in which this desire that is not satisfied with anything short of the vision of God can be called natural. In the first place, it is neither a sense appetite consequent upon sense knowledge nor a volitional appetite consequent upon intellectual knowledge. In the second place, it is the principle of motion and of rest which is primarily and per se in that in which there is the motion or rest. And in the third place, it is in us by our very nature, and is neither something learned nor superadded to our nature by some special infusion. (Fs) (notabene)

647h Sixth, an intrinsic principle of any act can be related to that act in several ways: as a productive principle of the act, or as a receptive principle of the act, either proximately receptive as a form, or remotely receptive as mere potency. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das natürliches Verlangen d. Intellekts 2 (desiderio intellectus, appetitus): Bestimmungen 7-9; natürlich - übernatürlich (vitaler Akt, Potenz, Form); Unsterblichkeit - visio beatifica (eg); kein Widerspruch: intellektuelles Geschöpf ohne Gnade

Kurzinhalt: We are left, therefore, with the conclusion that an intrinsic natural principle is related to the vision of God as mere potency which only God can actuate.

Textausschnitt: 649a Now, no principle that is natural to us is capable of producing a supernatural act of any sort. Producer and product are proportionate to each other; but the natural and the supernatural are simply disproportionate. And note that those who recognize a so-called vital act as the sole productive principle (see appendix 1 above, §8) tend to see an internal contradiction in a natural desire for a supernatural vision. (Fs) (notabene)

649b Besides, nothing that is natural can be related to something supernatural as form to second act. For both form and second act have the same definition, as, for example, the definition of sight and seeing. But the definitions of natural and supernatural being are totally different. (Fs)

Again, nothing that is natural can be related to the supernatural as mere potency that can be actuated by a created agent. For what is supernatural exceeds the proportion of any finite substance whatsoever; but nothing produced by a finite agent can exceed the proportion of that agent. (Fs)

649c We are left, therefore, with the conclusion that an intrinsic natural principle is related to the vision of God as mere potency which only God can actuate. See Summa theologiae, 3, q. 9, a. 2, ad 3m, and q. 11, a. 1 c. (Fs) (notabene)
And this is all the more clear from the fact that the form by which God is seen in his essence is the divine essence itself, and the disposition for receiving God in the intellect is the light of glory (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12, aa. 4 and 5). (Fs)
649d Seventh, an intrinsic principle can be related to an act in two ways: directly and explicitly, or indirectly and implicitly. (Fs)
The natural desire of the intellect is related to the totality of being in the first way. This same desire is related to the vision of God in the second way, inasmuch as this desire does not rest unless and until it sees what God is. (Fs) (notabene)

649e Be careful, therefore, not to confuse this natural desire with a specifically supernatural act. Supernatural acts belong to a certain genus and are specified by their proper objects. But a universal tendency, whether of the intellect towards being or of the will towards good, is not specifically supernatural: Nor can the supernaturality of such a tendency be deduced from the fact that being implicitly includes supernatural beings and good implicitly includes supernatural goods. All that can be deduced from the tendency is that the supernatural is not utterly impossible; and thus does Aquinas conclude to the possibility of the beatific vision in Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12, a. 1. (Fs)

649f Eighth, there is one kind of natural appetite that is founded upon the perfection of its subject, and another that is founded not upon its perfection but only upon its perfectibility. (Fs) (notabene)
649g Our natural desire for immortality belongs to the first kind (Summa contra Gentiles, 2, c. 55, ¶13, §1309 and c. 79, ¶6, §1602; Summa theologiae, 1, q. 75, a. 6 c). For if immortality is not some new perfection added to a spiritual soul but only the perpetual continuation of the same perfection, a continuation which is deduced from the notion of the soul and results naturally from the essence of the soul. (Fs)

650a Our natural desire for the vision of God belongs to the second kind. For that vision can neither be deduced logically from the perfection of a created intellect nor result naturally from the essence of a created intellect. Hence this desire is based entirely upon the perfectibility of the created intellect. The perfection of the intellect does not consist in being ignorant or asking questions, but in knowledge and answers; but its perfectibility does consist in its ignorance and is manifested in its questioning. (Fs)
650b Ninth, exigency can be understood in two ways. In the first sense, exigency is properly speaking a certain need that a thing has for something else. Thus, an end has an exigency for means, a necessary efficient cause necessitates its effect, a formal cause necessitates its primary formal effects, and a relative necessarily calls for a correlative. Understood in the second sense, an exigency is improperly speaking predicated of creatures inasmuch as a need results in them from the exigencies of divine wisdom or divine goodness. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 21, a. 1, ad 3m, and Summa contra Gentiles, 2, cc. 28-30. (Fs)

650c In the first sense, a natural desire has no exigency whatsoever for the vision of God. It has no exigency by reason of an end, for an appetite is not an end but a means, and the same means can be used for different ends. In other words, if the end is [an intellectual] vision, intellect is necessarily a means to that end; but if intellect is a means, the end is possibly, but not necessarily, such a vision. Nor does it have an exigency by reason of efficient causality, for a natural desire does not cause the vision, much less necessarily cause it; nor by reason of a formal causality, for a desire is not a formal cause; nor by reason of its being a relative term, for its correlative is not the act of seeing but the implicit and indirect desirability of the vision itself. (Fs)

650d Nor does the desire have an exigency for this vision in the second meaning of exigency. For although, when God acts, he necessarily acts in accordance with his infinite wisdom and goodness, it by no means follows that he actually destines an intellectual creature to that vision as to its end. (Fs)

God in his infinite goodness can do whatever his infinite wisdom can conceive: for the goodness of the will consists in following a wise intellect; and the infinite goodness of his will consists in perfectly following his infinitely wise intellect. (Fs)

650e Besides, God can do with infinite wisdom whatever absolutely speaking he is able to do. For God is not more powerful than he is wise, as if his power were more extensive than his wisdom; but, since his power and his wisdom are the same reality with his divine essence, 'the divine wisdom embraces the whole range of his power,' and so 'there is nothing within the power of God that is not within the order of divine wisdom' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 25, a. 5 a). (Fs)

653a Moreover, God can absolutely speaking do whatever does not involve an internal contradiction (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 25, a. 3 c). But an intellectual creature without grace is not self-contradictory; otherwise grace would not be a free gift but would be given of necessity to every intellectual creature. Absolutely speaking, therefore, God can create an intellectual creature without actually destining it to the beatific vision as its end. But, as we have said, whatever absolutely speaking God can do, he can also do with his infinite wisdom and infinite goodness. There is therefore no exigency on the part of divine wisdom or divine goodness for an intellectual creature to be actually destined to the vision of God as its end. See the encyclical of Pius xn, Humani Generis (db 2318, ds 3891).

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das natürliches Verlangen d. Intellekts 3 (desiderio intellectus, appetitus); Einwand, Widerspruch: natürlich - übernatülich; direktes Objekt d. V:. Sein -> negative Formulierung: "ruht nicht eher ..."

Kurzinhalt: ... we reply that the direct and explicit object of this natural desire is not to behold God in his essence; it is being. Since God as something to be seen in his essence falls within the formality of being, the consequence is that ...

Textausschnitt: 653b Let us now proceed to answering the following objections. (Fs)
A first objector says that to speak of a natural desire for a supernatural vision is to make a self-contradictory statement. (Fs)

To this we reply that if a natural desire either constitutes such a vision or is the principle from which the vision naturally results or which requires the vision, then we grant the objection; but if not, we deny it. (Fs)

653c But the objector rejoins: Acts are specified by their objects. But the object of this natural desire is absolutely supernatural, namely, the vision of God through his essence. This natural desire, therefore, is a supernatural act, which implies a contradiction. (Fs)

To this we reply that the direct and explicit object of this natural desire is not to behold God in his essence; it is being. Since God as something to be seen in his essence falls within the formality of being, the consequence is that this natural desire does not rest until it beholds God in his essence. Yet this consequence reveals not an explicit but only an implicit object; and because this consequence is not an affirmation but a negation (namely, 'it does not rest until...'), it indicates an object that is not only implicit but also, in a way, indirect. (Fs) (notabene)

653d Besides, to this object, being, this natural appetite is not related as act. Only the divine act of understanding can be related to being as act, just as only God's will can be related to good as act (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 79, a. 2; q. 54, a. 2). Every created intellect is to being as potency, and indeed not proximate potency as form, but as mere potency, remote and obediential. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das natürliches Verlangen d. Intellekts 4 (desiderio intellectus, appetitus); Einwand 1a: Potenz kann nicht oboediential sein; oboedientiale Potenz zu Akt; Nichtwiderspruch (Essentialismus); Definition (actus perfecti, a. imperfecti usw.); Weisheit Gottes

Kurzinhalt: Essentialists think that there is nothing in things but essences, that is, what can be known through definitions; and since there is no relation between definitions that are simply different except that of noncontradiction, they necessarily conclude ...

Textausschnitt: 653e The objector further rejoins: But this sort of potency cannot be obediential. For this potency implies an ordination or relation to act, while obediential potency is related to act only by the negative relation of noncontradiction. (Fs) (notabene)

To this we reply that this negative conception of obediential potency fits in with some systems, but not with all. (Fs)

655a Essentialists think that there is nothing in things but essences, that is, what can be known through definitions; and since there is no relation between definitions that are simply different except that of noncontradiction, they necessarily conclude that nature is related to the gifts of grace only by the negative relation of noncontradiction. (Fs)

655b As we explained above (appendix 1, §2 and §3), the same definition can be verified in reality either as an act of what is complete (actus perfecti), such as the act of understanding, or as a form or first act, such as the habit of knowledge, or as essential or remote potency, such as the possible intellect, or as an act of what is incomplete (actus imperfecti), as in a fetus. Besides, remote essential potency can be related to form in two ways: as capable of being moved to receiving a form by a natural agent, or as capable of being moved to receiving a form by the omnipotent power of God alone. If only God's omnipotence can move a potency to form, that potency St Thomas calls 'obediential'; see Summa theologiae, 3, q. 11, a. 1 c. (Fs) (notabene)

655c There are two ways in which St Thomas's doctrine is very apt. (Fs)

First, the saying that 'grace perfects nature' is not just a tag, but also an affirmation to be understood (Summa theologiae, 3, q. 9, a. 2, ad 3m). (Fs)

655d Second, it is characteristic of wisdom to set things in order, and it belongs to infinite wisdom to order all reality. Thus, St Thomas is able to say that whatever God can do absolutely speaking, he can do with infinite wisdom. Those who think otherwise regarding obediential potency are forced to hold that divine wisdom cannot establish a positive order between nature and grace. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das natürliches Verlangen d. Intellekts 4 (desiderio intellectus, appetitus); Einwand 2: Glückseligkeit (beatitudo) als Geschuldetheit d. Natur?; vollkommene - unvollkommene G.; indirektes - direktes Verlangen d. Schau Gottes

Kurzinhalt: To desire implicitly and indirectly the vision of God inasmuch as the intellect tends to being is one thing; but it is quite another thing to want to see God, for this would be a specifically supernatural act specified by an absolutely supernatural ...

Textausschnitt: 655e A second objector states: This natural desire results in an exigency for the vision of God. Without beatitude, something owed to nature is denied it; unless the desire is satisfied, there is no beatitude; and without the vision of God, the desire remains unsatisfied. (Fs)

Kommentar (04/11/10): Lat. Text zu "Without beatitude ..." bringt Klarheit: Nam nisi datur beatitudo, non solvitum debitum naturae.

To this objection we make the following reply. Whether without imperfect beatitude nature is denied something owed to it is a question we may leave aside here; but we deny that nature is denied what is its due if it is not granted perfect beatitude; for 'perfect beatitude is natural to God alone' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 62, a. 4). For the distinction between perfect and imperfect beatitude, see ibid. 1-2, q. 5, a. 5; q. 3, a. 6. (Fs)

655f We grant that if this desire is unsatisfied there is no perfect beatitude; but we deny that if this desire is unsatisfied there would be no imperfect beatitude. See Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 3, a. 8. On the constant opinion of theologians on this point from the Middle Ages down to the middle of the seventeenth century, see E. Elter, 'De naturali hominis beatitudine ad mentem Scholae antiquioris,' Gregorianum 9 (1928) 269-306. (Fs)

657a The objector rejoins: Therefore naturally speaking the blessed would be unhappy. (Fs)

In reply, we deny that naturally speaking the blessed would not have everything they want. We concede, however, that they would not have everything that the divine omnipotence could bestow upon them. (Fs)

657b To desire implicitly and indirectly the vision of God inasmuch as the intellect tends to being is one thing; but it is quite another thing to want to see God, for this would be a specifically supernatural act specified by an absolutely supernatural object. Such an act would not exist in a possible order of reality in which no specifically supernatural act occurs. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Das natürliches Verlangen d. Intellekts 4 (desiderio intellectus, appetitus); Einwand 3: tatsächliche - mögliche Welt (Scotus - Thomas); Konzepte - Verstehen

Kurzinhalt: ... that Scotus, denying the priority of the act of understanding over concepts, takes concepts themselves as the foundation of knowledge as they would be necessarily either connected to one another or opposed to one another. Hence ...

Textausschnitt: 657c A third objector says that Aquinas seems to speak quite often as if this present order of reality were the only possible one. (Fs)

Our reply is simply that he does not so speak. He may seem to say this when interpreted as if he had adopted the principles of Scotus's methodology, but not if he is interpreted according to his own methodological principles. (Fs)

657d The point we are making here is that Scotus, denying the priority of the act of understanding over concepts, takes concepts themselves as the foundation of knowledge as they would be necessarily either connected to one another or opposed to one another. Hence, he considers theology to be scientific only insofar as it determines truths which, being absolutely necessary and universal, would be valid for every possible order of reality. Accordingly, anyone who is steeped in Scotistic principles thinks that theologians always talk about merely possible orders or, if they happen to be speaking about the actual order of things, supposes this to be an exception that should be noted as such. (Fs) (notabene)

657e St Thomas, on the other hand, having understood that the act of understanding is prior to concepts, distinguishes different degrees of knowledge according to different acts of understanding. Thus, according to him, God, in comprehending the divine essence, knows perfectly absolutely all things that are possible. But Christ as man, by reason of his beatific vision, beholds the divine essence but does not know it comprehensively; thus, he knows all actual reality and all that lies within the power of creatures, but not all that is within the power of the Creator, for this presupposes a comprehension of the divine essence (Summa theologiae, 3, q. 10, a. 2). Finally, a theologian, since he does not know what God is (ibid. 1, q. 1, a. 7, ad 2m), is capable of attaining only that knowledge which is subalternate to the knowledge possessed by God and the blessed (ibid. q. 1, a. 2). Hence, theology knows God through analogies that are imperfect. It relates actual beings to God inasmuch as they manifest God's free will and suppose an ordering on the part of his wisdom (Summa contra Gentiles, 2, cc. 24, 26; 3, c. 97, ¶13, §2735 and ¶16, § 2738); but it treats of merely possible reality only incidentally in its discussion of God's omnipotence (sec, for example, Summa theologiae, 1, q. 25). Contrary though this may be to Scotistic principles, it is surely not unreasonable to consider as mad any theologian who firmly believes that he knows things that he says Christ as man was ignorant of. (Fs)

659a One may conclude from this just how great the difference is between Scotistic and Thomist methods, and how mistaken are those who would interpret St Thomas according to the methodological notions of the Scotists. It was out of the question that Aquinas, who practically always dealt with actual things, should have been continually declaring that what he was dealing with were actual things. Yet this is what is expected by those who, like our objector, seem to think that Aquinas very often spoke as if this present order of reality were the only one possible. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Wort, Analogie; Unterschied 1, 2: inneres Wort - göttliches Wort (menschliches Wort: Potenz - Akt; Vielheit)

Kurzinhalt: The first difference between the inner word in our mind and the divine Word is this, that our word can be formed before it actually is formed, while the divine Word cannot... The second difference is that our words are many, but the divine Word is one ...

Textausschnitt: 25 The Analogy of the Word

659b The first difference between the inner word in our mind and the divine Word is this, that our word can be formed before it actually is formed, while the divine Word cannot. (Fs)

For since every word arises from the knowledge of one who understands, and since our intellect is potency, it follows that, just as we are able to understand before we actually do understand, so a word can be formed in us before it actually is formed. (Fs) (notabene)

659c The divine intellect, however, is the act of all being and never was nor ever could have been potency; and the divine Word is likewise always in act and never was nor ever could have been in potency. (Fs)

For this reason the procession of the divine Word is said to be the procession of an act from act, processio operati; for it is not an act received in some potency or educed from potency, nor is it a perfection which perfects something perfectible. Neither is it an operation that is really distinct from and consequent upon form, and so cannot be said to be the procession of an operation, processio operationis.1 (Fs)

659d The second difference is that our words are many, but the divine Word is one and unique. (Fs)

659e For just as our intellect step by step comes to understand one thing after another, and properties after essences, and makes particular judgments about the existence of every individual thing, so we utter a multitude of inner words. (Fs)

661a But as the divine existence is the same as the divine essence, God in one and the same act understands both what he is and that he is. Moreover, as all other things are contained eminently in the divine essence and virtually in the divine power, so in the selfsame act by which God understands himself as primary object he understands all other realities as secondary objects. And since in one unique act he understands both himself and everything else, so also in one unique Word he both conceives and affirms himself, and in thus uttering himself he likewise utters all other things just as they are contained within him. See Summa theologiae, 1, q- 34, a. 3.

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Wort, Analogie; Unterschied 3, 4: inneres Wort - göttliches Wort (esse naturale - esse intelligibile; verursacht - nicht verursacht)

Kurzinhalt: Now there is this difference between God and creatures, that in no creature are existence and understanding the same ... The fourth difference is that our word is caused and produced in the proper sense

Textausschnitt: 661b The third difference concerns the natural mode of existence (esse naturale) and the intellective mode of existence (esse intelligibile). (Fs)

Every word is in a way the very thing that is expressed by that word; otherwise a word would not be the medium in which either the essence or the existence of a thing is known. And indeed, if a thing is understood by analogy, the word conceived or uttered by the one who understands is partly similar to that thing and partly different from it. But if a thing is understood by its quiddity and is exactly conceived, the word conceived by the one who understands is in every respect similar to the thing. (Fs) (notabene)

661c Now there is this difference between God and creatures, that in no creature are existence and understanding the same (Summa theologies, i, q. 54, a. 2), whereas in God there is no distinction whatsoever between existence and understanding (ibid. q. 14, aa. 2 and 4; q. 16, a. 5, ad 2m). Hence, it follows that in creatures there is a difference between the natural mode of existence and the intellective mode of existence, while in God these two modes of existence are absolutely identical. (Fs)

661d When, therefore, we perfectly understand and perfectly conceive anything, the word we utter in our intellect is entirely similar to the thing understood, but only in such a way that the word is the intellective existence of the thing and not its natural existence. But since God comprehends and perfectly conceives himself, the Word of God is not only a perfect likeness of the divine essence but also is that essence itself according to its natural mode of existence. Therefore the Word is God. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 2 c. and ad 2m; q. 34, a. 2, ad im; Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 11, ¶11, §3471; Depotentia, q. 8, a. 1 c. ad fin. (Fs)

661e The fourth difference is that our word is caused and produced in the proper sense, while the divine Word is not caused nor properly speaking produced. (Fs)

661f What is caused or, properly speaking, produced is distinct from that which causes or produces it. Now, our inner word is distinct from the act of understanding from which it proceeds and so can be said to be caused and, in the proper sense, produced. But the divine Word, who is God proceeding from God, is in no way distinct from the divine essence or substance, but is numerically one with it. (Fs)

663a Nevertheless this substantial identity between God as conceiver and God as conceived is not to be understood as if there were no procession at all. The divine essence is truly communicated from the Father to the Son. But this communication is not a causation or a production in the proper sense, but an intelligible emanation.1 Just as our word is not only produced by an act of understanding but also intrinsically is because of the intelligibility understood in the act of understanding, so also the divine Word in some way is because of divine intelligibility as understood. I say, 'in some way,' because in us the act of understanding and the word are two different things, whereas in God the originating principle of the Word is not just the understood intelligibility of God but God whole and entire, and similarly the Word that is originated is not only God as conceived but is God whole and entire. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Wort, Analogie; Unterschied 5: inneres Wort - göttliches Wort (Zeugung)

Kurzinhalt: It is obvious, however, that our inner word is not generated in the proper sense of the term, since our word is similar to a thing only according to its intellective mode of existence but not according to its natural mode of existence.

Textausschnitt: 663b The fifth difference is the fact that in us the procession of the word is not a generation, whereas the procession of the divine Word is truly and properly speaking a generation. Hence the Word is the Son of God. (Fs)

663c In its proper sense, generation is the origin of something alive from a conjoined living principle, with a resulting likeness in nature (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 2). It is said to be the origin of a living thing so as to exclude the production of mineral substances, which could be termed generation in a broad sense. It is further said to be the origin of a living thing from a conjoined living principle in order to exclude the origin of living things from God's creating act. Again, it is said to be the origin of what is living from a conjoined living principle that is similar to it; for our hair and nails are living and originate from us, but they are not similar to us. Finally, it is said to be the origin of what is living from a conjoined living principle with a resulting likeness in nature; that is, the similarity results by reason of the nature of the origin and of the procession, so that the origin of Eve from Adam's side is excluded. (Fs) (notabene)

663d Now, the Word is alive: it is the living God. (Fs)

The Word is from a living principle; for it is from God's act of understanding, which is God's life (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 18, a. 3). (Fs)

663e The Word is from a living principle that is conjoined and similar to it; for it is of one and the same substance with it. (Fs)

665a The Word is similar by reason of the procession itself; for the intellectual emanation of the Word by its very nature is such that in the Word there is conceived exactly what the one understanding understands. Again, the emanation of the Word by its very formality is the emanation of that which is formally true; and it is of the very formality of truth that it not be different from that which it expresses. (Fs)
665b It is obvious, however, that our inner word is not generated in the proper sense of the term, since our word is similar to a thing only according to its intellective mode of existence but not according to its natural mode of existence. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Wort, Analogie; Unterschied 6: inneres Wort - göttliches Wort (Notwendigkeit); Wort Gottes - Wissen um viele Dinge (eminenter im Wesen, virtualiter in d. Macht), Einwände: Scotus, Beweis d. Wortes in Gott?

Kurzinhalt: The sixth difference is that we can prove the necessity of our inner word, but can only accept on faith the necessity of the divine Word, although it is knowable in itself... Similarly, in God the existence of a Word cannot be demonstrated from ...

Textausschnitt: 665c The sixth difference is that we can prove the necessity of our inner word, but can only accept on faith the necessity of the divine Word, although it is knowable in itself. (Fs)

For as we said above (appendix 2, §7), in our case there is a fourfold necessity for an inner word because the object that moves our intellect, namely, a quiddity or nature existing in corporeal matter, is not the same as the object to which our intellect tends as to its end, that is, being in its fullest extent. (Fs)

665d In the case of God, however, as he cannot be moved by anything else, so also he cannot tend to anything else as to an end. In God, therefore, the one who understands and the act of understanding and that which is understood are all one and the same. The primary object of the divine intellect is the divine substance itself, which is one with the divine act of existence and the divine act of understanding. But the secondary object of the divine intellect is this same divine substance as eminently containing other things within itself, and the divine power as virtually containing other things within itself. (Fs)

665e So, then, in God the existence of a Word cannot be demonstrated from the fact that God knows himself; for through the same pure act there are verified in God both what is knowing and what is known. (Fs)

665f Similarly, in God the existence of a Word cannot be demonstrated from the fact that God knows many other things. For every act of understanding apprehends many things as one. This apprehension of many realities together implies multiplicity neither in the act of understanding itself, nor in the species by which understanding occurs, nor in its primary object, nor, per se, in other things besides the act of understanding. No multiplicity is implied in the act of understanding itself, because it is a single intellectual apprehension of many things. No multiplicity is implied in the species by which understanding occurs, for this species is to the act of understanding as first act is to second act and therefore, since the second act is one, so also is the first act. No multiplicity is implied in the primary object, for in it many things are understood not in a multiplicity but in and through a unity. No multiplicity per se is implied in other things besides the act of understanding, for the act of understanding per se is the ultimate source of multiplicity and produces multiplicity not of necessity but by a wholly free decision. (Fs) (notabene)

667a One may object that multiplicity in the primary object is implied insofar as many other realities are contained eminently in the divine essence and virtually in the divine power. (Fs)

667b To this we would reply that 'to be contained eminently in the essence and virtually in the power' means simply that the intellect understands many other things in one absolutely simple essence or power. In other words, according to our way of conceiving things, what are contained eminently in the divine essence or virtually in the divine power add to the mere essence or power not real relations but conceptual relations (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 15, a. 2, ad 4m). (Fs)

667c One may further object, with Scotus, that those relations would not be conceptual relations but real relations. For God's knowledge is perfectly objective. If, then, those relations are in the divine essence prior to every act of the divine mind, they are indeed seen by God but they are real relations because they precede the act of his mind. If, on the other hand, they are not in the divine essence prior to every act of the divine mind, they are obviously conceptual relations but cannot be seen by God's perfectly objective knowledge. See [Duns Scotus] In I Sent. (Opus Oxoniense), d. 35, q. unica, n. 7 (Vives x, 544). (Fs)

667d Our answer to this objection of Scotus is that certainly it is valid if one grants the Platonic principle that in all knowledge, and indeed by the very nature of knowledge, there is a duality, so that an object is somehow prior to knowledge. If, on the contrary, one affirms Aristotle's principle that all knowledge is grounded upon an identity, the whole objection vanishes. For if the one who understands and the act of understanding and that which is understood are one and the same, the criterion for distinguishing between real relations and conceptual relations depending on whether they precede or follow every act of the mind cannot be applied.1

667e Note that this is the same solution to the argument in favor of a formal distinction on the side of the reality. Scotus maintains that God's objective intuition either sees paternity as totally identical with divinity on the side of the reality or sees it as in some way distinct on the side of the reality. Well, if you grant this, Scotus has won his point. If you deny it, then on the side of the reality paternity is totally identical with divinity, so that the Son cannot be seen as God without by the same token being seen as Father. The solution to this is to deny the supposition: God's act of understanding and his essence are not two different things; and both the Father and the Son perfectly understand the mystery that each is identical with the divine essence without being identical with each other. (Fs; nicht klar dieser Absatz)

669a A further objection might be raised that we are unable to understand a multiplicity of things without uttering a multitude of inner words; and therefore since God perfectly understands an infinity of things, he must utter at least one Word. (Fs)

669b In reply we would say that we understand many things through many words because we proceed through several acts in which we understand particular things to an understanding of these several things in a unity. And yet when we have understood several things in a unity we also are wont to utter a single word, words like 'geometry,' 'history,' 'Catholicism,' 'romanticism.' But whether we utter one word or many, we do not on that account understand more; for since every word proceeds from the knowledge of the one who understands, every single thing must be understood before being conceived or uttered, and nothing more is contained in the word than is understood in the act of understanding itself - something that can be seen in a way in people who do not understand very much but spout a great deal of sesquipedalian verbiage. Now, God in a single intellectual intuition perfectly understands both himself and all other things. Without this understanding he could not utter both himself and all else in a single Word; and given this understanding, since he already has a perfect understanding of all things, it is not apparent to us why he should utter any Word. (Fs)

669c A further objection might be that the existence of a Word in God can be demonstrated; for every pure perfection must be acknowledged to be in God as we know God by our natural knowledge. But an intellectual emanation is the best and greatest perfection to be found among creatures; therefore an intellectual emanation must be acknowledged to exist in God. (Fs) (notabene)

669d Our answer to this objection is that a pure perfection must be acknowledged to be in God if it is known by natural reason to be pure, but not if it is known to be such by faith alone. (Fs)

Now by our human reason we do not know intellectual emanation to be a pure perfection, although from what we know by faith we may conclude with some probability that it is. (Fs) (notabene)
On the basis of this distinction we deny the objection. (Fs)

669e Finally, in order to understand the solution to these and all other difficulties, one must keep in mind the distinction between a quidditative knowledge of God by which he is known in his essence and the analogical knowledge of God by which from his effects, by way of proportion, negation, and excess, God is conceived and his existence proven. (Fs) (notabene)

671a If God is known in his essence, then certainly the divine procession of the Word is also known. But all that we can conclude from this is that the procession of the Word in God is necessary with respect to itself, quoad se, for in this life we do not know what God is. (Fs)

671b But if God is known only by way of analogy, then (1) it is certain that God both understands and is understood, and yet from this the procession of the divine Word cannot be proven; (2) it is certain that God knows many other things, but neither from this can the procession of the Word be proven; (3) without revelation it is not certain that the intellectual emanation of the Word is a pure perfection, (a) because all realities are present in God in a more eminent way than in us, (b) because we cannot positively reconcile the utter simplicity of God (which is demonstrable) with the plurality introduced by an emanation, and (c) because one cannot argue from an emanation to the notion of person as a subsistent relation by the light of reason alone; but (4) given divine revelation, human reason, enlightened by faith, has gradually over the course of many centuries arrived at some understanding of this mystery, albeit imperfect and merely analogical. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Liebe, Hervorgang, Analogie; das Gute 1-4 (konkret; analoges Wissen davon; Ordnungsgut; Weisheit); universales (durch Wesenheit) - partikuläres Gut; Kosmos, Ordnung, Inkarnation

Kurzinhalt: Since to love is to will good to someone or something ... it seems we ought to start from good as the object of love...

Textausschnitt: 26 The Analogy of Proceeding Love

671c Since to love is to will good to someone or something (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 20, a. 3), it seems we ought to start from good as the object of love. (Fs)

671d First, then, every good is concrete. The true and the false, since they are in the mind, can be abstract and universal inasmuch as things are known not in act but in potency, and not completely but incompletely ([Aristotle] Metaphysics, XIII, 10, 1087a 15-19). But good and evil, on the other hand, are not in the mind but in things (In VI Metaphys., lect. 4, § 1240), and hence every good is concrete. For good and being and ontological truth are convertible. (Fs)

671e Second, as being is known only analogically, so also can we in this life know good only analogically. And so just as we go from finite beings by way of a certain proportion to arrive at some sort of conception of being itself, in the same way we must proceed from particular goods to the universal good. 'The universal good is that which is good in itself and by its essence, because it is the very essence of goodness itself; but a particular good is good by participation' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 103, a. 2 c). Hence, as the divine essence is the universal principle of all being, so the divine goodness is the universal principle of all good. It follows, therefore, that all things desire God by the very fact that they desire any thing in any way (ibid. q. 44, a. 4, ad 3m). For insofar as they desire something, they desire it on account of some good; and if they desire something on account of some good-by-participation, all the more do they desire it on account of the universal good, since that which gives to a thing a certain perfection, itself possesses that perfection all the more. (Fs)

673a Third, in addition to particular goods which need to be put into some order, there exists the good of order itself whereby they are ordered. Thus, men seek economic goods and devote all their physical and mental resources to securing them; but much more do they desire and eagerly strive for the good of the economic order itself, without which all industrial and commercial activity grinds to a halt. Hence Aquinas's remarks about the excellence of order, (1) that 'the universe [Greek: cosmos, 'order'] as a whole is a more perfect participation and manifestation of the divine goodness than is any individual creature whatsoever' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 47, a. 1 c), (2) that 'the end of the universe is a good existing within it, namely, the order of the universe itself (ibid. q. 103, a. 2, ad 3m), (3) that intellectual creatures, although governed [by divine providence] for their own sake, are nevertheless further ordered for the sake of the perfection of the universe which itself is ordered to God as its ultimate end (Summa contra Gentiles, 3, c. 112, ¶10, §2865), and (4) that the Incarnation of the Word is ordered to the restoration of the order of the universe (Summa theologiae, 3, q. 1, a. 3). (Fs)

673b Fourth, to set things in order is the work of wisdom. And so just as God grasps in his own essence the idea of the entire actually existing order in such a way as to have a proper knowledge of all things according to all their determinations and relations (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 15, a. 2 a), so likewise must God be said to grasp in his own essence the ideas of all possible orders with all their determinations; 'for divine wisdom comprehends absolutely all that God's power can do' (ibid. q. 25, a. 5 c). From this we may conclude that the divine goodness is so good as to be the principle and foundation of all good both actual and possible. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Liebe, Hervorgang, Analogie; das Gute 5 (Wille - Vernunft); Notion d. Willens: Objekt, Vernunft, Endziel; Präexistenz - Ursache; intellektuelle Emanation - Hauchung (spiratio): aktiv (Vernunft), passiv (Wille)

Kurzinhalt: ... the essential notion of will consists in this, that it is an inclination that follows the intellect, so that it not only wills the object presented to it by the intellect but also wills it on account of the motive or end for which the intellect ...

Textausschnitt: 673c Fifth, as we proceed from good to order and from order to wisdom, so we must proceed from wisdom to will. Beings that have a natural mode of existence also have a natural inclination to operate in accordance with their mode of existence. But those that have an intentional mode of existence, either in sense or in an intellect, are inclined to action not by themselves but by a conjoined appetite, sentient or rational as the case may be (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 80, a. 1). Therefore, the essential notion of will consists in this, that it is an inclination that follows the intellect, so that it not only wills the object presented to it by the intellect but also wills it on account of the motive or end for which the intellect judges that the object ought to be willed. (Fs; tblStw: Wille) (notabene)

673d The following will illustrate this intrinsic dependence of the will upon the intellect: 'Effects proceed from a causal agent inasmuch as they preexist in it; for every agent produces some likeness to itself. Effects preexist in their cause, however, according to the manner of the cause. Hence, since the divine act of existence is its act of understanding, its effects preexist in it in an intellective manner, and accordingly they proceed from it in an intellective manner. Consequently they also proceed in a volitional manner; for its inclination to do what the intellect has conceived pertains to its will' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 19, a. 4 c). (Fs)

675a Be careful, therefore, not to think of the will as if it were a natural appetite ignorant of its object, or as if it were an animal appetite that knows its object and desires it as known but without any concern about motives or ends. For the will is such that it not only desires good ordered in an intelligible way but also desires it because of the principle of that order, that is, the end - in other words, it desires value. (Fs)

675b Besides, as the will is moved by its object because of a motive, so an inner word or concept moves the will not only as attracting it by presenting it with an object that is good, but also as obliging this rational appetite in a rational way by determining a motive or end. This intellectual emanation is called spiration, and is active on the part of the intellect but passive on the part of the will. (Fs) (notabene)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Liebe, Hervorgang, Analogie; das Gute 6, 7 (Wille, Liebe, complacentia; Liebe als Prinzip d. Einheit); Liebe im Liebenden : Gewusste im Wissend (Unterschied, Quasi-Identifikation)

Kurzinhalt: Sixth, of all the acts that the will performs, the most fundamental is love. Love is a certain contented quiescence (complacentia) in what is good ...

Textausschnitt: 675c Sixth, of all the acts that the will performs, the most fundamental is love. Love is a certain contented quiescence (complacentia) in what is good; all the other acts of the will are grounded in love and are different from love insofar as they are concerned with something that is connected with or opposed to the object of love. Thus, longing is concerned with a good that is absent, hope with a future good, joy with a present good, hatred with an evil that is opposed to good, sadness with a present evil, and so forth. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 20, a. 1 c. (Fs) (notabene)

675d Seventh, love is a principle of unity both by reason of its object and by reason of the act itself. (Fs)

Love is unitive by reason of its object because, since every good is a good for someone, love looks to two things, namely, the good which it wills and the one for whom it wills that good (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 20, a. 3). Also, since the good of order itself is the greatest good, a love that is good wills particular goods for those to whom those goods properly belong in accordance with the wise ordering of things. Thus order is observed in God's love for his creatures (ibid, and a. 4), and created charity itself is regulated by order (ibid. 2-2, q. 26). (Fs)

675e Love is unitive by reason of its act inasmuch as the love in the lover is in a way the beloved in the lover. This is partly like and partly different from the way in which what is known is in the knower. (Fs)

675f It is similar with respect to the conditions for the correspondence of truth. The statement, 'This man is known,' is true as long as there exists in someone an act of knowing this person. It is similarly true that 'This man is loved' as long as there exists in someone an act of loving this man. And so 'being known' and 'being loved' are not in the one known or loved but in the one who knows or loves. (Fs)

677a But there [eg: is] a difference according to the way in which being known is in the knower and being loved is in the lover. A man being known is in the knower according to an intellective, an intentional, mode of being. But a man being loved is in the lover, not by way of an intentional representation, but by way of a real inclination and a quasi-identification. For a friend is said by his friend to be dimidium animae meae, 'half of my soul'; and a lover lives not for himself alone but also, and perhaps more so, for the other person (Summa theologiae, 1-2, q. 28). (Fs) (notabene)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Liebe, Hervorgang; Unterschied 1-5, Analogie: göttliche - menschliche Liebe

Kurzinhalt: A second difference is that we very often love with mixed motives ... A fifth difference is that our love places the beloved in the lover by way of a certain inclination and a quasi-identification; but divine love is God himself ...

Textausschnitt: 677b We are now in a position to proceed to a consideration of divine love on the basis of an analogy with our human love. (Fs)

The first difference is that our love only gradually and with considerable difficulty reaches up to the supreme good, while from all eternity divine love is directed to divine goodness, which it perfectly comprehends. (Fs)

677c A second difference is that we very often love with mixed motives, whereas divine love extends both to the divine goodness itself and to all other goods solely on account of that same divine goodness. (Fs)

677d A third difference is that in us an act of love arises contingently and imperfectly from a dictate of right reason, whereas the act of divine love proceeds from the divine intellect and word by way of an emanation that is intellectual and absolutely necessary. (Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (11/11/10): In dieser Weise -- was von vielen Lonerganeans etwas verächtlich als faculty psychology abgetan wird -- lässt sich gleichsam die göttliche Liebe mit der menschlichen vergleichen, was nicht möglich ist, wenn der Wille in diesem metaphysischen Sinn aufgelöst wird in das bloße "deliberating".

677e A fourth difference is that in us acts of love are multiple and are bound up with the sentient part of our nature (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 20, a.1, ad im and ad 2m); but the act of divine love is unique and simple and separated from all material reality: 'God, however, as in a single act he understands all things in his essence, so in a single act he wills all things in his goodness' (ibid. q. 19, a. 5 c). (Fs)

677f A fifth difference is that our love places the beloved in the lover by way of a certain inclination and a quasi-identification; but divine love is God himself as loved in himself as lover with the fullness of reality and identity. For just as the divine act of understanding is the divine existence itself, so equally is divine willing the divine existence itself. When, therefore, God loves himself, this love is not only God being loved by way of some inclination, but is that very reality that is God (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 3, ad 2m; Summa contra Gentiles, 4, c. 19, ¶7, §3563). Therefore, just as the Word of God is God, so is divine proceeding Love also God. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Liebe, Hervorgang (processio); Folgerungen (corallary), Analogie: göttliche - menschliche Liebe; Hervorgang (processio) von Wort und Liebe: Unterschiede (Zeugung); Liebe in Gott: essentiell - notional; Aussagen über Gott: essentiell - personal

Kurzinhalt: To all the foregoing we may add some corollaries... First, it may seem as if the procession of the Word and the procession of Love are absolutely one and the same, since they do not differ in any respect.

Textausschnitt: 677g To all the foregoing we may add some corollaries. (Fs)

First, it may seem as if the procession of the Word and the procession of Love are absolutely one and the same, since they do not differ in any respect. For they cannot be distinguished on the basis of either their principle or their term, since in both cases God proceeds from God, nor on the basis of their act, since in God understanding and willing are the same reality, nor on the basis of a power, since in God intellect and will are the same, nor on the basis of a conceptual distinction between the divine intellect and will, since a conceptual distinction cannot serve as the foundation for a real distinction. (Fs) (notabene)

679a Now, all this is true, and so must be admitted and granted. Yet it remains that these two processions are really distinct according to the real order between them. For, 'as there is an order between the word and the principle from which it proceeds, even though in God intellect and the conception of his intellect are the same reality, so, even though in God intellect and will are the same, nevertheless, because it is of the nature of love not to proceed except from a conception of the intellect, therefore it follows that in God the procession of Love is distinct from the procession of the Word on the basis of this order between them' (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 3, ad 3m). (Fs)

One must be careful, however, not to say that one of these processions precedes or is prior to the other. In God, 'there is nothing that precedes or is subsequent to anything else' (db 39, ds 75, nd 16); and yet there is an order, since multiplicity without order is just confusion (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 42, a. 3). (Fs)

679b Second, it may seem as if the procession of Love, like the procession of the Word, is also a generation, since in both cases God proceeds from God. But against this is the fact that it is of the nature of generation that there not only proceeds that which is similar in nature [to its principle], but also that that which proceeds is similar by reason of the procession itself. Now, by its very nature the procession of an inner word is such that what is conceived in the word is the very same thing as what is understood by the intellect. But by its very nature the procession of love is such that it does not reproduce its object in the mind but rather that the mind joins and unites itself affectively with the object loved. Therefore, the procession of the word is for a resulting likeness in nature, whereas the procession of Love in God is the procession of that which is similar in nature. See Summa theologiae, 1, q. 27, a. 4. (Fs) (notabene)

679c Third, note here that love in God can be understood in two ways. First, it can be understood essentially, in that divine existence is divine willing and divine willing is love, and in this sense the Father and the Son as well as the Holy Spirit are divine love itself; and all three divine persons equally love whatever God loves. Second, it can be understood notionally, in that love is proceeding love; in this sense only the Holy Spirit is Love because only the Spirit proceeds as Love. In this notional sense of love, the Father and the Son are said to love, not because they are love, but because they are the principle of Love; and just as we are said to love by a love whose principle we are, so the Father and the Son are said to love by the Holy Spirit, proceeding Love. And this Love, since it is God, is that Love by which the Father and the Son love whatever God loves. See Summa theologiae, 1 q. 37.

681a Fourth, speaking more generally, one may say that in reference to God nouns and verbs are predicated either personally or essentially depending upon whether they include in their essential idea a relation of origin. The divine persons are distinguished by reason of mutually opposed relations of origin (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 28, a. 3; q. 40, a. 2). Accordingly, if a noun or verb includes in its notion a relation of origin, it is predicated of one or at most two divine persons, while if it does not include such a relation, it is predicated equally of the three persons. Thus being and existing, intelligence and understanding, love and loving, and all similar notions are predicated essentially, that is, are predicated equally of all three persons on account of the divine essence which they share. But to utter and to be uttered, to generate and to be generated, Word and Image, to spirate and to be spirated, proceeding Love and Gift - since all of these imply a relation of origin either on the part of the originating principle or on the part of the originated, they are said to be predicated personally of the Father alone, or of the Son alone, or of both Father and Son together, or of the Holy Spirit alone, depending upon the relation implied. (Fs) (notabene)

681b Fifth, just as the generation of the Word, so the procession of Love in God, although knowable in itself and necessary, is something that we can know only by faith. The reasons for this are the same as those given above concerning the Word [§ 25]. We can demonstrate that God loves himself but we cannot demonstrate that God spirates himself. Indeed, any who try to do so would seem not to have understood the meaning of spiration; for spiration does not mean that from the mutual love between the Father and the Son something else proceeds; it means that the Father and the Son are one principle from which their mutual love proceeds (Summa theologiae, 1, q. 37, a. 1, ad 3m). (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; Terminologie: Relation, Subjekt, Fundament, innere, äußere R., reales, begriffliches Sein;

Kurzinhalt: relation: the order of one to another;1 its opposite is absolute; and as regards a relation, we distinguish: ...;

Textausschnitt: Are there internal relations?
Terminology

687b
relation: the order of one to another;1 its opposite is absolute; and as regards a relation, we distinguish:

689a subject: that which is related to another; hence to fulfil the definition of subject it suffices to be related to some other, and for now it does not matter whether it be a being-which or a being-by-which,

term: that to which a subject is related,

third term of comparison [also called the foundation, fundamentum]: that with respect to which the subject is related to the term. Further,

an internal relation is one that is so intrinsic to the subject that it cannot be negated without negating the subject also, and

an external relation is one that may be present or absent without affecting the subject. Finally,

real being is that which is truly affirmed to exist, either that which exists or that by which an existent being is constituted, while

conceptual being is that which is conceived and is truly affirmed to be conceived but which cannot be truly affirmed as existing. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen - Argumente 1-2; Akzidenz - Relation - reale interene Relation; Substanz: per se - Natur, in Relation zu Akzidentien, Tätigkeiten

Kurzinhalt: If there are real accidents, there are real internal relations; but there are real accidents; therefore there are real internal relations.

Textausschnitt: Arguments

689b
1 If there are real accidents, there are real internal relations; but there are real accidents; therefore there are real internal relations. (Fs)

The major premise is proved in two steps: (1) if there are accidents, there are internal relations; (2) if accidents are real, internal relations are real. (Fs)

As to the first step: an accident is defined as that whose mode of being is to be in another; but to have the mode of being of being in another is to have a relation to that other; and since this relation is part of the definition of accident, it is an internal relation, since no part of a definition can be negated without negating the thing defined. (Fs) (notabene)

As to the other step: the reality of an accident is the reality of what is stated in the definition of an accident; therefore, the reality of an accident necessarily includes the reality of an internal relation. (Fs)

The minor premise is proved elsewhere, and is commonly admitted. (Fs)

689c
2 If there are real finite natures, there are real internal relations; but there are real finite natures; therefore there are real internal relations. (Fs)

As to the major premise: every finite nature is defined by its relation to something else, namely, to accidents that naturally result from it, and to operations of which it is the remote or the proximate principle. Also, it is clear that no nature can be real without that relation that is in its very definition also being real. (Fs) (notabene)

The minor premise is evident and is proved elsewhere. (Fs)

691a
Corollary: Since every finite substance is also a finite nature, it follows that every finite substance possesses real internal relations. Note, however, that a finite substance can be considered in two ways: first, generically, and in this way it is defined absolutely as that whose mode of being is to be per se, in its own right; second, specifically, and in this way a specific nature can be defined only in relation to its accidents and operations. Thus, a man is both a substance and a nature; but inasmuch as he is said to be a substance he is considered only generically as a being per se, while inasmuch as he is a nature he is defined as a rational animal, where the word 'rational' can be neither defined nor explained except in relation to an intellect. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen - Argumente 3-8; reale interne Relation: Seele, metaphysische Prinzipien (Potenz, Form, Akt, Habitus, Tätigkeit), analytische P., reale Quantitäten, Naturgesetze, organische Teile (Fuß); rationale Psychologie

Kurzinhalt: Finally, there is an abundance of real internal relations in rational psychology, as is clear from the definitions of faculties and habits, from the specification of acts by their objects, from the close connection between the senses and their organs ...

Textausschnitt: 691b
3 If souls are real, there are real internal relations; but souls are real; therefore there are real internal relations. (Fs)

The major premise is clear from both of Aristotle's definitions of the soul. Whether the soul is said to be the first act of a body capable of life, or is described as that principle whereby we live and sense and understand, the very definition of soul includes a relation either to the body or to vital, sentient, and intellectual operations. Now a relation that is part of a definition cannot be negated without negating the thing defined; and the reality of the thing defined necessarily includes the reality of whatever is part of its definition. (Fs)

The minor premise is proved elsewhere and is commonly admitted. (Fs)

691c
4 If the metaphysical principles of things - potency and act, matter and form, essence and existence, operational potency and habit, and habit and operation - are real and really distinct from each other, internal relations are also real. But the antecedent is true; therefore the conclusion is also true. (Fs; tblStw: Prinzipien) (notabene)

As to the major premise: although the metaphysical principles of things cannot be defined, they are explained in terms of a certain proportion. This proportion is in fact a mutual relation and is also internal, since it cannot be negated without the principles themselves being negated. Therefore if these principles are real and really distinct from each other, the internal relations by way of which they are mutually proportionate are also real. (Fs)

The minor premise is proved elsewhere and is quite commonly admitted. (Fs)

691d
5 If there are analytic principles with a relative predicate, there are subjects of internal relations; and if such subjects are real, their internal relations are also real. But there are analytic principles with a relative predicate, and they are truly applied to real subjects. Therefore there are real internal relations.1 (Fs)

693a As to the first major premise: the predicate of an analytic principle can be either absolute or relative, but in either case it is such that it cannot be negated without negating the subject, since an analytic principle is that in which the predicate belongs to the definition of the subject; therefore, if there are analytic principles with a relative predicate, there are subjects of internal relations. (Fs)

As to the second major premise: if there are real subjects of internal relations, there are real internal relations; for an internal relation cannot be negated without negating its subject, and therefore if there is really a subject, there is really a relation as well. (Fs)

As to the minor premise: the principles of efficient causality and of final causality (1) are analytic, (2) relate the caused to the cause, and (3) are truly applied to contingent beings. (Fs)

693b
6 If there are real quantities, there are real internal relations; but there are real quantities. Therefore there are real internal relations. (Fs)

As to the major premise: to say 'how much' is to ask a question to which no answer can be given except in terms of a relation of proportion. Therefore, all quantified things by their very nature stand in some proportion to all other quantified things; and since this proportion pertains to the very formality of quantity, quantities cannot be real without there likewise being real proportions. (Fs)

The minor is evident.2

693c
7 If there are natural laws that (1) from the very nature of things result according to some physical necessity and (2) link things that are real and really distinct from each other, then there are real internal relations. But there are such laws. Therefore, there are real internal relations. (Fs)

The major premise seems evident, since the first point above indicates the internality of the relation and the second point its reality. (Fs)

The minor premise is clear from physics and chemistry, at least if these sciences are understood according to the mind of philosophia perennis. (Fs)

693d
8 If organic parts are found in living things, real internal relations are also found in them. But the antecedent is true, and therefore the conclusion is also true. (Fs)

695a The major premise is clear from the fact that every organic part is the way it is because it performs determined works and functions with regard both to the other parts and to the organic whole. Hence, Aristotle rightly held that the severed foot of an animal is no longer a foot except in an equivocal sense; and the same holds for all the other parts. Now a subject that ceases to be univocally what it is as a result of being separated from other things is conjoined with those others by internal relations; and therefore, if there truly are organic parts, there really and truly are real internal relations as well. (Fs)

The minor premise is evident. (Fs)

695b
9 Finally, there is an abundance of real internal relations in rational psychology, as is clear from the definitions of faculties and habits, from the specification of acts by their objects, from the close connection between the senses and their organs, from the dependence of our intellects upon the senses, from the dependence of appetition upon apprehension, from the ordering of questions to acts of understanding, of acts of understanding to inner words to be uttered, of inner words uttered to acts of will, and vice versa from the dependence of acts of understanding upon questions, of inner words upon acts of understanding, and of acts of the will upon inner words. All these relations are internal because they either belong to the very definitions, or flow from the definitions, or are determined by human nature in its present state. (Fs)



____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen - Einwände, Antworten darauf; interne R.: real - nicht nur begrifflich (Fehler: falsches Verständnis von real); i. R.: bestimmt (Subjekt) - unbestimmt (Term); i. R.: universal - nicht universal

Kurzinhalt: That every internal relation is indeterminate on the part of its subject, we deny; that it is indeterminate on the part of its term we concede to be true in many cases, but not in all... We deny that an internal relation is universal as to what it ...

Textausschnitt: Objections

695c
1 Internal relations seem to be merely conceptual beings, for they are found not in things themselves but only in the possibly false theories proposed by philosophers and scientists. (Fs)

To this we reply that if by 'real' you mean that which is known prior to all intellectual operation, we grant that in that case internal relations are merely conceptual beings. But if the real is being, that which is, that which is known by understanding and judging, then internal relations that are understood and conceived without being affirmed would be merely conceptual beings, but not those that are not only understood and conceived but also truly affirmed to exist. (Fs) (notabene)

695d Internal relations are not only understood and conceived but are also truly affirmed. For above all it is heretical to deny that the intellectual soul is per se and essentially the form of the human body. But the soul is not the form of a body without a relationship to that body; it is not essentially the form of a body unless related to that body by an internal relation; and this internal relation is not a mere conceptual being, for it would be rash to say that the decrees of the Council of Vienne [1311-12] and the Fifth Lateran Council (DB 480, 738; DS 900-901, 1440-41, ND 410) were dealing only with concepts and not with realities. (Fs)

697a
2 No real being is indeterminate. But every internal relation is indeterminate, and therefore no internal relation is real. (Fs)

The major premise is evident, and the minor premise is clear from examples. For the internal relation of proportion between any quantified beings is not specific and arithmetical, such as the double to the half, but is generic and algebraic, such as a to x. (Fs)

697b To this we reply as follows. The difference between an absolute and a relative consists in this, that an absolute reality possesses its entire meaning within itself, whereas a relative reality has its complete meaning only by comparison to something else. We would therefore make the following distinction regarding the major: we grant that no real absolute being is indeterminate; but that no real relative being is indeterminate is true insofar as it receives its determination from the subject, but not insofar as it receives its determination from the term. (Fs) (notabene)

We contradistinguish the minor premise accordingly. That every internal relation is indeterminate on the part of its subject, we deny; that it is indeterminate on the part of its term we concede to be true in many cases, but not in all. For example, the relation of a finite being to its first cause and ultimate end is internal and wholly determinate. (Fs) (notabene)

As to the conclusion, then, we grant that internal relations do not have the determination that is proper to absolutes, while denying that this indetermination on the part of the term negates the reality that is proper to relations. For a relation, as is commonly observed, is the smallest and weakest of beings. (Fs)

697c
3 No real being is universal. But every internal relation is universal; therefore no internal relation is real. (Fs)
The major premise is common doctrine among Aristotelians, and the minor is proved from the fact that an internal relation is concluded to from the universal idea by which a subject is defined. (Fs)

697d We reply by granting the major premise and distinguishing the minor. We deny that an internal relation is universal as to what it intends, while conceding that it is universal as to the manner in which it is intended. For just as we know absolute beings universally without positing absolute universals in things, so in the same way we know relatives universally without positing relative universals in things. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; äußere Relation: Hinfufügung einer neuen Wirklichkeit zu einer internen Relation? Lösung

Kurzinhalt: In light of what we have said, our answer to the question is that an external relation does not add to the reality of an internal relation another reality intrinsic to the subject.

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 34
Does an external relation add another reality intrinsic to the subject besides the reality of the internal relation?

Meaning of the Question

699a Generally speaking, an external relation is more determinate than an internal relation. For an internal relation results from the very notion and intelligibility of the subject. But an external relation arises not from the subject alone but from the comparison between subject and term. Thus, it is of the very nature of an accident that it inhere in some substance, and it is of the very nature of a quantified object that it relate to every other quantified object in some proportion. But it is not of the nature of an accident that it inhere in this substance, nor is it of the nature of a quantified object that it relate to this quantified object in such or such a specific arithmetical proportion. (Fs)
699b Accordingly, since the truth-correspondence between the intellect and the thing must be adamantly maintained, wherever some greater determination in truths is noticed, an equal determination must be acknowledged in things. Hence, since an external relation is more determinate than an internal relation, then, by reason of the truth of the external relation another reality must surely be acknowledged in addition to that which is acknowledged by reason of the truth of the internal relation. (Fs)

699c Nevertheless, there immediately arises a doubt whether that other reality that is proper to an external relation is intrinsic to the subject of an internal relation, or perhaps extrinsic to the subject and to be found rather in the term. Hence the present question of whether an external relation adds another reality intrinsic to the subject over and above the reality of the internal relation. (Fs)

Solution to the question

704a In light of what we have said, our answer to the question is that an external relation does not add to the reality of an internal relation another reality intrinsic to the subject.1

To put it in concrete terms, if A is really and truly twice what B is, then that 'twice' has its truth-correspondence through the reality of an internal relation by which A really regards all quantified beings and, at the same time, through the reality of B which objectively determines that indeterminate internal relation. (Fs) (notabene)

705a Again, if A is really and truly twice B, then that 'twice' does not have truth-correspondence through a reality that is received in A itself and is added to the reality of its internal relation. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; innere - äußere Relation; absolute - relative R. (Peter ein Mann - P. als Freund von X); Vergleich: formal - objektiv; Bestimmung: formal - objektiv

Kurzinhalt: In external relatives, however, truth regards not only the subject but also the term, and therefore in external relatives there is no truth-correspondence except in the two realities, one of which is intrinsic to the subject and the other extrinsic to ...

Textausschnitt: Preliminary clarifications

699d Since questions of this kind have been discussed since the Middle Ages and apparently never settled, it is quite necessary to present first some clarifications in order to obviate any ambiguity or confusion in our treatment of this matter. (Fs)

699e
1 First of all, then, the question is not the one that is usually discussed, namely, whether a relative really adds something to an absolute. For the reality of an internal relation is certainly something relative. Therefore, the only question now is whether a real external relation adds some further reality onto a real internal relation. (Fs)

701a
2 The question is not about just any additional reality but solely about that which is intrinsic to the subject. For it is clear that a greater determination is present in an external relation because in addition to a real subject, a real term is also taken into consideration. The present question is not about what is clear but about what is in doubt, namely, whether in addition to the reality of the term another reality intrinsic to the subject is to be acknowledged. (Fs)

701b
3 Further, it must be clearly and distinctly understood in what respects absolute predicates and relative predicates agree and in what respects they differ. (Fs)

They agree in this, that both predicates, absolute and relative, are truly attributed to the subject. Thus, Peter is truly a man, and Peter is truly a friend of Paul. (Fs)

They differ, however, in this, that an absolute predicate expresses the reality of the subject and that alone, whereas an external relative predicate expresses the reality of the subject and at the same time points to another reality. Thus, 'to be a man' expresses only Peter's reality, but 'to be a friend of Paul' considers not only the reality of Peter but also the reality of Paul. (Fs) (notabene)

701c
4 From this it follows that there is one truth-correspondence in the case of absolutes and another in the case of external relatives. (Fs)

In absolutes, truth regards only the subject by itself, and therefore in absolutes there is no truth-correspondence except in the reality intrinsic to the subject. For example, no being is truly a man by any other reality than his own. (Fs)

In external relatives, however, truth regards not only the subject but also the term, and therefore in external relatives there is no truth-correspondence except in the two realities, one of which is intrinsic to the subject and the other extrinsic to the subject. For example, just as no thing by itself alone is truly twice, so also this truth, 'A is twice B,' cannot have its truth-correspondence in the reality of A alone. (Fs) (notabene)

701d
5 But further, comparison and composition must by no means be confused. Both, it is true, consist in a certain synthesis. But the relative comparison of a subject to a term leaves the subject and the term distinct from each other and really two. A composition of two things, however, makes those two to be simply one being. For example, potency and act can be compared and potency and act can be compounded; but they are compared through a relation, whereas they are compounded inasmuch as these two coalesce into one real being. One must not think that a new reality results from a comparison simply because a new reality does result from composition. (Fs)

703a
6 Again, since comparison properly speaking is an act of the intellect, and yet the subject of a relation is commonly said to be compared to its term in an objective way, in order that real beings not be confused with conceptual beings one must distinguish between a formal comparison, which is made only in the mind, and an objective comparison, which is nothing other than the order or respect of the subject to its term. (Fs)

703b
7 From this it follows that a similar distinction must be acknowledged between a formal determination and an objective determination. A formal determination is in the intellect which apprehends the subject and the term, compares them, and arrives at an affirmation of their determinate relation. Objective determination, on the other hand, does not take place in the mind but is already in things; for a determinable is objectively present, namely, a subject which by its very nature really through an internal relation 'regards' the totality of at least possible terms; similarly, a determinant is objectively present, namely, the term which, inasmuch as it is found among those things that are necessarily 'regarded' by the subject, provides a real foundation by which the objectively determinable becomes objectively determined. (Fs)

703c
8 Finally, although a relation is called a 'respect' or 'regard,' and although a subject is said to have respect or regard to its term, this metaphor should not be taken literally as if the subject looks at or perceives its term. And therefore although a determination of the object perceived is necessarily also in the perceiving subject, one can by no means conclude that the determination that a relation has from its term necessarily produces an equivalent determination in the subject that has a respect or regard to its term by way of a relation. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; innere - äußere Relation; Argumente: eine äußere Relation fügt keine neue Wirklichkeit zu einer inneren hinzu

Kurzinhalt: Furthermore, the opinion affirming an additional reality leads to very serious difficulties... according to the opinion affirming an additional reality intrinsic to the subject, when any quantified being changes, all other quantified beings in the ...

Textausschnitt: Arguments

705b
1 In multiplying real beings, truth-correspondence must be preserved. (Fs)

But the opinion denying an additional reality preserves the truth-correspondence, whereas the opinion affirming an additional reality denies it. (Fs)

Therefore, the negative opinion is to be accepted and the affirmative rejected. (Fs)

As to the major premise: being is known only through what is true. (Fs)

As to the minor premise: as is clear from the fourth preliminary clarification, there is no truth-correspondence in external relatives apart from two realities, of which one is intrinsic to the subject and the other extrinsic to the subject. (Fs)

Now the negative opinion has no truth-correspondence apart from these two realities, one that is intrinsic to the subject, namely, an internal relation, and the other extrinsic to the subject, namely, the term. (Fs)
But the opinion affirming an additional reality intrinsic to the subject has its truth-correspondence through this additional reality alone. (Fs)

We substantiate the minor as follows. In truth, A is not twice B except through the reality of A and the reality of B. In the negative opinion, A is twice B solely through the reality of A and the reality of B; whereas in the affirmative opinion, A is twice B through an additional reality intrinsic to A. (Fs)

705c
2 Again, no opinion is admissible that so fails to distinguish clearly between an absolute and a relative that it tends rather to confuse the two. (Fs)

But such is the affirmative opinion. Therefore it is not admissible. (Fs)

As to the minor premise: as has been explained in the third preliminary clarification, absolutes express a reality intrinsic to a subject, but external relatives express not only a reality intrinsic to a subject but also another reality extrinsic to it. (Fs)

Now, one who because of an external relation as external opts for a new reality intrinsic to a subject surely so fails to distinguish between absolutes and external relatives as rather to confuse them; but the affirmative opinion opts for a new reality intrinsic to a subject because of an external relation as external. Therefore, the affirmative opinion cannot be admitted. (Fs)

705d
3 Furthermore, the opinion affirming an additional reality leads to very serious difficulties. (Fs)
707a Each and every quantified being is really related to all other quantified beings in the entire universe by relations that are real, external, and specific. (Fs)
Likewise, all other quantified beings are related to each and every quantified being by relations that are real, external, and specific. (Fs)

For this reason, according to the opinion affirming an additional reality intrinsic to the subject, when any quantified being changes, all other quantified beings in the entire universe would also necessarily change. But no natural cause can be found for all these changes, which necessarily and instantaneously would occur in accordance with extremely exact numerical laws. Therefore, this opinion is inadmissible. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; innere - absolute - äußere Relation; Thomas, Textstellen; abslute - relative Prädikate;

Kurzinhalt: For a change in a real relation a change in the subject of the relation is not a necessary requirement; a change in the term is sufficient.

Textausschnitt: St Thomas's Doctrine

707b What St Thomas taught on this matter is clear from the following quotations. (Fs)
De potentia, q. 7, a. 8, ad 5m:'... it is not necessary, in order that any new relation be predicated of something, that there be any change in that thing; it suffices that there be a change in any of the terms, for the cause of an order between two things is something inherent in each of them. Hence, any change on the part of that which caused the order nullifies the order between the two.'

707c De potentia, q. 7, a. 8 c: 'It must be said that in this respect a relation differs from quantity and quality in this, that quantity and quality are accidents of some kind that remain in the subject; but, as Boethius says, "relation" does not mean "as remaining in the subject," but "as in a certain transit to another" ... But what is attributed to something "as proceeding from it to something else" does not enter into composition with it, as neither does action enter into composition with the agent. And on this account the Philosopher too proves in the Physics, Book v, that there cannot be motion in "(the being related) to something"; because without any change in that which is related to another, a relation can cease to be only through the change of the other; as also is clear about action, that there is no movement as regards action except metaphorically and improperly; as we say that one passing from leisure to act is changed; which would not be the case if relation or action signified something remaining in the subject.'

707d De potentia, q. 7, a. 9, ad 7m: '... there is nothing to prevent an accident of this kind [relation, action] from ceasing to be without causing any change in its subject; for it does not have the perfection of its being in that subject, but through transition into another; and with the cessation of that transition, the being of this accident ceases with respect to its act but remains with respect to its cause - as when the material [being heated] is removed, the heating also ceases, although the cause of the heating remains.'

709a In V Phys., lect. 3 (Leonine edition, vol. 11, 237, §8): 'In the case of those relations, therefore, whose reality is found in only one of the extremes [subject or term], there is no difficulty in saying that when that extreme changes some new relationship is predicated of the other extreme without its being changed, since nothing real is added to it. But in the case of those relations whose reality is found in both extremes, there seems to be this difficulty, that something is predicated of one of them by reason of a change in the other without any change in the former, since nothing new is added to anything without that thing being changed. Hence, we must conclude that if someone becomes equal to me through a change in him and without any change in me, that equality was first in me in some way, as in the basis upon which it possesses real existence; for from the fact that I have such or such a quantity, I am in a position to be equal to all those who have the same quantity. When, therefore, someone acquires this quantity, that common basis of equality applies to him, and so nothing new comes to me from the fact that I begin to be equal to him as a result of the change in him.'
See also Super I Sententiarum, d. 26, q. 2, a. 1, ad 3m; In VII Phys., lect. 6, Leonine edition, vol. 11, 344; Summa theologiae, 3, q. 16, a. 6, ad 2m. (Fs)

709b In the above passages, note the following points:

a) There is a distinction between absolute and relative predicates: an absolute predicate is 'remaining in the subject'; a relative and external predicate is 'directed or proceeding towards another.'
b) For a change in a real relation a change in the subject of the relation is not a necessary requirement; a change in the term is sufficient. (Fs)

It is not a valid escape to invent a distinction between improper change and change properly so called, since St Thomas expressly says, 'and so nothing new comes to me from the fact that I begin to be equal to him [someone else] as a result of a change in him.'

709c
c) St Thomas's example suggests a distinction between an absolute, an internal relation, and an external relation. Where he says, 'from the fact that I have such or such a quantity,' he states an absolute. When he adds, 'I am in a position to be equal to all those who have the same quantity,' he indicates an internal relation. When he concludes, 'when, therefore, someone acquires this quantity, that common basis of equality applies to him,' there is added a determinate external relation without there being any new reality intrinsic to the subject. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; innere - äußere Relation; Einwände - Antworten; innere R.: kein Schluss möglich auf äußere R.

Kurzinhalt: But a real internal relation is not enough. For an external relation is more determinate than an internal relation, and this greater determination demands some greater reality, or otherwise there is no truth-correspondence. Our reply is ...

Textausschnitt: Objections
711a

1 Unless an additional reality intrinsic to the subject is admitted, there are no such things as real relations; but the consequence is false, and therefore the antecedent is false. (Fs)
To this we reply that this objection would hold only if one denies that there are real internal relations. (Fs)

2 But a real internal relation is not enough. For an external relation is more determinate than an internal relation, and this greater determination demands some greater reality, or otherwise there is no truth-correspondence. (Fs)

Our reply is that it demands a greater reality extrinsic to the subject but not a greater reality intrinsic to the subject. (Fs)

3 But it does demand a greater reality intrinsic to the subject. For what is truly predicated of anything is intrinsic to that thing. But an external relation is truly predicated of the subject; therefore, the reality of an external relation is intrinsic to the subject. (Fs)

We admit that an absolute predicate indicates a reality intrinsic to the subject. An external relative predicate, however, indicates a reality that is simply the reality of an internal relation, not a reality added to an internal relation. (Fs)

711b
4 But the reality of an internal relation does not suffice. For an internal relation has a respect to any of its terms according to some general reason, whereas an external relation has a respect to this term according to a specific reason; therefore, there are two respects which, as respects, are really and truly distinct from each other. (Fs)

We agree that these two respects are distinct conceptually as respects, and we also agree that they are two in extramental reality by reason of the reality that is intrinsic to the subject and the reality that is extrinsic to the subject; but we deny that they are two through the reality intrinsic to the subject. (Fs)

5 But an extrinsic reality cannot make two real respects out of one. (Fs)

We agree that an extrinsic reality cannot constitute an additional reality intrinsic to the subject, but we deny that an extrinsic reality cannot constitute an objective determination of any respect. (Fs)

711c
6 Perhaps there are external relations that lack internal relations which they determine. (Fs)

713a That in reality there are lacking the internal relations that external relations determine, we deny. But in our minds there is lacking that complete understanding of reality that would enable us in each individual case to assign with certitude and without any fear of error the internal relation that grounds an external relation. (Fs) (notabene)

713b It is most important to note, therefore, that the mere understanding of words and the observation of individual contingent facts are sufficient in order to know an external relation. On the other hand, knowledge of a real internal relation requires an understanding of the things themselves. For this reason all our examples of internal relations are taken from the sciences, and that knowledge of an internal relation is not had until those sciences are sufficiently developed as to be able to furnish an object for reflection and analytical investigation. (Fs)

713c But although all real internal relations cannot be assigned until all things are completely understood, we should not doubt that all things are completely intelligible simply because we do not understand them all. At any rate, it seems sufficient for our present purposes to have proven that there are real internal relations in accidents and in finite substances, in souls and in the metaphysical principles of beings, in things that are caused and quantified, and in natural, living, and intellectual beings. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Schöpfung - absolute, relative Realität 1 (beide in einer bestimmten Hinsicht); Terminologie: Schöpfung, relativ, absolut, einfach; Argumente

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 35
Do there exist in creation (1) a simply absolute reality, (2) a simply relative reality, (3) a reality that is absolute in a qualified sense, (4) a reality that is relative in a qualified sense?
Terminology

713d
in creation: hence, prescinding from God.
exist: not a question of concepts but of things.
reality: either of what is, or of that by which what is is constituted.
absolute: opposite of relative.
relative: that which has an order to another being.
simply: in every respect; according to its total reality; without qualification.
in a qualified sense: in some respect, but not in every respect; according to part of its reality but not to the whole of it. (Fs)


____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Schöpfung - absolute, relative Realität 2 (beide in einer bestimmten Hinsicht); Argumente 1; Subjekt - Relation

Kurzinhalt: 2 Every subject of a real relation is absolute... 6 Among created things there exist those that are absolute in a qualified sense and relative in a qualified sense... 8 Among created things there is nothing that is absolute in every respect.


Textausschnitt: Arguments

713e
1 A relation is either internal or external. (Fs)

715a For a relation either is or is not so intrinsic to a subject that it cannot cease to be without the subject ceasing to be. (Fs)

2 Every subject of a real relation is absolute. (Fs)

For since a relation is the order of one to another, it is either the order of an absolute to another or it is the order of a relation to another being. But a relation of a relation is only a conceptual being, and the order of a relation to another is a relation of a relation. Therefore, every subject of a real relation is absolute. (Fs)

3 The subject of a real internal relation is not simply absolute. (Fs)

Anything whose essence includes a relation is not simply absolute. But a relation is part of the essence of every subject of an internal relation, and therefore the subject of an internal relation is not simply absolute. (Fs)
4 A real internal relation does not posit in things a reality that is simply relative. (Fs)

Since an internal relation is part of the essence of its subject, it is posited in things by the very positing of its subject; and every subject of a real relation is absolute. (Fs)

5 A real external relation does not posit in things a reality that is simply relative. (Fs)

It is already proven that an external relation does not add to the reality of an internal relation a further reality intrinsic to the subject. (Fs)

6 Among created things there exist those that are absolute in a qualified sense and relative in a qualified sense. (Fs)

Such are the subjects of internal relations. They are absolute inasmuch as they are subjects, and relative inasmuch as they are relations in their very essence: accidents, natures, souls, the metaphysical principles of beings, the subjects of analytic principles having a relative predicate, quantified things, things subject to the laws of nature, organic parts, faculties, habits, and psychological operations. (Fs)

7 Among created things there is nothing that is relative in every respect. (Fs)

If one such did exist, it would be a relation. But a relation is either internal or external, and neither posits in things a reality that is relative in every respect. (Fs)

Also, whatever is real can be affirmed; whatever can be affirmed participates in the formality of the absolute since it already stands outside its causes and in itself; and therefore every relative, inasmuch as it is real, is in some respect absolute. (Fs) (notabene)

715b
8 Among created things there is nothing that is absolute in every respect. (Fs)

717a What is simply absolute has no real causes, either extrinsic or intrinsic. But that which has no extrinsic causes is not created, and that which has no intrinsic causes is not finite. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Schöpfung - absolute, relative Realität 3 (beide in einer bestimmten Hinsicht); Argumente 2; begriffliche Relation: Gott - Geschöpf; Relation: Substanz - Natur - Akkzidenz usw; R. - Wissen; reale, begriffliche R.; Quantität

Kurzinhalt: As it is true that we know nothing without relations, so these relations are either real or conceptual. Thus, we speak of God as being simply absolute as to what is outside of him not because we know God without relations, but because ...

Textausschnitt: 717b Besides, every created thing is a certain nature. But every nature is an intrinsic principle of operations, and every such created principle is really related to another really distinct from it. (Fs)

Also, if any created thing were simply absolute, it would at least be a simply absolute substance. But, as we concluded above, no concrete substantial entity but only the generic formality of substance is simply absolute, since everything that is a substance is also a nature. (Fs)

Furthermore, we know nothing unless we affirm it; we affirm nothing unless we conceive it; but without relations we conceive nothing, and therefore we know nothing without relations. (Fs)

717c The fact that we conceive nothing without relations is clear on both a priori and a posteriori grounds: a priori, because every finite act of understanding is synthetic as apprehending many things as one; a posteriori, because in going through every primary concept you will always find analogy, proportion, and comparison, such as of essence to existence, potency to act, matter to form, nature to operation, a part to the whole, accident to substance, the sensible to the sense, the appetible to the appetite, the intelligible to the intellect. Similarly, in mathematics rules determine operations, and operations generate numbers of every kind; in physics objects are defined through the laws by which they are connected to one another; in chemistry elements are defined through the various series of relations that are found in the periodic table; in physiology organs are defined by the functions they have with regard to the whole body; and so on. (Fs) (notabene)

717d As it is true that we know nothing without relations, so these relations are either real or conceptual. Thus, we speak of God as being simply absolute as to what is outside of him not because we know God without relations, but because we affirm the relations of God to creatures to be not real but conceptual. Likewise, in knowing created things prescientifically, when we still do not know their causes, we do not know them without relations; but these relations are but conceptual relations, since they pertain to connections that are merely linguistic or, more generally, psychological.1 But when we come to understand them, we know them through their causes; and since their causes are real, their relations must necessarily be real as well. (Fs)

719a Someone might say that quantity is simply absolute. But quantity is an accident, and therefore its mode of being is to be in another; and so as an accident it is related to another. Besides, 'quantity' comes from the question, 'Quantum?' 'How much?' There is no answering this question except by comparing one quantity to another. There is no known quantity, therefore, without a relation, and so the objector would seem to be thinking of some unknown quantity. (Fs) (notabene)

719b But it might be further objected that 'to itself and 'to another' are absolutely diverse formalities, and that therefore an absolute and a relative are two absolutely different realities. Our answer is that 'to itself is the relation of something to itself, and hence is only a conceptual being; but it seems improper to make a judgment about reality according to what are merely conceptual beings. Again, 'not to another' and 'to another' are surely utterly diverse formalities. Besides, they cannot both be predicated of the same thing in the same respect, although there is nothing to prevent them from being predicated of the same thing according to different respects. Thus, a thing is not 'to another' according to the generic formality of substance, and yet it is 'to another' according to the specific formality of nature. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen: transzendental - kategorial 1; Vorbemerkung: Wissenschaft, Definition (3 Stufen); Terminologie: Kategorie, Relation: kategorial (predicamental) - transzendental

Kurzinhalt: Is the division of relations into predicamental and transcendental appropriate? ... Accordingly, since definitions express knowledge, we distinguish in the same way between initial, final, and intermediate definitions.

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 36
Is the division of relations into predicamental and transcendental appropriate?
Preliminary Note


719c Since science is the certain knowledge of things through their causes - something that is not very easily or very quickly acquired by human beings - there is an initial stage in the development of a science in which the causes are completely unknown, a final stage in which the causes are known with certainty, and many intermediate stages in which the knowledge of causes gradually increases. (Fs) (notabene)

Accordingly, since definitions express knowledge, we distinguish in the same way between initial, final, and intermediate definitions. (Fs)

Initial definitions, if they are more than nominal definitions, indicate nothing about things except their external appearance. (Fs)

Final definitions express the very essences of things, their intrinsic constitutive causes. (Fs)

Intermediate definitions are those that are based partly on some clarity about causes and partly on names or on a description of external appearances. (Fs)

721a Again, since the divisions of things necessarily follow their definitions, distinctions about divisions must be made in the same way as distinctions about knowledge itself and about definitions. (Fs)

Initial divisions, then, are those that are made in the initial stage of a science and are based upon initial definitions. (Fs)

Final divisions are those that are made in the final stage of a science and are based on final definitions. (Fs)

Intermediate divisions are those that are made in an intermediate stage of a science and are based on intermediate definitions. (Fs)

Terminology

721b relation: the order of one to another. (Fs)

appropriately, in accordance with a certain stage of a science; as is clear from the preliminary note, there is nothing to prevent the same division from being appropriate to one stage of a science and inappropriate to another stage. (Fs)

predicament [also category]: any of the ten categories that Aristotle listed in a short treatise on logic [The Categories]: substance, quantity, quality, relation, action, passion, place, time, posture, and accessory. (Fs)

predicamental relation: a relation that is found only in the fourth category. (Fs)
transcendental relation: a relation that is not restricted to the fourth category. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen: transzendental - kategorial 2; Theorem 1: transzendentale R. - letzte Ursachen (Potenz - Akt, Materie - Form, Wessen- Sein usw.)

Kurzinhalt: 1 Transcendental relations are not known unless the ultimate causes of things are known

Textausschnitt: Theorems

1 Transcendental relations are not known unless the ultimate causes of things are known.

721c Among transcendental relations are the relation of potency to act, of matter to form, of essence to existence, of nature to operation, of accidents to substance. (Fs)

And among the ultimate intrinsic constitutive causes of things are potency and act, matter and form, essence and existence, nature and operation, substance and accidents. (Fs)

Therefore, at least not all transcendental relations can be known without knowing the ultimate causes of things. (Fs)

721d And therefore, since in the initial stage of a science the causes are not known, there can be at that stage no or at best only a very incomplete consideration of transcendental relations. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; Kategorie - Ursache; Aristoteles: Rückführung der Kategorien zur Kenntnis von Ursachen: Substanz -> Form (Materie), actio u. passio -> Bewegung und Relation; Kategorien - Akkzidenz

Kurzinhalt: 2 The predicaments are not causes... There is a progression from the predicaments to a knowledge of causes. Thus, in Metaphysics, Book VII, substance is reduced to form as to a cause of being ...

Textausschnitt: 2 The predicaments are not causes.

723a The predicaments express the ultimate kinds or categories of beings, and ultimate categories are not ultimate causes. [Our reasons for this are the following.]

[a] In Aristotle there are the ten predicaments which we listed above, but also four causes, namely, final cause, agent, matter, and form. (Fs)

[b] Again, Aristotle treated the ten predicaments only in a work on logic, while he investigated causes in his Metaphysics, Physics, De caelo et mundo, De generatione et corruptione, De anima, and so on. (Fs)

[c] In science there is a serious disagreement about causes, but no such disagreement about nominal definitions or descriptions of appearances. For more than twenty centuries the ten predicaments have remained unchallenged and unchanged. On the contrary, extrinsic causes and especially intrinsic causes have been the subject of great controversy - for example, whether there is a real distinction between potency and act, between matter and form, between essence and existence, between substance and accidents. (Fs)

[d] There is a progression from the predicaments to a knowledge of causes. Thus, in Metaphysics, Book VII, substance is reduced to form as to a cause of being; in Book VIII, material substance is reduced to matter and form; in Book XII, Aristotle posits separate substances, which are forms without matter. In addition, Aquinas made a real distinction between essence and existence and therefore was able to distinguish between God and angels in terms of intrinsic causes, for he affirmed that an angel is a form that is not its existence, whereas God is a form that is his existence. (Fs)

[e] In Physics, Book III, Aristotle reduced action and passion to motion and relation. He defined action as a motion of this thing as being from it, and passion as a motion of this thing as being in it. Now motion is not restricted to only one predicament, since it is found in place, in quality, and in quantity; and the relation of motion either to the agent or to the patient does not seem to be predicamental, since he is discussing motion, not substance. (Fs)

[f] In Physics, Book IV, place is reduced to the immobile first boundary of the container, and time is reduced to the number and measure of motion in terms of before and after. (Fs)

[g] Nine of the predicaments are reduced to a single real intrinsic cause, namely, to accident, that is, to that to which it is proper to be in another. (Fs)

[h] Substance that is the first predicament does not mean the same as substance defined as that to which it is proper to be per se. For predicamental substance is divided into first (this man, this ox) and second (man, ox). Now it does not at all belong to second substance to be per se; for second substance is a universal, and it does not belong to a universal to be per se but only in another, that is, in the mind. Nor does it belong only to first substance to be per se; for first substance is a supposit, which already is per se, and it belongs to a substantial individual essence, which is not a supposit, to be per se. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen: tranzendental - kategorial; Wissenschaft (mittleres Stadium): Wissen deskriptiv und durch Ursachen

Kurzinhalt: First, since transcendental relations suppose a knowledge of causes, they are surely not considered in the initial scientific stage ... Second, since in the final stage a science is so completely developed that the realitities are known with ...

Textausschnitt: 3 Only in the intermediate scientific stage are relations divided into predicamental and transcendental, and even in that state such a division is not very suitable.

725a First, since transcendental relations suppose a knowledge of causes, they are surely not considered in the initial scientific stage, in which the causes are unknown. (Fs)

Second, since in the final stage a science is so completely developed that the realities are known with certitude through the causes, all consideration of the predicaments is now omitted, since the predicaments are not causes. (Fs) (notabene)

Third, in the intermediate stage, wherein the realities are defined partly according to their causes and partly by nominal definitions or by external appearances, there certainly can be a division of relations according to which they are found in a particular predicament or over several predicaments. (Fs)

Fourth, this division is not very suitable even in the intermediate stage. Science is defined as certain knowledge of things through their causes; but the aforesaid division of relations according to the predicaments seems to suppose that a science is a certain knowledge of things not through causes but through the predicaments. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen: tranzendental - kategorial; Antwort auf Einwände (dass Kategorien keine konstituierende Prinzipien seien); operatio, actio - energeia poiesis; Entgegnung zu Krempel: die Relation von Potenz zu Akt usw. nur konzeptuell

Kurzinhalt: Hence he [Krempel] concluded that real transcendental relations were introduced into Thomism not only later on but even contrary to the mind of St Thomas.

Textausschnitt: Objections

725b
1 The essences of things are intrinsic constitutive causes. But essences are defined by genus and [specific] difference. Therefore predicaments, which are ultimate genera, belong to the knowledge of causes itself. (Fs)

Reply. That a definition by any genus and any difference is a definition of an essence, we deny; that a definition by a genus that expresses a cause and by a difference that expresses a cause is an essential definition, we grant. We deny that predicaments are genera that per se express causes, although they might per accidens express causes, inasmuch as they are the starting point from which the search for causes could begin. (Fs) (notabene)

725c
2 Intrinsic causes are those to which other things are ultimately reduced. But other things are reduced in this way to predicaments. Therefore, predicaments are intrinsic causes. (Fs)

The minor premise is proven by the following example: every immanent operation is reduced not to the predicament of action but to the predicament of quality; and this sort of reduction is a reduction to another as ultimate. (Fs)

727a [Reply]: We distinguish the major premise as follows: that an intrinsic cause is that to which something else is ultimately reduced whereby it is better known with respect to us, we deny; but whereby it is better known with respect to itself, we grant. (Fs)

And we distinguish the minor premise accordingly: other things are reduced to predicaments to know them better with respect to us, we grant; but to know them better as they are in themselves, we deny. (Fs)

727b As to the above example: the difficulty arises from the fact that the medieval Latin words operatio and actio were used indifferently to signify what the Greeks without any confusion indicated by the words energeia and poiesis. Also, that difference which is expressed through a reduction to predicaments is even more clearly manifested through reduction to causes. For operatio or actio as poiesis refer to an exercise of efficient causality; but actio or operatio as energeia refer to second act, and second act is explained by way of a fundamental proportion, namely, that of potency to act. For example, as the possible intellect is to an intelligible species as first potency to first act, so the intelligible species is to the act of understanding as second potency to second act. See De potentia, q. 1, a. 1 c. (Fs) (notabene)

Excursus

727c According to A. Krempel,1 St Thomas taught that there was no real relation except that of substance to an actually existing term;2 that therefore relations present in the six last predicaments,3 the relation of potency to act,4 the relation of essence to existence,5 and the relation of matter to form6 were not real but only conceptual relations. Hence he concluded that real transcendental relations were introduced into Thomism not only later on but even contrary to the mind of St Thomas.7

727d This same author, however, did acknowledge as being against his thesis that a real relation of one accident to another was affirmed in Summa theologiae 1, q. 28, a. 1, ad 4m.8 But in order to explain this fact, he resorted to two hypotheses: either that those articles on the trinitarian relations were composed by a secretary, or that St Thomas himself was mentally fatigued.9

729a But these two hypotheses seem to us to be scarcely probable, since here in dealing with the trinitarian relations you will find a new and extremely astute ordering of the material such as could be attributed neither to an inexperienced secretary nor to a mentally fatigued Aquinas. Therefore, this author's thesis, insofar as it is negative and exclusive, must be judged to be false. (Fs)

Besides, the passages we have referred to above which deny that a subject necessarily acquires or loses a certain reality by the fact that it acquires or loses a real relation, the author interprets as follows,10 saying that the distinction between 'to be changed' and 'to become' has been imported from elsewhere and inserted into the text in order to save the systematic thesis; and the word 'nothing' in In V Phys. (lect. 3) is passed over in silence.11 This sort of interpretation once again leads us to deny the author's thesis in its negative and exclusive aspect. (Fs)

729b Nevertheless, since there is no smoke without fire, we feel that we must by all means grant that there are many things in St Thomas that favor this author's thesis. As to how they are to be understood, however, we think it is in some way indicated from the present question, namely, that in every science there are initial, intermediate, and final stages both with respect to a knowledge of causes and with respect to a systematic presentation of this knowledge. And the more one has contributed to the development of a science, the more one knows the causes and the less12 one is able to make use of a systematic presentation of this knowledge. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen (real geschaffene): bezüglich Wesen (intern - extern), bezüglich Sein (ens quod - ens quo); Terminologie,

Kurzinhalt: Are real created relations appropriately divided into internal and external as regards essence, and into beings-which and beings-by-which as regards existence? ... In terms of existence, the division of relations into beings-which and beings-by-which ...

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 37
Are real created relations appropriately divided into internal and external as regards essence, and into beings-which and beings-by-which as regards existence?
Terminology

729c
relation: the order of one to another.
created: no reference, therefore, to the divine relations.
731a

real: that which is truly affirmed to be.

appropriately: that is, with respect to the final scientific stage in which things are known with certainty through their causes.

division: true negative comparisons; for example, 'This is not that.'

essence: that which is known through the first intellectual operation in answering the question, What is it?

existence: that which is known through the second intellectual operation in answering the question, Is it?

internal: that which is intrinsic to a subject in such a way that it cannot be negated without negating the subject. (Fs)

external: that which is not intrinsic to a subject in such a way that it cannot be negated without negating the subject. (Fs)

being-which (eg: ens quod): that which is; that which is truly affirmed to be. (Fs)

being-by-which (eg: ens quo): that by which that which is is constituted; that which is truly affirmed to be, not, however, as what is, but as that by which something is. (Fs)

Arguments

731b
1 The division into essence and existence is appropriate, for all our knowledge is ultimately reducible to the first and second intellectual operations. (Fs)

2 In terms of essence, the division of relations into internal and external is appropriate. For every relation is an order of a subject to a term; an internal relation is a relation that belongs to the very definition of the subject; an external relation is a relation as objectively determined by a term. (Fs) (notabene)

3 In terms of existence, the division of relations into beings-which and beings-by-which is appropriate. For science is the certain knowledge of things through their causes. But things are beings-which, and the intrinsic causes of things are beings-by-which. Moreover, the reality of a being-which is not the same as the reality of a being-by-which; for beings-which are those things that simply are, and beings-by-which are those things that themselves are not but that by which something is. Finally, since neither a simply absolute nor a simply relative being exists among created things, it is clear that the reality of every real relation is the reality of either some being-which or of some being-by-which. (Fs) (notabene)

731c This division, then, of relations into beings-which and beings-by-which is what is foreshadowed in the intermediate stage of science by the division into predicamental and transcendental relations. (Fs)

Objection

733a It is not proper to divide relations into internal and external, since external relations do not add another reality to the reality of an internal relation. (Fs)

Reply: the appropriateness of the division of relations in terms of essence is not measured according to the reality of that which is divided. Besides, although an external relation adds no further reality intrinsic to the subject, nevertheless it is objectively determined by another reality extrinsic to the subject. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; mehrer (innere reale) R. eines Absoluten 1; Beispiel: Seele (Bezug zum Körper, Vitalen usw.), actio, passio (Bewegung), R. d. Trinität: real u. innerlich zu Gott

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 38/1 -- Can several real relations be internal to one and the same absolute? ... Besides, the trinitarian relations are both real and internal to God, since whatever is in God also exists necessarily.

Textausschnitt: QUESTION 38
Can several real relations be internal to one and the same absolute? Are they really distinct from the absolute? Are they really distinct from one another?
As to the first question

733b It is obvious from examples that there can be several internal real relations of one and the same absolute. (Fs)

For the soul is really related to the body as well as to vital, sentient, and intellectual operations; and these relations are internal, for they are in the very definitions of soul. (Fs)

Also, action and passion are one and the same act, differing by relation in that action is the act of this as from this, while passion is the act of this as in this. See In III Phys., lect 5; Summa theologiae, 1, q. 28, a. 3, ad im. Further, since every effect produced by a creature is necessarily really from the agent and really in the patient, these relations are both real and internal to the effect. (Fs)

Besides, the trinitarian relations are both real and internal to God, since whatever is in God also exists necessarily. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; mehrer (innere reale) R. eines Absoluten 2; reale innere Relationen: kein realer Unterschied zum "Absoluten", dem sie innerlich sind

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 38/2 -- Can several real relations be internal to one and the same absolute? ... Are they really distinct from the absolute? ... it is clear ... (2) that the reality of what is absolute in a qualified sense cannot be really distinct from ...

Textausschnitt: As to the second question

733c Those are distinct of which one is not the other. (Fs)

Those are conceptually distinct of which one as conceived is not the other as conceived. (Fs)

Those are really distinct of which one as real is not the other as real. (Fs)

733d From what we determined above (question 35), it is clear (1) that the reality of what is simply absolute and the reality of what is simply relative cannot be the same reality, (2) that the reality of what is absolute in a qualified sense cannot be really distinct from every relative reality, (3) that the reality of what is relative in a qualified sense cannot be really distinct from every absolute reality, and (4) that the reality of an internal relation is the reality of a relative in a qualified sense. (Fs)

735a From this it is also clear that real internal relations cannot be really distinct from the absolute to which they are internal. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; mehrer (innere reale) R. eines Absoluten 3; gegensetige entgegengesetze R.; reale Unterscheidung (Beispiel: Vater - Sohn: Vater wäre sein eigener Vater); nicht entgegengesetzte R zu einem A.: begrifflich (Seele -> Leib, Tätigkeiten usw.)

Kurzinhalt: QUESTION 38/3 -- Can several real relations be internal to one and the same absolute? ... Are they really distinct from one another? ...

Textausschnitt: As to the third question

735b For the solution to this question we must distinguish between mutually opposed relations and relations that regard different terms. (Fs)

Real relations that are mutually opposed necessarily involve a real distinction; otherwise these relations themselves would cease to exist. (Fs) (notabene)

For example, if a father were the same in every respect as his son, the father would be his own father and the son would be his own son; and since the relation of anything to itself is only a conceptual relation, there would be no real paternity and no real sonship. (Fs) (notabene)
Likewise, if an agent and a patient were identical in every respect, the same thing in the same way would be both in act, as agent, and in potency, as patient, which implies a contradiction. (Fs)

735c On the other hand, real relations internal to one absolute which are not mutually opposed are distinct only conceptually, but the distinction has a foundation in reality. (Fs)

They are distinct conceptually: each relation regards the other as its term. Thus, the soul relates to the body as form, but relates to vital, sentient, and intellectual operations in that it is a nature, a principle of operations. In like fashion an effect is related to the agent as that from which it exists and to the patient as that in which it exists. (Fs) (notabene)
These relations are distinct conceptually with a foundation in reality: the terms which the relations regard are really distinct from each other. (Fs)

735d These relations are not really distinct: the more perfect each one is, the greater is its power; and the greater its power is, the more things there are to which its power extends. Thus, one and the same act of understanding relates simultaneously (1) to the agent intellect from which it exists as from its principal cause, (2) to the phantasm from which it exists as from its instrumental cause, (3) to the phantasm in which it beholds its species illumined, (4) to the acts of sensing from which the phantasms were derived, (5) to the objects of sensation which were known through the acts of sensing, (6) to the simple inner word which proceeds from the act of understanding, (7) to the compound inner word by which the objectivity of the simple word is judged, (8) to the real beings that are known in the word, (9) to the goods that are known through judgments of value, (10) to the acts of the will that are consequent upon the intellect, (11) to the operations that are directed and carried out by the intellect and will; finally (12), the more perfect the act of understanding, the more it comprehends as a unified whole, and thereby extends to more sensible objects, more acts of sensing, more phantasms, more simple and compound words, more goods, more acts of the will, and more operations. These relations are internal, since they belong to the very formality of an understanding that is joined to the body and directs the will and operations. These relations are also real, since the act of understanding itself is real, and there can be no real thing which does not really include whatever belong to its essence. Hence also St Thomas: '... it is not contrary to the simplicity of anything for it to have a multitude of relations between other things and itself; indeed, the more simple a reality is, the more relations accompany it' (De potentia, q. 7, a. 8 a). (Fs; tblStw: )

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Relationen; Relation der Identität: transitiv? (Beispiel: Bruder); Identität - reale Unterscheidung

Kurzinhalt: A BRIEF QUESTION -- Is the relation of identity tranitiv? .. we conclude that the relation of identity is transitive with absolutes, but is not transitive when real and mutually opposite relations are really identical with one absolute.

Textausschnitt: A BRIEF QUESTION -- Is the relation of identity transitive?

737a The symbol xRy means x is related by the relation R to y. (Fs)

The relation R is said to be transitive if, given aRb and bRc, it necessarily follows that aRc. (Fs)

Hence we conclude: the relation of equality or fraternity is transitive; the relation of inequality or sonship is not transitive. (Fs)

737b Our question here is whether the relation of identity is transitive. (Fs)

In reply, we say that identity obtains inasmuch as real distinction is excluded. But there can be a real distinction in two ways: first, by the affirmation and non-affirmation of the same real attribute, for the same P cannot be both Q and not-Q,; second, by real and mutually opposed relations, as we demonstrated above (see [chap. 3, Assertion 6], p. 249). There is identity insofar as each of these ways of real distinction is excluded. (Fs)

737c Now, identity excludes the first way of there being a real distinction; for if a and b are really identical, whatever is affirmed as real of a is also affirmed as real of b; and vice versa. (Fs)

But identity does not rule out the second way of there being a real distinction; for the same absolute b can have two real and mutually opposed relations, a and c. (Fs) (notabene)

737d From this, therefore, we conclude that the relation of identity is transitive with absolutes, but is not transitive when real and mutually opposite relations are really identical with one absolute. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Theologie (Grenzen); theologisches Vestehen 1-5 (unvollkommen, analog usw, nicht selbst-evident, kein sicheres Beweisen): inneres Wort (einfach- zusammengesetz); erste, zweite Tätigkeit d. Verstandes

Kurzinhalt: ... theological understanding cannot lead to truths that are self-evident to us, or, in modern terminology, to analytic principles... only a hypothesis whose intrinsic possibility is imperfectly, analogically, and obscurely conjectured.

Textausschnitt: Section 3: Further Observations concerning the Same Act

743a After dealing with the nature of theological understanding, we must go on to consider how it is related to truth. This relationship is twofold, since theological understanding is related both to antecedent truth and to consequent truth. The truth that precedes this understanding's the truth revealed by God that we are seeking to understand, while the truth that is consequent upon it is the theological truth that emerges from this understanding. (Fs) (notabene)

743b First, then, one must by all means bear in mind that theological understanding is in itself neither true nor false.1 The reason is that theological understanding is, as we explained above, an instance of the first operation of the intellect, while truth and falsehood are found formally only in the second operation. Therefore, if we are considering only understanding, we can say that it is complete or incomplete, proportionate or analogical, clear or obscure, and so on. But as soon as we ask whether an understanding is true or false, we are no longer considering only understanding but have moved on to the next operation of of the intellect, where we ask, 'Is this so?' and weigh the evidence and make a judgment. (Fs) (notabene)

745a Second, whatever we intellectually grasp we also utter or express or manifest in an inner word. But it is one thing to grasp a cause or a reason, and something else to grasp the sufficiency of evidence. So there are two inner words. The first, by which something is defined in terms of its grasped cause or reason, is called the simple inner word. The second, by which what has been defined is affirmed or denied to exist, is called the compound inner word. And so, just as the understanding in the first operation is in itself neither true nor false, so also the simple inner word in which this understanding is expressed is in itself neither true nor false. (Fs) (notabene)

745b Third, what we conceive in an inner word we also express in outer words; and since a simple inner word is true or false potentially, the outer words themselves also are often said to be true or false by metonymy. But this can be misleading: one can pay more attention to the words themselves than to the intention of the speaker. If the compound inner word of affirmation or negation has not occurred, then outer words express only a simple inner word, whereby a definition or a hypothesis is considered, or some other person's idea is repeated; then of course even if there are many outer words, even if all are taken together, even if they contain the words 'is' or 'is not,' still those outer words cannot be either true or false, since they do not carry an intention to assert something, but only to consider or repeat an idea. Thus, the outer words that express theological understanding as such are not true or false even by metonymy. (Fs)

745c Fourth, as theological understanding itself is imperfect, analogical, obscure, gradually developing, and so on, so also the consequent inner word and the consequent outer words are imperfectly, analogically, and obscurely understood. (Fs)

745d Fifth, it is the nature of the human intellect that its second operation naturally follows upon the first. Once a quiddity is grasped, the question immediately arises whether such a thing exists, and when a cause has been grasped, the question immediately arises whether this or that thing results from such a cause; and from considering many quiddities or causes taken together, principles, demonstrations, and hypotheses emerge. Hence, since theological understanding is a first operation of the intellect, one may ask how it is related to the second, consequent operation. (Fs)

745d Now, theological understanding cannot lead to truths that are self-evident to us, or, in modern terminology, to analytic principles.2 For truths or principles of this sort are absolutely certain because they proceed from an understanding that is perfect, is proportionate to its object, and is clear, and admits of no further development. Theological understanding, on the other hand, is imperfect, analogical, obscure, and gradually developing. Therefore, theological understanding cannot ground truths that are self-evident to us, that is, analytic principles. (Fs) (notabene)

747a Again, theological understanding cannot lead to demonstrations that proceed with certitude from the intrinsic reasons or the causes of things. For the force of a syllogism is not intensive but only extensive; it is not intensive, because its conclusion always follows the weaker premise; it is extensive, because what is known through its premises extends to the conclusions. Therefore, since theological understanding cannot ground premises that are self-evident to us, it is likewise incapable of grounding conclusions that are demonstrated with certitude from the intrinsic reasons or causes of things. (Fs) (notabene)

747b Moreover, theological understanding cannot lead to hypotheses whose intrinsic possibility is clearly and perfectly grasped. For a hypothesis is but a simple inner word that inwardly says what is grasped by an act of understanding. Therefore, since theological understanding is imperfect, analogical, and obscure, it is impossible for a word that proceeds from it to be other than imperfectly understood, analogically understood, and obscurely understood. Hence, when something is understood in this way, its intrinsic possibility can surely be neither clearly nor perfectly grasped. (Fs)

It remains, then, that neither a truth that is self-evident to us nor a truth that is mediately demonstrated with certitude from intrinsic reasons nor a hypothesis whose intrinsic possibility is clearly grasped arises from a theological understanding as such, but only a hypothesis whose intrinsic possibility is imperfectly, analogically, and obscurely conjectured. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Theologie (Grenzen); theologisches Vestehen 6-11; 3 Quellen d. Wahrheit für Th.; Offenbarung -> Kirche -> Dogmen;

Kurzinhalt: [Theology ]... can still acquire the formality of truth from elsewhere, and that in three ways... Second, in the sources of revelation themselves and in their infallible interpretation by the church, there are contained many absolutely certain truths ...

Textausschnitt: 747c Sixth, although a theological understanding of itself does not lead to a truth but to a hypothesis, and one that is imperfectly understood, it can still acquire the formality of truth from elsewhere, and that in three ways. (Fs)

First, since theology is knowledge of God and of all other things in relation to God, and since there is much that we know by our natural reason about God and other things, this natural knowledge is an important starting-point and foundation for theology. This foundation, however, since it is incomplete and includes none of the truths of supernatural faith, is not sufficient in itself. (Fs)

747d Second, in the sources of revelation themselves and in their infallible interpretation by the church, there are contained many absolutely certain truths about both God and all other things as related to God. From these truths, therefore, as from premises, one can determine with certitude, or at least with probability, whether the formality of truth may be granted to a theological hypothesis. (Fs)

749a Third, one can begin from a theological hypothesis itself to make deductions. The more fully and accurately their conclusions agree with what we believe or know from other sources, the more probable the theological hypothesis itself can be judged to be. (Fs)

749b Seventh, there will be progress from the tentativeness of a hypothesis to the dignity of a theory if a theological understanding is the sort of synthesis that encompasses all or virtually all revealed truths together, if this synthetic understanding is conceived through an integral system, if this system both arises from natural knowledge and is consonant with supernatural knowledge, and if, finally, it enjoys the explicit and reiterated approval of the teaching church, or indeed, is even prescribed by church authority.1

749c Eighth, since, however, even the truth of a system is derivative and not equally certain in all particulars, one must always distinguish between those things that have been revealed and are believed by divine faith, those that are defined by the church and are believed by Catholic faith, and those to which theologians attach lower theological qualifications. (Fs) (notabene)

749d Ninth, the meaning of any truth is measured by the understanding from which that truth proceeds. Hence, since revealed truth proceeds from God's understanding, it is measured by God's understanding alone. Besides, since in this world God has given divine revelation to no one but the church to be faithfully preserved and infallibly interpreted, it is not for a theological system which proceeds from imperfect human understanding but solely for the teaching office of the church to determine the meaning of both the revealed truth and the sacred dogmas (DB 1788, 1800, 1818; DS 3007, 3020, 3043; ND 217, 136, 139). (Fs) (notabene)

749e Tenth, it is not at all contrary to this that in the course of time theological understanding, knowledge, and wisdom should increase, while nevertheless keeping the same meaning of the revealed truth, the same dogma, and the same content of faith (DB 1800, DS 3020, ND 136). (Fs) (notabene)

749f For the increase of theological understanding, knowledge, and wisdom consists, not in a closer approximation to a still unknown truth by way of increasingly probable theories, but in an ever more comprehensive understanding, knowledge, and wisdom regarding the same truth that has long been believed. The natural sciences, beginning as they do from sense data, find ever more probable and useful theories as their understanding grows, but without knowing the truth until everything is perfectly understood. Theology can by no means be equated with such sciences, since theology begins from a truth of faith and increases in such a way that it always adheres to the same truth; and this adherence is certainly necessary, so that if some other truth besides the one that was revealed were to be understood, then that understanding would not be theological. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Theologie; vertieftes theologisches Vestehen von Wahrheiten (4 Schritte); das V. ändert sich, nicht das Objekt; systematische Exegese - theologisches Vestehen; historische Exegese - Theologie (geschichtliche Heilsökonomie)

Kurzinhalt: Just as the higher angels understand more things through fewer species, so also those who are proficient in understanding revealed truths do not understand one thing after another, but understand the same thing more and more comprehensively...

Textausschnitt: 751a But you may wonder how it can be that the same truth, understood in the same sense, can be less well understood at one time and better understood at another. The answer, of course, is because it is not the object but the very mode of understanding that varies. Just as the higher angels understand more things through fewer species, so also those who are proficient in understanding revealed truths do not understand one thing after another, but understand the same thing more and more comprehensively. This is best illustrated through examples. (Fs)

751b First, then, let us suppose that someone has read all of scripture and correctly understands each and every one of its statements. He understands many things quite well, but, because he understands each thing separately, he simply lacks a comprehensive way of understanding. (Fs) (notabene)

751c Now let us suppose someone else who has not only read all of scripture and correctly understood each of its statements, but has also begun to take a further step. This person makes comparisons between various scriptural texts, prescinds from purely accidental differences, and discovers essentially the same meaning in a number of texts. What she deems to be essentially the same she accurately conceives and expresses in technical terms; and when she has gone over the whole of scripture, comparing, prescinding, discovering, and expressing what she has found, she comes finally to formulate in new technical terms the same revealed truth understood in the same sense. (Fs)

751d In this example, even though the very same truth is expressed, and even though the same truth is understood in the same sense, still it is understood in a different way. For in the first example many things were understood separately, whereas in this they are understood together and as a unity. In the first example not only the essential elements were understood but also all the accidental ones - who is speaking in each of the scriptural utterances and with whom, on what occasion, in what circumstances, for what purpose, what actions were described, what images, figures of speech, or parables were reported, and what emotions, sentiments, and feelings were aroused. But in the second example the focus is on the essentials alone, prescinding from practically all accidental features. And whereas previously only biblical expressions and concepts were used, now only new technical terminology and abstract and essential concepts are employed. (Fs)

751e But let us imagine a third person, one who undertakes a further inquiry. This person has not only read all of scripture, understood all of its diverse texts and compared their differences, prescinded from its accidental elements and discovered, conceived, and technically expressed its essentials, but also has delved more deeply into it. For it is not easy to understand how the truths of revelation, even when reduced to their essentials, are consistent with one another. God is one, yet there are three persons. Christ is God and yet is man. Everything depends upon the gratuitous will of God, yet only by our own merits are we granted the heavenly crown. And there are 600-odd further points1 that call for a new kind of understanding. For the systematic exegesis of the words of scripture is not the same as the understanding of the facts and deeds that are related in scripture. One who understands the essential elements of what is stated in scripture is doing a systematic exegesis and comes upon theological problems. One who seeks an understanding of truths taught in the scriptures has set out upon the road of theology. In the next section, the fourth, we shall tell what this road is like and how multifaceted it is. But right now this point must be well understood, that although a theologian introduces another kind of understanding, he is intent upon understanding the same revealed truth. The meaning of a revealed truth is not changed by theological understanding; rather, that very truth itself, understood in the same sense, is grasped more fully, more clearly, and in a more ordered way. (Fs)

753a Finally, the fourth way in which the same truth is understood is a new step in comprehension. According to Aristotle, science has two meanings: it is science in potency when it is merely of universals; it is science in act when it is applied to particular things.2 Besides systematic exegesis, therefore, there is historical exegesis, which, far from omitting the accidentals, includes them synthetically. Besides systematic theology, there is a theology that is more concrete and more comprehensive, which deals with and seeks to understand the economy of salvation as it evolves historically. This new step in comprehension has over a lengthy period of time been gradually prepared by copious studies in the biblical, conciliar, patristic, medieval, liturgical, ascetical, and other areas of research, but in such a way that its synthetic character is not yet clearly apparent, since today's scholars seem to resemble more the twelfth-century compilers than they do the thirteenth-century theologians in the proper sense. Still, just as the diligence of Peter Lombard and other collectors of 'sentences' initiated and laid the groundwork for the theology that followed, so also those today who are engaged in learned and solid research in scripture and patristics and other fields can surely look forward to a theology at some time in the future that is at once more concrete and more comprehensive. But a legitimate expectation of a future reality is one thing, while a bold premature assertion that it has already arrived is quite another. For if in other sciences all true progress consists in adding new elements while exactly including the old (physicists do not repeat measurements made long ago, although they accept new theories), no one, I think, will fail to notice how much more this conservative law of progress is operative in theology, which is intent solely upon attaining a fuller understanding of the same truth. (Fs) (notabene)

755a We have presented, therefore, four ways in which the same revealed truth can be more and more comprehensively understood. When to these is added the way in which God understands revealed truth and the way in which the blessed participate in the divine understanding, it seems quite obvious that the same truth can be understood in many different ways. (Fs)

755b These observations on the act by which the goal is attained should suffice. For understanding the mysteries is the first operation of the intellect, is imperfect, analogical, obscure, gradually developing, synthetic, fruitful. This understanding, although in itself it is neither true nor false, and although of itself it does not necessarily lead to truth, nevertheless it gets its truth from other sources, both because it follows from the revealed truths themselves, or is at least consistent with them, and because it is an understanding of the revealed truth itself. (Fs)

755c Let it not be said that these distinctions are more subtle than they are useful. It is surely the same being that has both essence and existence. It is the same proposition that expresses either the intelligible, which is also true, or the true, which is also intelligible. But the object that is an intelligible truth as intelligible is formally different from the object that is an intelligible truth as true. The former object as such is attained through the first operation of the intellect, and the latter object as such is attained through the second operation of the intellect. Therefore, although the formal objects are distinguished only through a rather subtle reduplication, still the operations by which these formal objects are attained are really different. But furthermore, as we shall soon see, not only are these operations really distinct from each other, but also the ways or methods that lead to an understanding of the faith through the first operation and those that lead to the certitude of the conclusions through the second operation are vastly different. With good reason Aquinas took very seriously the distinction between arguments from authority and the magisterial disputations. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Wissenschaft allgemein (Wege zum Ziel); Analyse, Synthese, Geschichte

Kurzinhalt: This first movement is called (1) analysis, because it leads from what is apprehended indistinctly to well-defined causes or reasons, (2) the way of resolution, because it resolves things into their causes, (3) the way of discovery, because through it ...

Textausschnitt: Section 4: The Threefold Movement to the Goal

755d After having discussed the goal and the act by which it is attained, we must now consider more carefully the movement that proceeds to that goal. (Fs)

755e In any science that is little developed, it is easy to distinguish between analysis and synthesis, that is, between the way of resolution and the way of composition. For, since we attain a knowledge of causes through inquiry and investigation, there necessarily exists some ordinary, prescientific knowledge by which we apprehend an object without as yet knowing its causes. Therefore, the first movement by which we proceed to acquire scientific knowledge begins from ordinary prescientific knowledge of things and terminates in knowing their causes. This first movement is called (1) analysis, because it leads from what is apprehended indistinctly to well-defined causes or reasons, (2) the way of resolution, because it resolves things into their causes, (3) the way of discovery, because through it are found hitherto unknown causes, and (4) the way of certitude, because the ordinary prescientific knowledge of things is most obvious to us, and therefore the arguments that are most certain to us begin from this ordinary knowledge to bring to light what are more remote from us and more obscure. (Fs; tblStw: Wissenschaft) (notabene)

757a Since science is not only the knowledge of causes but the understanding of things through their causes, consequent upon the first scientific movement there is a second movement that begins from the causes that have been discovered and terminates at things understood in their causes. This movement is called (1) synthesis, because fundamental reasons are used both to define things and to deduce their properties, (2) the way of composition, because causes are used to produce or to constitute the things, and (3) the way of teaching or of learning, because it begins from fundamental and very simple concepts in order that, with the gradual addition of other elements, it may proceed in an orderly fashion to an understanding of the science as a whole. (Fs) (notabene)

757b For examples of the two ways, you may compare the history of physics or chemistry with the textbooks used for teaching these sciences. For from the history it is clear that these sciences begin from sensible data, go on to examine these data, and produce proofs from the most obvious data available. And yet if you go to the textbooks, you will find that they begin [in chemistry] with the periodic table of the elements from which 300,000 compounds are derived, or in physics, Newton's laws of motion, Riemannian geometry, and those strange 'quantum' operators. For inquiry or research or proof begin from what is obvious; but teaching begins with those concepts that can be understood without presupposing an understanding of other things. (Fs)

757c In addition to these two movements there is a third. For the two movements described above are not performed once for all but are continually repeated. Nor is it the same two movements that are repeated, but later research discovers more remote and truer causes, so that the first prior movement is corrected and the second prior movement is sometimes completely revised. In this case what we have termed the third scientific movement is simply the history of the sciences, which embraces within its concrete unity the entire series of all that down through the centuries has been discovered in the way of resolution or set forth in an orderly way in the way of composition. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Theologie; Analogie zu Naturwissenschaften (Analyse, Synthese, Entwicklung); Kirchenväter (Analyse), Mittelalter (Synthese)

Kurzinhalt: First, just as in our natural knowledge there is a prior ordinary apprehension of things by which the things themselves are clearly known although their causes are not, so also in our supernatural knowledge there is ...

Textausschnitt: 759a Now, just as theology itself is analogous to the natural sciences, so also are there three movements in theology that are analogous to the three movements in a natural science. (Fs)

759b First, just as in our natural knowledge there is a prior ordinary apprehension of things by which the things themselves are clearly known although their causes are not, so also in our supernatural knowledge there is a prior knowledge common to all the faithful by which with utmost certitude we accept as true the things that have been revealed by God, even though we have not yet acquired a theological understanding of them. (Fs) (notabene)

759c Next, just as the scientific movement begins from the ordinary and manifest knowledge of things to discover, define, and demonstrate causes, so also human reason enlightened by faith begins from the truths of faith and, having inquired into them diligently, reverently, and judiciously, acquires some understanding of the mysteries (DB 1796, DS 3016, ND 132). (Fs)

759d Third, one who proposes a scientific theory defines systematically all the causes previously discovered and, beginning in an orderly way from the more simple and more basic elements, proceeds through those that are intermediate and complex so as to be able at last to know distinctly and manage effectively the things themselves, as they concretely exist and function, according to all their interconnected reasons or causes. In a similar way, one who not only has some understanding of each of the revealed truths individually but has also arrived at some synthetic understanding of them all, defines systematically all their quasi-reasons and causes and, beginning in an orderly way from the more simple and more basic elements, proceeds through intermediate questions so as to be able at last to give a systematic exposition of everything that concerns God himself and God's creatures, according, as it were, to all their deepest reasons or ultimate causes.1

759v Fourth, since in the intelligible order human beings are as potency only, it cannot be that an entire science possible to us should attain the summit of perfection in one particular period, so that the rest of humanity in future centuries can merely be humble disciples of their predecessors. Hence, in our natural knowledge we see one hypothesis and one theory after another, and in our supernatural knowledge all agree that there has been development not only in theology but also in dogmas. We do not believe that we have already arrived at the summit of theological perfection, nor do we expect that it will ever be futile and superfluous to pray and desire in concert with the [First] Vatican Council that 'there be growth and great progress in understanding, knowledge, and wisdom, both on the part of each and all and on the part of every person and of the church as a whole ...'2

761a If you are looking for examples of this, read the Fathers and theologians. The Fathers were mainly engaged in the first, analytic movement in understanding individual truths of revelation as well as in refuting heretics. The second, synthetic movement developed in the Middle Ages, as first the testimonies of scripture and the opinions of the Fathers were collected and collated, and then, with the help of philosophy, theological summas were constructed in the way of teaching or learning, with the goal of furthering synthetic understanding. Finally, in recent times a certain mixed movement seems to have come into use that sees to and addresses the needs of everyone together. Thus, in theological texbooks you will find the analytic movement in the arguments from the councils, from sacred scripture, from the Fathers, from the common consent of theologians, and the synthetic movement in the series of theses, in the definition of terms, in the arguments from theological reason, and in the solution of difficulties. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Intelligible Emanation (emanatio intelligibilis, Definition); Existenz: real - intentional; in Gott: Emanation - keine Kausalität (unbewusst); Sohn u. Geist a se und nicht a se; psychologische Analogie

Kurzinhalt: 2 Chapter 2, from the Definition of Emanatio Intelligibilis through Assertion I; Intellectual emanation, then, is the conscious origin of an act both within intellectual consciousness and by virtue of intellectual consciousness itself as determined by ...

Textausschnitt: 2 Chapter 2, from the Definition of Emanatio Intelligibilis through Assertion I

761b Intellectual emanation, then, is the conscious origin of an act both within intellectual consciousness and by virtue of intellectual consciousness itself as determined by the act.'2

This emanation is certainly not a conceptual being but real, nor is it an intentional real being but a natural real being. (Fs)

It is a real being: it is not conceived such that it is said not to be, but it is both conceived and affirmed to be. (Fs)

761c It is a natural being: that is, it is not affirmed to be really in the intellect as a medium through which something else is known; rather, it is affirmed to be really in the intellect as belonging to the very nature of the intellect. For whatever we know is really within us, not, however, by way of natural existence but by way of intentional existence; and so right now, when we are conceiving intellectual emanation and affirming that it exists, an intellectual emanation is present intentionally in this conception and judgment. But our intellect itself, and our species, acts, words, will, habits, and volitions all belong to the natural reality that is our intellectuality, and to the same natural reality belong those intellectual emanations of one act from another. And so before we either conceived or asserted anything about intellectual emanation, there were intellectual emanations present within us, not indeed intentionally but really and naturally. (Fs)

763a Besides, although an intellectual emanation is something that is very perfect, still by the natural light of reason it cannot be shown to be a pure perfection; hence, by the natural light of reason it cannot be demonstrated that there is any intellectual emanation in God (db 1816, ds 3041, nd 137). (Fs)

Moreover, even if reason illumined by faith affirms two intellectual emanations in God, so that the Son originates by way of the procession of truth and the Spirit by the way of the procession of holiness, nevertheless reason, even when illumined by faith, can never perfectly grasp these divine emanations (db 1796, ds 3016, nd 132).

763b Still, if we posit such emanations in God, we are already making significant progress in understanding how the Son is both a se, from himself, and not a se, not from himself, how the Spirit is both a se, from himself, and not a se, not from himself, and how the way in which the Son is not a se, not from himself, differs from the way in which the Spirit is not a se, not from himself. (Fs)

For,3 let us assume that there is in God real intellectual emanation. (Fs)

Now that which emanates is necessarily infinite. If it were finite, it would not be God; if it were not God, it would be a creature; if it were a creature, it would be outside of God; if it were outside of God, it is impossible for it to be that which emanates within the divine consciousness. Therefore, it is infinite. (Fs)
763c Again, the infinite is unique. Therefore, that which emanates and that from which it emanates are one and the same. Therefore, God emanates from God, light emanates from uncreated light, true God emanates from true God. (Fs)

763d Furthermore, although that which emanates and that from which it emanates are one and the same God, this does not negate the formality or the reality of emanation. Certainly, nothing is the cause of itself; but we have not posited causality. In fact, we have for some time now been seeking something other than causality, so that the Son or the Spirit would not be created or made, and each would be both God and therefore a se, from himself. (Fs)

765a Moreover, not only have we not posited causality, we have put forward something far more excellent than causality. For causality is simply an imperfect and unconscious imitation of the intelligible order, which is present intentionally in the mind of the creator. But intellectual emanations, as they are grounded upon our created participation in uncreated light, so do they constitute in us that celebrated image of the triune God from which the psychological analogy is derived. (Fs) (notabene)

Further, what can take place in us in three finite acts can be present in God through one infinite act. But through three finite acts we grasp the sufficiency of evidence, by virtue of this grasp of evidence we judge, and by virtue of our affirmation of goodness we love. So through one infinite act God by his intellect grasps his infinite perfection, by virtue of this grasp of his perfection affirms it, and by virtue of this affirmation of his perfection loves. (Fs) (notabene)
765b Yet we should not be surprised at our inability to understand these things perfectly, but should rather expect it. After all, we are dealing with the supreme mystery of the Holy Trinity. Still, the fact that we are not deceiving ourselves is suggested by St Thomas: 'That which proceeds by an external procession must be different from that from which it proceeds. But what proceeds internally by an intellectual process does not have to be different. Indeed, the more perfectly it proceeds, the more is it one with that from which it proceeds.4
Therefore, the Son is a se, from himself, because he is God. And the Son is not a se, not from himself, because he proceeds by the intellectual emanation of truth. (Fs)

765c Likewise, the Spirit is a se, from himself, because he is God. And the Spirit is not a se, not from himself, because he proceeds by the intellectual emanation of holiness. (Fs)
The way in which the Son is not a se, not from himself, differs from the way in which the Spirit is not a se, not from himself, because the emanation whereby truth proceeds is not the same as the emanation by which holiness proceeds. (Fs)

765d Now if these things have been understood to some extent, then, since a concept emanates from an act of understanding, we may proceed to a correct conception of the divine processions. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Trinität, göttliche Hervorgänge (processio) - intellektuelle Emanation; Terminologie; Thomas v. Aquin: psychologische Analogie; tertium comparationis (dreifaltiger Gott - menschlicher Geist)

Kurzinhalt: ASSERTION 1 -- The divine processions are to be conceived through their likeness to intellectual emanation ... That the divine processions can be conceived analogically is theologically certain...

Textausschnitt: ASSERTION 1
The divine processions are to be conceived through their likeness to intellectual emanation

Terminology

765e
procession: the origin of one from another.
767a
divine processions: generation, by which the Son is the the only-begotten (DB 54, DS 125-26, ND 7), and spiration, by which the Holy Spirit proceeds (DB 691, DS 1300-1302, ND 322). (Fs)

concept, conception, inner word: that which proceeds by virtue of intellectual consciousness determined by an act of understanding. Thus, in the first operation of the intellect definitions and hypotheses proceed, and in the second operation affirmations and negations proceed. In more recent usage, the noun 'concept' or 'conception' is restricted to the term that proceeds in the first operation; St Thomas uses the same word for both terms.1 Finally, the divine Word is word in both senses: for just as in God existence and essence are identical, so also in God the first and the second operations of the intellect are identical, and therefore in God the word as definition and the word as affirmation are identical. (Fs)

through their likeness: analogously, hence, neither essentially nor only verbally. (Fs)

emanation: any sort of originating; also called procession, process. (Fs)

intellectual emanation: the conscious origin of an act both within intellectual consciousness and by virtue of intellectual consciousness itself as determined by the act.2

Theological Note

767b That there are divine processions is of divine and catholic faith; see, for example, the Nicene-Constantinopolitan Creed, DB 86, DS 150, ND 12. (Fs)


That the divine processions are to be conceived is theologically certain. What is not conceived cannot be believed. But the church proposes the divine processions as to be believed. (Fs)
767c That the divine processions are not to be conceived through their essence, if conceiving something through its essence is rightly understood, is theologically certain, for to conceive something through its essence makes demonstration possible, and demonstrating a mystery of the faith is anathematized by the [First] Vatican Council (DB 1816, DS 3041, ND 137). (Fs)

767d That the divine processions can be conceived analogically is theologically certain; for according to Vatican I there is some analogical understanding of the mysteries (DB 1796, DS 3016, ND 132); and once there is analogical understanding, analogical conception ensues. (Fs)

769a That the divine processions are to be conceived according to the psychological analogy is the common opinion of theologians with some foundation in scripture and tradition.3

769b That in this psychological analogy the tertium comparationis, in which the likeness between the triune God and our mind is found, is intellectual emanation or procession seems to be the opinion of St Thomas.4 (Fs) (notabene Fußnote)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Trinität, göttliche Hervorgänge (processio) - intellektuelle Emanation 2; psychologische Analogie, tertium comparationis: i. E.; Unterschied: kausale - i. E.;

Kurzinhalt: The divine processions are to be conceived through a likeness to intellectual emanation if this is the only way to conceive them. But there is no other way to conceive them. Therefore ...

Textausschnitt: Meaning of the Assertion

769c The question is whether in the psychological analogy the central element or tertium comparationis is intellectual emanation. This question presupposes (1) everything that has been revealed by God, proposed by the church, and accepted by faith; (2) everything that is generally dealt with in the treatise on God as one concerning the knowability of God and the meaning of the mysteries; (3) everything that is established in the treatise on the triune God in the way of analysis, that is, through deduction from what are prior, better known, more manifest with respect to the faithful. As all these are presumed to be known or to have been determined from other sources, they need not be repeated here. (Fs)

769d The present question, therefore, is placed as the starting point of the way of synthesis, that is to say, as that which must be understood first so that everything else can be understood. (Fs)

771a Besides, since the aim of the way of synthesis is understanding, and since understanding belongs to the first operation of the intellect, the question is about conception. (Fs)

Also, we cannot determine here whether the conception that is proposed is really the first in the way of synthesis; this is determined later, if in fact we get to the end of this way without finding anything else to be first. (Fs)

The Argument

771b The divine processions are to be conceived through a likeness to intellectual emanation if this is the only way to conceive them. But there is no other way to conceive them. Therefore, the divine processions are to be conceived through a likeness to intellectual emanation. (Fs) (notabene)

771c With the antecedents of the way of synthesis being presupposed, the major premise is evident. Since processions exist (DB 86, DS 150, ND 12), they ought to be conceived, at least by theologians. But in this life they cannot be conceived except mediately and through a likeness; for they are really identical with the divine essence (DB 391), and in this life the divine essence is known only mediately and through a likeness (DB 530, 1659; DS 1000-1001, 2841; ND 314; Summa theologiae, 1, q. 12). However, since conception is consequent upon understanding and since the mysteries can be understood imperfectly and analogically (DB 1796, DS 3016, ND 132), the processions also can be conceived analogically or through a likeness. See the brief question [below], p. 785. (Fs) (notabene)

771d The minor premise is to be proved in two parts: first, that the divine processions can be conceived through a likeness to intellectual emanation, and second, that they cannot be conceived through a likeness to any other emanation whatsoever. (Fs)

The first part of the minor is proved as follows:
A divine procession is conceived when there is posited in God that from which there follow the reality of the emanation, the consubstantiality of that which emanates, and our imperfect understanding of both of these taken together. (Fs)

But when intellectual emanation is posited in God, there follow the reality of the emanation, the consubstantiality of that which emanates, and our imperfect understanding of both of these taken together. (Fs)

Therefore, when intellectual emanation is posited in God, a divine procession is conceived. (Fs)

771e The major premise of this syllogism is clear from our analysis of the fundamental problem. For we are seeking an imperfect understanding of the fact that both the Son and the Holy Spirit are from themselves and not from themselves. In concluding to the reality of an emanation, we arrive at the conception of the Son and of the Spirit as not being from themselves; in concluding to the consubstantiality of that which emanates, we arrive at the conception of the Son and of the Spirit as being from themselves; and lastly, inasmuch as both of these elements taken together are but imperfectly understood by us, we arrive at that obscure conception that the [First] Vatican Council mentions (DB 1796, DS 3016, ND 132). (Fs)

773a The minor premise of this syllogism is proven in three parts. First, once an intellectual emanation is posited in God, the reality of the emanation follows. For because it is posited, not only in our mind, but in God himself, it follows that that emanation is in reality, as real being and not just conceptual being. Besides, from the positing of intellectual emanation in God, it follows that that emanation really is in God, not only intentionally as an object known by God but also naturally on the side of God's consciousness, which, in virtue of understanding, utters a true word, and in virtue of understanding and uttering a true word, spirates love. (Fs)

773b Second, from the positing of intellectual emanation in God, the consubstantiality of that which emanates follows. For that which emanates is either finite or infinite. If it is finite, it is a creature, it is outside God, it is not within the divine consciousness, and so no intellectual emanation is posited. But if it is infinite, then, since the infinite is unique, it is God. (Fs)
773c Third, there is an imperfect understanding of divine procession inasmuch as causal emanation is excluded and intellectual emanation is affirmed. (Fs)

For because a divine procession is not a causal emanation, that which proceeds in God has no cause and therefore is from itself. Besides, since nothing is the cause of itself, God is truly said to be from the same God to the extent that causal emanation is excluded. (Fs)

However, because a divine procession is an intellectual emanation, that which proceeds in God has an intellectual principle from which it proceeds, and so it is not from itself; and yet it proceeds within the divine consciousness, and therefore it is infinite, it is God, and, since the formality of a cause has been excluded, it is from itself. (Fs) (notabene)

773d Besides, these very differences clearly show how great is the difference between intellectual emanation and causal emanation. Intellectual emanation is the principle of sufficient reason within intellectual consciousness itself; causal emanation is the same principle insofar as there can be a participation and remote imitation of it apart from an intellectual consciousness that is actually understanding.1 (Fs) (notabene Fußnote)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Trinität, göttliche Hervorgänge (processio) - intellektuelle Emanation 3; Unterschied (Lonergan: Divinarum Personarum - De Deo Trino): kausale - intellektuelle Emanation; Unterschied (Thomas - Aristoteles); Wirkursache; p. operati - operationis

Kurzinhalt: The act of understanding is to the possible intellect, the act of loving is to the will, as act to potency, as perfection to its perfectible... But the inner word is to our intelligence in act as is act to act...

Textausschnitt: 773d Besides, these very differences clearly show how great is the difference between intellectual emanation and causal emanation. Intellectual emanation is the principle of sufficient reason within intellectual consciousness itself; causal emanation is the same principle insofar as there can be a participation and remote imitation of it apart from an intellectual consciousness that is actually understanding.1 (Fs) (notabene Fußnote)

Fußnote 17:

17 [A major difference in content between the two versions appears in their respective treatment of causality. In Divinarum Personarum the difference even in us between the emanation and an exercise of causality is stressed, while in De Deo Trino mention is made of a causality in us that is peculiar to consciousness. In Divinarum Personarum causality is 'imperfecta quaedam et inconscia imitatio ordinis intelligibilis qui in mente creatoris intentionaliter adest' (a certain imperfect and unconscious imitation of the intelligible order that intentionally exists in the mind of the creator) that is not found in the created image of the Trinity, that is, in our emanatio intelligibilis; whereas in De Deo Trino the notion of causality is extended to include a peculiar kind of causality proper to conscious acts. No help is given, though, to indicate just what that 'modum causalitatis proprium conscientiae' might be. More help is provided in the earlier work now available as the book Verbum, where a distinction is presented between the Aristotelian restriction of efficient causality to the exercise of an influence that proceeds from one being to another, on the one hand, and 'a more general notion' found in Aquinas, on the other hand. The following is from Verbum 205-206. (Fs)

Aquinas developed a more general notion of efficient causality than that defined by Aristotle. Thus principium operati, principium effectus, processio operati include the idea of production but do not include the Aristotelian restrictions of in alio vel qua aliud. The act of understanding is to the possible intellect, the act of loving is to the will, as act to potency, as perfection to its perfectible; the procession is processio operationis and cannot be analogous to any real procession in God. But the inner word is to our intelligence in act as is act to act, perfection to proportionate perfection; in us the procession is processio operati; in us dicere is producere verbum, even though it is natural and not an instance of Aristotelian efficient causality. (Fs)

Even more helpful is the following, from ibid. 207, reflected a bit, but not this clearly, in De Deo Trim's explanation of the phrase 'actu priori determinatae.'

There are two aspects to the procession of an inner word in us. There is the productive aspect; intelligence in act is proportionate to producing the inner word. There is also the intelligible aspect: inner words do not proceed with mere natural spontaneity as any effect does from any cause; they proceed with reflective rationality; they proceed not merely from a sufficient cause but from sufficient grounds known to be sufficient and because they are known to be sufficient. I can imagine a circle, and I can define a circle. In both cases there is efficient causality. But in the second case there is something more. I define the circle because I grasp in imagined data that, if the radii are equal, then the plane curve must be "uniformly round. The inner word of defining not only is caused by but also is because of the act of understanding. In the former aspect the procession is processio operati. In the latter aspect the procession is processio intelligibilis. Similarly, in us the act of judgment is caused by a reflective act of understanding, and so it is processio operati. But that is not all. The procession of judgment cannot be equated with procession from electromotive force or chemical action or biological process or even sensitive act. Judgment is judgment only if it proceeds from intellectual grasp of sufficient evidence as sufficient. Its procession also is processio intelligibilis]

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; psychologische Analogie; intellektuelle Emanation: unvollkommenes Verstehen (3 Unvollkommenheiten)

Kurzinhalt: The first imperfection is that we do not clearly and distinctly grasp the formality of intellectual emanation. The only intellectual emanation in us is the procession of one accidental act from another; therefore ...

Textausschnitt: 775a Moreover, it is not at all impossible for being to be understood, the true affirmed, and the good loved in the same act. For acts are necessarily distinguished insofar as they regard specifically different objects. But being, the true, and the good are so far from being specifically different as to be convertible with one another.1

777a Furthermore, it is by no means contradictory for being to be understood, the true affirmed, and the good loved in the same act in such a way that this affirmation is nonetheless really and truly from understanding and this love really and truly from both affirmation and understanding. This would certainly be contradictory if 'from' indicated causal emanation. Likewise, there would be a contradiction if there were different objects specifying the understanding, the affirmation, and the love. Again, there would be a contradiction if the principle of emanation and that which emanates from the principle were the same in every way. But we are positing not causal, but intellectual emanation. Nor do we posit specifically different objects, but objects that are convertible: being, the true, the good. And although it is not the case that one act emanates from another, still one subsistent person proceeds from another subsistent person. (Fs)

777b Once this is well understood, the force of the psychological analogy becomes evident. For in the finite consciousness of one person, one accidental act intellectually emanates from another accidental act. But in the infinite consciousness of pure act, where there can be no accidents, one subsistent person intellectually emanates from another subsistent person. (Fs) (notabene)

777c But if we have demonstrated some understanding, we must must now take the easier road on the opposite side, to determine that this understanding is imperfect. The first imperfection is that we do not clearly and distinctly grasp the formality of intellectual emanation. The only intellectual emanation in us is the procession of one accidental act from another; therefore we can scarcely conceive divine intellectual emanation, in which the emanation is both true and real while the act is completely one and the same. These two appear to be so contrary to each other that, while we can conceive them separately, we can scarcely consider them together. (Fs) (notabene)

The second imperfection is the radical difference between created and uncreated intellectual emanation. In created emanation one accidental act proceeds from another. But in uncreated emanation one subsistent person proceeds from another. Although what follows throws some light on this, at the same time it most clearly reveals the limitations of the psychological analogy. For although in both cases there are one and three, still in the image there is one person and three accidental acts, while in God there is one act and three subsistent persons. Nor is the numerical similarity so significant that the totally diverse enumerated realities can be understood clearly and distinctly on diverse grounds. (Fs) (notabene)

777d Finally, the third imperfection is that not only is it impossible to demonstrate the divine processions by the natural light of reason, but also, after these processions are affirmed in faith, the process of reasoning that leads to affirming intellectual emanations is lengthy, difficult, and obscure. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Psychologische Analogie; intellektuelle Emanation - Ausschluss anderer Arten von E:, Sein: Potenz oder Akt -> Gott nicht Potenz, also...; Agens - Natur; intellektuelle, willentliche Natur

Kurzinhalt: Since being is divided into potency and act ... With all this clearly understood, it is apparent that every other formality of emanation except the processions of intellectual consciousness is excluded.

Textausschnitt: 779a We proceed to the second part of the minor through complete successive disjunctions in order to exclude every other emanation except intellectual emanation. (Fs)

Since being is divided into potency and act, an emanation is either from potency to act or from act to act. But in God there is no potency, and so a divine procession is from act to act.1 (Fs) (notabene)

But the act is either the same or different, and so the emanation is either from one act to another or from the same act to the same act.2 But a divine procession is not from one act to another, for the Son and the Holy Spirit are the same God, and therefore the same pure act, as God the Father. Therefore, a divine procession is from the same act to the same, in the words of the Council of Nicea: 'God from God, light from light, true God from true God' (DB 54, DS 125, ND 7). (Fs) (notabene)

779b Again, the formality of emanation is either in the manner of an agent or in the manner of a nature; for an agent is the principle of an act in another, whereas a nature is the principle of act in that in which the nature is. But a divine procession is not in the manner of an agent. For, first of all, the Son is not made or created, and the Spirit is not made or created (DB 39, DS 75, ND 16 ). And besides, every emanation in the manner of an agent is based on causality; but nothing is the cause of itself, and therefore an emanation of the same act from the same act cannot be in the manner of an agent. It remains, then, that a divine procession is in the manner of a nature. (Fs) (notabene)

779c Further, a nature is either material or spiritual. But God is in no way material; therefore a divine procession is in the manner of a spiritual nature. (Fs)

Moreover, to the extent that a spiritual nature is not known to us, no likeness is available to us for conceiving the divine processions. Hence, we have to consider a spiritual nature with respect to what is known to us, namely, what consists in intellect and will. Therefore, the divine processions must be conceived in the manner of an intellectual and volitional nature. (Fs) (notabene)

779d Now, not only this last conclusion but also all the preceding ones must be taken into consideration. Hence, we are seeking an analogy from an intellectual and volitional nature neither in its being limited through a conjoint material nature, nor as perfecting itself as an agent, nor as going from potency, whether remote or proximate, to act, nor in that one act emanates from another. (Fs)

781a But a mere accumulation of negations does not suffice. For in that way we should certainly know only what a likeness for conceiving the divine processions is not. But such 'learned ignorance' is not a basis for understanding the mysteries, nor does it progress even one step along the way of synthesis. (Fs) (notabene)

781b Therefore, we must discover that positive formality which is not causal but natural, not in the manner of a material nature but of an intellectual and volitional nature, not about a passage from remote or proximate potency to act, but about act itself. In fact, although on account of the deficiency in our image it is necessary to consider one act emanating from another, we must not even do this except to discover that which by its own intrinsic formality does not require a multiplicity of acts. (Fs) (notabene)

With all this clearly understood, it is apparent that every other formality of emanation except the processions of intellectual consciousness is excluded. (Fs)

Corollary

781c Accordingly, questions about various metaphysical principles regarding either potentiality or action, from which our finite acts of understanding, affirming, or loving proceed, are superfluous in trinitarian theology. For from what we have said they simply do nothing to contribute to a trinitarian analogy that consists entirely in intellectual emanation. For this reason we have put into appendix 1 everything regarding the thought of St Thomas on this subject. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; der Geliebte im Liebenden (amatum in amante): konstituiert durch Liebe - erzeugt durch Liebe (7 kontrodiktorische Folgen)

Kurzinhalt: St Thomas's writings passim concerning the procession of love from the word are so clear that there can be not only no doubt but not even the slightest obscurity about his opinion on 'the beloved in the lover.'

Textausschnitt: 4 Chapter 2, Question 41

783b If 'the beloved in the lover' is constituted by love, then (1) 'the beloved in the lover' is nothing other than the love itself, (2) 'the beloved in the lover' is produced not by love but by the word, (3) the procession of love and the procession of what is termed 'the beloved in the lover' are formally the same, (4) the procession of love does not take place within the will but from the intellect into the will, and therefore (5) the procession of love differs from the procession of the word, which takes place entirely within the same potency and not from one thing to another, (6) the Holy Spirit is love, and therefore (7) the Holy Spirit is the 'beloved in the lover,' (8) the Holy Spirit proceeds immediately from the Word, and (9) the Holy Spirit does not proceed from love. (Fs)

783c If, on the other hand, 'the beloved in the lover' is produced by love, then (1) 'the beloved in the 'lover' is really distinct from love, (2) 'the beloved in the lover' is produced not by the word but by love, (3) the procession of love is formally one thing and the procession of what is called 'the beloved in the lover' is formally somediing else, (4) the procession by way of the will takes place entirely within the will, (5) the procession by way of the will is altogether similar to the procession of the word, which takes place entirely within the intellect, (6) the Holy Spirit is not love itself but that which is really distinct from love and is produced by love, (7) the Holy Spirit is 'the beloved in the lover,' (8) the Holy Spirit does not proceed immediately from the Word, and (9) the Holy Spirit proceeds from love. (Fs)

783d Thus, each opinion has nine consequences, all of which except the seventh are mutually contradictory. By understanding these many important differences, we can easily determine St Thomas's opinion on the procession of love, that is, whether he sides with us in affirming that 'the beloved in the lover' is constituted by love or with John of St Thomas2 and Thomists generally in teaching that 'the beloved in the lover' is produced by love.3 (Fs)

785a St Thomas's writings passim concerning the procession of love from the word are so clear that there can be not only no doubt but not even the slightest obscurity about his opinion on 'the beloved in the lover.' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Trinune God: Systematics

Titel: The Triune God: Systematics

Stichwort: Divinarum Personarum; Wissen - Bilderdenken; Scotus

Kurzinhalt: noch nicht

Textausschnitt: 8 Response to the Scotist Position on Formal Distinction on the Side of the Reality1

789a I reply that God's knowledge is one kind of knowledge, our knowledge is another, and imagining both divine and human knowledge is still another. (Fs)

In God understanding and being are absolutely identical; hence, the truth of divine knowledge is not a similitude between knowing and the known, for similitude supposes duality; it consists, rather, in the absence of dissimilitude. (Fs)

789b In us, however, since we progress from understanding in potency to understanding in act, we know insofar as through inquiry we understand, and through understanding we speak inner words, and through words spoken interiorly as through means-in-which we contemplate beings.2

Still, since we are not only rational but also animal, we not only investigate the proper nature of our knowledge so as to understand what we discover, speak in inner words what we have understood, and through true words contemplate the reality of our knowledge, but we can also forgo this arduous and lengthy task, so that by picturing someone who is seeing and the object of sight we think we know for certain what knowledge is. (Fs)

789c This picturing of knowledge, once it is admitted, leads necessarily to a formal distinction. For since looking at looking cannot be clearly and distinctly pictured in the imagination, it is impossible for us to think even about divine knowledge without separating the object as displayed on the side of the object and the subject which truly knows because it sees everything that is presented to it on the side of the object and sees nothing except what is displayed there. (Fs)

This picturing of knowledge is clearly the basis of the major premise of the first objection. For it posits as if they were two, God the Father as knowing and God the Father as displayed objectively prior to all operation of the mind. We set up a trilemma concerning this object: either two realities are displayed or only one is displayed; and if only one is displayed, either there is a nonidentity of formalities on the part of the thing itself or there is not. If this is granted, then since knowledge is supposed to be nothing else than a facsimile of the object being seen in the subject seeing it, the necessary conclusion is either the Sabellian or the Arian heresy, or an intermediate formal distinction. (Fs)

791a The gnoseological foundations of this argument must be denied. For we know real things inasmuch as we know beings; and we know beings inasmuch as we utter true judgments by means of which beings become known to us; and true judgments are both either affirmative or negative, and either simple or compound, so that judgment is necessarily either (1) A is, or (2) A is not, or (3) A is B, or (4) A is not B. (Fs)

791b Now, those things are distinct when one is not the other, and therefore it is only through true negative compound judgments (type 4) that distinctions are known. Besides, a true negative compound judgment is either of the first intention that makes judgments about things or of the second intention that makes judgments about concepts. If there is a judgment of the first intention, then A as real is not B as real, and the distinction is real. If, on the other hand, the judgment is of the second intention, then concept A is not concept B, and the distinction is conceptual. Finally, because our mode of conceiving is not the same as our mode of existing, it is possible for a conceptual distinction to arise, either solely from our mode of conceiving, or also from the mode of existence of things; and therefore conceptual distinctions are further divided into purely conceptual distinctions and conceptual distinctions with a basis in reality. (Fs)

To add to these distinctions another, a formal, distinction is to sin by an excess of realism, as if things themselves were not constituted by their own real principles but also by our conceptual formalities. For unless there is posited in real things themselves something else that is called formal, most certainly there cannot be in addition to a real distinction another distinction that is called 'formal on the side of the reality.' If formal is something besides real, it is not real; if it is not real, it does not exist among things. On the other hand, if formal is not something besides real, then it is real; and if formal is real, surely a formal distinction coincides with the real. (E11; 19.03.2011, Fest des hl. Josef)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Natur -> Ziel: Washeit des Seienden (Quidditas entis): ens per essentiam - ens per participationem (in metaphysischer u. "kognitionaler" Fromulierung) ; quidditatives - analoges Verstehen

Kurzinhalt: The quiddity of being is that by which, when understood, being in its totality is understood. That quiddity is the divine essence itself... with respect to quiddity being is divided in two ways.
First, it is divided into being by essence and being by ...

Textausschnitt: PART 1. The Notion of Person

1/1 Since a person is a distinct being subsisting in an intellectual nature, we must first speak of an intellectual nature both from the side of the object toward which this nature tends (§ 1, Being) and from the side of the subject who easily falls short of so lofty an aim (§ 2, Existenz). (9; Fs)

Lateinischer Text, Anfang oben: Cum persona sit subsistens distinctum in natura intellectuali ...

2/1 Next, since a subsistent being is one in the strictest sense of the word, we shall deal with the notion of 'one' (§ 3) and with the notion of 'subsistent' (§ 4), so that we may then go on to deal with the notion of 'distinct subsistent' or 'supposit' (§ 5) and with the formality of 'person' (§ 6). (9; Fs)

1 Being

3/1 With regard to being, three points are to be treated: the quiddity of being [1-2], the intention of being [3-4], and the extension or denotation of being [5]. (9; Fs)

1-2 Quiddity of being (eü)

1 The quiddity of being is that by which, when understood, being in its totality is understood. That quiddity is the divine essence itself. (9; Fs) (notabene)

4/1 For, once the divine essence is understood, (1) some being is understood, since this essence is identified with 'to be,' and (2) being is understood in its totality, both because God by comprehending the divine essence understands perfectly every being whatsoever, and because the blessed in heaven seeing God's essence behold both God and other beings in God in proportion to the perfection of the vision they possess.1 (9; Fs)

5/1 But when you understand any finite essence, you do not understand being. For a finite essence does not include 'to be.' Accordingly, if you understand a finite essence, you do not understand 'to be'; and if you do not understand 'to be,' you do not understand being. Again, when you understand a finite essence, you apprehend merely properties that are hypothetical or that are abstracted from 'to be.'2 (11; Fs)

2 Thus, with respect to quiddity being is divided in two ways.

First, it is divided into being by essence and being by participation.
6/1 Being by essence is being whose essence is its own 'to be'; or, to put it in cognitional terms, it is being through the understanding of whose essence being is understood in its totality. (11; Fs) (notabene)

Being by participation is being whose essence is not its own 'to be'; in cognitional terms, it is being through the understanding of whose essence you do not understand being but apprehend only the hypothetical properties derived from its essence. (notabene)

7/1 Another division is into being known quidditatively and being known analogously.
Being known quidditatively is being as known through the mediation of an understanding of the divine essence.

Being known analogously is being as known through understanding finite essences and comparing them with the 'to be' received in them.3 (11; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Unterschied: intentio intendens - i. intenta (bewusstes Streben nach Sein - Seinsbegriff)

Kurzinhalt: Now, if a finality and dynamic orientation is intellectually and rationally conscious, it is rightly called 'intention.' However, since this intention does not constitute knowledge but leads to it through questioning, it is an intending intention, not ...

Textausschnitt: 3-4 Intention of being (eü)

3 The intention of being is either intending or intended.

8/1 The intention intending being is simply the cutting edge of the intellect in accordance with its natural finality, that is, in accordance with its radical dynamic orientation. For the intellect is 'that by which it is possible to make and become everything.' Hence, since the intellect regards 'everything,' it regards being; and since it regards 'everything' with respect to making and becoming, it regards being in accordance with its finality or dynamic orientation. Finally, since the intellect is defined as 'that by which it is possible to make and become everything,' this finality is natural and this dynamic orientation is radical. (11f; Fs)

9/1 Furthermore, this natural finality and dynamic orientation (1) is not unconscious, like that of a heavy object with regard to the law of gravity, nor (2) is it only sensitively conscious, such as the desire of a hungry being for food, but (3) it is intellectually and rationally conscious, since it is that sense of wonder that Aristotle considered to be the beginning of all knowledge and all philosophy. For from this wondering all questions arise, whether about the essences of things (What is it? Why is it so?) or about their existence (Is it? Is it so?). (13; Fs)

10/1 Now, if a finality and dynamic orientation is intellectually and rationally conscious, it is rightly called 'intention.' However, since this intention does not constitute knowledge but leads to it through questioning, it is an intending intention, not an intended one. (13; Fs)

11/1 Through this intending intention, being becomes known to us of itself and naturally1 and cannot be unknown to us.2 Moreover, since this intending intention itself is natural and cannot go unknown, it is specifically one and the same in every single human being; for what is natural both existed before the rise of Greek culture and does not cease to exist just because the Scholastics are scorned. (13; Fs)

4 On the other hand, the intended intention of being, the explicit concept of being, differs with different thinkers. Parmenides, Plato, Aristotle, Avicenna, Aquinas, Scotus, Hegel3 - they all conceive being differently. (13; Fs)

12/1 This diversity stems from the fact that being is the most fundamental concept of all, one from which many consequences flow. A science that deduces conclusions from premises is easy enough. Nor is that understanding difficult by which principles become known, for as soon as the terms are known, the principles are grasped. But that sapiential knowledge whose function it is to order all things and make judgments about all things is extremely difficult; and therefore it is very difficult to choose primitive terms in such a way that true principles are grasped, and that not only true but also all true conclusions are deduced from them. Since this most fundamental concept presents the most formidable difficulty, it is no wonder that many brilliant thinkers have gone astray in this matter of the intended intention, or concept, of being.4 (13f; Fs)

13/1 Now, however, from what we said about the quiddity and the intending intention of being, we may safely go on to consider the explicit concept of being. (15; Fs)

Since the cutting edge of the intellect regards 'everything,' it follows that the concept of being embraces the total reality of the entire universe; for if even the least part or aspect is left out, it no longer regards 'everything.' (15; Fs)

Since the process whereby we gain knowledge of each single thing involves two questions (What is it? and Is it?), it follows that the concept of being is the concept of a composite consisting of essence (what it is) and existence (that it is). (15; Fs)

Since the intending intention does not constitute knowledge but only leads to knowledge through questioning, the concept of being may seem to be empty, yet in fact it is the fullest of all. It seems empty because through the intending intention alone nothing is yet known. On the other hand, it is the fullest of all, because the concept of being denotes and signifies not what is already known but that towards which the intending intention tends; and since it intends everything, since it drives on to know the full reality of the entire universe, it is indeed the fullest of all concepts. (15; Fs)

14/1 Further, it follows that the differences of being are not something over and above being. If they were, they would indicate something other than being; but apart from being there is nothing at all, and so the differences of being cannot be over and above being.
Again, it follows that being is not a genus; for a genus does not include its differences within itself. Etc., etc.5 (15; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Elemente d. Metaphysik: Potenz, Form, Akt (Definition, Bedeutung); M. als vollständige heuristische Struktur des proportionierten Seins

Kurzinhalt: Potenz bezeichnet die Komponente des proportionierten Seins ... Form bezeichnet die Komponente des proportionierten Seins ... Akt bezeichnet die Komponente des proportionierten Seins, die erkannt wird, indem man das virtuell unbedingte "Ja" des ...

Textausschnitt: XV. Kapitel DIE ELEMENTE DER METAPHYSIK

495a Das vorhergehende Kapitel skizzierte ein Programm, das vorliegende Kapitel fuhrt es aus. Wir haben die latente Metphysik des menschlichen Verstandes explizit zu machen, und der erste Schritt wird darin bestehen, ihre Elemente herauszuarbeiten. Es gibt deren sechs: Zentrale Potenz, zentrale Form, zentraler Akt, konjugate Potenz, konjugate Form und konjugater Akt. Im Lichte der vorangehenden Kapitel wird es eine relativ kurze Aufgabe sein, ihre Unterschiede herauszuarbeiten und sie miteinander in Verbindung zu bringen. Die Vorherrschaft der Gegenpositionen läßt es aber als unratsam - wenn nicht gar unmöglich - erscheinen, das Problem der genetischen Methode in Angriff zu nehmen, ehe wir instande sind, unsere metaphysischen Grundbegriffe anzuwenden. Das vorliegende Kapitel verdankt deshalb seine Länge und alle Komplexität, die es aufweisen mag, der Notwendigkeit, die Notion von Entwicklung zu klären und die heuristische Struktur der genetischen Methode sowohl im allgemeinen wie auch als angewandt auf den Organismus, die Psyche, die Intelligenz und die Kombination aller drei im Menschen zu umreißen. (Fs)

1. Potenz, Form und Akt

495b Die Metaphysik haben wir aufgefaßt als die vollständige heuristische Struktur des proportionierten Seins. Sie zielt auf eine unbestimmt entfernte Zukunft ab, in welcher der ganze Bereich des proportionierten Seins verstanden sein wird. Sie fragt, was hier und jetzt von dieser zukünftigen Erklärung erkannt werden kann. Sie antwortet, daß, wenn auch die volle Erklärung vielleicht nie erreicht werden wird, zumindest die Struktur dieser erklärenden Erkenntnis schon jetzt erkannt werden kann. (Fs) (notabene)

495c Denn das proportionierte Sein ist alles, was durch Erfahrung, intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen erkannt werden kann. Es gibt demnach drei Komponenten in diesem Erkennen, wovon indes nur eine unbekannt ist. Der Inhalt des intelligenten Erfassens des proportionierten Seins bleibt notwendigerweise so lange unbekannt, bis die volle Erklärung erreicht ist. Der Inhalt des vernünftigen Bejahens hingegen ist bereits bekannt - er ist ein virtuell unbedingtes "Ja". Und der Inhalt der Erfahrung, der im vollständig erklärenden Erkennen überleben wird, ist ebenfalls schon bekannt; denn er ist die intellektuell strukturierte Erfahrung des empirischen Residuums; und wir wissen schon, daß Erfahrung in ihrer intellektuellen Struktur stattfindet, wenn sie durch das unvoreingenommene und uneigennützige Erkenntnisstreben beherrscht wird. Ähnlich haben wir schon ermittelt, daß das [432] empirische Residuum in der Individualität, der Kontinuität, dem zufälligen Zusammentreffen, den Aufeinanderfolgen und dem nichtsystematischen Abweichen von den intelligiblen Normen liegt; d. h. in all dem, was die durch die Erfahrung - und nur durch die Erfahrung - erkannt werden soll. (Fs) (notabene)

496a Wir wollen dementsprechend drei Termini einführen: Potenz, Form und Akt. (Fs)

Potenz bezeichnet die Komponente des proportionierten Seins, die erkannt wird im vollständig erklärenden Erkennen durch eine intellektuell strukturierte Erfahrung des empirischen Residuums. (Fs) (notabene)

Form bezeichnet die Komponente des proportionierten Seins, die zu erkennen ist, nicht durch ein Verstehen der Namen der Dinge noch durch ein Verstehen ihrer Relationen zu uns, sondern durch ein vollständiges Verstehen der Dinge in ihren Relationen zueinander. (Fs) (notabene)

Akt bezeichnet die Komponente des proportionierten Seins, die erkannt wird, indem man das virtuell unbedingte "Ja" des vernünftigen Urteils ausspricht. (Fs) (notabene)

496b Es folgt, daß Potenz, Akt und Form eine Einheit bilden. Was nämlich erfahren wird, ist das, was verstanden wird; und was verstanden wird, ist das, was bejaht wird. Die drei Ebenen der kognitiven Tätigkeit ergeben ein einziges Erkennen. Denn Erfahrung allein ist noch nicht menschliches Erkennen; Erfahrung und Verstehen genügen noch nicht zum Erkennen; erst wenn das Unbedingte erreicht ist und die Bejahung oder die Verneinung eintritt, liegt Erkenntnis im eigentlichen Sinne des Wortes vor. In ähnlicher Weise bilden auch die Inhalte der drei Erkenntnistätigkeiten eine Einheit; es ist ja nicht so, daß wir ein erstes proportioniertes Seiendes durch Erfahrung, dann ein zweites durch Verstehen und dann noch ein drittes durch das Urteilen erkennen; im Gegenteil: Die drei Inhalte verschmelzen in ein einziges Erkanntes. Und so sind Potenz, Form und Akt, weil sie durch Erfahrung, Einsicht und Urteil erkannt werden, nicht drei proportionierte Seiende, sondern drei Komponenten in einem einzigen proportionierten Seienden. (Fs) (notabene)

496c Es folgt weiter, daß Potenz, Form und Akt nicht nur eine Einheit bilden, sondern auch unter eine gemeinsame Definition oder Spezifikation fallen. Denn Erfahrung definiert und spezifiziert nicht; sie stellt lediglich vor. Und auch das Urteil definiert und spezifiziert nicht, sondern bejaht oder verneint bloß, was schon definiert oder spezifiziert wurde. Alles Definieren und Spezifizieren geschieht auf der Ebene des Verstehens, und so hat auch die Einheit, die durch Potenz, Form und Akt gebildet wird, nur eine einzige Definition oder Spezifikation, die dadurch erreicht wird, daß man die Form erkennt. (Fs) (notabene)

497a Schließlich, diese Darlegung von Potenz, Form und Akt gilt für jede mögliche wissenschaftliche Erklärung. Eine wissenschaftliche Erklärung ist ja eine Theorie, die in Fällen verifiziert worden ist; als verifizierte bezieht sie sich auf den Akt; als Theorie bezieht sie sich auf die Form; als in Fällen verifizierte bezieht sie sich auf [433] die Potenz. Ferner, als Theorie des klassischen Typus bezieht sie sich auf Formen als Formen; als Theorie des statistischen Typus bezieht sie sich auf Formen, insofern diese Häufigkeiten festlegen, von denen die Akte nicht systematisch divergieren; als Theorie des genetischen Typus bezieht sie sich auf die Bedingungen der Emergenz der Form aus der Potenz. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Elemente d. Metaphysik: Potenz, Form, Akt; Gemeinsamkeit, Abweichung: Aristoteles (deskriptiv) - Lonergan (erklärend); A.: sensibilia propria als Form; Konflikt mit der Wissenschaft der Renaissance

Kurzinhalt: Die psychologische Erläuterung genügt unseren Definitionen... Die physikalische Erläuterung hingegen fällt nicht unter unsere Definitionen. Die Form wird durch Einsicht erkannt; aber Aristoteles betrachtete das, was er die sensibilia propria nannte ...

Textausschnitt: 497b Im folgenden werden wir verschiedene Typen von Potenz, Form und Akt unterscheiden. Es muß aber schon hier daraufhingewiesen werden, daß wir zwar Aristoteles' Terminologie verwenden und den Termini eine Bedeutung zuweisen, die Aristoteles als die seinige anerkennen würde; daß aber Aristoteles' Neigung von einer lediglich deskriptiven Erkenntnis Gebrauch zu machen und unser Bestehen auf Erklärung verschiedene Ausgangspunkte einschließen sowie auch verschiedene Tendenzen und verschiedene Implikationen. So ist es gesunde Aristotelische Lehre zu behaupten, Potenz stünde zur Form wie das Auge zur Sicht und die Form zum Akt wie die Sicht zum Sehen. Aber es ist eine noch deutlicher hervortretende Aristotelische Lehre, zu sagen, die Potenz stünde zur Form wie die Privation von Wärme zur Wärme und die Form zum Akt wie die Wärme zum Wärmen. Nun genügt die psychologische Erläuterung unserer Definition, aber die physikalische kann mit ihr nicht in Einklang gebracht werden. (Fs) (notabene)

497c Die psychologische Erläuterung genügt unseren Definitionen. Form ist ja, was durch die Einsicht erkannt wird; "Sicht" wird aber erkannt, insofern wir die Augen als die Organe der Sicht verstehen, oder insofern wir die Erfahrungen des Sehens als im Besitz der Sicht begründet verstehen. Ferner, der Akt wird erkannt im "Ja" des Urteils, und wir wissen, daß eine Person sieht nicht bloß durch eine Untersuchung der Augen und auch nicht dadurch, daß wir die untersuchten Augen als Organe der Sicht verstehen, sondern indem wir behaupten, daß die verstandene Sicht zur Anwendung gebracht wird. Schließlich, die Potenz ist das, was durch die intellektuell strukturierte Erfahrung des empirischen Residuums erkannt wird, und eine solche Erfahrung findet dann statt, wenn wir die Augen untersuchen, um sie zu verstehen. (Fs) (notabene)

497d Die physikalische Erläuterung hingegen fällt nicht unter unsere Definitionen. Die Form wird durch Einsicht erkannt; aber Aristoteles betrachtete das, was er die sensibilia propria nannte, als Formen: etwa Farben, Schalle, warm und kalt, feucht und trocken, hart und weich, schwer und leicht usw. Dies sind, gelinde gesagt, sehr zweideutige Formen; im Objekt sind sie potentiell wahrnehmbar; in der Wahrnehmung sind sie aktuell wahrnehmbar; als benannte werden sie mit jeglicher hinreichend ähnlicher Qualität in Verbindung gebracht und zwar durch eine Einsicht, welche erfaßt, wie der Name zu verwenden ist; als Objekte der Untersuchung gehen sie in eine heuristische Struktur ein, die das sucht, was erkannt werden kann, wenn sie einmal verstanden sind; als erklärte schließlich werden sie mit Gesetzen in Verbindung gebracht, die implizit konjugate Termini definieren. Unter welche Bedeutung aus unserem Fünferkatalog fällt nun Aristoteles' Form "Wärme"? [434] Ferner, der Akt ist das, was erkannt wird im "Ja" des Urteils; aber "wärmen" kann nicht auf diese simple Weise erkannt werden. "Warm machen" zu erkennen bedeutet, daß es zwei Fälle von Wärme gibt und daß die eine kausal aus der anderen hergeleitet wird. Und Potenz schließlich wird erkannt durch die intellektuell strukturierte Erfahrung des empirischen Residuums. Die Potenz zur Form Wärme aber ist die Privation ebendieser Form; diese Privation wird nicht allein durch die Erfahrung der gegenteiligen Form, Kälte, erkannt, sondern dadurch, daß wir sie als das Gegenteil von Wärme und als die Wärme ausschließend erkennen.1 (Fs) (notabene)

498a Es ist leicht zu sehen, warum die Zweideutigkeiten in den physikalischen Notionen des Aristoteles einen Konflikt mit der Wissenschaft der Renaissance unausweichlich machten. Wenn die Form der Wärme das ist, was durch ein Verstehen von Wärme erkannt werden kann, dann mußten die Aristoteliker den Verstehensversuchen der Wissenschaftler zustimmen. In der Tat fand eine Art Komödie von Irrtümern statt. Die Aristoteliker hatten wenig Verständnis für die Aristotelische Lehre von der Einsicht in imaginative Vorstellungen und hatten keine Notion von der heuristischen Struktur, die auf eine Einsicht zugeht. Andererseits faßten die Wissenschaftler das Erklären nicht als ein Erkennen, insofern man versteht, auf; ihr Denken war von der Notion der Objektivität als Extraversion beherrscht; in diesem Sinne verneinten sie, daß die sensibilia propria "da draußen" seien; und sie faßten das Erklären als die Zurückführung der scheinbaren Qualitäten auf die realen Dimensionen der Materie in Bewegung auf. Vier Jahrhunderte müßten uns nun eigentlich genügen, diese Irrtümer zu durchschauen. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Metaphysik; zentrale, konjugate Formen; Einheit von P., F. und A.;

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 2. Zentrale und konjugate Formen

499a Der zweite Schritt in der Ausarbeitung der vollständigen heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins wird in der Unterscheidung von zwei allgemeinen Fällen von Potenz, Form und Akt bestehen. Denn obwohl die Formen des proportionierten [435] Seins nur dann vollständig erkannt werden können, wenn die vollständige Erklärung erreicht wird, kann dennoch die vorhandene Existenz heuristischer Techniken sofort zeigen, daß es verschiedene Arten von Formen gibt. Wenn es aber verschiedene Arten von Formen gibt, muß es auch verschiedene Arten von Potenz und Akt geben; denn Potenz, Form und Akt bilden ein einziges Erkanntes und teilen eine gemeinsame Definition; und Potenz und Akt, welche die Definition einer Art von Form teilen, müssen von Potenz und Akt, die die verschiedene Definition einer anderen Art von Form teilen, verschieden sein. (Fs)

499b Nun liegen der klassischen Methode zwei heuristische Prinzipien zugrunde. Das erste ist, daß Ähnliches ähnlich verstanden wird, daß eine Differenz im Verstehen eine bedeutsame Differenz in den Daten voraussetzt. Das zweite ist, daß die Ähnlichkeiten, die für die Erklärung relevant sind, nicht in den Relationen der Dinge zu uns, sondern in ihren Relationen zueinander liegen. Wenn nun diese heuristischen Prinzipien angewendet werden, ergeben sich Klassifizierungen mittels sinnesmäßiger Ähnlichkeit, dann Korrelationen, und schließlich die Verifikationen von Korrelationen und Systemen von Korrelationen. Verifizierte Korrelationen schließen aber notwendigerweise die Verifikation der Termini, die durch die Korrelationen implizit definiert sind, mit ein; und nicht mehr als solche implizit definierten Termini als in Beziehung zueinander. Denn was genau verifiziert wird, ist nicht diese oder jene Einzelaussage, sondern die generelle und abstrakte Aussage, auf die hin Reihen von Reihen von Einzelaussagen konvergieren. Dementsprechend gibt es eine heuristische Grundstruktur, welche zur Bestimmung von Konjugaten führt, das heißt, von Termini, die durch ihre empirisch verifizierten und erklärenden Relationen implizit definiert werden. Solche Termini als zusammenhängende werden durch Verstehen erkannt und sind deshalb Formen. Wir wollen sie konjugate Formen nennen. Weil derartige Formen im empirischen Residuum der Erfahrung verifiziert werden, bilden sie Einheiten mit konjugaten Potenzen und konjugaten Akten. Demnach ist die konjugate Potenz Potenz zu konjugater Form, und der konjugate Akt ist Akt konjugater Form, wobei Potenz zu Form und Akt der Form hier bedeutet, daß die in Frage stehenden Potenz, Form und Akt eine einzige Einheit bilden. (Fs) (notabene)

500a Ferner, die heuristische Struktur, welche zur Erkenntnis konjugater Formen fuhrt, macht nun eine andere Struktur notwendig, welche zur Erkenntnis zentraler Formen führt. Man erreicht ja erklärende Konjugate, indem man Daten als ähnlich mit anderen Daten betrachtet; die Daten aber, die ähnlich sind, sind auch konkret und individuell; und als konkret und individuell werden sie insofern verstanden, als man in ihnen eine konkrete und intelligible Einheit, Identität und Totalität erfaßt. Und man kann auf dieses Erfassen weder verzichten, noch es überschreiten. Denn [436] die Wissenschaft macht Fortschritte durch die Wechselwirkung zunehmend genauer Beschreibungen und immer befriedigenderer Erklärungen derselben Objekte. Wenn nun die Objekte nicht dieselben sind, besteht keine Beziehung zwischen Beschreibung und Erklärung und deshalb kein Grund, warum eine Erklärung die Beschreibung modifizieren soll, oder warum eine Beschreibung zu einer besseren Erklärung führen soll. Aber das einzige Objekt, welches dasselbe ist, ist die konkrete und intelligible Einheit, Identität und Totalität; denn die erklärenden Konjugate verändern sich; und die beschreibenden oder erfahrungsmäßigen Termini unterstehen Modifikationen und Neuanordnungen. Solange also die Wissenschaft fortschreitet, bleibt die Notion der intelligiblen Einheit unverzichtbar. Nun müssen aber wissenschaftliche Konklusionen in ihrem Ziel nicht minder als in ihrer Entwicklung durch Evidenz gestützt werden; die Evidenz für solche Konklusionen liegt im Wandel; und ohne konkrete und intelligible Einheiten gibt es nichts, das sich wandeln könnte. Denn Wandel ist nicht die Substitution eines Datums durch ein anderes und auch nicht die Ersetzung eines Begriffs durch einen anderen; er besteht in derselben konkreten und intelligiblen Einheit, welche die Vereinheitlichung nacheinander verschiedener Daten liefert; und deshalb kann es ohne diese Einheit keinen Wandel geben und ohne Wandel fehlt ein gewichtiger Teil - wenn nicht gar das Ganze - der Evidenz für wissenschaftliche Konklusionen. Schließlich ist die Wissenschaft auf konkrete Probleme anwendbar; aber weder beschreibende noch erklärende Erkenntnis kann auf konkrete Probleme angewendet werden ohne den Einsatz des Demonstrativums "dieses", und dieses Demonstrativum kann nur insofern verwendet werden, als es ein Bindeglied zwischen Begriffen und Daten als individuellen gibt; allein die Notion der konkreten und intelligiblen Einheit der Daten liefert ein derartiges Bindeglied, und deshalb ist diese Notion notwendig für die Wissenschaft als angewandte. (Fs) (notabene)

501a Nun werden konkrete und intelligible Einheiten durch Verstehen erkannt und sind deshalb Formen. Sie sind aber ganz verschieden von den konjugaten Formen und müssen deshalb als ein anderer Typus von Formen anerkannt werden, den wir "zentrale Form" nennen wollen. Und wie die konjugate Form eine konjugate Potenz und einen konjugaten Akt impliziert, so impliziert die zentrale Form eine zentrale Potenz und einen zentralen Akt. (Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: A Third Collection

Titel: A Third Collection

Stichwort: Geschichte, Heilung; verschiedene Diagnose: Russel (Mensch böse), Popper (dumm, einfältig)

Kurzinhalt: A creative process is a learning process. It is learning what hitherto was not known. It is just the opposite of the mental coma induced by the fables and jingles that unceasingly interrupt television programs in our native land and even in the great ...

Textausschnitt: 7 Healing and Creating in History

1/7 The topic assigned me reads: Healing and Creating in History.
What precisely it means or even what it might mean, does not seem to be obvious at first glance. An initial clarification appears to be in order. (100; Fs)

2/7 We have to do with healing and creating in history. But no particular kind of history is specified, and so we are not confined to religious or cultural or social or political or economic or technological history. Again no people or country is mentioned, neither Babylonians nor Egyptians, Greeks nor Romans, Asians nor Africans, Europeans nor Americans. It would seem, then, that we have to do with healing and creating in human affairs. For human affairs are the stuff of history, and they merit the attention of the historian when they are taken in a relatively large context and prove their significance by their relatively durable effects. (100; Fs)

3/7 Now if "history" may be taken broadly to mean human affairs, it is not too difficult to obtain at least a preliminary notion of what is meant by the other two terms in our title, "healing" and "creating." For there comes to hand a paper by Sir Karl Popper entitled "The History of Our Time: An Optimist's View."1 In it he opposes two different accounts of what is wrong with the world. On the one hand, there is the view he attributes to many quite sincere churchmen and, along with them, to the rationalist philosopher, Bertrand Russell. It is to the effect that our intellectual development has outrun our moral development. He writes:

We have become very clever, according to Russell, indeed too clever. We can make lots of wonderful gadgets, including television, high-speed rockets, and an atom bomb, or a thermonuclear bomb, if you prefer. But we have not been able to achieve that moral and political growth and maturity which alone could safely direct and control the uses to which we put our tremendous intellectual powers. This is why we now find ourselves in mortal danger. Our evil national pride has prevented us from achieving the world-state in time.
To put this view in a nutshell: we are clever, perhaps too clever, but we also are wicked; and this mixture of cleverness and wickedness lies at the root of our troubles.2

4/7 In contrast, Sir Karl Popper would argue that we are good, perhaps a little too good, but we are also a little stupid; and it is this mixture of goodness and stupidity that lies at the root of our troubles. After avowing that he included himself among those he considered a little stupid, Sir Karl put his point in the following terms: (101; Fs)

The main troubles of our time—and I do not deny that we live in troubled times—are not due to our moral wickedness, but, on the contrary, to our often misguided moral enthusiasm: to our anxiety to better the world we live in. Our wars are fundamentally religious wars; they are wars between competing theories of how to establish a better world. And our moral enthusiasm is often misguided, because we fail to realize that our moral principles, which are sure to be over-simple, are often difficult to apply to the complex human and political situations to which we feel bound to apply them.3

5/7 In upholding this contention Sir Karl was quite ready to descend to particular instances. He granted the wickedness of Hitler and Stalin. He acknowledged that they appealed to all sorts of hopes and fears, to prejudices and envy, and even to hatred. But he insisted that their main appeal was an appeal to a kind of morality. They had a message; and they demanded sacrifices. He regretted that an appeal to morality could be misused. But he saw it as a fact that the great dictators were always trying to convince their people that they knew a way to a higher morality. (101; Fs)

6/7 Now one may agree with Lord Russell. One may agree with Sir Karl. Indeed, there is no difficulty in agreeing with both, for the Christian tradition lists among the effects of original sin both a darkening of intellect and a weakening of will. But whatever one's opinion, it remains that there is a profound difference between diagnosing a malady and proposing a cure. Whether one stresses with Lord Russell the conjunction of clever but wicked or with Sir Karl the conjunction of good but stupid, one gets no further than diagnosis. On the other hand, when one speaks of healing and creating, one refers to positive courses of action. To this positive aspect of the issue, we now must turn. (101f; Fs)

7/7 The creating in question is not creating out of nothing. Such creating is the divine prerogative. Man's creating is of a different order. Actually, it does not bring something out of nothing, but it may seem to do so. William James, the American psychologist and philosopher, has described three stages in the career of a theory. First, "[...] it is attacked as absurd; then it is admitted to be true, but obvious and insignificant; finally it is seen to be so important that its adversaries claim that they themselves discovered it."4 Such a theory is creative. (102; Fs)

8/7 Let me illustrate this need for human creating from the contemporary economic situation. Last year there was published a thick volume by Richard Barnet and Ronald Miiller with the title, Global Reach, and the subtitle, The Power of the Multinational Corporations. Its thirteen chapters fell into three parts. The first set forth the aims of the multinational corporations: they propose to run the world, for they can do the job and our little national governments are not equipped to do so. The second set of chapters delineated what the multinational corporations were doing to the underdeveloped countries: they have been making them more hopelessly worse off than otherwise they would be. The third set finally asked what these corporations, which in the main are American, have been doing to the United States; the answer is that they are treating the States in the same way they are treating the underdeveloped countries and, in the long run, the effects will be the same as in the rest of the world. (102; Fs)

9/7 Now if the multinational corporations are generating worldwide disaster, why are they permitted to do so? The trouble is that there is nothing really new about multinational corporations. They aim at maximizing profit, and that has been the aim of economic enterprise since the mercantile, the industrial, the financial revolutions ever more fully and thoroughly took charge of our affairs. The alternative to making a profit is bankruptcy. The alternative to maximizing profit is inefficiency.5 All that the multinational corporation does is maximize profit not in some town or city, not in some region or country, but on the global scale. It buys labor and materials in the countries where they are cheapest. Its credit is unimpeachable and so it can secure all the money it wants from whatever banks or money markets are in a position to create it. Its marketing facilities are a global network and to compete one would have first to build up a global network of one's own. The multinational corporation is a going concern. It is ever growing and expanding. It is built on the very principles that slowly but surely have been moulding our technology and our economics, our society and our culture, our ideals and our practise for centuries. It remains that the long-accepted principles are inadequate. They suffer from radical oversights. Their rigorous application on a global scale, according to Barnet and Miiller, heads us for disaster. But as the authors also confess: "The new system needed for our collective survival does not exist."6 When survival requires a system that does not exist, then the need for creating is manifest. (102f; Fs)

10/7 While it can take a series of disasters to convince people of the need for creating, still the long, hard, uphill climb is the creative process itself. In retrospect this process may appear as a grand strategy that unfolds in an orderly and cumulative series of steps. But any retrospect has the advantage of knowing the answers. The creative task is to find the answers. It is a matter of insight, not of one insight but of many, not of isolated insights but of insights that coalesce, that complement and correct one another, that influence policies and programs, that reveal their shortcomings in their concrete results, that give rise to further correcting insights, corrected policies, corrected programs, that gradually accumulate into the all-round, balanced, smoothly functioning system that from the start was needed but at the start was not yet known. (103; Fs)

11/7 This creative process is nothing mysterious. It has been described by Jane Jacobs in her The Economy of Cities,7 as repeatedly finding new uses for existing resources. It has been set forth in the grand style by Arnold Toynbee under the rubric of "Challenge and Response" in his A Study of History, where the flow of fresh insights takes its rise from a creative minority, and the success of their implementation wins the devoted allegiance of the rank and file.8 (103; Fs)

12/7 I have spoken of insights, and I had best add what I do not mean. An insight is not just a slogan, and an ongoing accumulation of insights is not just an advertising campaign. A creative process is a learning process. It is learning what hitherto was not known. It is just the opposite of the mental coma induced by the fables and jingles that unceasingly interrupt television programs in our native land and even in the great republic to the south of us. (103f; Fs)

13/7 Again, insights are one thing, and concepts are quite another. Concepts are ambiguous. They may be heuristic, but then they merely point to unspecified possibilities, as highly desirable as justice, liberty, equality, peace—but still just empty gestures that fail to reveal how the possibilities might be realized and what the realization concretely would entail. Again, concepts may be specific, but then they are definite, rounded off, finished, abstract. Like textbooks on moral theology they can name all the evils to be avoided but get no further than unhelpful platitudes on the good to be achieved. For the good is never an abstraction. Always it is concrete.9 The whole point to the process of cumulative insight is that each insight regards the concrete while the cumulative process heads towards an ever fuller and more adequate view. Add abstraction to abstraction and one never reaches more than a heap of abstractions. But add insight to insight and one moves to mastery of all the eventualities and complications of a concrete situation. (104; Fs)

14/7 The creative process culminates in system, but the system is only system on the move. It never reaches static system that comes into existence and remains forever after. So it is that, when the flow of fresh insights dries up, when challenges continue and responses fail to emerge, then the creative minority becomes the merely dominant minority and the eagerness of the rank and file, that exulted in success, turns into the sullenness of an internal proletariat frustrated and disgusted by the discovery that a country in which, more and more, everything had worked has become a country in which, more and more, nothing works. Such is the disenchantment that, to use Toynbee's terms, brings to an end the genesis of a civilization and introduces first its breakdowns and eventually its disintegration. (104; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Vorwort zur dt. Ausgabe I; Lonergan in der Schule von Thomas von Aquin; intelligere in sensibili; verbum complexum

Kurzinhalt: Das Verstehen1 geschieht also im Konkreten, Einzelnen; es legt eine Form in dem Gegebenen frei. Erst dann ist unser Verstand imstande, intelligent einen Begriff zu bilden ... Ähnliches gilt für das Urteil: Auch das sog. verbum complexum

Textausschnitt: I. Die Vorbereitung: In der Schule von Thomas von Aquin

XIa Bernard J. F. Lonergan (1904-1984) war Mitglied der Gesellschaft Jesu und lehrte Theologie zuerst in seinem heimatlichen Kanada und dann an der Gregoriana Universität zu Rom, bis er 1965 aus Gesundheitsgründen nach Toronto zurückkehrte. 1971-1972 lehrte er an der Harvard Divinity School; von 1975 bis 1983 war er Visiting Distinguished Professor in Boston College, Massachusetts. (Fs)

Daß ein Theologe ein umfangreiches Buch über Erkenntnis- und Seinslehre schreibt, ist eher ungewöhnlich. Es soll hier der Weg nachgezeichnet werden, auf dem Lonergan zur Abfassung dieses Werkes kam, und zugleich eine erste Orientierung zum Verständnis desselben gegeben werden. (Fs)

XIb Bereits in seiner Dissertation für das Doktorat in der Theologie über ein Element in der Gnadenlehre des Thomas von Aquin1 wurde Lonergan anhand eines textuell gut belegten Falls mit dem evolutiven Charakter der menschlichen Erkenntnis konfrontiert. Die Theologen des XII. und XIII. Jahrhunderts hatten einer nach dem anderen um das Problem der Vereinbarkeit von menschlicher Freiheit und Gottes Gnade gerungen. Als Thomas dran kam, war die Phase des Übergangs von der eher paränetisch-praktischen Verkündigung dieser Grundwahrheit des christlichen Glaubens zu einer systematischen Durchdringung derselben mittels der wieder entdeckten Begrifflichkeit aus der Philosophie von Aristoteles noch nicht zu einer befriedigenden Position gelangt. Die Synthese, die Thomas durch seine wiederholte Behandlung zustande bringen konnte, erwies sich in der historischen Untersuchung Lonergans als eine Sache weder allgemeiner Begriffe noch syllogistischer Schlußfolgerungen; vielmehr als die Leistung einer sich nach und nach vertiefenden und erweiternden Erklärung der mannigfaltigen und bis dahin widerspenstigen Daten der Hl. Schrift und der Tradition; eine Synthese also "nicht so sehr durch einen einzigen meisterhaften Zug als vielmehr durch die unzähligen nacheinander vollzogenen Anpassungen, die fortdauernd der intellektuellen Vitalität entstammten"2. (Fs)

XIc Die Diskursivität der menschlichen Erkenntnis, in deren Mittelpunkt ein Akt des Verstehens steht, erhielt eine systematische Klärung in einer zweiten Untersuchung, die Lonergan noch während der letzten Kriegsjahre und unmittelbar danach anstellte, als er Theologie in Montreal und dann in Toronto lehrte3. Das direkte Thema war ein theologisches, nämlich die seit Augustin herkömmliche Analogie, die im Geist des Menschen ein Abbild des dreieinigen Gottes sieht. In der Tat aber lief die eindringliche und anhand vieler Textstellen belegte Untersuchung der Schriften von Thomas auf eine Studie über die Erkenntnislehre, aber auch die Seelenlehre und die Metaphysik des mittelalterlichen Meisters hinaus. (Fs)

XIIa Im Unterschied zu der bei den Thomas-Forschern üblichen Perspektive von einer Metaphysik der Erkenntnis stellte Lonergan fest, daß Thomas zwar metaphysische Begriffe und Lehrsätze von Aristoteles durchgehend benutzt hat, daß aber diese von ihm verwendet wurden, um Handlungen systematisch auszudrücken, die der Mensch in seiner Erkenntnistätigkeit vollzieht. Für Lonergan galt es deshalb, diese bewußten und damit nachprüfbaren Elemente ausfindig zu machen und sie in ihrer Eigenart zu thematisieren. Das Hauptresultat der Untersuchung einer solchen introspektiv nachvollziehbaren Lehre war die Einsicht, daß Thomas die Schlüsselrolle beim Zustandekommen der menschlichen Erkenntnis nicht dem inneren Wort, weder als Begriff noch als Urteil, zuschrieb, sondern dem vorhergehenden Akt des Verstehens. Es ist nicht schwer einzusehen, welche revolutionäre Bedeutung eine solche These Lonergans in bezug auf eine jahrhundertelang dominierende philosophische Tradition hat. Man denke an den Vorrang des Begriffs als allgemein in einflußreichen Strömungen der Scholastik, vor allem Skotistischer Prägung, bis hin zur Neuscholastik mit ihrer rein metaphysischen Erklärung des Allgemeinbegriffs. Aber auch an Kant, der aus keinem anderen Grund seine Kritik der reinen Vernunft schrieb, als um die Frage: "Wie sind synthetische Urteile a priori möglich?" zu beantworten, wofür er zu Begriffen a priori Zuflucht nahm. (Fs)

XIIb Der Begriff hat nach Thomas seinen Urprung in dem Akt, den er "intelligere" nennt - ein Verstehen "in sensibili", d. h. in den Daten der Sinne (oder des Bewußtseins), das dem "noein en tois phantasmasi" des Aristoteles im II. Buch. Kapitel 7 von De anima entspricht. Dieser Akt fügt der Mannigfaltigkeit des Gegebenen einen Komplex von Beziehungen und damit eine Intelligibilität hinzu, die das Mannigfaltige unter einem bestimmten Aspekt zur Einheit führt. Das Verstehen4 geschieht also im Konkreten, Einzelnen; es legt eine Form in dem Gegebenen frei. Erst dann ist unser Verstand imstande, intelligent einen Begriff zu bilden, der das im einzelnen, aber nicht auf das einzelne eingeschränkte erfaßte Intelligible in einem Begriff allgemein ausdrückt. (Fs) (notabene)

XIIIa Ähnliches gilt für das Urteil: Auch das sog. verbum complexum geht aus einem vorhergehenden Verstehensakt hervor, der die Entsprechung zwischen den tatsächlich vorhandenen Daten und ihrer Interpretation erfaßt und damit den Grund fur die absolute Setzung der mentalen Synthesis in einer Bejahung bzw. Verneinung liefert. Erst durch das Urteil als Setzung wird das, was zunächst bloß gegeben und dann bloß gedacht war, als Wirklichkeit erkannt. (Fs) (notabene)

XIIIb Genau die wesentliche Unterscheidung von Begriff und Urteil als dem zweiten (nach dem der Erfahrung) und dritten Schritt im Erkenntnisprozeß zusammen mit ihrer Begründung in einem direkten bzw. reflexiven Verstehensakt erklärt zwei Grundeigenschaften der menschlichen Erkenntnis: Einerseits ihren evolutiven Charakter, der von der Reihenfolge immer exakterer und umfassenderer Einsichten in die Daten stammt; andererseits die bleibende Gültigkeit dessen, was in der absoluten Setzung des Urteils als wahr und damit als wirklich erkannt wurde. (Fs) (notabene)

XIIIc Der Ertrag seiner Studie über das Verbum bei Thomas war für Lonergan ein Doppelter. Auf der objektiven Seite vermochte er wesentliche Elemente in der Theorie der Erkenntnis von Thomas wieder zu entdecken, die durch eine jahrhundertelange Tradition subtiler Metaphysiker zum großen Teil überdeckt worden waren. Wie wir sehen werden, ermöglichten genau diese Elemente Lonergan, eine Theorie der Erkenntnis eigens zu entwickeln, die den kulturellen Errungenschaften Rechnung trägt, die die Zeit seit Thomas bis zu uns hervorgebracht hat. Auf der subjektiven Seite vollzog Lonergan in sich selbst die für die moderne Kultur kennzeichnende anthropologische Wende, allerdings ohne die vielfältigen Verkürzungen, die in der Moderne das menschliche Subjekt verzeichnet haben. Bei aller Korrelativität von ens und mens nahm Lonergan die Erkenntnislehre als Ansatz zu seiner Reflexion über die Realität; genauer, diejenige empirische, intelligente, rationale und moralische Intentionalität, die den Menschen als wissendes und verantwortliches Subjekt konstituiert. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Vorwort zur dt. Ausgabe I. 1: Inhaltsübersicht v. Einsicht; Kap. 1 (Einsicht in Mathematik); Kap. 2-5 (Physik); Kap. 6-7 (Common Sense); Kap. 8 (Ding); Kap. 9-11 (Urteil); Kap. 12 (das Reale, Sein); 14-17 (Erkenntnis d. Seins) ; Kap. 19-20 (Gott)

Kurzinhalt: Zuerst (Kap. I) wird die Einsicht in der Mathematik untersucht, wo am deutlichsten gezeigt werden kann, daß es eine vorbegriffliche Erkenntnistätigkeit auf der intellektuellen Ebene gibt,

Textausschnitt: II. Eine Untersuchung über den menschlichen Verstand im heutigen Kontext

XIVa Nach mehr als zehn Lehrjahren bei dem mittelalterlichen Meister war Lonergan imstande, das, was er gelernt hatte, selbst darzulegen und zu entfalten, aber jetzt in sich selbst und in seinen Implikationen, unabhängig von seinem historischen Auftreten bei Aristoteles und Thomas. Aber auch in diesem eigenständigen Unternehmen war seine langfristige Absicht eine theologische. Er stellte eine philosophische Untersuchung über den menschlichen Verstand als eine Erforschung der Methoden an, die heute in den vielfältigen Sparten des Wissens angewandt werden, um so eine Methode der Theologie ausarbeiten zu können, die dem höchst differenzierten Stand des theologischen Forschungs- und Lehrbetriebs im Kontext des zeitgenössischen geistesgeschichtlichen Kontextes entsprechen würde. Es war ein äußerlicher Umstand, nämlich die Berufung zur Gregoriana Universität, der Lonergan nahelegte, seinen Plan zu ändern und den rein philosophischen, eher vorbereitenden Teil abzurunden und zu veröffentlichen unter einem Titel - Insight. A Study of Human Understanding -, der an die klassischen Texte der englichen philosophischen Tradition erinnert: dem Essay bzw. dem Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding von Locke und Hume1. Die zwei Gesprächspartner Lonergans in diesem seinem Hauptwerk sind die Revolution, die die Naturwissenschaft in der modernen Kultur herbeigeführt, und die kritische Wende, die die Philosophie Kants inauguriert hat. (Fs)

XVa Da es hier nicht möglich ist, auf den Inhalt des Buches im einzelnen einzugehen, mag es genügen, 1) eine Übersicht des Inhalts anzugeben , 2) die drei darin immer wiederkehrenden Themen zu umreißen und 3) die eigentliche und letzte Intention des Verfassers zur Sprache zu bringen. (Fs)

1. Eine Inhaltsübersicht

XVb Die ersten acht Kapitel handeln von der Einsicht ins Sinnliche, auf die das Studium von Thomas Lonergan aufmerksam gemacht hatte. Zuerst (Kap. I) wird die Einsicht in der Mathematik untersucht, wo am deutlichsten gezeigt werden kann, daß es eine vorbegriffliche Erkenntnistätigkeit auf der intellektuellen Ebene gibt, und wo diese Tätigkeit (das Verstehen in den Daten) am präzisesten im Begriff ihren Ausdruck findet. (Fs)

XVc In den Kapiteln II bis V wird die Existenz und Eigenart der Einsicht in der Physik untersucht, wo der sich entwickelnde Prozeß der Erklärung der Daten eine große Rolle spielt, und der bloß hypothetische Charakter dessen, was der Verstand in den Daten erfaßt, wegen des experimentellen Verfahrens der neuzeitlichen Wissenschaft deutlich hervortritt. Aber es muß klar gegen ein mehrfach geäußertes Mißverständnis gesagt werden, daß Lonergans Theorie von der Erkenntnis keine Wissenschaftstheorie in dem Sinne ist, daß sie nur für die Erkenntnisart gelte, die der Naturwissenschaft eigen ist. Der Grund seiner eingehenden Analyse der Art und Weise, wie die Naturwissenschaftler ans Werk gehen, ist, daß bei ihnen am genauesten ein Einzelfall des Verstehens unter die Lupe genommen werden kann. Dadurch läßt sich ermitteln, was nämlich die Voraussetzungen dieses Aktes sind, wie er stattfindet, was er erfaßt, wie er in einem Begriff bzw. in einem Gesetz formuliert wird, und damit, was er dem bereits vorliegenden Stand der Erkenntnis hinzufügt. Außerdem hat die moderne Naturwissenschaft in ihren neuesten Errungenschaften - etwa wie sie den Gegenstand in der Relativitätstheorie und das Ereignis in der Quantenmechanik auffaßt - den unübersehbaren Beweis erbracht, daß das, was der Verstand in den Daten entdeckt, das Intelligible, von sich aus und deshalb überhaupt nicht in der Einbildungkraft vorstellbar ist. Nun aber findet sich derselbe strukturelle Akt in allen Bereichen des Wissens, in denen die Menschen von ihrer Intelligenz Gebrauch machen. (Fs) (notabene)

XVd Kapitel VI und VII befassen sich mit der Erkenntnis des Common Sense als einer Spezialisierung der Intelligenz im Bereich des Einzelnen und Konkreten. Während die ersten sieben Kapitel die Intelligenz betrachten, insofern sie unter einem abstrahierenden Gesichtspunkt Korrelationen erfaßt, die die Daten unter einem Aspekt zu einer Einheit führen, geht Kapitel VIII zu einer anderen Art von Einsicht über, die in den Daten insgesamt eine konkrete Einheit-Identität-Totalität erfaßt, die wir mit dem Terminus "Ding" bezeichnen. Das Ding als konkretes stellt den Gegenstand dar, in dem Common Sense und Naturwissenschaft sich treffen. (Fs) (notabene)

XVIa Kapitel IX bis XI handeln vom Urteil als der Phase, die der Begriffsbildung folgt und den Erkenntnisprozeß zum Abschluß führt. Wichtig ist hier die Analyse des reflexiven Verstehensaktes, der den de facto unbedingten Grund liefert, weswegen der Verstand das Urteil als absolute Setzung der zunächst bloß gedachten mentalen Synthesis fällen kann. Kapitel XII geht auf das Objekt ein, das durch den Vollzug der intelligenten und rationalen Dynamik unseres Geistes (der Intentionalität) erkannt wird: das Reale, das Sein. Kapitel XIII wirft die Frage nach der objektiven Geltung unserer Erkenntnis auf, warum sie nämlich als Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit gelten kann. (Fs)

XVIb Kapitel XIV bis XVII arbeiten ausführlich unsere Erkenntnis des Seins - zunächst des unserer Erkenntnisart proportionierten Seins - in seinen Grundstrukturen aus; also das, was unter dem herkömmlichen Namen der Metaphysik gemeint ist. Kapitel XVIII geht über das rein erkenntnismäßige Moment unserer Intentionalität hinaus, um ihren freien und verantwortlichen Vollzug zu untersuchen; es handelt also von der Ethik. (Fs)

XVIc Kapitel XIX befaßt sich mit der Wirklichkeit, die jenseits des beschränkten Bereichs unserer äußeren und inneren Erfahrung liegt, zugleich aber von derselben intelligenten und rationalen Intentionalität, die die Erkenntnis der "Welt" hervorbringt, in ihrer uneingeschränkten Tragweite intendiert wird; kurzum, mit der Frage nach Gott. Kapitel XX fragt danach, wie das personale Wesen, von dem die Welt ihren Ursprung hat, und dem die Eigenschaften der höchsten Weisheit, Allmacht und Güte zuerkannt werden, mit dem Übel in der Welt umgeht. Die Antwort auf diese Frage führt eine Verschiebung des Zentrums der menschlichen Interessen herbei, die den Zugang zu jener übernatürlichen Realitätsordnung öffnet, von der die christliche Theologie spricht. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Vorwort zur dt. Ausgabe I. 2: die drei Grundthemen; Mythos v. Anschauung (als ein "taking a look"); Implikation: Sein als innerlich intelligibel und rational; Wirklichkeit als: Sein - "already out there now real"; echte Objektivität - authentische Subjekt

Kurzinhalt: 1) Was tue ich, wenn ich erkenne? 2) Was erkenne ich, wenn ich dies tue? 3) Warum ist dieses Tun ein Erkennen? (im Sinne von Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit); Anschauung (als ein "taking a look") ... "Echte Objektivität ist die Frucht authentischer ...

Textausschnitt: 2. Die drei Grundthemen

XVId Das Buch ist in zwei Teile gegliedert1: 1) Die Einsicht als Tätigkeit, 2) die Einsicht als Erkenntnis. Später hat Lonergan seine Ansicht dahingehend differenziert, daß er sein Werk als die Antwort auf drei Grundfragen betrachtete, nämlich: 1) Was tue ich, wenn ich erkenne? 2) Was erkenne ich, wenn ich dies tue? 3) Warum ist dieses Tun ein Erkennen? (im Sinne von Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit)2. Das, was eine Philosophie wesentlich kennzeichnet und sie von den anderen unterscheidet, ist ihre "Grundposition", d. h. die Position, die sie in bezug auf Erkenntnis, Realität und Objektivität einnimmt. (Fs) (notabene)

XVIIa
2.1 Die erste Frage zielt darauf ab, die Natur der menschlichen Erkenntnis zu klären. Dies ist auf demselben Weg zu erreichen, wie in allen anderen Fällen, in denen es darum geht zu erkennen, was etwas sei: Man muß die Daten der in Frage stehenden Wirklichkeit untersuchen. Diese Daten sind im Falle der Erkenntnis unsere eigenen Erkenntnishandlungen, die thematisiert werden, d. h. zum Gegenstand einer Untersuchung gemacht werden können, weil sie bewußte Handlungen sind. Das Ergebnis einer solchen introspektiven Analyse ist, daß die vielfältigen Handlungen, aus denen der Erkenntnisprozeß besteht, und die in den verschiedenen Arten von Erkenntnis eine jeweils verschiedene Ausformung aufweisen, sich auf drei wesentlich voneinander verschiedene und nach den dem Erkenntnisprozeß selbst innewohnenden Gesetzen verbundene Ebenen verteilen: Die Erfahrung, die Einsicht (die im Begriff ihren Ausdruck findet) und das Urteil. (Fs)

XVIIb Die menschliche Erkenntnis im vollen Sinne des Wortes ist also eine dreigliedrige dynamische Struktur, die erst im Urteil das erreicht, d. h. erkennt, wonach sie von Anfang an fragt: Das Sein, die Wirklichkeit. Der "Mythos", den Lonergan ständig vor Augen hat, wenn er von der Erkenntnis als einer Struktur spricht, und den er in all seinen Erscheinungsformen bekämpft, ist die Auffassung von der Erkenntnis a!s einer Art Anschauung (als ein "taking a look"), als einer Tätigkeit nach dem Modell des Sehens mit den Augen, deren Wesen also in einer, sei sie auch angeblich intellektuellen, Extraversion besteht und nicht in ihrer uns durchaus bewußten Intelligenz und Rationalität. Denn eine solche naheliegende, dennoch irreführende Metapher macht, konsequent genommen, die Handlungen, die wir de facto vollziehen, wenn wir erkennen wollen, wie die Dinge wirklich sind, überflüssig bzw. gegenstandslos. Dies bedeutet freilich kein Verbot, von einer Anschauung zu reden, falls dieses Bild als Abbreviatur der genannten, introspektiv feststellbaren Handlungen verstanden wird. (Fs) (notabene)

XVIIc
2.2 Wie Lonergan die Frage nach dem, was die Erkenntnis ist, durch die Analyse der intelligenten und rationalen Dynamik (Intention) beantwortet hat, die den Erkenntnisprozeß trägt und von innen her normiert, so legt er fest, was die Wirklichkeit sei, indem er die Beziehung der Wirklichkeit zu denselben Handlungen thematisiert, durch die die Wirklichkeit erkannt wird: "Das Sein ist das Zielobjekt des reinen Erkenntnisstrebens" (348); oder, wenn man den zwei Momenten im Vollzug dieses Erkenntnisstrebens explizit Rechnung trägt: "Das Sein ist all das, was durch ein intelligentes Erfassen und ein vernünftiges Bejahen zu erkennen ist" (391); oder, auf die Wirklichkeit Bezug nehmend, die unserer Erkenntnisart (in der die Intentionalität auf Daten der Erfahrung angewiesen ist) direkt entspricht, und die deshalb ihren ersten und proportionierten Gegenstand ausmacht: Das Sein ist "all das, was durch menschliche Erfahrung, intelligentes Erfassen und vernünftiges Bejahen zu erkennen ist" {ebd.). (Fs)

XVIIIa Es handelt sich um eine operative Definition, die die Wirklichkeit mittels der Handlungen definiert, die nötig sind, um sie zu erkennen, und die sich jeder Mensch spontan zu eigen macht, wenn er etwas erkennen oder wenn er eine als falsch entdeckte Erkenntnis korrigieren will: Durch die Aufmerksamkeit auf alle relevanten Daten, durch den Versuch, sie zu erklären, durch die unvoreingenommene Abwägung darüber, ob nicht doch Daten vorliegen, die seine Interpretation der Daten und damit den Gegenstand, wie er ihn zunächst gedacht hat, in Frage stellen. (Fs)

XVIIIb Die von Lonergan ausgearbeitete Auffassung von der Wirklichkeit impliziert, daß das Sein innerlich intelligibel und rational ist, insofern es genau das ist, was durch unsere Intelligenz und unsere Rationalität erkannt wird, oder, negativ ausgedrückt, sie impliziert, daß das Sein weder jenseits des Intelligiblen noch außer ihm noch verschieden von ihm ist (499). Die Lehre von der Korrelativität zwischen der Intelligenz und der Vernünftigkeit unserer Intentionalität einerseits und der Wirklichkeit andererseits kommt der Lehre gleich, daß wir die Wirklichkeit nicht durch eine problemlose Erfahrung erkennen, nicht durch eine ad hoc postulierte Anschauung, die nicht mit der Erfahrung, der intelligenten Untersuchung und der kritischen Reflexion identisch wäre. Kurzum, es gilt zwischen der Wirklichkeit als Sein zu unterscheiden, die Gegenstand der Erkenntnis intelligenter und rationaler Wesen ist, und der Wirklichkeit als dem "jetzt schon da draußen Realen" ("already out there now real", 251 u. ö.), die Gegenstand einer animalischen Erkenntnis ist, die sich in einem extravertierten Streben erschöpft. Es gilt, zu der Einsicht zu gelangen, daß "der ungreifbare Akt der rationalen Zustimmung die notwendige und zureichende Bedingung für die Erkenntnis der Wirklichkeit ist" (538). (Fs)

XVIIIc Sich eine solche Auffassung von der Wirklichkeit zu eigen zu machen, ist, so warnt Lonergan, eine Entdeckung, "die einer noch nicht gemacht hat, wenn er keine klare Erinnerung an ihre bestürzende Merkwürdigkeit hat" (xxviii). Es ist wahrhaftig keine Übertreibung, wenn Lonergan in seinen späteren Schriften von einer intellektuellen Bekehrung spricht, um von der Auffassung vom Sein als dem Zielobjekt einer Tendenz nach dem Modell der sinnlichen Extraversion zur Auffassung vom Sein als dem, was durch eine richtige Erklärung der Daten erkannt wird, überzugehen; oder, anders gesagt, um den weitverbreiteten Trugschluß zu durchschauen, das Selbstverständliche an unserer Erkenntnis (die Anschauung eines Gegen-standes) sei das, was unsere Erkenntnis selbstverständlich ist (416). (Fs)

XIXa
2.3 Mit seiner Lehre von der Erkenntnis und der Wirklichkeit hat Lonergan auch die Frage nach der Objektivität beanwortet, d. h. die Frage, warum wir durch die genannten Handlungen die Wirkichkeit zu erkennen vermögen. Eine solche Erklärung ist in einer doppelten Eigenschaft unseres Erkenntnisprozesses zu finden. Erstens, der Prozeß besteht im Vollzug einer kognitiven Intentionalität, deren Tragweite unbegrenzt ist, und die deshalb ihren Gegenstand anstrebt, insofern er "ist" -wobei das "ist" mit keiner restringierenden Qualifikation behaftet ist und deswegen unbedingte Geltung hat. Die Unbegrenztheit unserer geistigen Dynamik ist Bedingung dafür, daß das Objekt der Erkenntnis als Sein intendiert wird. Zweitens, der Vollzug der kognitiven Intentionalität findet seinen Abschluß im Urteil. Was wir durch Fragen beabsichtigen, die innerhalb keines Immanenzprinzips eingeschlossen sind, wird durch die Antwort auf dieselben Fragen erkannt, insofern das Urteil als absolute Setzung unserer Suche nach dem Sein Genüge tut. (Fs)

XIXb Es besteht deshalb eine innere Verbindung von Objektivität und Subjektivität. Die menschliche Erkenntnis als wahre Erkenntnis ist die Leistung eines Subjektes, das auf die Daten aufmerksam ist, das sich vor der Mühe der Untersuchung nicht drückt, das gewillt ist, über das zur Entscheidung anstehende Urteil zu reflektieren, ohne der Versuchung nachzugeben, für adäquat jene Entsprechung von Interpretation und Daten zu halten, die seinen Interessen und seinem Wunschdenken entgegenkommt. Erst dann urteilt es. All dies aber findet nicht statt ohne eine eigene Moralität des Erkennens, die das Subjekt persönlich in Anspruch nimmt. Daraus erhellt der Sinn einer Aussage, die mehrmals beim späten Lonergan wiederkehrt: "Echte Objektivität ist die Frucht authentischer Subjektivität"3. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Erkenne dich selbst; Aneignung d. rationalen Selbstbewusstseins; picture thinking -> Wahrheit d. Urteils

Kurzinhalt: Und am Ende seiner Arbeit ... nennt [Lonergan] das Buch einen "Essay zur persönlichen Aneignung des eigenen rationalen Selbstbewußtseins" ... vom picture thinking der Erkenntnis als Anschauung zur Wahrheit des Urteils,

Textausschnitt: 3. Eine moderne Version des "Erkenne dich selbst"

XIXc Mit dem zuletzt Gesagten haben wir bereits angedeutet, was Lonergan mit der "Einsicht" eigentlich vorhat. Im vorliegenden Werk wird der Leser gewiß grundlegende philosophische Einsichten finden; auf sie habe ich soeben aufmerksam gemacht. Bei aller Bedeutung dieser Lehrstücke liegt jedoch nicht in ihnen das, was der Verfasser dem Leser letztlich mitteilen will. Im ersten Absatz der Einleitung legt Lonergan in fünf Distinktionen die Absicht fest, die ihn bei der Abfassung des Buches geleitet hat. Die aufschlußreichste ist die dritte: "Es geht nicht darum, eine Liste der abstrakten Eigenschaften der menschlichen Erkenntnis aufzustellen, sondern dem Leser zu helfen, sich die seinen eigenen Erkenntnisaktivitäten innewohnende konkrete, dynamische und immer wieder wirkende Struktur anzueignen." Und am Ende seiner Arbeit nennt er das Buch einen "Essay zur persönlichen Aneignung des eigenen rationalen Selbstbewußtseins" (748). (Fs)

XIXa Lonergan sieht die Gefahr bzw. die Versuchung des Lesers darin, daß er sich für die Ausführungen über Einsichten in Mathematik, Physik, Common Sense und Philosophie interessiert, und während er an die jeweiligen Objekte denkt, "seine eigenen Handlungen hinsichtlich der Objekte vernachlässigt. Damit verfehlt er das Wesentliche. Die verschiedenen Objekte werden nur deshalb erwähnt, um den Leser aufzufordern, sein eigenes Bewußtsein der Handlungen zu intensivieren, die er vollzieht, indem er sich mit den Objekten befaßt. Wenn man nun diese Falle umgeht - und dies ist nicht leicht -, ergibt sich eine zunehmende Erleuchtung, die den Leser dazu führt, daß er Lonergan nicht mehr braucht, weil er selber die Entdek-kung gemacht hat und imstande ist, es selbst zu tun"1. (Fs)

XIXb Was mit einer solchen Aneignung seiner selbst gemeint ist, erläutert Lonergan im selben Zusammenhang durch folgenden Vergleich: "Wie man in gewissen Methoden der Therapie seine eigenen vorher verdrängten Gefühle zu merken, zu nennen, anzuerkennen und zu identifizieren lernt, so wird man in diesem Buch aufgefordert, in sich selbst die eigenen Handlungen, von denen man Erfahrung hat, und die Dynamik, die von einer Art von Handlungen zu einer anderen führt, genau zu entdecken. In dem Maße, als man diese Entdeckung macht, wird man in den Besitz der Elemente kommen, auf die ein grundlegender Satz von Termini und Beziehungen verweist. Dieser Besitz wird zu einem Verstehen seiner selbst führen, das in der Tatsache gründet, daß man sich selbst verstanden hat."2

XIXc Es ist nicht unangemessen, das Hauptwerk Lonergans als eine moderne Version des alten "Erkenne dich selbst" anzusehen, wobei sich selbst erkennen bedeutet, die eigene Subjektivität zu entdecken und sie sich ausdrücklich und konsequent zu eigen zu machen, jene intelligente, rationale und verantwortliche Dynamik nämlich, die uns zu Personen macht. Damit wird der einzelne in seiner unvertretbaren Individualität aufgefordert, in sich selbst den Übergang zu vollziehen vom picture thinking der Erkenntnis als Anschauung zur Wahrheit des Urteils, und von dem, was gefällt als Kriterium für die eigenen Entscheidungen, zu dem was in Wahrheit gut ist, nämlich zu jenem Wert, zu dem dieselbe Intentionalität uns verpflichtet, wenn sie uns die Frage stellen läßt: "Was soll ich tun?"

XXa Ein solches rationales und verantwortliches Streben aber kann weder bei der als bloßem Faktum existierenden Welt halt machen noch bei einem Wert, der im Horizont der Vergänglichkeit die absolute Verpflichtung des Gewissens nicht zu begründen vermag. Will man nicht dem Obskurantismus huldigen, so fordert uns unsere eigene Intentionalität auf, über die Welt hinaus zu gehen zur Anerkennung einer Wahrheit, in der die Antwort auf alle unsere Fragen liegt, und eines uneingeschränkten, personalen Guten, der die sittliche Bemühung der Mühe wert macht. Solcherart ist der folgerichtige Ausgang des langen Wegs, den Lonergan bei seiner Untersuchung jener Einsicht zurückgelegt hat, die kein Mensch völlig vermeiden kann. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Seiendes, Sein: Umfang: kollektiv, distributiv (im engen und weiten Sinn)

Kurzinhalt: In a stricter sense, being is that which is. Thus God, angels, humans, animals, plants, and minerals are beings in the stricter sense because they themselves are. More broadly speaking, a being is that which is in some way or other related to what is.

Textausschnitt: 5 Denotation of being (eü)

5 Now that we have dealt with the quiddity of being and its intending and intended intention, we must say a word about its extension or denotation.

15/1 With regard to its extension, being is understood either collectively or distributively. Collectively being denotes 'everything'; distributively it denotes 'the total reality of each single thing.' (15; Fs)

Moreover, if being is taken distributively, it can be understood in a stricter or a broader sense. (17; Fs)

16/1 In a stricter sense, being is that which is. Thus God, angels, humans, animals, plants, and minerals are beings in the stricter sense because they themselves are.

More broadly speaking, a being is that which is in some way or other related to what is. Thus the following are called beings in a wider sense: (1) the intrinsic principles of a finite being, (2) accidents, (3) things that are possible, (4) 'beings of reason,' beings that exist only in the mind. None of these is that which itself is, and yet all of these are in some way or other related to what is. For (1) the principles of being do not themselves exist, but something exists through them; (2) accidents do not exist, they inhere, exist-in; (3) possible beings do not exist but can exist; and (4) beings of reason have not a natural but only an intentional act of existence. (17; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Seiendes, Sein: Schlussfolgerungen; Licht des Verstandes (intentio intendens): geschaffene Ähnlichkeit mit dem ungeschaffenen Licht

Kurzinhalt: Fifth, the intending intention of being is the very light of our intellect... Sixth, the light of our intellect is a participated likeness of uncreated light.

Textausschnitt: 6 Conclusions (eü)

6 Granted the foregoing, these conclusions readily follow. (17; Fs)

17/1 First, far from being abstract, being is precisely that by which we can intend and signify the concrete. When you speak of something concrete, you are speaking of a thing in its total reality. But no human being knows anything in its total reality. Accordingly, we denote and signify the concrete not by knowing it but by intending it through the intending intention of being. (17; Fs)

Second, being is the greatest not only in extension but also in intention. The followers of Scotus and Hegel maintain that being is minimal in intention. But what leads them astray is the fact that by the intending intention of being alone, although potentially we know everything, we actually know nothing. (17; Fs)

Third, since being includes everything it must not be considered the sole preserve of philosophers to the exclusion of all other branches of knowledge. For just as philosophy alone is not the science of all reality, so too philosophy alone is not the science of being. (17; Fs)

Fourth, theology deals with being insofar as it deals with God and everything that is related to God. For God is being by essence, and if you eliminate God, you eliminate the intrinsic intelligibility of being. And the absolutely supernatural beatific vision of God is the only knowledge possible to a creature whereby being can be known quidditatively. Finally, to deal with everything as it is related to God means in some way to deal with everything and therefore with being. (17; Fs)

Fifth, the intending intention of being is the very light of our intellect. For by this intention and light (1) we wonder intellectually about sensible things; (2) we are turned away from sensible things as sensible; and (3) we are turned to questions about the entire range of intelligible truth. (17; Fs) (notabene)

Sixth, the light of our intellect is a participated likeness of uncreated light.1 (19; Fs)

Seventh, the divine Word is being by essence intellectually begotten, and the incarnate Word is being by essence intellectually begotten and incarnate. Hence we read, 'He was the true light that enlightens everyone coming into the world' (John 1.9),2 and 'For this was I born and for this have I come into the world, to bear witness to the truth. Everyone who is of the truth hears my voice' (John 18.37).3 See also other Johannine passages that speak of light and darkness. (19; Fs)

Eighth, since the intended intention of being has been understood by various people in various ways, a historian must distinguish between the different philosophical and theological schools. (19; Fs)

18/1 On the other hand, because the intending intention of being is specifically one and the same in all, one can imagine nothing more absurd than what is heard all too often, namely, that divine revelation lacked any intention of being, that the intention of being was imported into Christian thought from Hellenism, Gnosticism, Platonism, Aristotelianism. (19; Fs)

19/1 Again, because the intending intention of being is part of human nature and common to all, the theologian must pay particular attention to it for the reason that, in keeping with the meaning of the sources of revelation themselves, this intention cannot be absent from those sources. And for the same reason this holds also for the notions of potency, form, and act as they will be defined later. (19; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Existenz; hierarchische Ordnung von Dingen (Aufhebung, sublation?); Mensch: die höhere Synthese als potentiell nicht aktuell

Kurzinhalt: Although physical, chemical, biological, and psychic laws are operative in us, the higher synthesis itself is not actual but potential. For we are not made in such a way that by some natural necessity our reason must rule over our lower nature, but ...

Textausschnitt: 2 Existenz1 (eg: lat: Ex-sistentia - 'on being oneself')

Fußnote oben:

[The choice of Existenz to translate 'De ex-sistentia' is based on Lonergan's usage in the 1964 lecture 'Existent and Aggiomamento,' where Existenz is coupled with 'on being oneself.' See Collection (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1988 [CWL. 4]) 222. 'On being oneself' was a key theme in Lonergan's 1957 lectures on existentialism, published in CWL 18; there, however, he tended to limit the use of the word Existenz to discussions of the philosophy of Karl Jaspers, in which it is a key technical term. Elsewhere in this section his ex-sistere is rendered to 'exist' (that is, using inverted commas) and similarly for cognate terms, while Existenz is used to translate ex-sistentia. Usually Lonergan's Latin word 'exsistentia' does not have this dramatic significance, and then it has been changed to 'existentia.' The same holds for the verb 'exsistere,' which becomes 'existere.' But when Lonergan added a hyphen, as here, his spelling of the Latin word is retained.]

7 Ex-sistentia (eü)

20/1 7 Kierkegaard used to ask whether he was really and truly a Christian. Contemporary philosophers ask what it means to be a human being in the proper, genuine, authentic sense. (19; Fs)

21/1 These questions deal not with just any existence of a thing but with its existence as that thing is conceived normatively. Kierkegaard did not think it sufficient to be born in Denmark and thus by the law of the land to belong to the official Danish Christian Church. Nor do contemporary writers regard one to be a human being in the proper sense just because one can produce a clear and authentic birth certificate. Rather they ask whether human beings exist as they ought to 'according to the eternal reasons,' to borrow a phrase from Augustine. (21; Fs)

22/1 This question is by no means pointless. While a human being is defined as a rational animal, still we must be sufficiently well developed as animals before we begin to act rationally. We do not regard children as having reached the age of reason until they are seven years old, nor do we judge young people to have reached majority until the age of twenty-one. And producers of public entertainment aim at adapting their shows to the mentality of twelve-year-olds, since that is reckoned to be the average mental age of the adult population. (21; Fs)

23/1 But if you prefer to disregard popular opinion and get at the heart of the matter, you must investigate and understand the hierarchic order of things. In chemical elements the laws proper to chemistry prevail, while leaving intact the laws of physics. In plants the laws of biology prevail, but without violating any of the laws of chemistry and physics. In animals the laws of animal psychology prevail, but in such a way that no law of chemistry, physics, or biology is violated. From this you will perhaps conclude that the hierarchic order of things is such that each higher genus, as if by a kind of Aufhebung, retains lower laws while at the same time doing away with them. For the lower laws are completely retained, since they are perfectly observed; but they are also completely dispensed with since they are wholly subordinated to the overriding control of a higher synthesis. (21; Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (27.10.12): Zu "Aufhebung" oben. Ist Lonergans Ausdruck für "Aufhebung" später sublation?

24/1 Now while this conclusion holds true for all other beings, we immediately note an exception in the case of human beings. Although physical, chemical, biological, and psychic laws are operative in us, the higher synthesis itself is not actual but potential. For we are not made in such a way that by some natural necessity our reason must rule over our lower nature, but that it ought to do so. Such dominion must be achieved through the exercise of one's reason and personal freedom in order for one to become a true, proper, authentic and genuine human being. It is up to each one, therefore, out of the potentiality each one has, to achieve his or her own Existenz. (21; Fs) (notabene)

25/1 The paradox inherent in this Existenz comes to light immediately. For human beings do not strive to 'exist' through intellects already actuated by wisdom, understanding, and knowledge, nor through wills already endowed with virtues. Rather, one has to begin from that famous tabula rasa and from a will devoid of virtues so that one may at last learn what one ought to be and will to make oneself what one ought to be. (21; Fs) (notabene)

26/1 Once this is grasped, it can surely come as no surprise that very few 'exist,' that very few have learned that 'the real' or the 'really real' is what becomes known under the name of being through the mediation of concepts and judgments, that very few have come through a kind of dark night of the senses so purified as to surrender themselves wholeheartedly, effectively, and perseveringly to the intelligible and true good. (23; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Existenz; d. Mensch auf der sinnlichen Ebene (ästhetische Sphäre der existentiellen Subjektivität)

Kurzinhalt: And so it happens that those who do not 'exist' regard being as nothing, while those who do 'exist' judge non-being to be nothing. Such clear, distinct, and mutually contradictory positions, however, would not even be conceived except by those who ...

Textausschnitt:

27/1 8 This being the case, if you wish to be of service to others, it is necessary (1) that you 'exist' yourself, so that it is not a matter of the blind leading the blind, and (2) that you try to effect a conversion in others rather than to prove them wrong. For since the type of person you are determines how you see your aim in life,1 it surely follows not only that the type of person you are in desiring determines how you will see the aim of your desiring but also that the type of person you are in apprehending determines how you will see the aim of your apprehending. (23; Fs)

28/1 To whoever, therefore, is immersed in the world of the senses - or, as they say nowadays, to one living in the aesthetic sphere of existential subjectivity - things will be seen as real only insofar as they are perceptible to the senses; and they will be seen as nothing insofar as they cannot be so perceived. (23; Fs)

29/1 But to the extent that one emerging from the world of the senses is converted to the intelligible world, things will be seen to be real insofar as they are (that is, insofar as they can be known by being understood and affirmed), and things will be seen to be nothing insofar as they are not. (23; Fs)

30/1 And so it happens that those who do not 'exist' regard being as nothing, while those who do 'exist' judge non-being to be nothing. Such clear, distinct, and mutually contradictory positions, however, would not even be conceived except by those who have already begun to 'exist' to some extent, since a problem clearly grasped is a problem half solved. (23; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Existenz; Ziele und Mittel (direkt, indirekt, natürlich, übernatürlich); Einsicht, Vernunft (Kultur des Dialoges: Antike, Mittelalter) ; natürliche M. nicht ausreichend: Akademie -> Skeptizismus, Lyceum -> Empirismus

Kurzinhalt: However, since natural means of this kind are indirect, they are also not so effective as to exclude all possibility of self-deception. For they do not act in such a way as to diagnose the disease and cure it; rather they propose the goals, provide ...

Textausschnitt: 9 End and Means (eü)

31/1 9 As to what can help one to be converted and so begin to 'exist,' we must distinguish between end and means, between direct and indirect means, and between natural and supernatural means. (23; Fs)

32/1 Means that are natural and indirect are clear enough. When you speak, you have to use your mind and reason; and when you use your mind and reason, you have not only to attend to the data of sense but you are also concerned with the intelligible and the true. For this reason both the ancient Greeks with their love of talk and the medievals with their passion for disputation arrived at being, led along as it were by human nature itself. Modern thinkers, on the other hand, who have worked out their systems in isolation, more often than not have drawn from their profound musings ideas indicating that they have hardly been liberated from a kind of sensism. (23f; Fs) (notabene)

33/1 Again, when human persons interact with one another, they must use their intellect and reason and also be aware that the others are likewise using theirs. Through this exercise there arises and develops an orientation that is the opposite of that which characterizes animals. For to the extent to which one does not 'exist,' one is a kind of focal point of thoughts and desires in relation to which everything else is judged useful or useless. Intellect and reason are of so little importance as to be deemed comparable to animal faculties; for the intellect is considered to be to a human being what swiftness is to a deer, bravery to a lion, or venemous fangs to a snake. But when one has begun to 'exist,' one understands that there is a certain order to the universe and concludes that one is a subordinate part of that order, and so learns to put the common good before one's own private good. On this basis, therefore, the present-day esteem for the person must be reckoned among the aids that contribute to personal conversion and Existenz, just as in an earlier time the Greek fondness for talk and the medieval passion for disputation had done. (25; Fs)

34/1 However, since natural means of this kind are indirect, they are also not so effective as to exclude all possibility of self-deception. For they do not act in such a way as to diagnose the disease and cure it; rather they propose the goals, provide the circumstances, and favor those actions from which more often than not a happy outcome may be hoped for. Although the ancient Greeks did arrive at being, later on the Academy fell into skepticism and the Lyceum into empiricism. And although the medievals plumbed the depths of being, in the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries they were unable to stem the tide of decadence, conceptualism, nominalism, and skepticism. Just as in former times the Stoics had propounded a truly lofty doctrine of morality and yet remained materialists, so too the personalists of our day, while they praise true virtue, nonetheless do not refrain from looking down on and holding in contempt disciplines that are truly scientific. (25; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Existenz; Konversion, übernatürliche Mittel; Sinne, Vernunft, Glaube

Kurzinhalt: The less reason is perturbed by the life of the senses, the more effectively will faith be able to enlighten reason. And the more effectively faith enlightens reason, the more fruitfully will reason, thus enlightened, attain with God's help some ...

Textausschnitt: 10 Supernatural Means (eü)

35/1 10 For this reason, means that directly regard the goal must be added to indirect means. The goal is that a human being 'exist,' that human rationality go from a potency to dominate to actually exercising complete and perfect control. To this end the direct means is a certain deep and radical conversion that is conscious and deliberate. Normally the first step towards this conversion is that one suspect, discover, and admit, at least to oneself, that one is not yet converted. For if the keen mind of Augustine thought for years that only material bodies were real, those less gifted than Augustine generally differ from him not in that they perceive that being is the really real and that non-being is nothing, but rather in the fact that through their confusion and indecision they have never clearly and distinctly conceived the problem, much less definitively settled it. (25f; Fs) (notabene)

36/1 Supernatural means are far more efficacious than these natural means, direct or indirect. Although we are naturally endowed with that intending intention of being that is a participated likeness of uncreated light, and with that natural desire that is not at rest until being-by-essence is known through its essence,1 still we do not proceed toward this end by natural means.2 Our justification, by which the sensitive element of our being is subject to our reason and our reason to God,3 is the supernatural effect of the free gift of divine love4 inasmuch as God operates in us so that we may be able to cooperate with God.5 (27; Fs)

37/1 This supernatural conversion which, although primarily directed towards the goal of eternal life, includes natural conversion, also carries along with it that by which one can 'exist' even in this life. One who was brought up in the Catholic faith learned even as a child that spiritual things are real; one who holds to Catholic dogmas arrives at what is real by what is true; one who agrees with the [First] Vatican Council cannot make light of that understanding of the mysteries commended by the Council; and one who, following the lead of the church, pursues theology according to the principles, method, and doctrine of St Thomas Aquinas,6 must at least suspect that we advance in knowledge by questioning, since the whole of Thomas's theology consists in asking questions and answering them. (27; Fs)

38/1 Since this is so, it cannot be denied that our faith and, in its proper place, Catholic theology penetrate and direct the whole human mind in such a way as effectively and profoundly to invite, entice, and almost force one toward Existenz. And yet, 'let one who is just be further justified' (DB 803, DS 1335). One who has received the grace that makes a human being whole, righteous, and just should strive, with the help of grace, that grace be further increased.7 The more completely reason is subject to God and the sense appetite to reason, the less does the sensitive element obscure and darken the rational. The less reason is perturbed by the life of the senses, the more effectively will faith be able to enlighten reason. And the more effectively faith enlightens reason, the more fruitfully will reason, thus enlightened, attain with God's help some understanding of the mysteries of faith. (27f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Existenz; Erbsünde, Gnade; Unterschied zw. Philosophen (Existenz auf verschiedenen Ebenen); thomistische Theologie

Kurzinhalt: ...who disregard divine revelation and proceed empirically and concretely ... may appear to be considering human beings as they are, but in fact are ignoring what divine wisdom has devised and divine goodness has bestowed to alleviate the human condition.

Textausschnitt: 11 Existence theology (eü)

11 With all this well understood, the following points should also be noted.

39/1 First, what we have very briefly written about the meaning of Existenz merely touches the surface. There are many different intermediate stages between the extremes of a coherent sensism and an equally coherent intellectualism. And one must not think that each individual lives consistently at one fixed stage but rather that we more or less go back and forth between stages. Just as the surface of the ocean is disturbed now by smaller and now by larger waves, and just as the water level falls and rises with the ebb and flow of the tides, so ought we to think of the various levels of perfection at which persons may 'exist.' (29; Fs) (notabene)

40/1 Second, once the complexity of the matter and the obscurity of the problem are grasped, do not imagine that with these notes you are ready to understand those authors who go by the name of existentialists. For what each one of them means by 'being' can be determined only by a painstaking investigation of that particular thinker. (29; Fs)

41/1 Third, there are many arguments to prove that this question of Existenz is theological rather than philosophical. For whoever strives to understand human beings as they actually are is investigating creatures infected by original sin and helped by God's grace, and as either cooperating with or resisting that grace. But it is theologians and not philosophers whose task it is to seek an understanding of original sin and of divine grace. Furthermore, in the actual order of things, by the one remedy of revelation God had a twofold end in view, namely, that supernatural truths might become known and that natural truths could be known with relative ease, with certitude, and with no trace of error (DB 1786, DS 3005). Hence, those who disregard divine revelation and proceed empirically and concretely, who regard only the mass of humanity rather than what human nature can do by itself, may appear to be considering human beings as they are, but in fact are ignoring what divine wisdom has devised and divine goodness has bestowed to alleviate the human condition. (29; Fs)

42/1 Fourth, there is also another sense in which the question of Existenz belongs to the theologian. For the critical problem which has arisen from the many disagreements and opposing views of philosophers is not simply absent in theologians: the latter, in their investigation of almost every speculative question, take up different positions with the result that they argue fruitlessly and inconclusively. Furthermore, if philosophers disagree because they 'exist' at different levels, theologians not only can suspect that they have not been entirely free of the same malady, but also should strive to help both themselves and the philosophers, since they are investigating the deeper causes and reasons for the human condition as it actually is. (29f; Fs)

43/1 Fifth, we must not overlook the fact that the numerous objections which are usually brought up against Thomist theology are most serious for those who do not 'exist,' but completely disappear for those who do. While it is true that the old should be expanded and perfected by the new,1 it is crucial that we strive really to understand the old. I know of nothing that can lead to this more effectively than that interior and radical conversion whereby one emerges from the shadows and admits to oneself that the real is the intelligible, the true, being, the good. (31; Fs) (notabene)

44/1 That does not mean, of course, that the senses, imagination, and affectivity are of no account. For we understand nothing in this life unless we turn our intellects to phantasms. And although we conceive God by denying all materiality and all that is perceptible by the senses, we cannot approach our Lord Jesus Christ, a man individuated by matter, save by beginning from this particular time and place familiar to us through our senses and then proceeding by our imagination until we arrive at the Palestine, the Bethlehem, the Nazareth, and the Jerusalem of two thousand years ago. But after arriving at the corporeal reality of the Lord by means of our senses, we ought to grasp by our mind that he is a man animated by a rational soul and believe by faith that he is not just man but also God. And finally, by theology we ought to understand to some extent what it means to be one person subsisting in two natures and being aware of himself through two consciousnesses. (31; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); Eins, das Eine (transzendental, formal, prädikamental) -> Erfahrung, erste, zweite Tätigkeit des Verstandes

Kurzinhalt: 'Transcendental one' is undivided in itself and divided from everything else; and this 'one' first becomes known in the second operation of the intellect, inasmuch as the object of judgment is necessarily subject to the principles of identity and ...

Textausschnitt: 3 The Meanings of 'One'

12 Transcendental, Formal, predicamental 'One' (eü)

45/1 12 We distinguish three meanings of 'one': 'transcendental one,' 'natural one' (that is, the formal 'one,' or one per se), and 'predicamental one.'

'Predicamental one' is the principle of number, and it first becomes known through experience. For example, seeing my fingers I distinguish the first, the second, the third, and so on. (31; Fs)

'Natural or formal one,' one per se, is what first becomes known in the first operation of the intellect. Thus a pile of stones is said to be one-by-accident, since no intelligible principle of unity is apprehended in it but only spatial juxtaposition. A human being, on the other hand, or an animal is said to be one per se, not only because I perceive a spatial juxtaposition of parts but also because with my mind I grasp a unit that has its own proper intelligibility. (31f; Fs)

'Transcendental one' is undivided in itself and divided from everything else; and this 'one' first becomes known in the second operation of the intellect, inasmuch as the object of judgment is necessarily subject to the principles of identity and contradiction. For whatever is reasonably affirmed or denied is necessarily identical with itself and not confused with anything else. (33; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); das Subsistente, Subsistenz - das Eine: nähere Bestimmung d. Seienden: ungeteilt in sich getrennt von jedem anderen;

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 4 The Subsistent

13 The One - the Subsistent (eü)

46/1 13 That which is being in the stricter sense is also one in the stricter, that is the transcendental, sense. The reason for this is that 'one' adds nothing but negations to being, and therefore the whole perfection of unity necessarily has its foundation in the perfection of being. (33; Fs)

That 'one' adds nothing to being except negations is clear from the definition of 'one.' For what is one is undivided in itself and divided from everything else; but 'undivided in itself merely denies internal division, and 'divided from everything else' merely denies identification with or admixture of anything else. (33; Fs)

That the definition of 'one' is more fully verified in being in the stricter sense than in being in a broader sense is clear from a simple comparison.

47/1 Beings in the stricter sense are not only conceived and affirmed according to the principles of identity and non-contradiction, but in their ontological reality they are also undivided in themselves and divided from everything else. For minerals, plants, animals, human beings, and angels exist apart from one another and all have their own proper existence. (33; Fs)

48/1 On the other hand, beings taken in a broader sense are so conceived and affirmed according to the principles of identity and contradiction that in their ontological reality they are not completely divided from one another; and this is not something that just happens to them, but follows from their very nature. (33; Fs)

For accidents of their very nature inhere in a substance, and for that reason are not simply divided from everything else. The intrinsic principles of being by their very nature come together to form one being in the strict sense, and so are simply divided neither from each other nor from the whole they constitute. Things that are possible are nothing apart from the potency of the agent or that of matter, and hence they are not really distinct from that potency. Finally, 'beings of reason' are nothing outside the mind, and so they cannot be really separated from the mind. (33; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); das Subsistente, Subsistenz (Notion); Seiendes im engen Sinn: subsistieren; S. im weiten Sinn nicht s.: innere Prinzipien, Akzidenzien usw.; Christus als Gott und Mensch ist s.

Kurzinhalt: Ordinarily the subsistent is described as that which exists per se and in itself, a complete being, a whole in itself, simply divided from and existing separately and apart from everything else... (3) that the separated human soul falls somewhat ...

Textausschnitt: 14 Notion of the Subsistent (eü)

49/1 14. With these observations in mind, we come now to the systematic notion of the subsistent. Ordinarily the subsistent is described as that which exists per se and in itself, a complete being, a whole in itself, simply divided from and existing separately and apart from everything else. Hence, in refutation of the Platonic view, the usual question asked is whether universals subsist, that is to say, whether they are beings that exist outside the mind, separate entities (khôrista), substances (ousiai). Now everything that is predicated of a subsistent comes down to the fact that a subsistent is a being in the strict sense. For if it is a being, somehow or other it exists and somehow or other it is undivided in itself and divided from everything else. And if it is a being in the strict sense, it is that which is, substantial, being per se (otherwise it would be something accidental or something less), undivided in itself and this by its very nature, and simply divided from all else and so existing separately and apart. (35; Fs)

50/1 From all this it is evident (1) that beings in the strict sense (things which are) subsist, and therefore minerals, plants, animals, human beings, and angels are said to subsist; (2) that beings in the broader sense (things to which existence belongs only in a certain way) do not subsist, and therefore accidents, the intrinsic principles of being, possible beings, and beings of reason are not said to subsist; (3) that the separated human soul falls somewhat short of being a subsistent in the true sense, since a human being who has been separated into body and soul is not 'undivided in itself';1 (4) that the Eucharistic accidents, which by divine power are sustained without a subject, come somewhat closer to being truly subsistent, since they are more completely divided from everything else than is the case with accidents; and (5) that Christ, God and man, one being in the strict sense (a one, that is, which is divine and human), is also one subsistent. (35; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Titel: The Ontological and Psychological Constitution of Christ

Stichwort: Person (Elemente d. Definition); distinkt; notional d.: (Gott - göttl. Personen); d. subsistent (Vater, Sohn, Geist); indistinkt subsistent: Gott; Suppositum: real - hypothetisch; Unterschied: Suppositum - Subsistentes

Kurzinhalt: Things are distinct when one is not the other... The Father, the Son, and the Spirit are distinct subsistents; but God, as notionally distinct from the persons, is in some way an indistinct subsistent.

Textausschnitt: 5 The Distinct Subsistent or Real Supposit

15 Distinct: Created Things – Trinity (eü)

51/1 15 Things are distinct when one is not the other.

Among created things, a subsistent is by that very fact a distinct subsistent. (35; Fs)

In God, however, there is a notional distinction between God and the Father, between God and the Son, and between God and the Spirit. The Father, the Son, and the Spirit are distinct subsistents; but God, as notionally distinct from the persons, is in some way an indistinct subsistent. (35; Fs)

52/1 A supposit is understood in two ways: first, as a real supposit, this existing human being, for example; and secondly, as a merely hypothetical supposit which - prescinds from truth and falsity, and therefore from existence and non-existence. (35; Fs)

A real supposit is a distinct subsistent. (37; Fs)

A hypothetical supposit is one that comes in between concrete universal concepts and abstract universal concepts, such as, for example, between 'man' and 'humanity,' or between 'centaur' and 'centaurity.'1 (37; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: allgemein

Kurzinhalt: Dialektik ist die vierte unserer funktionalen Spezialisierungen und befaßt sich mit Konflikten... Die Funktion der Dialektik besteht darin, solche Konflikte zum Vorschein zu bringen und ein Verfahren bereitzustellen, das subjektive Differenzen ...

Textausschnitt: X. DIALEKTIK

1/X Die Dialektik ist die vierte unserer funktionalen Spezialisierungen und befaßt sich mit Konflikten. Konflikte sind entweder offen oder verborgen. Sie können in den religiösen Quellen, in der religiösen Überlieferung, in den Aussagen der Autoritäten oder in den Schriften der Theologen liegen. Sie können entgegengesetzte Forschungsrichtungen ebenso betreffen wie gegensätzliche Deutungen, Geschichtsdarstellungen, Arten der Einschätzung und Beurteilung, gegensätzliche Horizonte, Lehren, Systeme oder Verfahrensweisen. (239; Fs)

2/X Doch nicht jeder Gegensatz ist dialektisch. Es gibt Differenzen, die durch die Entdeckung neuer Daten beseitigt werden. Es gibt Unterschiede, die wir als perspektivisch bezeichnet haben und die lediglich die Komplexität der historischen Wirklichkeit bezeugen. Darüber hinaus gibt es aber fundamentale Konflikte, die sich aus einer explizit oder implizit vertretenen Erkenntnistheorie, aus einer ethischen Grundhaltung oder einer religiösen Anschauung ergeben. Sie modifizieren die eigene Mentalität grundlegend und sind nur durch eine intellektuelle, moralische oder religiöse Bekehrung zu überwinden. Die Funktion der Dialektik besteht darin, solche Konflikte zum Vorschein zu bringen und ein Verfahren bereitzustellen, das subjektive Differenzen objektiviert und Bekehrung fördert. (239; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Horizonte (komplementär, genetisch, dialektisch);

Kurzinhalt: Wie sich das Gesichtsfeld je nach dem eigenen Standpunkt verändert, so ändern sich auch der Bereich des eigenen Wissens und die Reichweite eigener Interessen je nach der Periode, in der man lebt, je nach sozialem Hintergrund und eigener Umwelt, je ...

Textausschnitt: 1. Horizonte

3/X Seiner wörtlichen Bedeutung nach bezeichnet Horizont die begrenzende Kreislinie, jene Linie, in der sich Himmel und Erde zu berühren scheinen. Diese Linie ist die Grenze des eigenen Gesichtsfeldes. Bewegen wir uns, so weicht sie vor uns zurück und schließt sich wieder hinter uns, so daß es für verschiedene Standpunkte auch unterschiedliche Horizonte gibt. Zudem gibt es für jeden unterschiedlichen Standpunkt und Horizont unterschiedliche Aufteilungen der Gesamtheit aller sichtbaren Gegenstände. Hinter dem Horizont liegen die Gegenstände, die wenigstens im Augenblick nicht zu sehen sind. Innerhalb des Horizonts liegen die Objekte, die jetzt zu sehen sind. (239; Fs) (notabene)

4/X Wie unser Gesichtsfeld, so ist auch der Bereich unseres Wissens und die Reichweite unserer Interessen begrenzt. Wie sich das Gesichtsfeld je nach dem eigenen Standpunkt verändert, so ändern sich auch der Bereich des eigenen Wissens und die Reichweite eigener Interessen je nach der Periode, in der man lebt, je nach sozialem Hintergrund und eigener Umwelt, je nach Erziehung, Ausbildung und persönlicher Entwicklung. So ist eine metaphorische oder vielleicht analoge Bedeutung des Wortes Horizont entstanden. In diesem Sinne ist das, was jenseits des eigenen Horizonts liegt, einfach außer Reichweite des eigenen Wissens und der eigenen Interessen: Weder weiß man darum, noch kümmert es einen. Was aber innerhalb des eigenen Horizonts liegt, ist in gewissem Ausmaß, groß oder klein, ein Gegenstand des Interesses und des Wissens. (240; Fs)

5/X Unterschiede im Horizont können komplementär, genetisch oder dialektisch sein. Zum ersten: Arbeiter, Werkmeister, Inspektoren, Techniker, Ingenieure, Manager, Ärzte, Juristen, Professoren haben unterschiedliche Interessen. Sie leben gewissermaßen in verschiedenen Welten. Jeder ist recht vertraut mit seiner eigenen Welt. Aber jeder weiß auch um die anderen, und jeder anerkennt auch die Notwendigkeit der anderen. So überschneiden sich ihre zahlreichen Horizonte mehr oder weniger, und im verbleibenden Rest ergänzen sie einander. Als einzelne betrachtet können sie sich nicht selbst genügen, aber zusammen genommen repräsentieren sie die Motivationen und Kenntnisse, die für das Funktionieren einer gemeinschaftlichen Welt erforderlich sind. Solche Horizonte sind komplementär. (240; Fs) (notabene)

6/X Zweitens können sich Horizonte genetisch unterscheiden. Sie sind dann als sukzessive Stufen eines Entwicklungsprozesses aufeinander bezogen. Jede spätere Stufe setzt frühere Stufen voraus, schließt sie teilweise ein und überformt sie zum Teil. Gerade weil die Stadien früher oder später sind, sind niemals zwei Stadien gleichzeitig. Sie sind nicht Teile einer einzigen gemeinschaftlichen Welt, sondern Teile einer einzigen Biographie oder einer einzigen Geschichte. (240; Fs)

7/X Drittens können Horizonte dialektisch entgegengesetzt sein. Was man in dem einen Horizont verständlich findet, kann in einem anderen unverständlich sein. Was für den einen wahr ist, ist für den anderen falsch. Was für den einen gut ist, ist für den anderen böse. Jeder kann sich in etwa des anderen bewußt sein, und daher kann jeder in gewisser Weise den anderen einschließen. Aber ein solches Einschließen bedeutet auch Negation und Ablehnung. Denn der Horizont des anderen wird zumindest teilweise einem Wunschdenken zugeschrieben oder der Annahme eines Mythos, der Unwissenheit oder dem Irrtum, einer Blindheit oder Illusion, der Rückständigkeit oder der Unreife, dem Unglauben, dem bösen Willen oder der Zurückweisung göttlicher Gnade. Die Ablehnung des anderen kann so leidenschaftlich sein, daß der Vorschlag, Offenheit sei wünschenswert, geradezu wütend macht. Die Ablehnung kann aber auch etwas von der Härte des Eises haben, ohne die geringste Spur von Leidenschaft oder anderweitig bekundetem Gefühl - vielleicht mit Ausnahme eines gezwungenen Lächelns. Astrologie und Völkermord liegen beide jenseits der Grenze - Astrologie aber wird lächerlich gemacht, Völkermord dagegen verabscheut. (240f; Fs)

8/X Und schließlich sind Horizonte das strukturierte Ergebnis früherer Leistung, wie auch die Bedingung und die Begrenzung weiterer Entwicklung. Sie sind strukturiert. Alles Lernen ist nicht bloß reine Addition zu früher Gelerntem, sondern organisches Wachsen aus vorher Gelerntem. So stehen all unsere Intentionen, Aussagen und Handlungen in Kontexten. Auf solche Kontexte berufen wir uns, wenn wir die Gründe für unsere Ziele angeben, wenn wir unsere Aussagen klären, erweitern und näher bestimmen, oder wenn wir unser Handeln erklären. In solche Kontexte muß jeder neue Gegenstand des Wissens und jeder neue Faktor in unseren Einstellungen eingepaßt werden. Was nicht hineinpaßt, wird nicht bemerkt oder - wenn unserer Aufmerksamkeit aufgezwungen - als nebensächlich oder unwichtig erscheinen. Horizonte sind also der Spielraum unserer Interessen und unseres Wissens; sie sind einerseits die ergiebige Quelle weiteren Wissens und Sorgens, andererseits aber auch die Grenze, die unsere Fähigkeit beschränkt, jetzt noch mehr aufzunehmen, als wir schon erreichten. (241; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Bekehrung und Zusammenbruch; Freiheit (horizontal - vertikal); neuer Horizont: Kontinuität, Umschwung; Bekehrung

Kurzinhalt: Der vertikale Freiheitsvollzug ist jener Komplex von Urteilen und Entscheidungen, durch den wir von einem Horizont zu einem anderen übergehen. Nun kann es eine Abfolge solch vertikaler Freiheitsvollzüge geben ...

Textausschnitt: 2. Bekehrung und Zusammenbruch

9/X Joseph de Finance zog eine Trennlinie zwischen dem horizontalen und dem vertikalen Freiheitsvollzug. Der horizontale Freiheitsvollzug ist eine Entscheidung oder Wahl, die innerhalb eines festgelegten Horizonts erfolgt. Der vertikale Freiheitsvollzug ist jener Komplex von Urteilen und Entscheidungen, durch den wir von einem Horizont zu einem anderen übergehen. Nun kann es eine Abfolge solch vertikaler Freiheitsvollzüge geben, bei der in jedem Einzelfall der neue Horizont, obwohl merklich tiefer, breiter und reichhaltiger, dennoch mit dem alten Horizont im Einklang steht und sich aus dessen Möglichkeiten entwickelt hat. Es ist aber auch möglich, daß der Übergang zu einem neuen Horizont einen völligen Umschwung einschließt; er geht aus dem alten Horizont hervor, indem er dessen charakteristische Merkmale verwirft; damit beginnt eine neue Sequenz, die immer größere Weiten, Tiefen und Reichtümer enthüllen kann. Solch ein völliger Umschwung und Neubeginn ist das, was man als Bekehrung bezeichnet. (241f; Fs) (notabene)

10/X Die Bekehrung kann intellektuell, moralisch und religiös sein. Obwohl jede der drei Bekehrungen mit den beiden anderen in Verbindung steht, ist dennoch jede einzelne ein jeweils anderes Ereignis und muß als solches in sich betrachtet werden

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: intellektuelle Bekehrung; Mythos (Wirklichkeit, Objektivität, Erkenntnis): Erkennen = Sehen; Unterschied: Welt der Unmittelbarkeit - W. d. Sinngehaltes; Folgen d. Mythe: Empirist, Idealist - kritischer Realist

Kurzinhalt: Intellektuelle Bekehrung ist eine radikale Klärung und infolgedessen die Beseitigung einer äußerst hartnäckigen und irrerührenden Mythe hinsichtlich der Wirklichkeit, der Objektivität und der menschlichen Erkenntnis.

Textausschnitt: Intellektuelle Bekehrung (eü)

11/X Intellektuelle Bekehrung ist eine radikale Klärung und infolgedessen die Beseitigung einer äußerst hartnäckigen und irrerührenden Mythe hinsichtlich der Wirklichkeit, der Objektivität und der menschlichen Erkenntnis. Die Mythe besagt, daß Erkennen dem Sehen gleicht, daß Objektivität ein Sehen dessen ist, was da ist, um gesehen zu werden, und nicht Sehen, was nicht da ist, und daß das Wirkliche das ist, was jetzt da draußen ist, um angeschaut zu werden. Diese Mythe übersieht nun den Unterschied zwischen der Welt der Unmittelbarkeit, z. B. der Welt des Kindes, und der durch Sinngehalt vermittelten Welt. Die Welt der Unmittelbarkeit ist die Summe dessen, was gesehen, gehört, getastet, geschmeckt, gerochen und gefühlt wird. Sie paßt recht gut zu jener Mythe über die Realität, die Objektivität und die Erkenntnis. Aber sie ist nur ein winziger Bruchteil jener Welt, die durch Sinngehalt vermittelt ist. Denn die durch Sinngehalt vermittelte Welt wird nicht etwa durch die Sinneserfahrung des Individuums erkannt, sondern durch die äußere und innere Erfahrung einer Kulturgemeinschaft und durch die ständig geprüften und nochmals überprüften Urteile derselben Gemeinschaft. Erkennen ist demzufolge eben nicht nur Sehen; es ist Erfahren, Verstehen, Urteilen und Glauben. Die Kriterien der Objektivität sind nicht bloß die Kriterien okularer Sicht; sie sind die miteinander verbundenen Kriterien des Erfahrens, des Verstehens, des Urteilens und des Glaubens. Die erkannte Realität wird nicht bloß angeschaut; sie wird gegeben in der Erfahrung, wird durch Verstehen geordnet und extrapoliert und wird durch Urteil und Glaube (belief) gesetzt. (242; Fs) (notabene)

12/X Die Folgen der genannten Mythe sind sehr verschieden. Der naive Realist erkennt die durch Sinngehalt vermittelte Welt, meint aber, er erkenne sie durch Anschauen. Der Empirist beschränkt objektive Erkenntnis auf Sinneserfahrung; für ihn sind Verstehen und Konzipieren, Urteilen und Glauben bloß subjektive Vollzüge. Der Idealist behauptet, daß menschliche Erkenntnis stets sowohl das Verstehen als auch die Sinneswahrnehmung einschließt; aber er bleibt bei der Wirklichkeitsauffassung des Empiristen, und so hält er die durch Sinngehalt vermittelte Welt nicht für real, sondern für ideal. Nur der kritische Realist vermag die Fakten der menschlichen Erkenntnis anzuerkennen und die durch Sinngehalt vermittelte Welt als die reale Welt anzusprechen; und er vermag dies nur insofern er zeigt, daß der Vorgang des Erfahrens, Verstehens und Urteilens ein Vorgang der Selbst-Transzendenz ist. (242f; Fs) (notabene)

Kommentar (18.11.12), zu oben: "Der naive Realist erkennt die durch Sinngehalt vermittelte Welt, meint aber, er erkenne sie durch Anschauen." Eine äußerst wertvolle Einsicht, um zu verstehen, weshalb so viele Menschen anfällig für subtile Propaganda sind. Beispiel: Die hartnäckige manipulative Berichterstattung über Kirche – bald wird diese Vermittlung als "wahre" Wirklichkeit der Kirche "gesehen".

13/X Wir erörtern nun nicht bloß ein Spezialproblem der Philosophie. Empirismus, Idealismus und Realismus bezeichnen drei völlig verschiedene Horizonte, die keine gemeinsamen identischen Gegenstände haben. Ein Idealist meint niemals das, was ein Empirist meint, und ein Realist meint niemals das, was die beiden anderen meinen. Ein Empirist kann schlußfolgern, daß es in der Quantentheorie nicht um die physikalische Wirklichkeit gehen könne, und zwar deshalb nicht, weil sie nur Beziehungen zwischen Phänomenen behandelt. Ein Idealist würde dem zustimmen und hinzufügen, daß dasselbe natürlich für die ganze Naturwissenschaft, ja in der Tat für die Gesamtheit des menschlichen Wissens überhaupt gelte. (243; Fs) (notabene)

14/X Der kritische Realist wird beiden widersprechen: Eine verifizierte Hypothese ist wahrscheinlich wahr; und was wahrscheinlich wahr ist, bezieht sich auf das, was in Wirklichkeit wahrscheinlich so ist. Um das Beispiel zu wechseln: Was sind historische Fakten? Für den Empiristen sind sie das, was da draußen war und was angeschaut werden konnte. Für den Idealisten sind sie geistige Konstruktionen, die sorgfältig auf den in Dokumenten überlieferten Daten fundiert und aufgebaut sind. Für den kritischen Realisten sind sie Ereignisse in der durch wahre Bedeutungsakte vermittelten Welt. Um ein drittes Beispiel anzuführen: Was ist ein Mythos? Es gibt psychologische, anthropologische, geschichtliche und philosophische Antworten auf diese Frage. Es gibt hierauf aber auch reduktionistische Antworten: Mythos ist eine Erzählung über Wirklichkeiten, die innerhalb des Horizonts von Empiristen, Idealisten, Historizisten und Existentialisten nicht zu finden sind. (243; Fs) (notabene)

15/X Genug der Beispiele. Sie lassen sich unbegrenzt vermehren; denn philosophische Probleme sind in ihrer Tragweite universal, und die eine oder andere Form des naiven Realismus erscheint sehr vielen Menschen als völlig unbestreitbar. Sobald sie anfangen, über Erkenntnis, Objektivität und Realität zu sprechen, taucht die Annahme auf, alles Erkennen müsse so etwas wie Sehen sein. Sich von diesem groben Irrtum frei zu machen und die Selbst-Transzendenz zu entdecken, die dem menschlichen Prozeß eigen ist, durch den man zur Erkenntnis gelangt, heißt oft mit tief verwurzelten Denk- und Sprachgewohnheiten zu brechen. Es bedeutet, die Herrschaft im eigenen Hause anzutreten, die nur zu haben ist, wenn man genau weiß, was man tut, wenn man erkennt. Es ist eine Bekehrung, ein neuer Anfang, ein anderer Beginn. Es gibt den Weg frei für immer weitere Klärung und Entwicklung. (243; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: moralische Bekehrung; moralisches Wissen: Besitz des sittlich guten Menschen

Kurzinhalt: Moralische Bekehrung verändert das eigene Entscheidungs- und Wahlkriterium, indem sie es von Befriedigungen auf Werte verlagert... So gelangen wir zu dem existentiellen Augenblick, wenn wir selber entdecken, daß unser Wählen uns selbst nicht weniger ...

Textausschnitt: Moralische Bekehrung (eü)

16/X Moralische Bekehrung verändert das eigene Entscheidungs- und Wahlkriterium, indem sie es von Befriedigungen auf Werte verlagert. Als Kinder oder Minderjährige werden wir überredet, umschmeichelt, angewiesen oder gezwungen das zu tun, was recht ist. Wenn unsere Kenntnis der menschlichen Wirklichkeit zunimmt und unsere Antworten auf menschliche Werte stärker und differenzierter werden, überlassen uns unsere Mentoren immer mehr uns selbst, damit unsere Freiheit ihren zunehmenden Drang nach Authentizität auch ausüben kann. So gelangen wir zu dem existentiellen Augenblick, wenn wir selber entdecken, daß unser Wählen uns selbst nicht weniger betrifft, als die gewählten oder abgelehnten Gegenstände, und daß es jedem von uns obliegt, selbst zu entscheiden, was er aus sich machen soll. Dann ist die Zeit gekommen, die vertikale Freiheit auszuüben, dann ist moralische Bekehrung die Entscheidung für das wahrhart Gute, für den Wert und gegen die Befriedigung, wenn Wert und Befriedigung einander widersprechen. (243f; Fs) (notabene)

17/X Eine solche Bekehrung ist natürlich längst noch keine moralische Vollendung, denn Entscheiden und Tun sind zweierlei. Man muß erst noch das eigene individuelle, das gemeinschaftliche und das allgemeine Vorurteil aufdecken und ausrotten.1 Man muß seine eigene Kenntnis der menschlichen Wirklichkeit und Möglichkeit, so wie sie in der bestehenden Situation gegeben sind, immer noch vervollkommnen. Man muß in dieser Situation die Elemente des Fortschritts und die Elemente des Verfalls sauber auseinanderhalten. Man muß seine eigenen intentionalen Antworten auf Werte und deren Prioritätenskala ständig überprüfen. Man muß auf Kritik und Protest hören. Man muß sich die Bereitschaft erhalten, von anderen zu lernen. Denn das moralische Wissen ist eigentlicher Besitz nur der sittlich guten Menschen, und bis man diesen Ehrentitel verdient, muß man ständig weiterstreben und immer noch lernen. (244; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Akt - dynamischer Zustand; religiöse Bekehrung; gratia operans, cooperans; Unterströmung des existentiellen Bewußtseins; Einfachheit und Passivität des Gebetslebens

Kurzinhalt: Religiöse Bekehrung ist Betroffenwerden von dem, was uns unbedingt angeht. Sie ist Sich-überweltlich-verlieben... eine solche Hingabe nicht als ein Akt, sondern als ein dynamischer Zustand, der den folgenden Akten vorgängig und deren Urgrund ist.

Textausschnitt: Religiöse Bekehrung (eü)

18/X Religiöse Bekehrung ist Betroffenwerden von dem, was uns unbedingt angeht. Sie ist Sich-überweltlich-verlieben. Sie ist völlige und dauernde Selbst-Hingabe ohne Bedingungen, Einschränkungen und Vorbehalte. Aber sie ist eine solche Hingabe nicht als ein Akt, sondern als ein dynamischer Zustand, der den folgenden Akten vorgängig und deren Urgrund ist. In der Rückschau enthüllt sich die religiöse Bekehrung als eine Unterströmung des existentiellen Bewußtseins, als die schicksalhafte Annahme einer Berufung zur Heiligkeit, vielleicht auch als eine zunehmende Einfachheit und Passivität des Gebetslebens. (244; Fs; tblStw: Bekehrung; tblStw: Gnade ) (notabene)

19/X Religiöse Bekehrung wird im Kontext unterschiedlicher religiöser Überlieferungen verschieden gedeutet. Für Christen ist sie die Liebe Gottes, die in unsere Herzen ausgegossen ist durch den Heiligen Geist, der uns gegeben ist. Sie ist Geschenk der Gnade, und seit den Tagen des hl. Augustinus wird zwischen wirkender (gratia operans) und mitwirkender Gnade (gratis cooperans) unterschieden. Die wirkende Gnade ersetzt das Herz von Stein durch ein Herz aus Fleisch, eine Ersetzung, die über dem Horizont eines Herzens von Stein liegt. Die mitwirkende Gnade ist das Herz aus Fleisch, das in guten Werken durch menschliche Freiheit wirksam wird. Wirkende Gnade ist religiöse Bekehrung. Mitwirkende Gnade ist die Wirksamkeit der Bekehrung, die schrittweise Hinbewegung auf eine völlige und vollständige Umwandlung des gesamten eigenen Lebens und Fühlens, aller Gedanken, Worte, Taten und Unterlassungen.1 (244f; Fs) (notabene)

20/X Wie intellektuelle und moralische Bekehrung ist auch die religiöse Bekehrung eine Modalität der Selbst-Transzendenz. Intellektuelle Bekehrung wendet sich zur Wahrheit, die durch kognitive Selbst-Transzendenz erreicht wird. Moralische Bekehrung wendet sich den Werten zu, die durch eine reale Selbst-Transzendenz erfaßt, behauptet und verwirklicht werden. Religiöse Bekehrung erfolgt zu einem völligen In-Liebe-Sein als dem wirkenden Grund aller Selbst-Transzendenz, ob im Streben nach Wahrheit, ob in der Verwirklichung menschlicher Werte oder in der Ausrichtung auf das Universum und auf dessen Urgrund und Ziel, die ein Mensch annimmt. (245; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Bekehrung: Beziehung (intellektuelle, moralische, religiöse): Aufhebung (sublation); Heiligkeit - Sünde; Flucht, Oberflächlichkeit: Ruhelosigkeit, Streben nach Vergnügen, Widerwille, Depression

Kurzinhalt: Obwohl religiöse Bekehrung die moralische aufhebt, und moralische Bekehrung die intellektuelle, darf man nicht unterstellen, daß die intellektuelle Bekehrung zuerst erfolgt, danach die moralische und schließlich die religiöse.

Textausschnitt: Beziehung der Bekehrungen zueinander (eü)

21/X Weil intellektuelle, moralische und religiöse Bekehrungen alle mit Selbst-Transzendenz zu tun haben, ist es möglich, wenn sich alle drei innerhalb ein und desselben Bewußtseins ereignen, ihre Relationen als Aufhebung zu verstehen. Ich möchte diesen Begriff eher im Sinne von Karl Rahner1 als von Hegel gebrauchen, um damit auszudrücken, daß das Aufhebende über das Aufgehobene hinausgeht, etwas Neues und Bestimmtes einführt, alles auf eine neue Grundlage stellt, und dennoch das Aufgehobene keineswegs beeinträchtigt oder gar zerstört, ja im Gegenteil seiner bedarf, es einschließt, all seine ihm eigenen Merkmale und Eigenheiten bewahrt und sie voranbringt zu einer volleren Verwirklichung innerhalb eines reicheren Kontextes. (245; Fs) (notabene)

22/X So geht moralische Bekehrung über den Wert Wahrheit hinaus zu den Werten im allgemeinen. Sie bringt den Menschen von der kognitiven zur moralischen Selbst-Transzendenz voran. Sie versetzt ihn auf eine neue existentielle Bewußtseinsebene und macht ihn zu einem Ursprungswert. Doch beeinträchtigt oder schwächt dies keineswegs seine Liebe zur Wahrheit. Er braucht die Wahrheit immer noch; denn er muß die Wirklichkeit und die reale Möglichkeit erfassen, ehe er auf einen Wert überlegt antworten kann. Die Wahrheit, die er braucht, ist immer noch die Wahrheit, die in Übereinstimmung mit den Erfordernissen des rationalen Bewußtseins erlangt wird. Jetzt aber strebt er sie um so sicherer an, als er nun gegen Vorurteile gut gerüstet ist; diese Suche nach der Wahrheit ist nun noch bedeutungsvoller und wichtiger, weil sie sich im allumfassenden Kontext des Strebens nach allen Werten ereignet und eine tragende Rolle spielt. (245f; Fs) (notabene)

23/X Ähnlich geht religiöse Bekehrung über moralische Bekehrung hinaus. Fragen nach Einsicht, nach Reflexion und nach Entscheidung offenbaren den Eros des menschlichen Geistes, seine Fähigkeit und sein Verlangen nach Selbst-Transzendenz. Doch diese Fähigkeit wird zur Erfüllung gebracht, und dieses Verlangen wandelt sich in Freude, wenn religiöse Bekehrung das existentielle Subjekt in ein liebendes Subjekt verwandelt, in ein Subjekt, das von einer totalen und damit überweltlichen Liebe gehalten, ergriffen und in Besitz genommen ist. Dann gibt es eine neue Grundlage für alles Werten und für alles Gute-Tun. In keiner Weise werden die Früchte intellektueller oder moralischer Bekehrung negiert oder gemindert. Im Gegenteil wird nun alles menschliche Streben nach dem Wahren und Guten in einen kosmischen Zusammenhang gebracht und durch ein kosmisches Ziel noch gefördert, wobei dem Menschen auch die Kraft der Liebe zuwächst, die ihn befähigt, das Leiden anzunehmen, das mit dem Rückgängigmachen der Verfallserscheinungen verbunden ist. (246; Fs) (notabene)

24/X Man sollte jedoch deswegen nicht denken, religiöse Bekehrung sei lediglich eine neue und wirkungsvollere Grundlage für das Streben nach intellektuellen und moralischen Zielen. Religiöse Liebe ist ohne Bedingungen, Einschränkungen und Vorbehalte; sie kommt aus ganzem Herzen, aus ganzer Seele und aus allen Kräften des Geistes. Dieses Fehlen jeder Begrenzung, das zwar dem uneingeschränkten Charakter menschlichen Fragens entspricht, gehört aber nicht dieser Welt an. Heiligkeit hat Wahrheit und sittliche Güte im Überfluß, hat aber auch ihre eigene, ganz bestimmte Dimension. Sie ist überweltliche Erfüllung, Freude, Friede und Glückseligkeit. Nach christlicher Erfahrung sind dieses die Früchte des In-Liebe-Seins mit dem geheimnisvollen und unbegreiflichen Gott. Auf ähnliche Weise unterscheidet sich auch die Sündhaftigkeit vom moralischen Übel; sie ist ein Mangel an völliger Liebe, ja sie ist die radikale Dimension der Lieblosigkeit. Diese Dimension läßt sich überdecken durch ständige Oberflächlichkeit, indem man letzten Fragen ausweicht und in allem aufgeht, was die Welt zu bieten hat, was unsere Wendigkeit reizt, unsern Körper entspannt und unseren Geist zerstreut. Doch diese Flucht ist nicht von Dauer, und dann zeigt sich der Mangel an Erfüllung in Ruhelosigkeit, das Fehlen der Freude im Streben nach Vergnügungen, das Fehlen des inneren Friedens in Ekel und Widerwillen - in einem depressiven Widerwillen gegen sich selbst oder in einem wahnhaften, feindseligen, ja sogar gewalttätigen Widerwillen gegen die Mitmenschen. (246f; Fs) (notabene)

25/X Obwohl religiöse Bekehrung die moralische aufhebt, und moralische Bekehrung die intellektuelle, darf man nicht unterstellen, daß die intellektuelle Bekehrung zuerst erfolgt, danach die moralische und schließlich die religiöse. Vom kausalen Standpunkt aus betrachtet, könnte man gerade umgekehrt sagen, daß an erster Stelle das Gottesgeschenk seiner Liebe steht. Sodann sehen wir mit den Augen dieser Liebe die Werte in ihrem Glanz, die wir in der Kraft dieser Liebe auch verwirklichen können - gerade das ist moralische Bekehrung. Und schließlich findet sich unter den Werten, die mit den Augen der Liebe gesehen werden, auch der Wert, die Wahrheiten zu glauben, die die religiöse Überlieferung lehrt, und in solcher Überlieferung und solchem Glauben liegen die Keime intellektueller Bekehrung. Denn das gesprochene und gehörte Wort geht von allen vier Ebenen des intentionalen Bewußtseins aus und dringt zu ihnen allen vor. Sein Inhalt ist nicht bloß ein Erfahrungsinhalt, sondern ein Inhalt der Erfahrung, des Verstehens, des Urteilens und Entscheidens. Die Analogie des Sehens führt zur Erkenntnis-Mythe; aber die Treue zum Wort nimmt den ganzen Menschen in Anspruch. (247; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik; Bekehrung - Zusammebruch (breakdown); Zerstörung kultureller Leistung; Auflösungsprozeß -> Erhaltung seiner Folgerichtigkeit: Spaltung, Unverständnis, Verdächtigung, Mißtrauen, Feindseligkeit, Haß, Gewalt

Kurzinhalt: Überdies bedeutet die Eliminierung eines echten Teils der Kultur die Verstümmelung eines früheren Ganzen, wodurch das Gleichgewicht gestört und der Rest entstellt wird im Bemühen um Kompensation.

Textausschnitt: Zusammenbrüche (eü)

26/X Neben der Bekehrung gibt es aber auch Zusammenbrüche. Was vom einzelnen, von der Gemeinschaft, von der Kultur langsam und mühselig aufgebaut wurde, kann zusammenbrechen. Kognitive Selbst-Transzendenz ist weder eine Idee, die leicht zu fassen ist, noch ein Datum unseres Bewußtseins, das leicht zugänglich und verifizierbar ist. Werte üben zwar eine gewisse esoterische Herrschaft aus, aber wiegen sie auf Dauer schwerer als Sinnenlust, Reichtum und Macht? Zweifellos hatte die Religion ihre Zeit, aber ist diese Zeit inzwischen nicht vorbei? Ist sie nicht lediglich ein illusorischer Trost für schwächere Seelen, ein Opium, das die Reichen verteilen, um die Armen zu beruhigen, oder die mythische Projektion der eigenen Größe des Menschen auf den Himmel? (247; Fs) (notabene)

27/X Anfangs werden nicht alle Religionen, sondern nur manche als illusorisch erklärt, werden nicht alle, sondern nur einige moralische Vorschriften als ineffektiv und nutzlos verworfen, wird nicht alle Wahrheit, sondern nur manche Form von Metaphysik als bloßes Gerede abgetan. Diese Negationen können wahr sein, dann sind sie ein Versuch, den Niedergang aufzuhalten und auszugleichen. Sie können aber auch falsch sein, und dann sind gerade sie der Anfang vom Niedergang. In diesem Fall wird irgendein Teil der kulturellen Leistung zerstört. Er hört auf, vertrauter Bestandteil der eigenen kulturellen Erfahrung zu sein. Er wird in eine vergessene Vergangenheit entschwinden, um vielleicht einmal von Historikern wiederentdeckt und rekonstruiert zu werden. (247f; Fs)

28/X Überdies bedeutet die Eliminierung eines echten Teils der Kultur die Verstümmelung eines früheren Ganzen, wodurch das Gleichgewicht gestört und der Rest entstellt wird im Bemühen um Kompensation. Zudem wird eine solche Eliminierung, Verstümmelung und Entstellung natürlich als Fortschritt bewundert, wobei die offenkundigen Übel, die sie hervorbringen, nicht etwa durch Rückkehr zur irregeleiteten Vergangenheit behoben werden, sondern durch weitere Eliminierung, Verstümmelung und Entstellung. Hat ein Auflösungsprozeß erst einmal begonnen, so wird er durch Selbstbetrug überdeckt und durch seine innere Folgerichtigkeit weiter erhalten. Das bedeutet aber nicht, daß er auf einen einzigen einförmigen Ablauf festgelegt ist. Verschiedene Nationen, verschiedene Gesellschaftsklassen und verschiedene Altersgruppen können unterschiedliche Teile vergangener Errungenschaften zur Beseitigung auswählen, unterschiedliche Verstümmelungen bewirken und unterschiedliche Entstellungen hervorrufen. Der zunehmenden Auflösung entsprechen dann zunehmende Spaltung, Unverständnis, Verdächtigung, Mißtrauen, Feindseligkeit, Haß und Gewalt. Der Sozialkörper wird dadurch auf vielfache Weise auseinandergerissen, wobei seine kulturelle Seele zu vernünftigen Überzeugungen und verantwortungsbewußten Verpflichtungen unfähig wird. (248; Fs) (notabene)

29/X Denn Überzeugungen und Verpflichtungen beruhen auf Tatsachen- und Werturteilen; solche Urteile wiederum beruhen weithin auf Glaubensüberzeugungen. Es gibt in der Tat nur wenige Menschen, die nicht sehr bald zu dem, was sie bisher geglaubt haben, Zuflucht nehmen müssen, wenn man sie in fast allen Punkten unter Druck setzt. Nun kann aber eine solche Zuflucht nur dann wirksam sein, wenn die Glaubenden eine festgefügte Front bilden, und wenn intellektuelle, moralische und religiöse Skeptiker eine kleine und bislang nicht einflußreiche Minderheit sind. Aber deren Zahl kann wachsen, ihr Einfluß steigen und ihre Stimmen können den Buchmarkt, das Erziehungssystem und die Massenmedien beherrschen. Dann beginnt Glauben nicht mehr für, sondern gegen die intellektuelle, moralische und religiöse Selbst-Transzendenz zu arbeiten. Was einst ein ansteigender, aber allgemein geachteter Kurs war, bricht als Seltsamkeit einer überholten Minderheit in sich zusammen. (248; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: 2 Aufgaben; D. in Beziehung zu Geschichte u. Interpretation; Geschichte (Fakten - Werte); intellektuelle, wertende Hermeneutik; Perspektivismus; Begegnung mit d. Geschichte

Kurzinhalt: Interpretation hängt vom eigenen Selbstverständnis ab, und die Geschichte, die man schreibt, vom eigenen Verstehenshorizont; und die Begegnung ist nun der einzige Weg, auf dem man das Selbstverständnis und den Horizont einer Prüfung unterziehen kann.

Textausschnitt: 3. Dialektik: Die Aufgabe

30/X Die Aufgabe, die sich in der Dialektik stellt, ist eine doppelte, weil unsere funktionalen Spezialisierungen Geschichte, Interpretation und spezielle Forschung auf zweifache Weise defizient sind. Friedrich Meinecke sagte einmal, es ginge in jeder historischen Arbeit sowohl um kausale Verbindung, als auch um Werte, daß aber die meisten Historiker dazu neigten, sich hauptsächlich entweder mit kausalen Verknüpfungen oder mit Werten zu befassen. Überdies behauptete er, die Geschichte, die den Werten Aufmerksamkeit schenkt, 'gibt uns [...] Inhalt, Lehre und Wegweisung für unser eigenes Leben'.1 (248f; Fs)

31/X Carl Becker ging sogar noch weiter. Er schrieb: 'Der Wert der Geschichte ist [...] nicht wissenschaftlich, sondern moralisch: indem sie den Geist befreit, die Sympathien vertieft, den Willen bestärkt, versetzt sie uns in die Lage, nicht die Gesellschaft, sondern uns selbst - was auch wichtiger ist - zu kontrollieren; sie befähigt uns, in der Gegenwart menschlicher zu leben und uns der Zukunft zu stellen, statt sie bloß vorauszusagen.2 Doch die funktionale Spezialisierung Geschichte, wie wir sie verstehen, befaßt sich mit Bewegungen, mit dem, was tatsächlich vor sich ging. Sie spezialisiert sich auf das Ziel der dritten Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins, auf das, was geschehen ist. Sie sagt nichts über Geschichte als primär mit Werten befaßte, und das zu recht, insofern als Geschichte, die sich hauptsächlich den Werten zuwendet, zu einer Spezialisierung nicht auf der dritten, sondern auf der vierten Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins gehört. (249; Fs)

32/X In ähnlicher Weise ging es in unserer Darstellung der Interpretation um das Verstehen der Sache, der Worte, des Autors, um das eigene Selbstverständnis, um die Beurteilung der Genauigkeit des eigenen Verstehens und um die Bestimmung, wie man das ausdrücken soll, was man verstanden hat. Doch neben einer derart intellektuellen Hermeneutik gibt es auch noch eine wertende Hermeneutik. Neben den potentiellen, formalen und vollständigen Sinngebungsakten gibt es auch noch konstitutive und effektive Sinngebungsakte. Nun ist aber die Erfassung von Werten und Unwerten nicht eine Aufgabe des Verstehens, sondern der intentionalen Antwort. Eine solche Antwort ist um so vollständiger und um so differenzierender, ein je besserer Mensch man ist, je feiner die Sensibilität und je zarter die eigenen Gefühle sind. Diese wertende Interpretation gehört zu einer Spezialisierung auf das Ziel der vierten Ebene und nicht auf das der zweiten Ebene des intentionalen Bewußtseins. (249; Fs)

33/X Dieserart ist eine erste Aufgabe der Dialektik. Sie hat der verstehenden Interpretation eine weitere, nämlich würdigende Interpretation hinzuzufügen. Sie fügt der Geschichte, die das erfaßt, was vor sich ging, jene Geschichte an, die die Leistungen bewertet, die Gut und Böse unterscheidet. Sie hat die spezielle Forschung zu lenken, die für eine derartige Interpretation und für eine solche Geschichte nötig ist. (249f; Fs) (notabene)

34/X Sodann gibt es eine zweite Aufgabe. Unsere Darstellung kritischer Geschichtswissenschaft versprach gleiche Ergebnisse nur für den Fall, daß Historiker vom gleichen Standpunkt ausgehen. Aber es gibt viele Standpunkte, und diese sind von unterschiedlicher Art. Da ist zunächst jene Färbung, die sich aus der Individualität des Historikers ergibt und zum Perspektivismus führt. Da ist die Unzulänglichkeit, die sich zeigt, wenn weitere Daten entdeckt werden und man zu besserem Verstehen kommt. Und schließlich gibt es noch die massiven Differenzen, die sich dann ergeben, wenn Historiker mit entgegengesetzten Verstehenshorizonten versuchen, die gleiche Ereignisfolge sich verständlich zu machen. (250; Fs)

35/X Mit derart massiven Differenzen hat es die Dialektik zu tun. Sie sind nicht bloß perspektivisch, denn der Perspektivismus ergibt sich aus der Individualität des Historikers; vielmehr ereignen sich diese massiven Differenzen zwischen gegensätzlichen, ja einander befehdenden Gruppen von Historikern. Sie lassen sich nicht, wie normalerweise, durch Entdekkung weiterer Daten beseitigen, denn weitere Daten werden aller Wahrscheinlichkeit nach ebenso entgegengesetzte Deutungen zulassen, wie die bisher verfügbaren. Die Ursache massiver Differenzen ist ein massiver Unterschied des Horizonts, und die angemessene Abhilfe ist hier nichts Geringeres als eine Bekehrung. (250; Fs) (notabene)

36/X Wie die Geschichtswissenschaft, so verspricht auch die Interpretation keine eindeutigen Ergebnisse. Der Interpret kann die Sache, die Worte, den Autor und sich selbst verstehen. Wenn er aber eine Bekehrung durchmacht, wird er ein anderes Ich verstehen müssen, und das neue Selbstverständnis kann auch sein Verständnis der Dinge, der Worte und des Autors modifizieren. (250; Fs) (notabene)

37/X Spezielle Forschung wird schließlich mit einem Blick auf besondere exegetische oder historische Aufgaben betrieben. Die Horizonte, die die Ausführung dieser Aufgaben leiten, lenken auch die Durchführung der Forschung. Man findet leicht, was in den eigenen Horizont hineinpaßt. Sehr gering aber ist die Fähigkeit, das zu bemerken, was man nie verstanden oder konzipiert hat. Die einleitende spezielle Forschung kann Unterschiede des Horizonts ebenso aufdecken wie die Interpretation und die Geschichtswissenschaft. (250; Fs)

38/X Kurz gesagt, die erste Phase der Theologie bleibt unvollständig, wenn man sie auf Forschung, Interpretation und Geschichte beschränkt. Denn so wie wir diese funktionalen Spezialisierungen konzipiert haben, nähern sie sich zwar einer Begegnung mit der Vergangenheit, erreichen sie aber nicht. Sie stellen die Daten zur Verfügung, sie klären, was gemeint war, und sie berichten, was geschah. Begegnung ist jedoch mehr. Sie trifft Menschen, würdigt die Werte, die sie vertreten, kritisiert ihre Mängel und läßt zu, daß unser Leben durch ihre Worte und Taten bis an die Wurzel in Frage gestellt wird. Zudem ist solch eine Begegnung nicht bloß ein freigestellter Zusatz zur Interpretation und Geschichtswissenschaft. Interpretation hängt vom eigenen Selbstverständnis ab, und die Geschichte, die man schreibt, vom eigenen Verstehenshorizont; und die Begegnung ist nun der einzige Weg, auf dem man das Selbstverständnis und den Horizont einer Prüfung unterziehen kann. (250f; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Problem; Vorhandensein oder Fehlen v. Bekehrung (8 Möglichkeiten) -> entgegengesetzte Horizonte; Reduktionismus (Mensch, Ratte); Gibson Winter

Kurzinhalt: ... führen dialektische Differenzen zu gegenseitiger Ablehnung. Jede von ihnen hält die Zurückweisung ihrer Gegner für den einzigen und allein intelligenten, rationalen und zu verantwortenden Standpunkt, und sobald sie genügend ausgearbeitet ist...

Textausschnitt: 4. Dialektik: Das Problem

39/X Vorhandensein oder Fehlen intellektueller, moralischer und religiöser Bekehrung führt zur Entstehung dialektisch entgegengesetzter Horizonte. Während komplementäre oder genetische Differenzen zu überbrücken sind, führen dialektische Differenzen zu gegenseitiger Ablehnung. Jede von ihnen hält die Zurückweisung ihrer Gegner für den einzigen und allein intelligenten, rationalen und zu verantwortenden Standpunkt, und sobald sie genügend ausgearbeitet ist, sucht sie nach einer Philosophie oder Methode, die das untermauern soll, was man unter angemessenen Anschauungen über das Intelligente, das Rationale und das Verantwortliche versteht. (251; Fs) (notabene)

40/X Daraus entsteht eine Verwirrung. Es können entweder alle drei Arten der Bekehrung fehlen, irgendeine kann vorhanden sein, oder zwei von ihnen oder alle drei. Selbst wenn man von den Unterschieden in der Vollkommenheit der Bekehrung absieht, gibt es also acht grundverschiedene Arten. Zudem wird jede Untersuchung innerhalb eines bestimmten Horizonts durchgerührt. Dies gilt auch dann, wenn man gar nicht weiß, daß man innerhalb eines Horizonts tätig ist, oder wenn man annimmt, gar keine Annahmen zu machen. Ob man sie audrücklich anerkennt oder nicht - dialektisch entgegengesetzte Horizonte führen zu entgegengesetzten Werturteilen, zu entgegengesetzten Darstellungen geschichtlicher Bewegungen, zu entgegengesetzten Deutungen der Autoren und zu unterschiedlicher Auswahl relevanter Daten in spezieller Forschung. (251; Fs) (notabene)

41/X Die Naturwissenschaft entgeht diesen Fallstricken zumeist. Sie beschränkt sich auf Fragen, die man unter Berufung auf Beobachtung und Experiment entscheiden kann. Sie bezieht ihre theoretischen Modelle von der Mathematik. Sie ist auf ein empirisches Wissen aus, bei dem Werturteile keine konstitutive Rolle spielen. Dennoch bieten diese Vorteile keine vollständige Immunität. Die Darstellung einer naturwissenschaftlichen Methode verhält sich zur Erkenntnistheorie wie das weniger Allgemeine zum Allgemeineren, so daß keine feste Schranke die Naturwissenschaft von der naturwissenschaftlichen Methode und von allgemeiner Erkenntnistheorie trennt. (251f; Fs)

42/X So war der mechanistische Determinismus früher einmal fester Bestandteil der Naturwissenschaft; jetzt ist er eine aufgegebene philosophische Meinung. Doch an seine Stelle trat Niels Bohrs Lehre von der Komplementarität, die philosophische Ansichten über die menschliche Erkenntnis und über die Wirklichkeit einschließt, und jedes Abrücken von Bohrs Position führt zu noch mehr Philosophie.1 Und obwohl Physik, Chemie und Biologie keine Werturteile abgeben, hat doch der Übergang von liberalen zu totalitären Systemen die Naturwissenschaftler über den Wert der Wissenschaft und über ihre Rechte als Wissenschartler nachdenken lassen, während die militärische und anderweitige Verwendung ihrer wissenschaftlichen Entdeckungen sie auf ihre Pflichten hinwies. (252; Fs)

43/X In den Humanwissenschaften sind die Probleme noch viel zugespitzter. Reduktionisten haben die Methoden der Naturwissenschaft auf die Erforschung des Menschen ausgedehnt. Ihre Ergebnisse sind dementsprechend nur insoweit gültig, als der Mensch einem Roboter oder einer Ratte ähnelt, und während solche Ähnlichkeit besteht, ergibt ihre ausschließliche Beachtung eine grob verstümmelte und entstellte Sicht.2 (252; Fs)

44/X Die allgemeine Systemtheorie lehnt Reduktionismus in all seinen Spielarten ab, ist sich aber dennoch ihrer ungelösten Probleme bewußt; denn die Systemtechnik schließt eine fortschreitende Mechanisierung ein, die darauf hinausläuft, die Rolle des Menschen im System auf die eines Roboters zu reduzieren, wobei Systeme im allgemeinen sowohl für konstruktive als auch destruktive Ziele verwendet werden können.3 (252; Fs)

45/X Gibson Winter hat in seinem Buch 'Elements for a Social Ethic'4 jene divergierenden Typen von Soziologie einander gegenübergestellt, die mit den Namen Talcott Parsons und C. Wright Mills verbunden sind. Nach der Feststellung, daß der unterschiedliche Ansatz zu verschiedenen Urteilen über die bestehende Gesellschaft führt, fragt er, ob der Gegensatz wissenschaftlich begründet oder ideologisch sei - eine Frage, die natürlich die Erörterung von der Geschichte des soziologischen Denkens der Gegenwart auf die Philosophie und Ethik verlagert. Gibson Winter gibt eine allgemeine Darstellung der sozialen Wirklichkeit, unterscheidet physikalistische, funktionalistische, voluntaristische und intentionalistische Typen von Soziologie und weist jedem Typus seine besondere Sphäre der Relevanz und Effektivität zu. Wo Max Weber zwischen Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik unterschied, unterscheidet Winter zwischen philosophisch begründeten und gegliederten Typen von Sozialwissenschaft, und andererseits der Sozialpolitik, die sich nicht nur auf die Sozialwissenschaft, sondern auch auf die Werturteile einer Ethik gründet. (252f; Fs)

46/X Demnach drängen sich in den Natur- und in den Humanwissenschaften Fragen auf, die durch empirische Methoden nicht zu lösen sind. Diese Probleme lassen sich in den Naturwissenschaften mit größerem und in den Humanwissenschaften nur mit geringerem Erfolg eingrenzen oder umgehen. Eine Theologie aber kann methodisch nur dann betrieben werden, wenn sie diese Fragen frontal angeht. Sie frontal anzugehen ist die Aufgabe unserer vierten funktionalen Spezialisierung, der Dialektik. (253; Fs) (notabene)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Struktur; 2 Ebenen (Operatoren - Material); Position - Gegenposition; Objektivierung des Horizonts; Material: Zusammenstellung, Vervollständigung, Vergleich, Reduktion, Klassifikation, Selektion

Kurzinhalt: Auf der höheren Ebene sind die Operatoren (operators)... Entwickle Positionen! Kehre Gegenpositionen um! Positionen sind Aussagen, die mit der intellektuellen, moralischen und religiösen Bekehrung vereinbar sind...

Textausschnitt: 5. Dialektik: Die Struktur

47/X Die Struktur der Dialektik weist zwei Ebenen auf. Auf der höheren Ebene sind die Operatoren (operators). Auf der unteren Ebene werden die Materialien gesammelt, mit denen operiert werden soll. Die Operatoren sind zwei Vorschriften: Entwickle Positionen! Kehre Gegenpositionen um! Positionen sind Aussagen, die mit der intellektuellen, moralischen und religiösen Bekehrung vereinbar sind; sie werden entwickelt, indem sie mit neuen Daten und weiteren Entdeckungen zu einem Ganzen zusammengefaßt werden. Gegenpositionen sind Aussagen, die mit der intellektuellen oder moralischen oder religiösen Bekehrung unvereinbar sind; sie werden umgekehrt, wenn die unvereinbaren Elemente beseitigt sind. (253; Fs) (notabene)

48/X Bevor man mit den Materialien operiert, müssen sie erst zusammengestellt, vervollständigt, verglichen, reduziert, klassifiziert und selektiert werden. Die Zusammenstellung umfaßt die ausgeführten Forschungen, die vorgeschlagenen Deutungen, die Darstellungen der Geschichtsschreibung und die Ereignisse, Aussagen und Bewegungen, auf die sie sich beziehen. Die Vervollständigung fügt wertende Deutung und wertende Geschichte hinzu; sie stellt die 'hunderteins guten Dinge'1, und das ihnen Entgegengesetzte heraus; sie ist Geschichte eher nach Art von Burckhardt als von Ranke.2 Der Vergleich untersucht die vervollständigte Zusammenstellung, um Affinitäten und Gegensätze herauszufinden. Die Reduktion findet die gleiche Affinität und den gleichen Gegensatz in vielfach unterschiedlicher Weise manifestiert; von den zahlreichen Manifestationen dringt sie zu der Wurzel vor, die ihnen zugrunde liegt. Die Klassifizierung bestimmt, welche dieser Quellen der Affinität oder des Gegensatzes aus dialektisch entgegengesetzten Horizonten entspringen und welche andere Ursachen haben. Die Selektion schließlich greift die Affinitäten und Gegensätze heraus, die auf dialektisch entgegengesetzten Horizonten beruhen, und übergeht andere Affinitäten und Gegensätze. (253f; Fs) (notabene)

49/X Nun aber wird diese Arbeit der Zusammenstellung, der Vervollständigung, des Vergleichs, der Reduktion, der Klassifizierung und der Selektion durch verschiedene Forscher ausgeführt, und diese werden von unterschiedlichen Horizonten aus tätig. Dementsprechend werden die Ergebnisse nicht gleichförmig sein. Aber der Ursprung dieses Mangels an Gleichförmigkeit wird dann offenkundig, wenn jeder einzelne Forscher daran geht, zwischen Positionen zu unterscheiden, die mit der intellektuellen, moralischen und religiösen Bekehrung vereinbar sind, und andererseits den Gegenpositionen, die entweder mit intellektueller oder moralischer oder religiöser Bekehrung unvereinbar sind. (254; Fs)

50/X Eine weitere Objektivierung des Horizonts wird erreicht, wenn jeder einzelne Forscher mit den Materialien operiert, indem er die Ansicht aufzeigt, die sich aus der Entfaltung dessen ergeben würde, was er als Positionen betrachtet hat, und aus der Umkehrung dessen, was er als Gegenposition angesehen hat. Und es gibt eine abschließende Objektivierung des Horizonts, wenn die Ergebnisse des soeben beschriebenen Vorgangs selbst als Materialien betrachtet werden, wenn sie dann zusammengestellt, vervollständigt, verglichen, reduziert, klassifiziert und selektiert werden, wenn Positionen und Gegenpositionen unterschieden und wenn Positionen entwickelt und Gegenpositionen umgekehrt werden. (254; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik als Methode; Grundanschauungen, Entwicklung, Verfall, Wendepunkte; intentionales Bewusstsein: Konflikt (Position - Gegenposition)

Kurzinhalt: Unsere vierte funktionale Spezialisierung geht über den Bereich der gewöhnlichen empirischen Wissenschaft hinaus... In dem Maße, wie sich die Untersuchung immer weiter ausdehnt, kommen Ursprünge und Wendepunkte ans Licht, Blüte und Verfall ...

Textausschnitt: 6. Dialektik als Methode

51/X Nachdem wir die Struktur einer Dialektik skizziert haben, ist nun zu fragen, ob sie der Definition von Methode genügt. Sie stellt offensichtlich ein Schema aufeinander bezogener und wiederkehrender Vollzüge dar. (254; Fs)

52/X Aber noch ist zu prüfen, ob die Ergebnisse weiterführend und kumulativ sind. Demzufolge prüfen wir, was geschieht, erstens, wenn die Dialektik von einer Person ausgeführt wird, die die intellektuelle, moralische und religiöse Bekehrung durchgemacht hat, und zweitens, wenn sie von jemandem ausgerührt wird, der noch keine intellektuelle oder moralische oder religiöse Bekehrung durchgemacht hat. (255; Fs)

53/X Im ersten Fall weiß der Forscher aus persönlicher Erfahrung, was intellektuelle, moralische und religiöse Bekehrung ist. Es wird ihm nicht schwerfallen, Positionen von Gegenpositionen zu unterscheiden. Wenn er Positionen entwickelt und Gegenpositionen umkehrt, wird er eine idealisierte Version der Vergangenheit bieten, etwas Besseres, als es die Wirklichkeit war. Zudem werden all diese Forscher zu einer Übereinstimmung tendieren und werden darin auch zum Teil von anderen Forschern unterstützt, die auf einem oder zwei, nicht aber auf allen drei Gebieten eine Bekehrung durchgemacht haben. (255; Fs)

54/X Im zweiten Fall dürfte der Forscher nur über das verfügen, was Newman notionales Erfassen (notional apprehension) der Bekehrung nennen würde, und er mag sich beklagen, daß Dialektik ein recht nebelhaftes Verfahren sei. Doch zumindest würde er radikal entgegengesetzte Aussagen erkennen. Auf dem Gebiet oder den Gebieten, auf denen ihm die Bekehrung fehlt, würde er Gegenpositionen fälschlich für Positionen und Positionen für Gegenpositionen halten. Wenn er daran ginge, das zu entwickeln, was er für Positionen hält, und das umzukehren, was er als Gegenpositionen ansieht, so würde er in Wirklichkeit Gegenpositionen entwickeln und Positionen umkehren. (255; Fs)

55/X Während die Durchführung der Dialektik im ersten Fall zu einer idealisierten Version der Vergangenheit führte, führt ihr Vollzug im zweiten Fall genau zum Gegenteil; sie stellt die Vergangenheit schlimmer dar, als sie wirklich war. Schließlich gibt es sieben verschiedene Wege, auf denen man dahin gelangen kann, denn der zweite Fall beinhaltet

(1.) jene, die überhaupt keine Bekehrungserfahrung haben,
(2.) jene, die eine Erfahrung nur intellektueller oder nur moralischer oder nur religiöser Bekehrung haben, und
(3.) jene, denen nur die intellektuelle oder nur die moralische oder nur die religiöse Bekehrung fehlt. (255; Fs)

56/X Wir möchten diesen Kontrast noch etwas mehr konkretisieren. Unsere vierte funktionale Spezialisierung geht über den Bereich der gewöhnlichen empirischen Wissenschaft hinaus. Sie begegnet Personen. Sie anerkennt die Werte, die jene vertreten. Sie mißbilligt deren Unzulänglichkeiten. Sie untersucht genau deren intellektuelle, moralische und religiöse Annahmen. Sie greift bedeutende Gestalten heraus, vergleicht ihre Grundanschauungen und unterscheidet Prozesse der Entwicklung und Prozesse der Verirrung. In dem Maße, wie sich die Untersuchung immer weiter ausdehnt, kommen Ursprünge und Wendepunkte ans Licht, Blüte und Verfall religiöser Philosophie, Ethik und Spiritualität. Und wenn auch nicht alle Gesichtspunkte vertreten sein mögen, besteht doch die theoretische Möglichkeit, die vierte funktionale Spezialisierung auf acht ganz unterschiedliche Arten auszuführen. (255f; Fs)

57/X Solche Divergenz ist jedoch nicht auf künftige Forscher beschränkt. Positionen und Gegenpositionen sind nicht bloß kontradiktorische Abstraktionen. Sie sind konkret zu verstehen als entgegengesetzte Elemente im fortschreitenden Prozeß. Sie müssen in ihrem eigenen dialektischen Charakter erfaßt werden. Menschliche Authentizität ist nicht eine reine Qualität, ist nicht friedliche Freiheit von jeglichem Versehen, von jedem Mißverständnis, von allen Fehlern und Sünden. Sie besteht vielmehr in einem Rückzug aus der Nicht-Authentizität, aus der Unechtheit, und dieser Rückzug ist nie eine permanente Errungenschaft. Er ist immer prekär, muß immer wieder von neuem unternommen werden und bleibt stets zum großen Teil eine Sache der Aufdeckung noch weiterer Versehen, des Eingeständnisses weiterer Verstehensmängel, der Korrektur weiterer Fehler und immer tieferer Reue über verborgene Sünden. Kurz, die menschliche Entwicklung erfolgt weithin durch die Auflösung von Konflikten, und im Bereich des intentionalen Bewußtseins sind die Grundkonflikte durch den Widerstreit von Positionen und Gegenpositionen bestimmt. (256; Fs) (notabene)

58/X Nur durch ein Vorankommen in kognitiver und moralischer Selbst-Transzendenz, wodurch der Theologe seine eigenen Konflikte überwindet, kann er hoffen, die Ambivalenz, die in anderen am Werk ist, zu erkennen, wie auch das Maß, in dem sie ihre Probleme lösten. Nur durch solche Einsicht darf er hoffen, all das recht zu würdigen, was in der Vergangenheit im Leben und Denken selbst von Gegnern intelligent, wahr und gut gewesen ist. Nur durch solche Einsicht kann er zur Anerkennung all dessen kommen, was an Desinformation, Mißverständnis, Irrtum und Bösem selbst in jenen vorhanden war, mit denen er verbunden ist. Zudem beruht ein solches Vorgehen auf Gegenseitigkeit. Wie es unsere eigene Selbst-Transzendenz ist, die uns fähig macht, andere richtig zu erkennen und fair zu beurteilen, so gelangen wir umgekehrt dazu, uns selbst zu erkennen und unsere Wertwahrnehmung auszuweiten und zu verfeinern, indem wir andere erkennen und würdigen. (256; Fs) (notabene)

59/X Soweit also die Forscher zusammenstellen, vervollständigen, vergleichen, reduzieren, klassifizieren und selektieren, bringen sie die dialektischen Gegensätze ans Licht, die in der Vergangenheit bestanden. Sofern sie eine bestimmte Ansicht zur Position erklären und ihr Entgegengesetztes zur Gegenposition und dann dazu übergehen, die Positionen zu entwickeln und die Gegenpositionen umzukehren, liefern sie sich gegenseitig die Evidenz für ein Urteil über ihre eigene persönliche Leistung an Selbst-Transzendenz. Sie enthüllen damit jenes Ich, das die Forschung betrieb, die Deutungen anbot, die Geschichte untersuchte und Werturteile abgab. (256f; Fs) (notabene)

60/X Eine derartige Objektivierung der Subjektivität ist so etwas wie eine Probe aufs Exempel. Wenn sie auch nicht automatisch wirkt, so gibt sie den Aufgeschlossenen, den Seriösen und den Aufrichtigen doch eine Gelegenheit, sich selbst einige Grundfragen zu stellen, zuerst über andere, schließlich aber auch über sich selbst. Sie thematisiert die Bekehrung und fördert sie dadurch. Ihre Ergebnisse werden sich weder sofort einstellen noch aufsehenerregend sein, da Bekehrung für gewöhnlich ein langsamer Reifungsprozeß ist. Sie besteht darin, daß man für sich selbst und in sich selbst entdeckt, was es heißt, einsichtig zu sein, rational zu sein, verantwortlich zu sein und zu lieben. Die Dialektik trägt zu diesem Ziel bei, indem sie letzte Differenzen herausstellt, das Beispiel anderer vor Augen führt, von denen man sich völlig unterscheidet, und indem sie uns Gelegenheit zur Reflexion gibt, zu einer Selbstprüfung, die zu einem neuen Verständnis des eigenen Ich und des eigenen Schicksals führen kann. (257; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik der Methoden (1. Teil); Sprachanalyse, (Wittgenstein) - Lonergans Position; Sprache: normale - ursprüngliche Bedeutung; Umkehr d. Kritik d. Sprachphilosophie an geistigen (vorsprachlichen) Akten

Kurzinhalt: Wenn man sich jedoch diesen Ansatz zu eigen macht, kann man die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache nicht unter Berufung auf die sie hervorbringenden geistigen Akte erklären... keine zulässige Lösung, denn sie macht geistige Akte wieder zur Grundlage der ...

Textausschnitt: 7. Die Dialektik der Methoden: erster Teil

61/X Wir hatten bereits angemerkt, daß das Vorhandensein und das Fehlen intellektueller, moralischer oder religiöser Bekehrung nicht nur entgegengesetzte Horizonte entstehen läßt, sondern mit dem Aufkommen einer genügenden Differenzierung auch entgegengesetzte Philosophien, Theologien und Methoden hervorbringt, um die verschiedenen Horizonte zu rechtfertigen und zu verteidigen. (257; Fs)

62/X Nun ist es aber nicht die Aufgabe der Methodologen, sich mit diesen Konflikten zu befassen, sondern jener Theologen, die im Bereich der vierten funktionalen Spezialisierung arbeiten. Zudem wird die Strategie des Theologen nicht darin bestehen, seine eigene Position zu beweisen oder Gegenpositionen zu widerlegen, sondern die Verschiedenheit herauszustellen und deren Wurzeln ans Licht zu bringen. So wird er diejenigen gewinnen, die volle menschliche Authentizität zu schätzen wissen, und er wird diejenigen überzeugen, die sie erlangt haben. In der Tat beruht die Grundidee der Methode, die wir entwickeln möchten, auf der Entdeckung dessen, was menschliche Authentizität ist, sowie auf dem Aufweis, wie man sich auf sie berufen kann. Es ist keine unfehlbare Methode, denn Menschen sind leicht nicht-authentisch, unecht; dennoch ist es eine machtvolle Methode, denn tiefstes Bedürfnis des Menschen und seine hoch gerühmte Leistung ist die Authentizität. (257f; Fs) (notabene)

63/X Der Methodologe kann und darf allerdings den Konflikt der Philosophien oder der Methoden nicht völlig ignorieren. Dies gilt besonders für den Fall weitverbreiteter Anschauungen, die implizieren, daß sein eigenes Vorgehen verfehlt, ja sogar verkehlt sei. Demzufolge habe ich in aller Kürze einige Anmerkungen zu machen, erstens zu gewissen Behauptungen der Sprachanalyse, und zweitens zu bestimmten Schlußfolgerungen, die aus Prämissen idealistischen Denkens gezogen werden. (258; Fs)

64/X In einem wertvollen Beitrag, der auf der dreiundzwanzigsten Jahresversammlung der 'Catholic Theological Society of America' gehalten wurde, erklärte Edward MacKinnon: (258; Fs)

65/X 'Seit der Veröffentlichung von Wittgensteins 'Philosophische Untersuchungen' gibt es einen wachsenden Konsens, daß die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache wesentlich öffentlich und nur im abgeleiteten Sinne privat sei. Wenn dies nicht so wäre, könnte Sprache nicht als Vehikel intersubjektiver Kommunikation dienen. Folglich wird die Bedeutung eines Terminus hauptsächlich durch Klärung seines Gebrauchs oder der Gruppe seiner Verwendungen erklärt, die mit ihm verknüpft sind. Dies erfordert sowohl eine Analyse, wie Termini innerhalb der Sprache fungieren, oder eine Untersuchung der Syntax, als auch eine Analyse der außersprachlichen Zusammenhänge, in denen ihr Gebrauch angemessen ist, oder der Fragen der Semantik und Pragmatik. (258; Fs) (notabene)

66/X Eine Folge dieser Position [...] ist es, daß die Bedeutung eines Wortes nicht durch Verweisung oder Rückführung auf private geistige Akte erklärbar ist. Nach herkömmlicher scholastischer Lehre haben Worte Bedeutung, weil sie Begriffe zum Ausdruck bringen. Bedeutungen liegen primär in Begriffen, in privaten geistigen Akten oder Zuständen, und dann erst abgeleitet in der Sprache, die solch einen Begriff zum Ausdruck bringt. Innerhalb dieser Sicht der Sprache stellt Transzendenz kein allzu schwieriges Sprachproblem dar. Ein Wort wie etwa 'Gott' kann ein transzendentes Wesen bedeuten, wenn es eben dies ist, was man beim Gebrauch dieses Wortes meint. So tröstend eine derart einfache Lösung sein mag - sie geht leider nicht.'1 (258; Fs) (notabene)

67/X Ich halte das für eine klare und hilfreiche Diskussionsgrundlage und möchte einige Bemerkungen anfügen, um meine eigene Position klarzumachen. (259; Fs)

68/X Erstens glaube ich nicht, daß sich geistige Akte ohne einen tragenden Ausdrucksstrom ereignen. Der Ausdruck muß nicht unbedingt sprachlich sein; er braucht nicht adäquat zu sein; er braucht auch nicht der Aufmerksamkeit anderer vorgelegt zu werden - aber er ereignet sich. In der Tat berichtet Ernst Cassirer, daß Forscher, die die Aphasie, Agnosie und Apraxie untersuchten, diese Störungen der Sprache, des Wissens und des Handelns allgemein miteinander verknüpft fanden.2 (259; Fs)

69/X Zweitens bezweifle ich nicht, daß die gewöhnliche Bedeutsamkeit der normalen Sprache ihrem Wesen nach öffentlich und nur in abgeleitetem Sinne privat ist. Denn Sprache ist ja gerade dann normal, wenn sie in gemeinsamem Gebrauch ist. Sie ist in gemeinsamem Gebrauch aber nicht, weil irgendein isoliertes Individuum zufällig entschieden hat, was sie bedeuten soll, sondern weil alle Individuen der betreffenden Gruppe verstehen, was sie bedeutet. In ähnlicher Weise lernen Kinder und Ausländer eine Sprache, indem sie zum Ausdruck gebrachte geistige Akte nachvollziehen. Aber sie lernen die Sprache, indem sie lernen, wie sie gewöhnlich gebraucht wird, so daß ihre private Kenntnis der normalen Sprache vom allgemeinen Gebrauch abgeleitet wird, der seinem Wesen nach öffentlich ist. (259; Fs)

70/X Drittens, was für die gewöhnliche Bedeutsamkeit der normalen Sprache gilt, gilt nicht für die ursprüngliche Bedeutsamkeit jedweder Sprache, ob normal oder literarisch oder fachspezifisch. Denn alle Sprache entwickelt sich, und zu jedem Zeitpunkt besteht jede Sprache jeweils aus den Ablagerungen der Entwicklungen, die bisher erfolgten und nicht veraltet sind. Sprachentwicklungen bestehen nun in der Entdeckung neuer Anwendungen für vorhandene Wörter, in der Erfindung neuer Wörter und in der Verbreitung solcher Entdeckungen und Erfindungen. Alle drei Vorgänge sind Sache zum Ausdruck gebrachter geistiger Akte. Die Entdeckung einer neuen Anwendung ist ein geistiger Akt, der durch den neuen Gebrauch zum Ausdruck kommt. Die Erfindung eines neuen Wortes ist ein geistiger Akt, der durch das neue Wort zum Ausdruck kommt. (259; Fs) (notabene)

71/X Die Kommunikation der Entdeckungen und Erfindungen kann technisch erfolgen durch Einführung von Definitionen, oder spontan, wenn z. B. A seine neue Wortkonstellation äußert, B antwortet, A in Bs Antwort erfaßt, wie erfolgreich er bei der Übermittlung des von ihm Gemeinten war, und er, je nach Ausmaß des Mißlingens, weitere Entdeckungen und Erfindungen sucht und ausprobiert. Durch einen Vorgang von Trial and Error nimmt ein neuer Wortgebrauch Gestalt an, und wenn eine genügend weite Verbreitung des neuen Wortgebrauchs erfolgt, dann ist ein neuer normaler Gebrauch eingeführt. Anders als die normale Bedeutsamkeit entsteht die Bedeutsamkeit als solche in ausgedrückten geistigen Akten, wird durch ausgedrückte geistige Akte übermittelt und vervollkommnet, und wird zur Normalsprache, wenn die vervollkommnete Kommunikation auf eine genügend große Zahl von Individuen ausgedehnt wird. (259f; Fs)

72/X Viertens scheint hinter dieser Verwechselung von normaler Bedeutsamkeit und ursprünglicher Bedeutsamkeit noch eine weitere verborgen zu sein. Denn zwei ganz verschiedene Bedeutungen kann man der Aussage beilegen, alle philosophischen Probleme seien Sprachprobleme. Wenn man Sprache als Ausdruck geistiger Akte versteht, wird man schlußfolgern, daß philosophische Probleme ihren Ursprung eben nicht nur im sprachlichen Ausdruck, sondern auch in geistigen Akten haben, und es könnte geschehen, daß man viel mehr Aufmerksamkeit den geistigen Akten widmet als dem sprachlichen Ausdruck. (260; Fs)

73/X Man kann aber auch der Meinung sein, geistige Akte seien bloß okkulte Entitäten, oder, falls sie wirklich existieren, sich die Philosophen bloß endlos abarbeiten, wenn sie ihnen besondere Aufmerksamkeit schenken, oder zumindest, wenn sie sie zur Grundlage ihrer Methode machen. Bei einer reduktionistischen Auffassung, oder bei einer mehr oder minder starken methodologischen Option, kann man dafür eintreten, den philosophischen Diskurs, zumindest den grundlegenden philosophischen Diskurs auf den Gebrauch der normalen Sprache zu beschränken, die vielleicht durch die Metasprachen der Syntax, der Semantik und der Pragmatik erhellt wird. (260; Fs)

74/X Wenn man sich jedoch diesen Ansatz zu eigen macht, kann man die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache nicht unter Berufung auf die sie hervorbringenden geistigen Akte erklären. Das wäre eine einfache Lösung. Es wäre eine wahre Lösung. Es ist aber keine zulässige Lösung, denn sie macht geistige Akte wieder zur Grundlage der Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache und tut dadurch gerade das, was die philosophische oder die methodologische Entscheidung verboten hat. Zudem übersieht man leicht innerhalb dieses Horizonts den Unterschied zwischen der Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache, die zur normalen Sprache geworden ist, und der hervorbringenden Bedeutsamkeit, die sie besitzt, wenn sie dabei ist, normale Sprache zu werden. Auf der Basis dieses Übersehens kann man behaupten, daß die Bedeutsamkeit der Sprache ihrem Wesen nach öffentlich und nur in abgeleiteter Weise privat ist. (260; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik der Methoden (2. Teil); Differenzierung d. Bewusstseins (allgemein, Theorie, Interiorität, Transzendenz); Interiorität: Gnoseologie, Epistemologie, Metaphysik (3 Grundfragen)

Kurzinhalt: Innerhalb der Welt der Interiorität sind deshalb geistige Akte als erfahrene und systematisch verstandene ein logisch Erstes. Von ihnen kann man zur Epistemologie und Metaphysik übergehen. Und von diesen dreien ausgehend läßt sich ... Sinn und Bedeutung

Textausschnitt: 8. Die Dialektik der Methoden: zweiter Teil

75/X Wir sprachen über geistige Akte und müssen nun dazu anmerken, daß solche Rede in genetisch verschiedenen Horizonten erfolgen kann. In jedem dieser Horizonte kann die Rede korrekt oder unkorrekt sein, doch je differenzierter der Horizont, desto inhaltsreicher, genauer und erhellender wird die Rede sein. (261; Fs)

76/X Von den genetisch verschiedenen Horizonten haben wir die wichtigsten bereits in den Abschnitten über 'Bereiche der Bedeutung' und 'Stadien der Bedeutung' im dritten Kapitel über 'Sinn und Bedeutung' aufgezeigt. Im voll differenzierten Bewußtsein sind vier Sinnbereiche. Der Bereich des Allgemeinverstands, der seine Bedeutungen in alltäglicher oder normaler Sprache zum Ausdruck bringt. Der Bereich der Theorie, in welchem die Sprache technisch ist, einfach objektiv in ihrem Bezug, und die sich daher auch auf das Subjekt und seine Tätigkeit nur als Objekte bezieht. Sodann gibt es den Bereich der Interiorität, in welchem die Sprache zwar vom Subjekt und seinen Handlungen als Objekten spricht, nichtsdestoweniger aber auf einer Selbstfindung beruht, die in persönlicher Erfahrung den Operator, die Operationen sowie die Vorgänge verifiziert hat, auf die sich die Grundtermini und -relationen der verwendeten Sprache beziehen. Und schließlich gibt es den Bereich der Transzendenz, in dem das Subjekt in der Sprache des Gebets und des betenden Schweigens auf die Gottheit bezogen ist. (261; Fs)

77/X Voll differenziertes Bewußtsein ist die Frucht einer äußerst langen Entwicklung. Im ursprünglich undifferenzierten Bewußtsein sind der zweite und dritte Bereich gar nicht vorhanden, während der erste und vierte einander durchdringen. Sprache verweist primär auf das Räumliche, auf das Besondere, das Äußere, das Menschliche, und wird nur durch spezielle Verfahren auf das Zeitliche, auf die Gattung, auf das Innere und auf das Göttliche ausgedehnt. Seit dem Beginn der Zivilisation kam es zu wachsender Differenzierung der Rollen und Aufgaben, die zu übernehmen und auszuführen sind, zu einer immer aufwendigeren Organisation und Regelung, um diese Übernahme und Ausrührung sicherzustellen, zu einer immer dichteren Bevölkerung und immer größerem Überfluß. Bei jeder dieser Wandlungen erweitern sich die kommunikativen, kognitiven, effektiven und konstitutiven Funktionen der Sprache, wobei sich als zusätzliche Segnung die Literatur entwickelt und differenziert, um die menschliche Leistung zu feiern, das Böse zu beklagen, zu hohem Streben zu ermahnen und den Menschen in Stunden der Muße zu unterhalten. (261; Fs)

78/X All dies kann vorankommen, obwohl Denken, Reden und Tun innerhalb der Welt des Allgemeinverstands, der auf uns bezogenen Personen und Sachen und der normalen Sprache bleiben. Soll aber die praktische Neigung des Menschen von Magie befreit und zur Entwicklung der Wissenschaft gewendet werden, soll seine kritische Neigung vom Mythos befreit und zur Entwicklung der Philosophie gewendet werden, und soll sein religiöses Anliegen allen Verirrungen widersagen und sich der Läuterung unterziehen, dann ist allen drei Vorgängen mit einer Differenzierung des Bewußtseins und einer Anerkennung der Welt der Theorie gedient. In solch einer Welt versteht und erkennt man die Dinge nicht in ihrer Beziehung zu unserem Sinnesapparat oder zu unseren Bedürfnissen und Wünschen, sondern in den Beziehungen, die durch ihre gleichförmige Interaktion miteinander konstituiert sind. Um von so verstandenen Dingen sprechen zu können, bedarf es der Entwicklung einer besonderen fachspezifischen Sprache, einer Sprache, die von der des Allgemeinverstands ganz verschieden ist. Zweifellos muß man innerhalb der Welt der Wahrnehmung und Sprache nach Art des Allgemeinverstands beginnen. Zweifellos muß man häufig zu dieser Welt Zuflucht nehmen. Es steht aber auch außer Zweifel, daß dieser wiederholte Rückzug und diese Wiederkehr nur für den schrittweisen Aufbau eines ganz anderen Modus der Wahrnehmung und des Ausdrucks sorgen. (261f; Fs) (notabene)

79/X Diese Differenzierung des Bewußtseins zeigt sich im platonischen Kontrast zwischen phänomenaler und noumenaler Welt, in der aristotelischen Unterscheidung und Korrelation dessen, was erstes für uns und was absolut erstes ist, in den Hymnen des Thomas von Aquin und seiner systematischen Theologie, in Galileis Sekundär- und Primärqualitäten, oder an Eddingtons zwei Tischen. (262; Fs)

80/X Bei dieser Differenzierung, die nur zwei Bereiche kennt, sind technische Naturwissenschaft, technische Philosophie und technische Theologie alle drei im Bereich der Theorie angesiedelt. Alle drei arbeiten grundsätzlich mit Begriffen und Urteilen, mit Termini und Relationen, und mit einer gewissen Annäherung an das logische Ideal der Klarheit, Kohärenz und Strenge. Und schließlich befassen sich alle drei in erster Linie mit Objekten, und wenn sie sich auch dem Subjekt und seinen Handlungen zuwenden, ist doch jede systematische Behandlung des Subjekts und seiner Handlungen - wie bei Aristoteles und bei Thomas - objektiviert, und zwar metaphysisch in Begriffen wie Materie und Form, Potenz, Habitus, Akt, Wirk- und Finalursache konzipiert.1 (262; Fs)

81/X Durch die weitere Entwicklung der Naturwissenschaft ist jedoch die Philosophie gezwungen, aus dem Bereich der Theorie auszuwandern, um ihre Grundlage nun im Bereich der Interiorität zu finden. Einerseits gibt die Naturwissenschaft jeden Anspruch auf Notwendigkeit und Wahrheit auf. Sie gibt sich mit verifizierbaren Möglichkeiten zufrieden, die eine immer bessere Annäherung an die Wahrheit bieten. Andererseits aber leistet ihr Erfolg totalitären Ansprüchen Vorschub, und die Naturwissenschaft selbst versteht ihr Ziel als die volle Erklärung aller Phänomene. (262f; Fs)

82/X In dieser Situation bleibt es der Philosophie überlassen, mit den Problemen von Wahrheit und Relativismus ebenso fertig zu werden wie mit der Frage, was unter Wirklichkeit zu verstehen sei, worin der Grund für Theorie und Allgemeinverstand zu suchen ist, welche Beziehungen zwischen beiden bestehen und welches die Grundlagen der spezifischen Humanwissenschaften sind. Die Philosophie ist mit der Tatsache konfrontiert, daß alles menschliche Wissen eine Grundlage in den Daten der Erfahrung hat, und da die Naturwissenschaft anscheinend auf die Sinnesdaten zumindest Okkupantenrechte erworben hat, muß die Philosophie nun auf den Daten des Bewußtseins Position beziehen. (263; Fs)

83/X Wie nun die Welt der Theorie von der des Allgemeinverstands ganz verschieden ist und dennoch nur durch einen vielfältigen Gebrauch des Wissens nach Art des Allgemeinverstands und der normalen Sprache aufgebaut wird, so ist auch die Welt der Interiorität ganz verschieden von den Welten der Theorie und des Allgemeinverstands, wird aber dennoch nur durch vielfältige Verwendung von mathematischem, naturwissenschaftlichem und allgemeinverständlichem Wissen und nur durch die normale wie auch durch fachspezifische Sprache aufgebaut. Wie die Welt des Allgemeinverstands und ihre Sprache das Rüstzeug liefern, um in die Welt der Theorie einzusteigen, so liefern die Welten des Allgemeinverstands und der Theorie und ihre Sprachen das Rüstzeug, um in die Welt der Interiorität hineinzukommen. (263; Fs)

84/X Während jedoch der Übergang vom Allgemeinverstand zur Theorie uns zu Entitäten führt, die wir nicht unmittelbar erfahren, bringt uns der Übergang vom Allgemeinverstand und von der Theorie zur Interiorität vom Selbstbewußtsein zur Selbsterkenntnis. Allgemeinverstand und Theorie haben uns vermittelt, was unmittelbar im Bewußtsein gegeben ist. Durch sie sind wir von bloß gegebenen Vollzügen und Prozessen und Einheiten zu einem Grundsystem von Termini und Beziehungen vorgedrungen, welche die Vollzüge und Prozesse und Einheiten unterscheiden, in Beziehung setzen und benennen und uns dadurch in die Lage versetzen, über sie klar, genau und erklärend zu sprechen. (263; Fs) (notabene)

85/X Solche Sprache wird jedoch nur von denen als klar, genau und erklärend empfunden, die ihre Lehrzeit hinter sich haben. Es genügt nicht, Allgemeinverstand zu haben und die normale Sprache zu sprechen. Man muß auch mit der Theorie und mit der technischen Sprache vertraut sein. Man muß die Mathematik untersuchen und dabei entdecken, was geschieht, wenn man sie studiert, und was geschah, als sie entwickelt wurde. Von der Reflexion über die Mathematik muß man zur Reflexion über die Naturwissenschaft weitergehen, muß ihre Verfahrensweisen kennenlernen, die Beziehungen zwischen aufeinanderfolgenden Stadien, die Verschiedenheit und die Beziehung klassischer und statistischer Methoden sowie die Eigenart jener Welt, die durch solche Methoden enthüllt wird - wobei man die ganze Zeit über nicht bloß den Objekten der Wissenschaft Beachtung schenken muß, sondern ebenfalls, so gut man kann, den bewußten Vollzügen, durch die man die Objekte intendiert. (263; Fs)
86/X Von der Genauigkeit mathemathischen Verstehens und Denkens, wie auch vom weitergehenden kumulativen Voranschreiten der Naturwissenschaft, muß man sich dann wieder den Verfahrensweisen des Allgemeinverstands zuwenden, muß man erfassen, wie er sich von Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft unterscheidet, muß seine eigenen Verfahren ebenso erkennen wie die Reichweite seiner Relevanz und seine ständige Gefahr, mit allgemeinem Unsinn (common nonsense) zu verschmelzen. Um es in größter Kürze zu sagen: Man muß Insight nicht nur lesen, man muß sich selbst auch in sich selbst entdecken. (264; Fs)

87/X Kehren wir nun zu den Beziehungen zwischen Sprache und geistigen Akten zurück. Erstens muß eine Sprache, die auf geistige Akte hinweist, entwickelt werden. Wie wir bereits festgestellt haben, wird der homerische Held nicht als denkend geschildert, sondern als einer, der mit einem Gott oder einer Göttin, mit seinem Pferd oder einem Fluß, mit seinem Herzen oder seiner eigenen Stimmung spricht. Bruno Snells 'Die Entdeckung des Geistes' berichtet, wie die Griechen ihre Erfassung vom Menschen schrittweise entwickelten und schließlich auf die Probleme der Erkenntnistheorie stießen. Bei Aristoteles gibt es eine systematische Darstellung der Seele und ihrer Potenzen, Habitus, Handlungen und ihrer Objekte. In mancher Hinsicht ist diese Darstellung verblüffend genau, aber sie ist unvollständig und setzt durchgängig eine Metaphysik voraus. Sie liegt weder im Bereich des Allgemeinverstands noch in dem der Interiorität, sondern im Bereich der Theorie. Sie wird durch die vollständigere Theorie des Thomas von Aquin ergänzt. (264; Fs)

88/X Sobald jedoch das Bewußtsein differenziert und systematisches Denken und Reden über geistige Akte entwickelt ist, erweitert sich die Leistungsfähigkeit der gewöhnlichen Sprache beträchtlich. Augustinus' eindringende Überlegungen zur Erkenntnis und zum Bewußtsein, Descartes' 'Regulae ad directionem ingenii', Pascals 'Pensées' und Newmans 'Grammar of Assent' bleiben sämtlich im Bereich der Erfassung und Sprache des Allgemeinverstands und tragen doch enorm zum Verständnis unserer selbst bei. Überdies zeigen sie die Möglichkeit, das bewußte Subjekt und seine bewußten Vollzüge kennenzulernen, ohne eine vorgängig metaphysische Struktur vorauszusetzen. Eben diese Möglichkeit wird verwirklicht, wenn eine Untersuchung der mathematischen, der naturwissenschaftlichen und der Vollzüge des Allgemeinverstands Früchte trägt im Erfahren, Verstehen und Bestätigen der normativen Struktur aufeinander bezogener und sich wiederholender Vollzüge, durch die wir im Wissen vorankommen. Sobald unsere Erkenntnis auf diese Weise erfaßt wird, kann man von der gnoseologischen Frage (Was tun wir, wenn wir erkennen?) zur epistemologischen Frage (Warum ist dieses Tun Erkennen?) übergehen und kommt von beiden dann zur metaphysischen Frage (Was erkennen wir, wenn wir dies tun?). (264f; Fs)

89/X Innerhalb der Welt der Interiorität sind deshalb geistige Akte als erfahrene und systematisch verstandene ein logisch Erstes. Von ihnen kann man zur Epistemologie und Metaphysik übergehen. Und von diesen dreien ausgehend läßt sich, wie wir es im dritten Kapitel versucht haben, eine systematische Darstellung von Sinn und Bedeutung in ihren Trägern, Elementen, Funktionen, Bereichen und Stadien geben. (265; Fs)

90/X Dennoch ist diese Priorität nur relativ. Neben der Priorität, die man mit der Aufstellung eines neuen Bereichs der Bedeutung erreicht, gibt es noch die Priorität dessen, was man braucht, wenn der Vorgang des Aufstellens ausgeführt werden soll. Die Griechen brauchten eine künstlerische, eine rhetorische und eine argumentative Entwicklung der Sprache, ehe ein Grieche eine metaphysische Erklärung des Geistes aufstellen konnte. Die griechische Leistung war nötig, um den Umfang des Wissens und der Sprache des Allgemeinverstands hinreichend auszuweiten, ehe Augustinus, Descartes, Pascal und Newman ihre Beiträge auf der Ebene des Allgemeinverstands zu unserer Selbsterkenntnis leisten konnten. Die Geschichte der Mathematik, der Naturwissenschaft und der Philosophie, wie auch das eigene persönlich reflektierende Engagement in diesen drei Wissensgebieten sind nötig, wenn Allgemeinverstand und Theorie das Rüstzeug für den Einstieg in die Welt der Interiorität liefern sollen. (265; Fs)

91/X Die Bedingungen, geistige Akte als ein logisch Erstes zu gebrauchen, sind demnach zahlreich. Wenn man darauf besteht, in der Welt des Allgemeinverstands und der normalen Sprache zu bleiben, oder wenn man sich weigert, die Welten des Allgemeinverstands und der Theorie zu überschreiten, dann wird durch eigene Entscheidung die Möglichkeit ausgeschlossen, die Welt der Interiorität zu betreten. Doch solche Entscheidungen seitens irgendeines Individuums oder einer Gruppe sind für die übrige Menschheit schwerlich bindend. (265; Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik der Methoden (3. Teil);

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Methode in der Theologie

Titel: Methode in der Theologie

Stichwort: Funktionale Spezialisierung; Dialektik: Eine ergänzende Bemerkung

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Die Einsicht

Titel: Die Einsicht Bd. I und II

Stichwort: Möglichkeit d. Ethik: Einleitung

Kurzinhalt: Die Metaphysik wurde aufgefaßt als die Durchführung der vollständigen heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins. Die Grundfrage des vorliegenden Kapitels ist, ob die Ethik in derselben Weise aufgefaßt werden kann.

Textausschnitt: XVIII. Kapitel DIE MÖGLICHKEIT VON ETHIK

A11, E11 ()
A13, E13; Insight 618a

671a Die Metaphysik wurde aufgefaßt als die Durchführung der vollständigen heuristischen Struktur des proportionierten Seins. Die Grundfrage des vorliegenden Kapitels ist, ob die Ethik in derselben Weise aufgefaßt werden kann. Unsere Antwort wird die Diskussion der in den Kapiteln über den Common Sense und im Abschnitt über die menschliche Entwicklung aufgeworfenen Fragen fortsetzen und die Fragestellung in drei Schritten in Angriff nehmen. (Fs)

Erstens, ein Versuch wird unternommen, Notionen wie das Gute, den Willen, den Wert und die Pflicht herauszuarbeiten. Aus dieser Bemühung folgt eine Methode der Ethik, welche zur Methode der Metaphysik parallel läuft, und zugleich eine kosmische oder ontologische Erklärung des Guten. (Fs)

671b Zweitens, die Möglichkeit von Ethik wird aus dem Gesichtspunkt der Freiheit und der Verantwortung ins Auge gefaßt. Die Relevanz des Kanons der statistischen Residuen wird in Betracht gezogen. Die Natur der praktischen Einsicht, der praktischen Reflexion und des Entscheidungsaktes wird umrissen. Es wird auf die wesentliche Freiheit und Verantwortung des Menschen geschlossen. (Fs)

Drittens, die Möglichkeit von Ethik wird aus dem weiteren Gesichtspunkt der tatsächlichen Freiheit untersucht. Ist eine Ethik in dem Sinne möglich, daß sie eingehalten werden kann? Ist der Mensch zu einer moralischen Frustration verdammt? Ist eine moralische Befreiung nötig, wenn die menschliche Entwicklung dem Zyklus von abwechselndem Fortschritt und Rückschritt entgehen soll?

671c Schließlich mag es nützlich sein anzumerken, daß es uns hier nicht um die Aufstellung eines ethischen Kodex geht, sondern eher um die Behandlung der relevanten vorgängigen Fragen. Das vorliegende Kapitel legt also nicht Verhaltensvorschriften dar, sondern die allgemeine Form von Verhaltensvorschriften. Es ist vielleicht nicht nötig darauf zu bestehen, daß der Übergang von einer solchen allgemeinen Form zu den besonderen Vorschriften spezifischer Bereiche der menschlichen Tätigkeit nur anhand eines Verstehens dieser Tätigkeiten geschehen kann. Es folgt daraus, daß ein Computer, wenn er mit Prämissen aus unserem Kapitel versorgt würde, nicht auf irgendwelche besondere Vorschriften schließen könnte. Ich schreibe nun aber nicht für Computer, sondern für Menschen, und weil vollständige moralische Abgestumpftheit eher selten ist, sehe ich mich in der Erwartung gerechtfertigt, daß Kritiker annehmen werden, die Leser dieses Buches werden imstande sein, von der entfernten Möglichkeit von Ethik, die hier erwiesen wird, zur unmittelbaren Möglichkeit überzugehen, die die Anspruchsvollen fordern mögen. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Existentialismus (Jaspers, Heidegger, Satre, Marcel); allgemeine Bestimmung; Begriff: Existentialismus

Kurzinhalt: The four that I named are the principal people in the field - the most notable - and they differ remarkably. Jaspers is a Kantian and a Lutheran. Heidegger is an apostate; he was a Jesuit novice for a while, and then he went to a seminary for the ...

Textausschnitt: 9 General Orientation1

219a The subject of existentialism is difficult to line up because there are as many different shades of opinion on every topic as there are writers, and the differences of opinion go right back through the entire history of each thinker. On the other hand, there are certain broad tendencies that are common, and we will concentrate mainly on those. In particular, the question this week, as last week, will be, What about? and not just, What is? We cannot hope to go through the various authors on existentialism in a week. One could spend a week on any particular one and even then not do an entirely thorough job. (Fs)

l The Term 'Existentialism'

219b By 'existentialism,' then, we shall understand the types of method and of doctrine exemplified by Karl Jaspers, Martin Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, and Gabriel Marcel. The term refers to types of method and of doctrine. The name 'existentialism' was admitted by Jaspers without any difficulty, and of course, Sartre has claimed to be the existentialist. On the other hand, Marcel admitted it for a while, but after Humani generis,1 and perhaps more particularly to disassociate himself from Sartre, he decided to refuse to call himself an existentialist. And Heidegger from the beginning claimed that he was concerned with Ek-sistenz. (He is very fond of re-writing words with hyphens in them.)2 (Fs)

220a The four that I named are the principal people in the field - the most notable - and they differ remarkably. Jaspers is a Kantian and a Lutheran. Heidegger is an apostate; he was a Jesuit novice for a while, and then he went to a seminary for the secular priesthood, where he lost his faith and went into philosophy. Sartre is a professional atheist. Marcel is a convert to Catholicism. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Existentialismus (allgemeine Bestimmung); Beziehung zu Positivismus und Idealismus

Kurzinhalt: They are separated, then, on the one hand from the positivistic scientific attitude, and on the other hand from the idealist position that to a great extent has dominated the philosophic schools of Europe.

Textausschnitt: 4 Relation to Positivism and Idealism
222b That question is, in the first place, anti-positivist. 'Being a man' is not any set of outer data to be observed. It is not any set of properties to be inferred from the outer data. It is not any course of action that can be predicted from the properties. With that simple negation, you cut off entirely any scientific definition within the contemporary secular notion of science. If the external data are not relevant, then the properties you can infer from the data are not relevant, and any prediction you can make on the basis of the outer data or the inferred properties is not relevant. 'Being a man' springs from an inner and free determination that is not scientifically observable. And, in general, the existentialists emphasize this point. They cut off from human science any positivistic interpretation and any secularistic interpretation of the term. (Fs)
222c In the second place, the question is anti-idealist. The various transcendental egos are neither Greek nor barbarian, bond nor free, male nor female. They do not suffer and they do not die. We do. And again, the existentialists grasp the point. They cut themselves off entirely from the idealists. They are separated, then, on the one hand from the positivistic scientific attitude, and on the other hand from the idealist position that to a great extent has dominated the philosophic schools of Europe. (Fs)
222d Now positivism and idealism have been major determinants in producing the contemporary world. From the Renaissance on, man has been deliberately making man. An ideal of man was born at the Renaissance. The Renaissance discovery of the ancients was really the formulation of a human ideal, and it was popularized and has spread over Western civilization from its source in the Renaissance into the cultured classes in the period of the Enlightenment, and in the present century throughout the whole of the population. It is connected with the breakdown of Christianity and the domination of a humanly inspired way of life. Insofar as positivism and idealism have been major determinants in producing the contemporary world, and in the measure that the contemporary world is found unsatisfactory or even disastrous - a common attitude on the continent of Europe after the last World War and the domination of the Nazis - existentialism has a profound resonance. It stands for something that is utterly different from the types of thinking that produced the mess we are in, and so it has a great appeal on that account. (Fs)
223a That fact would seem to be connected with the success of the existentialist writers. Sein und Zeit was published in 1927 in Husserl's periodical, Jahrbuch fur Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung, an annual for philosophy and phenomenological research. Within four or five years it had run through five or six separate editions. I have already mentioned Jaspers's Die geistige Situation der Zeit, which ran through six editions in German in a few years and has been translated into various languages. Sartre became popular particularly after the war, but his L'étre et le néant dates from 1942.1 He was a cafe hero in Paris. Gabriel Marcel is the hero of European seminarians and of people interested in bringing Christianity back to the masses; he can put Christian doctrine across with amazing skill and effectiveness. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Existentialismus (Jaspers, Heidegger, Satre, Marcel); allgemeine Bestimmung; Was ist der Mensch (Kierkegaard); der Mensch als Ergebnis seiner Entscheidung

Kurzinhalt: 'Being a man' in that sense results from a decision. It is consequent to the use of one's freedom. It is something we have to be. It makes one the sort of a man one is, and it involves risks.

Textausschnitt: 3 'Being a Man'1

221b A fundamental feature found among all these writers is that they are concerned with what it is to be a man, not in the sense of having a birth certificate but in a simple sense that is obvious to everyone and that has no technical backing of any kind. Last fall, when questioned during the Egyptian crisis, President Eisenhower - I think it was at a press conference - was asked by someone if it wasn't risky sending a fleet or making some other move in the Mediterranean, and he answered very briefly, 'We have to be men.'2 'Being a man' in that sense provides a very brief clue to what the existentialists are concerned with. 'Being a man' in that sense results from a decision. It is consequent to the use of one's freedom. It is something we have to be. It makes one the sort of a man one is, and it involves risks. (In the present instance, the risk of nuclear warfare was in the back of the mind of the journalist asking the question.) (Fs)

222a Now that simple notion of being a man as something that one has to be and that one is not necessarily, that comes about freely and makes one what one is, is perhaps an extremely complicated notion when one gets to analyzing one's ethical foundations, but it is a notion that anyone can grasp, and it is common to existentialists generally. It is a laicization of Kierkegaard's 'being a Christian.' Kierkegaard wanted to know whether he was a Christian. And he proposed to himself the answer, 'Well, after all, I'm a Dane, and everybody in Denmark automatically is a member of the Lutheran Church of Denmark as by law established. So what is this nonsense of asking me whether I'm a Christian?' Then he showed that the question had a deeper meaning. A similar question can be asked about 'being a man.' (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Existentialismus (allgemeine Bestimmung); Zeit und Geschichte

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt: 5 Time and History
223b This resonance with contemporary history fits in with existentialist concern with time and with history. 'Being a man' is not a result of your being born. It is something that results from your use of freedom, and what results from your use of freedom is not a property that necessarily remains with you. It is maintained by the continuous use of your freedom. It is precarious. One is ever being a man or becoming a man; one does not achieve it. You can play the hero for a day and be just the opposite the next day. So this business of 'being a man' is intrinsically connected with the notion of time, and that intrinsic connection with the notion of time involves a connection with history in the sense of the development of human institutions, human cultures, and human ideas. (Fs) (notabene)
224a The intrinsic connection between 'being a man' and time is highlighted in Heidegger's title Sein und Zeit (Being and Time) and in Marcel's title Homo Viator,1 man as a being on the way. However, concern with history on the grand scale appears only in Jaspers, as far as I know. His book Vom Ursprung und Ziel der Geschichte (The Origin and Goal of History) was published in Munich by Piper in 1949, and they released the eleven-thousandth copy in 1950. The other thinkers probably do not have the capacity to take such a broad view of history as Jaspers does in that book. Of course the center of history for a Christian is the birth of Christ, and there is 'before Christ' and 'after Christ.' But Jaspers starts out from the viewpoint of the history of culture, and for him the decisive period is what he calls the Achsenzeit, the axial period, which he locates in the period extending from about 800 B.C. to 200 B.C. There we find the rise of individualism and of philosophies of all types in Greece, the Hebrew Prophets, Zoroastrianism in Persia, Buddhism in India, Confucius and Lao-Tzu in China. Jaspers maintains that, while there were higher civilizations prior to that Achsenzeit, in Mesopotamia, in Egypt, in the Indus Valley, still those higher civilizations were simply enormous organizations of man. There was not man the individual, in the sense that the self-responsible individual thinking for himself was not significant in those civilizations. In the civilizations created during the Achsenzeit, in those five areas and within approximately a span of six hundred years that in Greece stems roughly from Homer to Archimedes, there emerged the individual. Any civilization that has come into contact with the Greeks since the Achsenzeit has either absorbed the Greek capacity for philosophy or else has vanished. People who do not come in contact with that development remain on the level of folk cultures or primitive cultures. His judgment on our own time is that it is not another Achsenzeit, but is rather something comparable to the initial discovery of fire, or of language, or of the fundamental art on which human living is based. He sees this in technical society and in the unification of the world. Jaspers is the most cultivated, the most broadly humanistic, and in a sense the most balanced and sane of any of these writers. He is a man of considerable talent, and he has none of the oddities that you find in, for example, Heidegger or Sartre. (Fs)
225a So much for what is positive.2 First, then, we are concerned with what it is to be a man, in the sense that 'being a man' results from the use of freedom and that 'being a man' is not a method that you acquire once for all. Second, 'being a man' remains something predicated precariously on the continuous use of freedom. It stands in radical opposition both to any positivistic approach to a consideration of man - to human science based upon the externals of man, on his behavior, on what you can observe or infer or predict on that basis - and again to idealism: the transcendental ego doesn't suffer or die, and we do. (Fs)

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort: Existentialismus (allgemeine Bestimmung); Existentialismus u. Scholastik; Schwäche d. Existentialismus: Ablehnung propositionaler Wahrheit (damit Ablehnung von Dogmen, Trient usw.); fides fiducialis - assensus intellectus in verum;

Kurzinhalt: This shows the weak point in existentialism: you can push it any way you want, and that is the weak point in unconcern with propositional truth.

Textausschnitt:

____________________________

Autor: Lonergan, Bernard J.F.

Buch: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Titel: Phenomenolgy and Logic: The Boston College Lectures on Mathematical Logic and Existentialism

Stichwort:

Kurzinhalt:

Textausschnitt:

____________________________

Home Sitemap Lonergan/Literatur Grundkurs/Philosophie Artikel/Texte Datenbank/Lektüre Links/Aktuell/Galerie Impressum/Kontakt